CRISTO RAUL.ORG ' |
READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
CONTEMPORARY EAST EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHYChapter III.Epistemology, Ontology, and Logic11.Karel Berka
Toward a Materialistic Foundation of Logic
In this paper we shall make an attempt to develop a materialistic
standpoint in the philosophical foundation of logic, directed against
Empiricism, Conventionalism, and Rationalism, on the one hand, and against
Nominalism and Platonism, on the other. Our analysis, starting from a
conception of logic implicitly present or explicitly accepted by the majority
of logicians will be developed in three steps, including (a) quasi-ontological
presuppositions or prelogical (in case the term
“ontology” would evoke misleading associations to some), (b) semantical assumptions and (c) an analysis of the concept
of “existence”.
The basic ideas of Materialism relevant for our purpose, especially the
assertion of the priority of objective reality, are further developed in this
specialized domain by adopting a “methological materialistic dualism”, consisting in the acceptance not only of a real world,
but also of a world of ideas, the latter being the result of the practical and
theoretical activities of mankind. This explicit extension seems necessary to
us if the specific status of logic is to be adequately characterized, and if the
usual claims of different idealistic interpretations of logic (which still
prevail) are to be challenged. Some misunderstandings which might perhaps arise
in this respect are due mainly to the traditional gap between logic,
historically closely connected with Rationalism, and materialistic philosophy,
focused primarily on the problems of the natural and social sciences.
On the philosophical level, the principal task of any satisfactory
foundation of logic consists in an analysis of the relation of logic to
experience and reality. What has always been conceived as an alleged paradox
when dealing with logic, especially by empirically minded men, has been the
contrast between the grounding of empirical knowledge by experience and the
grounding of logic by itself. The logically valid propositional forms are valid
simply by their form, without having to be tested by human experience. Why is
deductive logic certain, whereas all other branches of science (with the
exception of pure mathematics) yield no more than probable results? To this
question several answers have been given.
From the philosophical standpoint of Empiricism, considered broadly,
logical knowledge is nothing but a result of induction, and it differs from
other kinds only by its more abstract nature. For Conventionalism, often
combined with Subjective Idealism, the validity of logic is determined by
linguistic conventions. From the standpoint of Rationalism, which is adopted in
principle by Objective Idealists, the necessity of logic is given a priori or
simply postulated (or it is felt to be an expression of the human mind’s
creativity).
All these explanations are undoubtedly one-sided. It must be maintained
against Conventionalism, which played an important role in the philosophical
conceptions of the Vienna Circle, that the L-constants (being the basis of the
definition of L-following and hence also the fundament of logical proof,
deducibility, or derivability of logical syntax) are not selected arbitrarily
as linguistic conventions. We cannot presume that logic is wholly independent
of experience and reality. It has an empirical basis, but not in the sense
assumed by empiricists. All branches of science are primarily rooted in
reality. Scientific activities and the results of science are at the very
beginning conditioned by the reality reflected in our experience. From this
obvious fact, which is sometimes briefly characterized by the dictum “nature is
prior to man”, it does not follow that in this simple form the genetic
materialistic monism is eo ipso fully adequate as an explanation of the peculiarities of
logic. To maintain such an attitude would mean that in any possible case only
experience is relevant to science, and that theory plays but an advisory part,
or that everything must be ultimately checked by experience. In connection with
the manifold activities of man as zoon politicon, backed by the
evolution of his linguistic habits, his capacities of theorizing have grown in
such a manner that the formerly immediate dependence of all his activities on
reality has lost its compulsory character in certain domains. At a certain
period of human history, a special, relatively independent “world of ideas” has
emerged. The acceptance of this “reality” does not imply any Platonic world of
ideas. The real world is one. Methodologically however, these two “worlds”, the
real world and the “world of ideas”, are fixed by language; these two are
indispensable for any reasonable explanation of the theoretical sciences. Thus
we have the conception of a genetic materialistic monism, reflecting the
priority of nature, supplemented by a methodological materialistic dualism
which takes into account the creativity of human activities. The assumption of
these two “worlds”, which Empiricism ignores and its opponents misinterpret, is
a necessary condition for any understanding of the origin, development, and
special status of formal logic as a science.
