CHAPTER
XI.
THE
ATHENIAN PHILOSOPHICAL SCHOOLS
I.
THE
PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES
IN the
imaginary conversation of the Phaedo, Plato makes Socrates tell how he
had lost all interest in the physical science of his time. The ‘nature of
things’ had been sought, as it were, by taking the world to pieces and
imagining it formed either by differentiation out of some primitive stuff or by
the combination of several unchanging elements—a mechanical process, innocent
of design. Anaxagoras, indeed, had spoken of Mind giving the first impulse of
motion; but, to Socrates’ disappointment, this Mind was not employed to plan
the universe, in all its parts, ‘for the best’. It was as if the reason why
Socrates was then in prison should be found, not in his resolve to abide the
sentence of the law, but in the movement of the limbs that brought him thither.
Socrates did not himself attempt what Anaxagoras had left undone. He turned
from the world of things to seek wisdom in the world of discourse.
The result of
this re-orientation of philosophy was that the two great systems of the fourth
century, the Platonic and the Aristotelian, looked for the nature of things no
longer in a simpler material out of which they develop, but in some final
perfection of form towards which they aspire by a natural or divine impulse,
comparable to the conscious purposes of man. The mechanical interpretation of
Nature yields to the teleological. Socrates himself, as Aristotle says
(Metaphysics I, 6), had no system of Nature; but the revolution which set the
concept of design above mechanical and material causes followed naturally upon
his preoccupation with the intelligent guidance of man’s life towards his
proper good.
The external
facts of Socrates’ life have already been described. For our knowledge of his
philosophy we depend upon three witnesses: Xenophon, Plato, Aristotle; for
Socrates himself left no writings, and we learn nothing of his characteristic
doctrine from the Clouds of Aristophanes (first performed, 423 BC). The
Socrates of this comedy is a composite picture of at least three incompatible
types: the head of a resident school of atheistical Ionian science; the wandering Sophist, lecturing on rhetoric, grammar, and
other subjects to young men rich enough to pay his fees; and a ragged ascetic,
neglecting his worldly interests to teach morals. The third figure only has
something in common with the Socrates of Plato’s Apology and the ideal
philosopher of the Cynic School. The Sophist may be dismissed entirely. Our
other evidence, above all the Apology, denies that Socrates ever taught
physical science, though he may well have sought wisdom in that quarter and
failed to find it. Aristophanes recognized in Socrates and Euripides the two
most subversive exponents of the modern spirit, and he heaped upon them every
trait that he condemned, never dreaming that posterity would mistake his masks
for historical portraits.
The bulk of
Xenophon’s Memorabilia is not, even in intention, historical; it
belongs, with his Qeconomicus and Symposium,
to a type of apologetic literature known as ‘Socratic discourses.’ There were
many such works. The writers were to some extent in competition, each
correcting the others’ views of Socrates, who is a problematic figure to us
because he was so even to his followers. Aristotle classes these writings with
the prose mime as a form of fiction. They were imaginary conversations,
designed to show what the dead master was like; and, while preserving a general
fidelity to his character, the writers felt free to indulge in anachronism and
to express their own opinions through his mouth. All Plato’s dialogues are
subject to this convention. Aristotle must have known this literature, besides
what he learnt from Plato in an intercourse of twenty years. His evidence
provides the only means of fixing the point where Plato goes beyond his master;
for Xenophon’s work is not independent of Plato’s, and of the other Socratic
discourses only a few fragments survive.
No document
takes us nearer to the real Socrates than Plato’s Apology, which is not
an imaginary conversation in fictitious circumstances. Its aim is to give a
true account of Socrates’ work. That the account is not only true, but
substantially complete, may be inferred from the ‘high tone’ which Xenophon
found in all reports of Socrates’ speech. Plainly Socrates had not tried to
make an effective defence: he would not slur over anything in his past that
would tell against him. The misrepresentation of his character and work by the
comic poets is repudiated in terms that would have been futile, as well as
disingenuous, if the picture in the Clouds had been even a caricature of the
real man. He goes on to give his own account of his mission to Athenian society.
