CRISTO RAUL.ORG ' |
READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
CONTEMPORARY EAST EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHY
1.György Markus
Marx’s
Earliest Epistemology
In his first work, the doctoral dissertation
on the difference between the natural philosophy of Democritus and that of
Epicurus, the influence of Hegel on the epistemological viewpoint of Marx is
still strongly perceptible. The sole instrument to Marx for the correct
cognition of reality is philosophy, which is “genuine knowledge”, in contrast
not only to sensation and ordinary consciousness but also to the empirical and
experimental sciences of nature. These latter presuppose something
transcendental to be distinguished from human consciousness, and their purpose
is merely to drive the manifold of sensuous truth from simple and general
hypotheses. For these reasons, science does not maintain a consistent
opposition to religion, which in its most complete form, in Christianity, is
nothing else than the “completed philosophy of transcendence”. On the other
hand, the method of natural science, resting upon real possibilities, the
method of logical formulation, has a one-sided character shaped by the
understanding. While this method establishes for each individual phenomenon the
cycle of causes, conditions, etc., which underlie its existence, it mutilates
the universal and singular life of nature. In contrast, philosophy is the
negation of all transcendence. Its object is Mind, i.e., self-consciousness.
For just this reason, philosophy no longer presupposes that the categories are
the specifications of some reality, some object outside thought; it considers
these categories in their entirety, in their transition and movement, as an
independent substance and as its proper objects “Ordinary thinking always has
abstract categories ready which separate it from existence. All philosophers
have made the categories themselves into existing things”.
Mind (self-consciousness) which reveals
itself to be the genuine object of philosophy is not the empirical, individual
self-consciousness, which is unable to penetrate nature as a whole, which can
only abstract from it, and which denies it any independently existing objective
reality. This Mind is the concrete universal, the self-forming and developing
historical self-consciousness of mankind, which while disclosing itself in
nature does not distort nature, because according to its essence it represents
nothing but the final product and emergence into consciousness of the forces
that are active in nature, and these forces are of a mental character. Thus
philosophical knowledge is at the same time knowledge of nature taken as an
object. “When we recognize nature to be rational, its independence ceases. It
no longer alarms our consciousness, and indeed Epicurus makes the form of
consciousness in its immediacy, in its conscious realization, the for-itself in
the form of nature. Only when nature is entirely detached from conscious reason,
as reason is observed in nature itself, is nature entirely the possession of
reason. Any relation to nature as such is at the same time an alienation of
reason”.
The role of philosophy, however, is not
exhausted in its passive task of bringing things to consciousness. If the
object of philosophy is self-consciousness, philosophy can say no more about it
than what it is; self-consciousness can in theory (post festum) appear only as it has been
realized at a given historical stage in real life, in the morality, customs,
law, the state, etc., of the people. The philosophic system’s “relation to the
world is a relation of reflection”. In this manner Marx in his short sketches
on the history of Greek philosophy takes pains to reveal the connection between
Greek social and political life and philosophy. The development of
the philosophy of any era, therefore, means the effort to grasp the Zeitgeist in its totality, with the
final purpose of realizing “World-Philosophy”, which embraces all problems of the time and unites “abstract principles into a unified whole”. Thus the active, creative role of philosophy can be
explained. In “World Philosophy” the Zeitgeist has found itself, its complete and free expression as theoretical reason would then be realized per
se, it stands in contrast to the world itself
in which the same self-consciousness
is incorporated and transformed into substance. Being cannot realize itself without
contradiction, but only in alienated
form. The phenomenon, the immediate existence, contradicts the essence, the interior,
rational contents. For philosophy,
therefore, the world appears as false, and thus it becomes itself practical energy which turns itself
against this same false world. To the
degree, however, to which this practical philosophy, philosophical criticism, realizes
itself, the fact must become clear to it
that the limits and contradictions which it thinks it finds in opposing reality are the
limits and contradictions of its own intellectual content. As it realizes its principles in this fashion, it frees itself as well
as the world from these principles,
and prepares a new era for the development of self-consciousness. Only then is philosophy in
general and life according to “World Philosophy”
possible„
In this interaction and unity of the
passively reflecting and the actively forming, of the theoretical and the
practical, of the absolute and the historically relative, the theoretical
moment is decisive, not only because it appears in every practical activity,
but also in consequence of the application of the Hegelian teleology of the
concept, which is profoundly radicalized in its social content. The immanent goal
of historical development is the complete transformation of substance into the
subject, the exchange of all the supposedly naturally emerging specifications
and limits of the individual with conscious self-determination. The perspective
of this goal makes possible the elimination of all historically and nationally
limited knowledge and offers opportunities for judging at the level of the
“realm of reason”.