Against Empiricism we must argue with emphasis that its conception of
the process of abstraction is a faulty simplification, one which cannot explain
the special nature of logical constants. The definition of L-constants cannot
be conceived as simple collections of our experiences gained by the observation
of the linguistic habits of men. Logic as any other science adopts various,
historically determined empirical concepts, but this process is not a passive
transposition of experience into theory. Every theoretical concept with the
exception of primitive terms must be defined within the framework of a science.
Any theory is thus connected with the formation of new concepts, relativized to
the conceptual network of the theory in question. In logic, a formal science,
the difference between empirical and theoretical concepts is evidently stronger
than in any other factual science. This might be understood without any further
specification as a clear expression of Conventionalism or Objective Idealism.
If we stress only the creativity of concept-formation and disregard its
empirical basis, we adopt this standpoint, ultimately yielding the conclusion
that logical constants are no more than useful conventions.
As in any other theoretical science, concept-formation in logic has more
or less the character of idealization, which is (as commonly agreed) an
indispensable tool of theory construction. Only if we misinterpret the process
of idealization, which in different sciences admits different gradations, could
one argue that we are defending a concealed conventionalistic standpoint. If we admit, however,
idealization only in connection with its empirical basis, we reflect the actual
practice of science. The relation of idealized concepts to empirical ones may
not be factually traceable in every concrete case. It is only necessary to
admit this possibility, because otherwise it would be impossible to explain the
applicability of logic in both pure and applied science.
After this critical account of Empiricism and Conventionalism as the
extremes of possible philosophic attitudes to logic, we may approach the more
important questions which lead to the core of our inquiry. If we take into
account the historical development of logic, its present systemization and its
philosophical basis, it becomes clear that this relation must be understood in
two senses, i.e., as an immediate and as a mediated relation. The available
historical material shows clearly that the beginnings of logic are connected
chiefly with the evolution of science and with an analysis of linguistic
problems. The reflection of factual relations in reality is mediated through
linguistically fixed thoughts. The analysis and codification of different kinds
of reasoning, depending on propositions materially related to manifold facts,
cannot but take into account the formal aspects. The relation of logic to
reality is mediated through language. This fact, already manifest in the Stoic
and Medieval logics, is a special, characteristic feature of modern logic. We
can, of course, speak of an immediate relation of logic to reality if we ask
what corresponds to logical constants in reality. This immediate relation is
historically secondary, it does not characterize the trends of the evolution of
logic. Yet if we attempt to find a satisfactory grounding of logic, it plays an
important role.
From the very beginning, an analysis of the immediate relation of logic
to reality in modern theoretical discussions was connected with the renewal of
the problem of universals in logic and mathematics. Modern controversies
between Platonism and Nominalism deal with different problems, e.g., the problems
of the existence of logical and mathematical entities, infinity, etc. With
regard to our problem we are interested only in the question of ontological
commitments concerning the relation of logic to reality and its theoretical
reflection. These questions are accepted by most logicians as reasonable, even
if they are answered in a “neutral manner”, as by R. Carnap.
They are contained for the first time in Aristotle’s conception of logic. In
latter developments of logic formerly firm connections between logic and the
science of being were successively untied in favor of the connection of logic
with language. From this historically and systematically conditioned divorce of
logic from ontology (regretted in vain by the adherents of traditional logic
and philosophy), it does not follow that logic is independent of ontology, in
the sense that it has no relation to reality. That logic has no relation to
reality was held not only by the Vienna Circle as an expression of their
“anti-metaphysical" attitude), but also by working logicians, especially
in the purely syntactic period of modern logic. After the well-known results of
K. Gödel, which destroyed all hopes of realizing Hilbert’s programme, and of A. Tarski in the field of semantics; it was felt that logic cannot disregard the old
philosophical controversies, but must handle them in a new way.
The necessity of establishing the range of admissible variables not only
syntactically, but also semantically, led this time to considerations concerned
with a categorization of their values. The categorization of entities
designated or denoted by the variables of the language used in logic or
mathematics was in a certain sense already established by Russell’s theory of
types. This syntactically oriented theory was at first introduced only ad hoc, in order to eliminate the
logical paradoxes which arose in set theory and modern logic. With the semantical interpretation of the theory of types, it
became clear that the hierarchy of entities established by it is in fact a quite
natural categorization of designations, which could or rather had to be
introduced even though this had not been the original intension of B. Russell.
