CRISTO RAUL.ORG ' |
READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
CONTEMPORARY EAST EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHY
Chapter III.Epistemology, Ontology, and Logic13.Georg Lukacs.The Ontological Foundations of Human Thought and Activity
Everyone knows that in the last decade, a radical derivation from former
epistemological tendencies, neopositivism,
with its fundamental rejection of every ontological inquiry as unscientific,
has absolutely prevailed. Further, its dominance extended beyond philosophical
circles to the practical sphere. Once we seriously analyze the theoretical
motives of the political, military, and economic leadership of today, one finds
that it has been determined, consciously or unconsciously, by neo-positivist
methods of thinking. They have had unrestricted omnipotence; once the
confrontation with reality leads to the beginning of a crisis, the revolution
in the sphere of political economy permeates into the field of philosophy (in
the broadest sense).
Rather than being concerned with the ontological probings of the last decade, we shall restrict ourself to explaining certain problems initiated by Sartre
in this direction.
They arise in relation to Marxism. We know quite well that this
historical philosophy was rarely conceived as an ontology. Our study will
propose, on the contrary, that the philosophical conclusions of Marx, in fact,
were drawn from the logico-ontological idealism of
Hegel, arriving theoretically as well as practically with the outlines of an
historical materialist ontology. Hegel prepared the way, interpreting ontology
historically, in contrast to the religious ontology, by tracing the necessary
historical development from the “bottom”, from the simplest, to the “highest”,
to the most complicated objectifications of human culture. Obviously, stress
was placed upon social being and its productions, and as it was characteristic
of Hegel, man appears as self-creating.
Marxist ontology removes all logico-deductive
and historico-developmental,
teleological elements from the Hegelian. Also, with this materialism
“standing-on its feet”, the synthesis of simples disappeared from the series of
moving moments of this process. For Marx the starting point is neither the
ancient, materialist atom nor the Hegelian, highly abstract Being.
Ontologically, there are no such things. All existing things must always be
objective, always moving, changing parts of concrete complexes. Two basic
consequences can presently be drawn. First, all of being is an historical
process: second, the categories are not predicates of something existing or
coming into existence, nor, as well, (ideal) formal principles of matter.
Rather they are changing and changed forms of matter itself: “forms of
existing”, “determinations of existence”. Since the radical position of Marx
(departing also from the older materialism) was frequently interpreted in the
old spirit, the false idea arose, that Marx de-emphasized the importance of
consciousness as against material being. Later we shall show the falsity of
this view. What matters now is to see that Marx interpreted consciousness as a
later product of material ontological evolution. For a materialist philosophy
of evolution the later product must never be conceived to be less important ontologically.
Consciousness of reality reflects and possibly changes the bases of its
modifying activity, pointing to a measure of real Power, rather than something
frail.
Let us deal with the ontology of social being. We cannot grasp its
particular nature, if we fail to take account of its arising on the basis of
organic being (which develops from inorganic being). Science has already begun
to uncover the forms of transition from one level to another. We find a sudden
leap, something qualitatively new, which could never be deduced from simpler
forms. As the qualitatively new arises, this novelty is, in many cases, a
departure from the manner of reacting of the more fundamental forms to new
categories of reacting. One may mention the way in which light works upon
plants, in a purely physico-chemical
manner, developing later as sight in the higher animals. Thereby there arise
unique kinds of being (though the new forms should not be thought of as the
original, fundamental existences).
A certain higher development of organic reproductive processes is
necessary in order that labor will be able to emerge as a dynamic, structural
foundation for a new type of being. The essence of labor consists in its
surpassing the forms of living beings in its interaction with its environment.
It is not the perfecting of production which creates the essentially detached
moment, but rather the role of consciousness which stops being a mere
epiphenomenon of biological reproduction: whose product is, Marx states, a
result, which was already ideally contained in the beginning of the process,
“already in the idea of the worker”.
It is quite striking that the materialistic dichotomy of organic nature
and social being attributes a decisive role to consciousness. One should not,
however, forget that it is able to maintain its emerging complex of problems
(its highest type being freedom and necessity) only by the active role of
consciousness, precisely and genuinely ontologically. Where consciousness has
no effective power, such a contrast could not appear. When such a role belongs
to consciousness, it must resolve these antitheses.