The liquidation of this conception and its
radical, materialistic elimination do not proceed upon the level of abstract
philosophical speculation, but are the product of the pitiless analysis by Marx
of practical-political experiences. (Of course, certain theoretical influences,
especially the significance of Feuerbach’s influence, are certainly not to be
underestimated.) During his Rheinische Zeitung days, Marx’s political illusions were
shattered. The young Marx had presupposed that only in the state do the
material components become living members of the spiritual whole, and that only
in the state is the social totality constituted, participation in the life of
the social totality making the human being human. In terms of the problems of
economic life, only certain restrictions on private property through political
channels interested him. (With such measures he thought he could avoid rigid
social classes.) For this reason the essence of his social programme consisted in radical, Jacobin-revolutionary
transformation and democratizing the state.
But
during his journalistic activity, during his immediate contact with social
reality, the much more intricate interdependence of politics and economics, the
domination of economic phenomena over political ones became clear to him. At
this time he grasped the problem of the “poor classes”, which “in the conscious
structuring of the state had so far found no suitably important position”.
When, therefore, in the Spring of 1844 he fell into a politico-philosophical
crisis, he returned with his characteristic self-criticisms to the
investigation of his premises, to a critical analysis of the Hegelian
philosophy and especially of its theory of the state in his manuscript, Toward a Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy
of Right. In the light of his newly acquired
revolutionary conviction, which, although still in a generalized form, demanded
besides political reconstruction also the transformation of bourgeois society,
as well as the destruction of the alienated private character of its spheres as
the precondition of any democratic reform. Marx now criticized the Hegelian
conception of society, and further, Hegelian idealism and its dialectic in
general. All this was made possible by the view that, as the producer of
historical progress, there emerges for man no longer just intellectual-critical
activity directed towards political life but revolutionary practice
transforming the material conditions of life.
Accordingly, his attitude towards speculative-philosophical
knowledge is also revised. In his dissertation Marx viewed this knowledge,
precisely because of its critical character, as “genuine cognition”. Insofar as
philosophy transforms the specifications ascribed by ordinary thought to
external objects, the categories into independently existing things, and
regards these according to their essential place and role in the evolution of
self-consciousness, i.e. grasps their “concept”, philosophy offers a critical
yardstick by which it is henceforth objectively possible to measure individual
things as appearances of these specifications of self-consciousness; philosophy
makes it possible critically to contrast essential being freed from accidentals
from objects as merely sensuous. The evaluation of this method now passes into
its opposite; Marx rejects it in his manuscript of Kreuznach, precisely because of its argumentative
character. Since speculative thought separates categories from their proper
bearers and subjects, and considers them in themselves; it can give them a
meaning only by presupposing a definite relation among them in which each is
determined by the others. There thus emerges a fully formed, closed, a priori system of abstract ideas. Their
separation from reality, however, which Marx was earlier inclined to explain as
the necessary separation of Critical Philosophy from its object (though not in
so sharp a form), makes any actual criticism impossible. Such thinking locked
up in itself, if it now in default of inner content turns to reality and poses
as true knowledge, lacks any criterion for distinguishing, in the immediately
given, the real and the necessary from the accidental. The only criterion and
only requirement is that the object can be resolved into some abstract concept.
In this way emerges the “uncritical positivism” and the “pseudo-criticism” of
thought. For ordinary thinking philosophic thought can appear to be critical,
because it conceives the object as the incorporation of an abstract quality,
and accordingly its concept as formed from the object can diverge sharply from
the concept in everyday use. In its essence, however, this method is
apologetic, because it conceives the object which is supposed
to be the realization of self-consciousness, of Mind, etc., just as it appears
in everyday experience, and then accepts and thereby authorizes it. Further,
such knowledge is formal and unable to disclose the proper nature of the
object, and therefore is not knowledge at all,
The only kind of knowledge that can become
truly critical is that which follows the specific logic of its object and
reveals the real inner contradictions of things. This conception of scientific
knowledge is still quite widespread. The method of idealist dialectics is by no
means completely overcome. Our concern is not merely with the fact that we can
find formulations in Marx that reflect it, but also that Marx still later in
the Manuscripts quite frequently represents the result of an historical process
(that emerges from a long series of intermediate steps) as the immanent goal of
the process, as its essence, in order to obtain a critical measure of the
concrete historical phenomena of the process which contradict this essence and
are alienated from it. The positive solution to this question, the elaboration
of a scientific methodology, becomes the central quest of the later
philosophical interest of Marx.
The conception we have been dealing with
reflects in great measure the influence of Feuerbach. The two thinkers’
conceptions, however, diverge even at this time, and especially on this theme. According to Feuerbach the instrument for the knowledge of reality is
careful, truly human sense perception, while Marx proceeds from
rational-logical, discursive knowledge, seeing it as capable of disclosing the
“logic of the thing”. The differences between Marx and Feuerbach are sharply
evident, e.g., in the differing evaluations of the Hegelian notion of the “path
from the abstract to the concrete”, that methodological requirement according
to which scientific knowledge must move from the abstract to the concrete.