The theory of types, in a certain sense anticipated by Aristotle’s doctrine of
categories, was therefore the first attempt to give a systematic basis for the
language of logic. Now, if we take a further step and raise the question why
the theory of types is adequate to the present purposes of logic, we evidently
require a philosophical claim. This holds also for a semantical reinterpretation of the theory, as was attempted by Lesniewski.
In this situation, the older controversies in the philosophy of logic
were replaced by the controversy between Platonism and Nominalism. Both
participants in this controversy, in spite of irreconcilable standpoints,
agree that a categorization of the entities designated or denoted by variables
is a necessary assumption for any foundation of logic. The Nominalism in logic
and mathematics represented by N. Goodman, W. V. Quine,
and R. M. Martin, renounces abstract entities - classes, relations, properties,
etc. The Platonism, represented by A. Church and H. Scholz admits all kinds of abstract entities, and in its extreme form considers them
like Platonic Ideas. The dispute between Nominalism and Platonism with regard
to the so-called ontological problem is nowadays discussed on the basis of Quine’s formulation of ontological commitments. According
to this criterion, which was in principle admitted also by A. Church, it
depends on “the value of the variables and not on the supposed designata of the constant terms
that the ontology of a theory is to be sought”.
A language which admits variables that imply abstract entities as their
values, e.g. classes, relations, etc., is considered as Platonistic; whereas a language which does not
admit such variables is considered as nominalistic.
As existentially quantifiable free variables such a language admits only
individual variables. In the use of variables the Platonistic languages are unrestricted, provided
that the theory of types is strictly adhered to.
If we accept this dichotomy and terminology the usual languages of logic
and mathematics are Platonistic languages. The nominalistic philosopher of logic, who rejects the existence of abstract entities for
philosophical reasons, is now facing a very difficult task if he wants to
convince in a concrete fashion his philosophical opponents (or his neutrally
minded colleagues among working logicians and mathematicians). He must prove that
a nominalistic language
can serve equally well all the needs of logic and mathematics. He therefore
attempts a nominalistic reinterpretation of these languages. Since according to the criterion of
ontological commitments in a nominalistic language only individual variables may have a designative function, he must try
to reinterpret all predicates as syncategorematic terms, i.e., as expressions
that have no independent meaning, and to reduce all proper names and definite
descriptions to propositional forms with quantified individual variables.
We must here disclaim a deeper analysis of the absurd consequences of
this reductionism and shall mention but two features of this project, the
failure of which had to be admitted by Goodman and Quine themselves. We think that Nominalism fails to discern sufficiently sharply semantical and ontological decisions. From the
reinterpretation of the language, no conclusions can be drawn in regard to an
attempted philosophical foundation of a science. An elimination of certain
linguistic expressions does not eliminate the denoted or designated entities.
Secondly, the argument of nominalists to the effect that, a philosophical
problem can be solved on the level of language by semantic means, has most
undesirable consequences. If we accept the dichotomy between nominalistic and Platonistic languages, it
follows that, because the nominalistic reinterpretation of Platonistic language failed (every scientific language with the languages of logic or
mathematics as its framework must be a Platonistic language), every scientist is consciously or unconsciously bound to be a
Platonist. We take for granted, however, that whether somebody declares himself
a Platonist or nominalist, depends on personal philosophical beliefs, and not
on the language he uses. From a language (its syntax and semantics) one
cannot draw convincing conclusions about ontological questions. Ontological
decisions, whether explicitly or implicitly formulated, are prior to semantical decisions and are a necessary part of the
philosophical foundations of any science.
The result of this criticism is that we refuse to accept the dichotomy
“Nominalism-Platonism”, considering that it leads to the conclusion that we
must accept the Platonic solution. For an empiricist or materialist, Platonism
as a philosophical conception, whether in its extreme or moderate form, is
unacceptable.
It seems to us possible to find an appropriate philosophical foundation
for logic that overcomes the horns of the dilemma, “Nominalism-Platonism”, and
equally avoids redundant philosophical presuppositions which could stir up
emotional feelings unacceptable for scientists with different philosophical
beliefs. The suggested conception will admit only minimal philosophical
assumptions.
