CRISTO RAUL.ORG ' |
READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
CONTEMPORARY EAST EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHYChapter III.Epistemology, Ontology, and Logic
12.George A. Brutian
Lenin and Logic
Questions pertaining to logic have an important place in the theoretical
heritage of V. I. Lenin. It would be erroneous to see this only in terms of the
erudition of the creator of the world's first socialist state. Lenin saw
dialectics as the soul of Marxism, ascribing to dialectics not only the highest
form of philosophic thought, but also the method of transforming the
surrounding world in a revolutionary way.
Logic for Lenin not only had a quite direct relation to dialectics, but
was also seen as congruent with dialectics, in a certain sense. The focal
question in the problem-complex of logic raised by Lenin was that of the
relationship between logic, dialectics, and the theory of cognition. He
answered by positing a congruency of all three, seeing all three from a materialist
perspective. Lenin’s comprehension of these three was in full accord with the
views of the founders of dialectical materialism, Marx and Engels.
Engels had emphasized the historical aspect of materialism by
recognizing the transformation of materialism due to each epochal discovery in
the histories of the physical and social sciences. This approach is pertinent
also to the sciences of logic.
On the whole, the various theories of logic of given eras present by
their very nature are responses to the demands the sciences make upon logic at
any particular time.
Aristotle’s philosophy and his logical teachings were not dichotomized.
His philosophy also had subsumed under it the sciences, expressing the
quintessence of the intellectual comprehension of external reality and man's
spiritual world. Paradoxically, Aristotle, though it is correct to consider him
the founder of logic as a science, did not use the name “logic”, it came into
use later with the Stoics. It is also correct that Aristotle’s logic was
formalistic, though this needs qualification.
It is undoubtedly correct that Aristotle described with exceptional
insight the formal-logical attributes of thought, its structure and
construction. But, in addition to his formal-logical description of thought,
Aristotle inquired into a range of thinking lying beyond formal logic. Even
according to the classic writers of dialectical logic, some aspects of the
Aristotelian logic pertained to the problem-complex within the province of
dialectics. First of all there is the question of truth as a logical problem,
and there is the attempt to discern the contradictory nature of the form of
thinking, such issues of Aristotle’s philosophia prima attracted Lenin's attention. Lenin characterized Aristotle’s logic as “the
questioning, the search for the approach to logic (later) advanced by Hegel”
Philosophers and logicians in the period following Aristotle touched upon
problems, in various degrees, which often went beyond the framework of formal
logic. The evolution of these tendencies culminated in Kant’s “dialectical
logic”. This development was not just a terminological matter. Kant’s
transcendental logic, on the one hand, synthesized many elements of the
dialectics of thought, and, on the other, stimulated further development.
However, Hegel transformed these questionings, tendencies, and these fragments
into an entire system of dialectical logic. It was not unnatural, then, that,
in his logical inquiries, Lenin continually addressed himself to Hegel,
attempting to sublate him critically, never, of
course, rejecting Hegelian dialectics. Lenin copiously summarized Hegel,
appending numerous comments, while he concluded that the Science of Logic that
most idealist work of Hegel became less and less idealist, more and more
materialistic. As the recognized authority in materialistic
dialectics evaluated Hegel’s work as the acme of idealistic dialectics.
Moreover, the conception of logic of Lenin was a direct link, a stepping
stone, in the evolution of the notions of Mary and Engels. In this regard it is
apparent that there is a complete congruity of thought, an identity, of world
outlook for and of the goals of Marx, Engels, and Lenin. Hegel’s “critical
idealism” was sympathetically viewed by Lenin, as it had also been with Lenin's
predecessors, Marx and Engels. Lenin was convinced that a “critical
idealism” was closer to a “critical materialism” than to a crude materialism.
In contrast, dialectical materialists reject the “vulgar materialism” advocated
by Vogt, Büchner, and others. Thus, it is
demonstrated that science, in its progressive path, absorbs all that is
valuable, everything that was contributed by the founders of logic; even though
these contributors and founders had contrary world outlooks to dialectical
materialism.
Marx was the first to refashion dialectical logic and to put it into a materialistic
mold. He did not place, it is granted, his materialistic notions of dialectics
into specific treatises. The purpose which Marx set himself, the goal of
providing the working class with a theoretical tool for the revolutionary
transformation of the world, determined the form of expression of all of his
scientific interests. First of all, Marx analyzed the economic structure of
society, thus establishing a political economy, based on the principles of
dialectical logic derived from Hegel (but fundamentally reshaped by Marx). This
was accomplished to such a degree of perfection that Lenin observed, “though
Marx did not have a ‘Logic’, he did have the logic of Capital”.