Feuerbach sees in it nothing but the indirect, inconsistent theological
recognition of the reality of the world perceived by the senses; he rejects it
for the reason that knowledge must grasp the given in its
immediacy, revealing every specification in its concrete constitution. Thought, then, cannot reach
genuine independence, it has its
justification only as a moment which enriches and trains sense perception, not in
isolation from this. Categories in themselves
are merely instruments of cognition. Marx, on the other hand, criticizes Hegel
for the reason that Hegel does not realize the methodological principle he formulated, viz, he offers only the illusion of its realization.
While the process of thought in Hegel
apparently leads from the one-sided to the totality, exactly the opposite is the case. Hegel
identifies the concrete phenomenon with
its individual specification; he does not reconstitute the concrete as the complicated
totality of abstract specifications,
but attains merely the elaboration of the abstract specification. This is often
unnecessary because it is given as a finished social product anterior to all scientific thought, Marx states, “in reality Hegel did nothing
except dissolve the
‘political’” constitution into the universal abstract idea of ‘organism’, but in appearance and according
to his own view he evolved the
specific out of the universal idea”.
Just as Marx did later, Feuerbach departed
from the Hegelian philosophy for which it is society primarily that stands
contrasted to the individual, and not the contrary. He attempted, moreover, to
give a materialist interpretation of social substance, which Hegel had seen in essence within the morality, customs, religion, laws, and, above all, in the political character of
any era and people. Feuerbach
believed he could find this foundation in the material dependence human beings exhibit, so that the individual is unable to live alone apart from other men.
Feuerbach did not submit this material
dependence to any concrete, historical investigation. Thus social specifications appear
for him as specifications of nature
produced by training.
Feuerbach recognizes that thought is the
highest expression and incorporation of his humanity. In thought the individual
man appears as the one who incorporates the human species, and, therefore,
Feuerbach has reservations about thought. In thought the species appears as
species, as free of any natural dependence and precondition. Accordingly, the
individual who thinks is per se completely free and independent of any natural or social relationship. As a
result, when it is separated from the totality of the life of the species, the
highest product of the development of the species can become the negation of
the reality of the human being, of his social and natural dependence. For this
reason, Feuerbach saw in abstract thinking the subjective condition of all
alienation. Sensuous intuition, on the contrary, raises itself above
individual, egoistic need, conceiving the object as the beautiful, as the
specific manifestation of the essence of Nature and man, as the affirmation of
the essence of man. In this it remains passive and dependent upon its object:
this is the only correct form and the only means of human knowledge.
To Marx the foundations of Feuerbach’s
conception were alien and remained so. In his dissertation and in articles in
the Rheinische Zeitung he
completely shares Hegel’s views on the primacy and also on the character of
social substance. He then seeks to offer a materialist explanation for the
social totality, for which economic phenomena, which were left untouched in
Feuerbach’s naturalistic conception of society, serve as the point of departure.
In Marx’s Critique
of the Hegelian Philosophy of Right, we by no means encounter a
straightforward solution. On the one hand, Marx takes a definite position
against the mystification of the Hegelian philosophy which separated society
from distinct individuals, positing it as an independently existing thing,
permitting it to function as the hidden creator of history. Only individuals,
conceived in their immediate material reality, are the real creators of
history. However, the materialist explanation of history’s obedience to law,
affirmed by Hegel, and of the universal social relations and processes which
come about “behind the back” of human activities are by no means excluded.
Unlike Hegel, however, this materialist explanation cannot consist only in the
reduction of the phenomena of the state and political life to civil society,
especially when no answer is available to the question of how the alteration of
its economic determinants can be explained. At this time, this later question
had not been submitted to any investigation by Marx. This is why the above work
as well as the slightly later writing, On
the Jewish Question, contain many idealist formulations alongside
materialist ones for answering such concrete questions as the relationship of
the state and civil society, the evolution of the state and its consequences,
etc. At the same time, individual problems are dealt with by appealing to the
evolution of the “human spirit” (Geist) and self-consciousness.
Such
idealist formulations can be seen in On the Jewish Question; “But the religious spirit cannot be really secularized. For what is it but the non-secular form of a stage in the development of the human spirit? The religious spirit can only be
realized if the stage of development of
the human spirit which it expresses in religious form, manifests and constitutes itself in
its secular form. This is what happens in the democratic state”. Karl Marx; Early
Writings.
In this period, Marx also contrasts
scientific-theoretical knowledge sharply with material a activity. Practical need appears as a merely biological, egoistic interest for
which the inner essence, the specific nature of the object, is completely
indifferent : an interest which measures the object externally according to its
own standard, or considers it by means of “rules of some kind of convention”,
while theory conceives it as proceeding “in and for itself”. Practical need is
passive, its development can be stimulated only through change in exterior
conditions, and thus it cannot serve as a foundation and explanation of
theoretical notions that constantly develop.
The young Marx arrived at a consistent materialist view of the world, social theory, and epistemology, only by completely renouncing this estimate of practical activity. His philosophic materialism is completed only with the disclosure of the role of labor in shaping man and history. This shift begins in the summer of 1844 in Marx’s Paris Manuscripts. |