The philosophical foundations of logic will be found in a substantiated
classification of semantical (and hence of
syntactical) categories of the language of the formal sciences, based on a
categorization of corresponding entities. This categorization will be called
quasi-ontology or prelogic,
in order to show its similarity and dissimilarity to traditional ontology. We
develop this quasi-ontology on two levels. The quasi-ontology of the first
level can be summarized by diagram 1:
ENTITIES
FACTS OBJECTS
Processes-Things-Properties-Connections
The quasi-ontology of the first level is based on the priority of
reality, as well as on the assumption of the relative independence of the first
member of the object-subject relation in the theory of knowledge. It assumes as
real, i.e., existing in time and space, the following entities: facts,
processes, things, properties and connections. Being interested only in the
categorization of entities, we do not pay attention to the problem of an actual
distinction of them. For our purpose it is thus irrelevant to ask, e.g. “What
makes a thing a thing?”
Our categorization of objects is in fact broader than is needed in
contemporary logic. since it is possible to admit not only things but also
processes, we can speak of two different quasi-ontologies of the first level--a
discrete and continuous one. Contemporary logic is based on a discrete
quasi-ontology. The question whether it would be possible to develop, on the
basis of a continuous quasi-ontology, another form of logic, e.g., a logic of
processes, of actions, is quite reasonable; and one can find at present several
serious attempts in this direction,
The quasi-ontology of the second level can be characterized by diagram
2:
ENTITIES
VALUES OBJECTS
Truth Values-Confirmation Values Individuals-Classes-relations
Whereas the entities of the quasi-ontology of the first level are
objectively given, those of the quasi-ontology of the second level are
postulated. These entities are idealized results of human activities. From a
comparison of these two diagrams the following correspondences are manifest:
Facts-values, things-individuals, properties-classes, connections-relations.
From these two quasi-ontologies it follows that the hierarchy of
entities of the theory of types (which is basically unlimited) is admitted only
for the quasi-ontology of the second level. The logic dealing with idealized
entities is immediately related to the entities of the quasi-ontology of the
second level. But as these entities (being ideal constructions) are not
constructed independently of entities of the quasi-ontology of the first level,
logic stands in a mediated relationship to reality. Our quasi-ontologies are at
the same time an expression of methodological materialistic dualism by assuming
two worlds--the real world and the world of ideas.
From both categorizations, which show clearly the dependence of the
quasi-ontology of the second level on the quasi-ontology of the first level,
there follows as well our stand on the controversy between Platonism and
Nominalism. The acceptance of the quasi-ontology of the first level implies
immediately a rejection of Nominalism by accepting not only a “world of
individuals” in the sense of N. Goodman, but also a world with properties and
connections. Platonism is stronger. We cannot reject it on the basis of our
quasi-ontologies. This becomes possible only if we develop a modified
conception of semantics based on our quasi-ontologies, and examine the problem
of existence in logic.
Logical semantics in modern logic was founded by G. Frege’s conception, characterized by his well-known distinction of Sinn and Bedeutung. G. Frege has developed what might be called a two-dimensional
semantics: a name expresses (druckt aus) its
sense (Sinn) and denotes or means (bezeichnet, bedeutet)
its meaning (Bedeutung). In this two-dimensional semantics, as I
shall argue, two basically different semantical functions
are identified, namely the function of bezeichnen and bedeuten.
In respect to the special function of classical (two-valued extensional) logic,
this identification seems quite appropriate. For our purposes, especially if we
are interested in the problem of the relation of logic to reality and try to
avoid a Platonic solution (explicitly involved in Frege’s conception), a revision of this two-dimensional semantics is necessary. We
shall propose a three-dimensional semantics, which presupposes the quasiontologies of both levels.
This three-dimensional semantics which accepts as primary semantical categories the categories of “name” and
“proposition”, can be in either case characterized by diagram 3:
Designries Designation
Signification Signifies SEMANTICAL CATEGORY
Denotes denotation
with three semantical functions: the
signification-, designation-, and denotation-function. The aim of this revision
lies in the differentiation of the designation and denotation-function in
respect to our quasi-ontologies: the designation-function is related to the
quasi-ontology of the first level, and the denotation-function to the
quasi-ontology of the second level. This becomes manifest from a concretization
of the above-mentioned diagram:
Designates Fact
Judgment SIGNIFIES Proposition
Denotes Truth-Value
Designates Property Connection
Concept SIGNIFIES Name
Denotes Individual
Relation
This refined distinction makes clear the real process of abstraction,
combined with idealizations and constructions, a systematic classification of
variables in respect to corresponding ranges of values. The range of values of
variables is primarily determined by the designations and secondarily by the
denotations. It would be advisable to change the usual terminology and speak
either of variables in regard to the designations or denotations, but this
would be too pedantic. What is more important is an elucidation of the abstract
step from fact to truth-values, without accepting the Platonistic interpretation of truth-values as
abstract entities. It also becomes evident that logic cannot work with
fact-variables and is therefore compelled to substitute denotations, i.e.,
values, for the designations or propositions.