Lenin’s conception of logic was fully derived from the teachings of Marx
and Engels, presenting a new step in their development. Lenin called attention
to the subject matter of dialectical logic, its relationship per se to dialectics, in full accord
with the postulates of the founders of Marxism which refers to the most general
laws of the development of nature, society, and human thought. For Lenin the
logical structure of capital, Marx’s main work, is an application of logic,
dialectics, and epistemology of materialism to a particular science. Lenin
attributed an overriding significance to the fusion of these elements. The
congruity of logic, dialectics, and epistemology in materialism overcame,
according to Lenin, the gap between ontology and epistemology which had
characterized the various philosophic systems prior to Marx. Hegel had
perceived this gap, and he established a new system, postulating that logic is
identical with Thought about Being. He defined metaphysics as the science of
things comprehended in thought. Nevertheless, the identity of Thought and
Being, Hegel’s view that thought is the only attribute of reality, of ultimate
Being, does not contradict the materialistic conception of the classics of
Marxism. Following Marx and Engels, Lenin considered an inquiry scientific when
it approached its subject matter dialectically, simultaneously applying the
epistemology of materialism and dialectical logic.
This thesis of the congruity of logic, dialectics, and the theory of
cognition within materialism has elicited great interest in Soviet philosophic
literature. Expositions on the thesis above have formed the content of the
works of the following Soviet logicians and philosophers:
M.N. Alekseyev (Dialectics of the Forms of
Thinking, Moscow, 1959; Dialectical logic, Moscow, 1960)
V. Asmuss (Dialectical Materialism and Logic: An Essay
on the Development of Dialectical Method from Kant to Lenin, Kiev, 1924
V.A. Vyazulin (The
Logic of Capital of K. Marx., Moscow, 1960),
G. G. Gabrielyean (Marxist Logic as Dialectics and Theory of Cognition, Yerevan, 1969),
D. P. Gorski (The Problems of General
Methodology and Dialectical Logic, Moscow, 1966),
A. Kasymdjanov (The
Problem of the Congruity of Dialectics,
Logic and the Theory of Cognition, Based on the "Philosophic
Notebooks" of V. I. Lenin, Alma-Ata, 1962),
B.M. Kedrov (The Unity
of Dialectical Logic and the Theory of Cognition, Moscow, 1969),
P. V. Kopnin (The
Philosophic Ideas of V. I. Lenin and Logic, Moscow, 1969),
V. I. Maltsev (Essays on Dialectical Logic, Moscow, 1964),
Z. M. Orubshev (The
Unity of Dialectics Logic and the Theory of Cognition in "Capital" of
K. Marx, Bakre, 1968),
I. S. Narski (The
Problem of Contradiction in Dialectical Logic, Moscow, 1969; Dialectical
Contradiction and the Logic of Cognition, Moscow, 1969)
M. M. Rosental (Principles of Dialectical Logic,
Moscow, 1960)
S. B. Tseritelli (Dialectical Logic, Tiblisi, 1965),
and
B. I. Tshvekessov (Materialistic Dialectics and-the Theory of Cognition, Moscow, 1907).
This list is not all-inclusive. Among the works listed the fundamental
studies of V, Asmuss, B.
M. Kedrov, and P. Kopnin can be singled out.
The postulation of Lenin of the congruity of logic, dialectics, and the
theory of cognition is, on the whole, accepted by Soviet logicians and
philosophers, who in the course of many years have engaged in lively
discussions of these problems. Some, for instance M. N. Aleksyev, V. I. Tscherkasov, V. I. Maltsev, S. B, Tseritelli, with a few variations in their
viewpoints, insist on the independent existence of dialectical logic as a
science, distinct from dialectical materialism. According to this conception,
dialectical logic inquiries into the specific forms of dialectical thinking.
The unity of logic, dialectics, and epistemology, moreover, expresses itself in
the following manner: logic investigates the dialectical forms of thought as
based upon the theory of cognition of materialism. Thus, there are two forms of
thought here, one dialectical, one formal-logical. The former constituting the
subject matter of dialectical logic, the latter of formal logic. This peculiar
“logical dualism” was subject to criticism by its opponents.
Other Soviet logicians identified and explained materialism’s logic,
dialectics, and epistemology in a uniform way, since they followed Lenin's view
that it is not necessary to have three separate areas, for they all have the
same reference. Marxist philosophy was observed to be the science of the most
general laws of the development of nature, society, and human thought. Another
view, strongly expressed by K. S. Bakhradse,
resulted in acknowledging the existence of but one logic, viz. formal logic,
seeing logic as the science of the forms and laws of correct thinking. This
conception has been criticized, in turn; for, in essence, it denies the
existence of dialectical logic.
P. V. Roshin, M. N. Rutkevitch, and a few
other Soviet philosophers interpret Lenin’s thesis of the congruity of logic,
dialectics, and epistemology as the unity of the parts and the whole. The
subject matter of dialectical logic is represented as a part of the subject
matter of the Marxist theory of cognition, while the subject matter of
epistemology is given as a part of the subject matter of materialist
dialectics. The weakness of this view is the realization that it is logically
unfounded.