The Delphic
oracle had declared that no one was wiser than Socrates. Unconscious of any
wisdom, Socrates set out to refute the oracle by testing the recognized leaders
of thought and action. The statesmen he found to be unaware that they knew
nothing worth knowing. The poets, popularly esteemed as authorities on religion
and morals, could give no rational account of their poems; they wrote, it
seemed, ‘by some inspiration of genius.’ But among the craftsmen, (if only the
cobbler would stick to his last and not fancy he could govern Athens), Socrates
found what he called knowledge. We can infer what Socrates meant—or at least
what Plato, at this stage, thought he meant—by the wisdom which he always said
he did not possess and could not impart. The craftsman knows what he is trying
to do, and why, and how to do it. He can give an explicit account of his
knowledge; all his actions are intelligibly related to his purpose. Socrates’
ideal was to reduce conduct to an art of this type; hence he seldom discussed a
moral question without referring to the mason or the carpenter. Statesmen and
poets had no such knowledge of the true aim of public and private life; they
did not even feel the want of it.
For himself,
Socrates asserts that he has nothing to teach. Attempts have been made to
provide him with a Begriffsphilosophie. They
were based upon statements in Xenophon, now seen to be derived from Plato’s
dialogues, and upon a passage (Metaphysics, 1, 6) where Aristotle,
describing Socrates’ influence on Plato, observes that he tried to define moral
terms. Socrates’ essays in this kind had a practical motive. Clear notions, he
thought, are needed for right action; no one can be consciously and consistently
good unless he knows what goodness is. Aristotle gives no ground for ascribing
to Socrates a speculative interest in concepts or universals, or any theory of
their metaphysical status. In the Apology Socrates describes the
positive side of his mission thus: ‘I have no other business but to go about
persuading you all, both young and old, to care less for your bodies and your
wealth than for the perfection of your souls, and telling you that goodness
does not come from wealth, but it is goodness that makes wealth or anything
else, in public or in private life, a good thing for men. If, by saying that, I
am perverting the young, so much the worse; but if anyone asserts that I say
anything else, it is not true.’ The only positive doctrine professed by Socrates
is that, of all the aims men pursue in life, only one has any value, namely,
‘to make one’s soul as good as possible.’ This had never before been said in
Athens; it was a paradox, hard to understand. What is it, to be good? The
question could not be answered in the Apology, but our witnesses agree
in formulating certain principles which, at first sight, seem to be either
platitudes or obviously false. These Socratic propositions are: (1) Goodness
(virtue) is knowledge; (2) Goodness cannot be taught; (3) No one does wrong
willingly; (4) Happiness is the result of goodness.
(1) The
word arete (goodness) lacks some of the associations of ‘virtue.’ Linked
with the notions of function and performance, it denotes the excellence of
whatever is good for any work or end; in the plural it can mean ‘achievements.’
The ‘goodness’ taught by the Sophists was ability to manage affairs and to
attain the aims of personal ambition. The Socratics do not depart from this
usage; they differ only in their view of man’s function, which determines the
content of his ‘goodness.’ The soul’s function, says Socrates in Plato’s Republic,
is ‘to take thought and to govern’; more generally, it is ‘living’; man’s
goodness is that which enables him to live well, and so to ‘do well’ in another
sense—to be happy. The first Socratic proposition defines this goodness, on
which right living and happiness depend, as knowledge. This hard saying means,
as the Apology indicates, that there is, or should be, an art of living,
whereby all our actions would be consciously directed to an aim clearly
conceived—the good in which our function consists, the true end of life. If we
are to be good, this end must be known.
(2) How
is such knowledge gained ? It cannot, in the common sense, be taught. If the
end of life were health or riches or social success, we could learn the means
from the physician, the business man, the Sophist. Or, if ‘living well’ meant
conforming to the rules of conduct approved by society, this again could be
learnt as matter of ascertainable fact. But current beliefs about right and
wrong cannot be knowledge: they are not consistent even within any one society;
and no belief accepted on mere authority can be knowledge. I shall not know
that what others call right and good is really so, unless I can see it for
myself; and if I can see it, what others think becomes irrelevant. My action
must be determined solely by my own conviction. The implied postulate is that
every human soul has the power to discern, by direct intuition, what really is
good. Once cleared of the mists of prejudice and false appearance, its judgment
is infallible and beyond appeal. Socrates, accordingly, had no system of morals
to teach. He spent his time inducing anyone who would undergo the test to
examine his own beliefs, until their confusion and inconsistency led him to the
conviction that he did not know the true end of life.