It is true that in the case of names this substitution is not necessary,
but this does not in principle weaken the conception that logic is only mediately connected with the quasi-ontology of the first
level.
The third step in the proposed philosophical foundation of logic (the
problem of existence) deserves a somewhat broader introduction. It may,
however, suffice to point out some fundamental remarks. This controversial
problem, philosophically influenced by the refutation of the traditional
existence-proofs of God, has been studied, first of all in respect to its
formal expression, as reflected by the introduction of the existential
quantifier, and by the interpretation of propositions involving existence in
such a manner that the very structure of these propositions clearly shows that
existence is not a predicate. This can also be found in natural languages,
especially in English, when we compare, e.g., the following pair of expressions
“There are negative numbers” and “Negative numbers are”. The interest of
logicians and philosophers has further concentrated on questions involving
different kinds of existence, and on the explanation of the concept of
existence in connection with a distinction between what exists and does not
exist, and how something exists or does not. These subject-matters became urgent
especially in mathematics, where the available means of exhibiting the entities
which are asserted as existent are evidently different from other sciences,
e.g., in zoology.
These questions were systematically analyzed for the first time by G. Frege and B. Russell, who being the chief advocates of Logicism, identified mathematical and logical existence.
Because their logical systems were constructed with the intention to serve only
the needs of mathematics, the concept of logical existence became a paradigm
for all other kinds. In another regard this solution was strengthened by the
Formalism of D. Hilbert, who explicitly and with consistency identified logical
and mathematical existence. Against this simplification of mathematical
existence was directed the criticism of the intuitionists, who refused to
accept the admissibility of the existential import of propositions referring to
infinite domains. The intuitionists suggest another interpretation based on the
identification of mathematical existence with construction or constructibility. The
controversy whether to accept the identification of mathematical existence with
consistency or constructibility has not yet been decided in favor of the one or the other opposing conception.
The claims of logicists and formalists cannot be considered as adequate, because they imply an
identification of two domains--namely logic and mathematics--which are
methodologically very near, but substantially different, Neither can the claims
of intuitionists be accepted, considering that (in so far as classical
mathematics is concerned) they imply the existence only of entities of finite
domains. The requirement of actual constructions, which is the core of their intention,
cannot be realized for the objects of infinite domains. If we agree that
mathematical entities are entities gained by idealization, construction, and
abstraction; we must nevertheless differentiate whether we are concerned with
entities of finite or infinite domains. For finite domains an actual exhibition
is possible, but for infinite domains it is not possible.
For the present purpose the special aspects of mathematical existence
are less important, and it may suffice to say that for the existence of
different mathematical entities we would like to propose different
explications; actual constructions, i.e., constructions in a stronger sense, or
finite entities a construction in a weaker sense, including the axiomatic
method and the theory of models of infinite entities. This liberal attitude
expresses our conviction that, for the entities of a certain science, we cannot
formulate but one criterion of existence.
What seems to be more important is, first of all, a clear
differentiation between logical existence (L-existence) on one hand and
different kinds of factual existence (F-existence) on the other, or between
logical, ideal and factual existence. L-existence can be in fact identified
with consistency. For logic all entities exist which are subjected to the principium contradictionis. In this sense logic, or more
explicitly classical elementary logic, can be applied in all “possible worlds”
(in the sense of Leibniz), or, as we would say nowadays, in all the domains of
individuals. These domains are in principle non-empty, because the assumption
of logical existence rules out all internally inconsistent entities. From the
standpoint of existence only the impossible world is empty, and cannot
therefore contain any entities.
Besides L-existence we can distinguish different kinds of F-existence
(in a broad sense), if we want to underline the difference between consistency
and special criteria of existence in all other cases than in the case of
L-existence. However, another refined classification of non-logical or
F-existence is also possible. First of all, we can speak of F-existence (in a
narrow sense) and ideal existence, including (as the most distinguished case) mathematical
existence. secondly, we can further subclassify in
accordance with different strata of reality.