A more correct interpretation of Lenin’s view is offered by those
philosophers and logicians (Kopnin, Kedrov, Narski, and some others) who
consider that a unified system of logic, dialectics, and materialist
epistemology, depending upon the object of application, performs different
functions. The method of materialist dialectics as applied to the laws and form
of a single structure of human thought, in terms of a function of the reflection
of reality, assumes the quality of dialectical logic. Thus logic does not
inquire into specific forms of the dialectical form of thought, but rather
refers only to the dialectics of the common forms of thought of mankind,
whatever they may be, simple or complex. The correctness of this way of looking
at it is affirmed by Lenin himself: “in any sentence it is possible (and
imperative) to discover the budding of all elements of dialectics, to
demonstrate thereby that all human comprehension in the most general form has a
dialectical character”.
In full accord with Hegel, Lenin considered that the primary content of
logic (dialectical logic) presents itself in relations, i.e. in the transition,
in the contradiction, of concepts. In contradistinction to Hegel, Lenin began
with the viewpoint that all these concepts, as well as their relationships,
transitions, and contradictions, constitute reflections of the objective world.
According to Lenin, the dialectic of things creates the dialectic of ideas, not
vice versa. This analysis is not to be regarded as an end in itself, but as a
necessary condition for reaching truth. As with the German philosophers (in
particular Hegel), Lenin equated logic and truth.
To reach truth one must be guided by the entire arsenal of the
dialectical epistemology. In one of his works in which he examines the concrete
character of the question under discussion, Lenin emphasized these features of
dialectical logic: (1) overall comprehension, the inquiry into all aspects of a
thing, all its connections and “instrumentalities”; (2) inquiry into the thing
in its development, its “automobility” (self-movement), and changes; (3)
consideration of human practice in the comprehensive “determination” of the
thing; accordingly, practice becomes a criterion of truth, as well as a
practical determinant of the connection of the thing with human needs); and (4)
the principle of the concreteness of truth.
An important question arises. What is Lenin’s position on formal logic?
Does not Lenin’s development of dialectical logic signify a rejection on his
part of formal logic? This question is also important since dialectical logic’s
opponents (who are also opponents of Marxist philosophy as a whole and of
Hegelianism), since they have held up the attainments of formal-mathematical
logic, attempt to detect incongruities and contradictions between formal and
dialectical logic.
Lenin’s position on formal logic was based upon those of his
predecessors, the founders of Marxist philosophy. In principle, there is no
difference between Engels and Lenin’s viewpoints. Lenin underlined Engels’
belief of the independent existence of formal logic as a philosophic science. Formal
logic has acquired different interpretations, depending on the philosophic
position of its interpreters. One should not be surprised that, for the most
part, the categories of logic have received a metaphysical and an idealistic
interpretation. A careful and thoughtful reading of Lenin’s legacy relative to
logic inevitably must result in the conclusion, that he did not take a critical stand on formal logic and
its laws and categories as such. He only subjected the metaphysical and
idealistic interpretations of formal logic to criticism. These
misinterpretations absolutized formal logic by
viewing it as the only principle of truth, resulting in an unwarranted
transformation of formal logic into a universal and exclusive method of
cognition, according to Lenin.
Opponents of dialectics often advance the following statements: Since
dialectics recognizes the contradictions, dialectical logic cannot be
considered as compatible with formal logic. Formal logic, basing itself on the
law of non-contradiction, rules out, by its very nature, any contradictory
thoughts; upon admission of a contradiction any theory loses its value. For
example, this kind of criticism can be found in the well-known philosopher Karl
Popper.
This critique, however, overlooks its target. It misses a major point,
since it does not pay attention to a crucial distinction. Lenin recognized a
distinction between dialectical and formal-logical contradictions. Further,
there should be no doubt that the classics of dialectical materialism recognized
the principle of contradictory development as applying to everything existent.
Lenin saw as an essential part of dialectics the splitting of the one into many
and the respective cognition of these contradictory parts. He defined
dialectics succinctly as the study of the unity of opposites.
Certainly in all those cases, Lenin refers to contradictions in real life. He makes reference to contradictions in the process of thought, not formal-logical contradictions. Against the absence of a distinction between the two types of contradictions, Lenin took a strong stand. He ridiculed those who confused the “contradictions of real life” and “contradictions resulting from erroneous reasoning”. Lenin categorically asserted that the “logical contradictory”, under conditions of correct logical reasoning, does not have to result in a subject matter rent by contradictions. This kind of concept Lenin demonstrated in such concrete inquiries as economics, politics, and sociology. What he meant was that the dialectical contradiction is to be kept as an ultimate, which by itself does not have to enter into the sphere of every analysis of every subject matter.
UNIVERSITY OF YEREVAN, ARMENIAN S. S. R.
|