One can with good reason designate the laborer, who through his work
moves from an animal to a man, as an active being. Undoubtedly, laboring
activity arises as a solution to his needs. If, however, one were to pass over
its essence, one would be presupposing an immediate relation. On the contrary,
man, precisely because he is an active being, because he (parallel with social
evolution. in a progressive way), with his goals, the possibilities of his
gratification; generalizes his questions, and in his answers to these needs of
his activity, establishes and enriches his goals, often through extensive
adjustments, Thus, not only the answer but the question as well are direct
products of the activity of conscious conduct. Therefore indeed, the answers do
not cease being primary in this moving complex. Material need, as the motor of
individual as well as of social reproductive processes, first sets the labor
complex truly in motion, and all adjustments actually serve the purpose of
satisfying it. Certainly by means of this series of adjustments and man’s using
and controlling such powers there is effected a higher development of man's
capabilities, changing continuously both his relation to surrounding nature, as
well as the relationships between men, etc., while drawing from nature
practical, effective powers, relations, attributes, which had previously not
been released.
In the case of labor, there is also the possibility of its higher
development, which it ontologically imparts to it by man acting. Already in
this way, but wholly as a consequence of the transformation of the mere
reactive-passive adaptation of the reproductive processes in the environment,
through its conscious and active metamorphosis; labor does not become merely a
fact, in which the new type of social being attains its expression, but (quite
ontologically) arrives at a model case of a wholly new form of being.
Labor consists of telic (teleologrischen) projects,
which set the respective causal series in motion. This well-established fact
eliminates a thousandyear-old ontological
prejudice. In contrast to causality, which describes a spontaneous law, in
which the movements of all forms of being obtain their general expression,
teleology is a way of projecting (Setzulagsweise), one
constantly accomplished by consciousness, which, guiding it in definite
courses, nevertheless can set the causal series in motion. Since in the earlier
philosophies the teleological project was not understood as a special
peculiarity of social being, it was necessary to have puzzled out on the one
hand a transcendental subject, and on the other a peculiar character of
teleological acting relationships, in order to be able to speak about nature
and society’s tendency to develop in a teleological manner. The duality in this
state of affairs, that in a society which actually has become social, in the
majority of its activities, some totality moves the whole, is the teleological
origin, is equally its real existence whether the individual remains or is
included, yet they remain in causal relationships, which relationships are
completely detached from their teleological character; such is the distinctive
point of view here.
Every social practice (Praxis), if we think of labor as the model,
reconciles these opposites. On the one hand, each man faces the alternatives of
which he must decide whether he shall do something or abstain from so doing.
Every social act therefore originates from alternatives about future,
teleological projects. Social necessity can only be successful in the (often
anonymous) pressure on the individual, to accomplish his alternatives, deciding
upon a determinate course. Marx pointed out correctly in this situation that
men, “under penalty of destruction”, are pressed to act by the circumstances in
a certain way. However, men must consummate their activities, in the final
analysis, by themselves, even if they often act against their convictions.
From this unavoidable human situation of living in society is derived
the entirety of the real problems which we subsume under Freedom. Without
infringing upon the sphere of labor in its proper sense, we can refer to the
categories of value and duty. Nature knows neither the one nor the other. The
transformation of something into another in inorganic nature has,
self-evidently, nothing to do with values. The situation is altogether
different in respect to work. Knowledge distinguishes in general very clearly
the objectively existing Being in-itself of objects
from its merely conscious Being for-itself, which
one finds in the epistemic process. Now, however, the Being-for-itself of the
products of labor is transformed into its objective real, existing condition,
precisely to that through which it can fulfill, if correctly situated and
realized, its social function. In this way it becomes valuable (or in the case
of failure, worthless, valueless). It is only through the actual, objective
development of Being-for-itself that value can be derived. That these spiritual
(geistigere)
forms are drawn from the higher stuff of social life, does not put aside the
fundamental meaning of its ontological genesis.
Duty stands in an analogous relation. Duty constrains one through social
goals, determining human ways of behaving. It is the essence of labor that, in
all its variety, it must satisfy the initial goals to which men direct
themselves. For this reason duty is always implicit in each act. Also here, it
does not alter the existing, decisive factors, since this dynamic structure
will be transmitted to the purely spiritual laws of action.
It shows itself in opposition to the existing connecting links, which
lead from the original to the later spiritual ways of behaving; this in greater
clarity, in contrast to the epistemological-logical methods, by which the
course that leads from the higher forms from the original, become invisible, so
that these appear from our own historical era immediately as antitheses.