From this standpoint we cannot consider as convincing the famous
argument about the non-existence of Pegasus, centaurs, and so on. When we speak
of the alleged non-existence, then we have in mind entities of domains
described by zoology, or entities having some kind of F-existence. If we have
in mind another context, namely the framework of Greek mythology, i.e., some
kind of ideal existence, we cannot deny that they are non-existent. Without
reference to a definite domain of entities, there is no point in speaking about
existence or non-existence. This relativization does
not only hold in such extreme, often artificially selected, cases, but also in
regard to entities which are commonly accepted as existent. To speak about the
existence of a neutron in the system of classical physics is to speak about a
non-existent entity. This attempted classification of existence,
methodologically related to a conception or relative existence, stands in clear
opposition to all concepts of existence absolutely conceived by metaphysicians.
In practice the relativization of existence
is connected with different criteria for establishing whether something exists
or does not. As is already known, for L-existence we have assumed consistency,
for physical existence one can adopt subsistence in time and space. For these
reasons all disputes about whether something exists or not are simply idle,
when a corresponding framework is undetermined.
As presumably already recognized, this standpoint is partially
influenced by Carnap’s distinction of internal and external existential questions and statements. We
are similarly interested only in the existence of entities relative to a fixed
domain. This holds also in the case of our quasi-ontologies. When the existence
of facts and/or of truth values, of things, of-individuals, etc., is assumed,
only their relative existence in respect to these quasiontologies as forming their framework is
meant as well in regard to other entities of each of them. We do not postulate
that there exist, e.g., things as such, but only assume that there are things,
without being concerned with their special nature. It is, of course, quite
clear that in reality there are only specific things, not things in general.
The relativization of entities is determined also by
their mutual relations: the existence of one entity influences the existence or
non-existence of another. We cannot speak of an existing thing without assuming
that it has certain properties and is devoid of others. The acceptance of the
suggested stratification of reality, reflected in the quasi-ontology of the
first level, being at the same time the basis of a further stratification
related to those of the quasi-ontology of the second level, has no intended
metaphysical implications.
We neither make the attempt to reduce the proposed entities nor do we
try to explain, e.g., what makes a thing a thing.
What conclusions can be drawn from the above-mentioned analysis of
existence for the criticism of Nominalism and Platonism in logic? The existence
of the entities of the quasi-ontology of the first level must be evidently
understood as factual (in a broad sense), relativized in respect to different subclassifications. The conception of the quasi-ontology
of the first level is, of course, an idealization, needed for our philosophical
grounding of logic. The existence of the entities of the quasi-ontology of the
second level can be characterized as ideal existence. Truth-values,
individuals, classes, and so on, are idealized entities and their existence is
clearly distinct from the entities of the quasi-ontology of the first level.
The question whether there are, e.g., classes or not, if formulated in
this way, is inexact, and cannot therefore be unambiguously answered. We can
only ask whether they are or are not factual or ideal. In the former case our
answer will be negative, in the later case positive. Because ideal existence is without any doubt different from the
factual, we cannot assign to the entities of the quasi-ontology of the second
level temporal and spatial coordinates. The often raised question “And how do
ideal entities exist?”, with the implicit allusion to the answer, “They exist in
our minds” is only an expression of an anthropomorphic analogy with the
existence of physical entities in time and space. To interpret entities with
ideal existence as independent objects sui
generis is tantamount to misinterpreting their genesis, which is
historically and systematically based on the entities of the quasi-ontology of
the first level. To consider them in the traditional sense of Platonism as
entities in a realm of Ideas is doubtless an unfounded metaphysical
supposition. This extreme standpoint finds, of course, its support in
Nominalism by its one-sided (in principle empiricistic) conception, admitting only one kind
of existence, i.e., factual or physical existence. The unacceptable
consequences of both conceptions--that of Platonism and that of Nominalism--can
in our opinion be avoided by our differentiation and relativization of existence in respect to different frameworks.
By this exposition of the nature of existence in the framework of our
proposed materialistic foundation of logic, we are concluding this paper,
without pretending to :lave exhausted this controversial subject-matter.
CZECHOSLOVAK ACADEMY OF SCIENCES
THE INSTITUTE FOR THEORY AND METHODOLOGY OF SCIENCE
|