When we view something only from the projecting subject from a given
point in respect of the total process of labor, thus we see well enough that
this indeed consciously takes place within the telic project; and yet at no
time is it possible to observe all of the conditions of an activity, much less
foresee all its consequences. Of course, this does not stop man from acting.
There are countless situations which, at the risk of destruction, must be dealt
with unconditionally, despite the fact that man is able to observe only a
fraction of the circumstances. Often by laboring man realizes that he commands
only a small part of the conditions; he realizes, however, that he is able to
accomplish something thereby, since his need pressures him, and his labor also stands
as a gratification in expectation.
This unavoidable situation has two important consequences. First, the
inner dialectic of the continual perfection of labor while its process is being
carried out, owing to the observation of its results, etc.; the extent of the
known, achieved results constantly improves and consequently labor itself is
always manifold, always comprehending greater dimensions, will always be more
and more extensively modified, as well as intensively.
But since this process of perfection exhibits to us basic facts, which
the state of partial knowledge of complete conditions cannot overcome (parallel
to its growth), the manner of existing of labor brings forth the recognition of
a transcendent reality, whose unknown powers man somehow attempts to turn to
his advantage. This is not the place to investigate the various forms of
magical praxis, religious beliefs, etc., which grew out of this situation. They
should not be entirely ignored, however, constituting one form nevertheless of ideological
form. In relation to these things mentioned (magical praxis), and because labor
is not only the objective, ontological model of all human activity, but also it
is the prototype for the divine creation of reality, of all things, by means of
an omniscient creator teleologically producing
reality’s forms.
Labor is therefore a conscious process, presupposing less than
complete, concrete knowledge of specific ends and means. Since developments,
perfection, belong to its ontological token of essence, labor creates social
forms of a higher order. Perhaps the most crucial of these differentiations
would be the increasing independence of preliminary, preparatory labor, which,
always relative, separates knowledge as ends and means from concrete labor itself.
Mathematics, geometry, physics, chemistry, etc., were originally components,
instances, of this preparatory process of labor. Gradually, they grew to
independent disciplines, without being able to shed completely their original
function. At the same time, the more universal and independent these sciences
became, the more universal and perfect labor became; the more they spread out,
intensified, etc., the greater became the influence of such applied knowledge
upon the ends and means of the performance of work.
Such a differentiation takes place already in a relatively highly
developed form of social segmentation. This itself, however, is the most
elementary result of the development of labor itself. Even before it had been
brought to its maximum intensive development, during the same period this
consequence already emerged in the hunting situation. What is ontologically
noteworthy is the appearance thereafter of a new form of the telic project:
namely, it would appropriately not have to work thereby with a part of nature
for human projected goals, but a man (or many) would have to set up additional
telic projects in a predetermined manner. Since a certain kind of work can only
have a uniform, central goal, it implies that means must be found to insure unity
of purpose in the preparation and performance of work. Therefore, these new
telic projects must develop simultaneously with the division of labor in
actuality, and further must remain as indispensable elements in this segmentation
of work. From these social segmentations, and with the emergence of social
classes having antagonistic interests, these teleological projects become the
structural and intellectual foundations of that which is termed Marxist
Ideology. From these struggles, which are sharpened by the development of
production, ideologies show the forms by which men become conscious of these
contradictions, and by which they then fight them out.
Lore and more deeply these conflicts penetrate collective social life.
From personal and directly personal, annulled contradictions, and in everyday
life, they reach up to these crucial complexes of problems, which mankind had
attempted to eliminate in its great social revolutions. However, the most
fundamental type of structure always exhibits certain essential, common
characteristics: just as for labor itself it was inevitable that real knowledge
about its natural process would come to light, in order that the assimilation
of nature by society could be successfully administered; thus it is also
indispensable, too, that we have a certain knowledge about man's constitution,
men’s personal and social relationships, in order that we can bring about those
telic projects we desire to see fulfilled. With such vital discoveries,
initially taking the form of custom, tradition, and habit, as well as that of
myth, there arose the later sophisticated procedures of the sciences. Though we
cannot deal with the details in this lecture, his assimilation of nature and
ills telic projects influence his knowledge. This fact should not lead to a
theoretical exaggeration of unity, nor to absolute difference either. There are
ontological similarities and differences existing simultaneously, to which the
solutions can only be found in a concrete, socio-historical dialectic.
I have been referring to the socio-ontological principle. Each social
event that springs from telic, individual projects is nevertheless a pure,
causal character. The teleological genesis has important natural consequences
for the totality of social processes. On the one hand, conditions arise (with
all of their consequences), which nature would never produce; e.g. the
primitive wheel. On the other hand, every society develops so that necessity
ceases to operate mechanistically, spontaneously, its method of operating
becoming continually stronger to the extent that it causes, pushes, and
pressures men towards specific teleological decisions, or to prevent them from
making given decisions.
The total process of society is a causal one, which has its own
lawfulness, at no time, however, is this total process an objective,
consciously designed teleology. Also when they are successful, men or groups of
men realize their projected goals, consequently generating a situation quite
different from what they had willed. (One can mention, then, how the
development of the forces of production in antiquity destroyed the foundations
of society, how there emerged, at a given stage of capitalism, periodic
economic crises, etc.) This inner contradiction between telic projects and their
causal consequences increases with the growth of society, with the
intensification of socio-human interest in them. In relation to this widening
contradiction, great economic disasters (one can think of the crisis of 1929)
can rise, appearing to be unavoidable, natural catastrophes. During the
greatest upheavals, e.g. during great revolutions, however, history
demonstrates that the role of that which Lenin chose to term the subjective
factor was very significant. The difference between the projected goals and
their results are indeed expressed as the factual superiority of the material
elements and tendencies in the reproductive processes of society. This does
not mean for all time that this itself controls necessity, that no enduring
oppositions can be accomplished. The subjective factor, arising out of the
human reaction to such changing tendencies, remains open to many domains, a
constant occasionally modifying them, often being even the decisive factor.
We have attempted to demonstrate how the decisive categories and their
relations with social beings have already been present in labor. We shall not
detail the gradual advance of labor to its totalization in society. Thus, we simply skip over the most important mediating areas,
bringing out more clearly, at least, the most universal connection of the
genesis of society and history with their own development. Above all, we
propose to examine what economic necessity consists of. At the outset, it
should be emphasized that this is not a natural, necessary process, though Marx
himself, in his polemic with idealism, occasionally used such an expression.
In previous economic development, we can see three directional
developments, which have, it is well-known, come to pass, often very unevenly,
independently of men's desires and knowledge, which also lie at the foundation
of our telic projects.
First, socially necessary working time, labor-time for human
reproduction, tends constantly to diminish. As a general tendency this is not
disputed by anyone.
Second, this process of reproduction itself became ever more socially
intensive. When Marx spoke of a permanent “recession of nature’s barriers”, he
intended, on the one hand, that the basic form of human (and therefore of
social) life relative to nature’s processes never entirely ceases; while, on
the other hand, the quantitative as well as the qualitative aspects of the
purely natural laws recede in production, as well as in the product; that all
the decisive instances of human reproduction (such as nourishment and
sexuality) become transformed permanently and essentially into social moments
in their own right.
Third, economic development creates more and more critical qualitative
as well as quantitative relations between individuals, who originally appeared
in tiny, independent societies. At present one finds realized the greater and
greater economic predominance of the international market, already showing, at
the very least, an economically unified humanity. This unity lasts certainly
only as a reality and formation from real economic unifying principles. It
concretely manifests itself in a world in which this integration into our lives
creates the most difficult, the sharpest conflicts, e.g. in the Black question
in the U.S.A. We try to discern the important tendencies, external and internal
transformations of this social being through which its particular structure is
maintained, since the process in which man has developed from a being of nature
to a human personality, from a relatively highly developed kind of animal to
being a human, to mankind. All of that is the result of the initiation of the
causal series of complex society. The process itself has no goal. Its higher
development, in addition, includes the structuring of higher and higher
formations of more and more fundamental contradictions. Progress, indeed, is
the synthesis of human activities, but it is no way its consummation, in the
sense of a general Teleology: moreover, primitive, yet ever refined, economic
stages are destroyed again and again by evolution; therefore, objective
economic progress appears constantly in the form of new social conflicts. Thus
there is produced from the original community of men the seemingly insoluble
antinomies of class struggles; thereby also there are the most vexing forms of
inhumanity resulting from such progress. Thus today, the universality of human
alienation is a sign that economic development is about to revolutionize the
relationship of man to his work.
BUDAPEST, HUNGARY
|