(3) Critics,
ancient and modern, have raised the obvious objection: I may know what is good
and yet fail to desire it; mere knowledge is not enough to determine the will.
Socrates replied: No one does wrong willingly (or wittingly). The wrong-doer is
misled; his sense of what is really good, and good for him, is obscured by a
false appearance. The rival pleasure seems good, and he follows it. It is not
true, then, that he knows, at the moment, what is good. If he knew this, in the
full sense of ‘knowing,’ he could not desire anything else. In a conflict of
motives the fault lies, not in desire, which is divided between the two
objects, but in the failure to discern the true object from the false. Once we
can do that, the whole current of desire must flow towards the true good. Celui
qui n agit pas comme il pense, pense imparjaitement (Guyau).
The Charmides of Plato contains a discussion of self-control, starting from the Delphic
precept, Know thyself. The upshot is that self-control, like every other
virtue, means the knowledge of good and evil; and we may infer that this is
tantamount to self-knowledge—the recognition of a true self, at the core of our
being, which claims control over all the rest of what we call our ‘selves,’ and
is, in the last resort, the ‘soul’ we must care for. Both Plato and Aristotle
accepted the belief in this inmost self, and held it to be the divine element
in man. Its peculiar form of desire, always directed to the true good it can
perceive, they called by a special name, ‘Wish’ (boulesis).
When we act wrongly, we do what we like, but not what we wish; the insight of
the true self is for the moment obscured.
(4) Finally,
happiness is the result of goodness. The sacrifice of pleasures that falsely
seem good is not a sacrifice of happiness. There is no real conflict between
duty and pleasure, because no pleasure is comparable to the satisfaction of the
soul which follows the inward recognition of good. To live well is the same as
to live happily. This doctrine could easily be misconstrued to mean that virtue
is to be chosen for its reward in terms of worldly goods. Xenophon constantly
ascribes this vulgar ‘utilitarianism’ to Socrates. It must be remembered that
Socrates was not usually engaged in setting forth the moral principles above
formulated,—we owe the formulation to Plato—but in drawing out and criticizing
other men’s notions about conduct. No doubt he generally talked to them on
their own level; he may often have recommended virtue as a means to health or
social esteem. This would suffice to mislead a Xenophon; but the Socrates of
Plato holds that worldly prosperity and honour are indifferent; what matters is
‘to care for one’s soul.’ The unresting pursuit of
moral goodness is happiness, though poverty, suffering, and death be the cost.
We do not will the good in order to be happy; we are happy in willing it.
This simple
and profound doctrine of the right way of life is the philosophy of Socrates.
Upon the question whether it had, in Socrates’ mind, a religious background or
sanction Xenophon cannot be trusted; we depend entirely on the Apology and the
earlier dialogues of Plato. One thing is clear: the moral doctrine is
self-contained, requiring no support from theological beliefs. If the
distinction between good and evil, right and wrong, is absolute, and can be
known directly by the inward eye of every soul, no supernatural sanction for
conduct is needed, though it might exist. In the Euthyphro Socrates
discusses religion with a self-satisfied formalist, and, in the course of a
subtle argument, makes him admit that right conduct cannot be defined as
conduct pleasing to the gods. Their approval is, in logical terms, an accident;
it does not make an action right. The action is approved because it is right,
absolutely and without condition. Hence a theology professing to interpret the
will of heaven as a guide to conduct is superfluous. Further, if happiness can
be attained only by knowing and choosing what is good, it is attainable in this
life, in proportion to our success in fulfilling the condition. No belief in
rewards or punishments after death could influence conduct. The good man is
happy now, the bad unhappy. If there is a future life, it will be the same
then; if there is not, goodness is not to be renounced as unremunerative. This
truth Socrates undertakes to prove in the Republic.
Whether, and
in what sense, the historic Socrates believed in gods or in immortality is a
doubtful question. Xenophon says that he sacrificed both publicly and in his
own house; but conformity implied no acceptance of dogma. He prayed, we are
told, though never for the satisfaction of particular wants. ‘His formula of
prayer was simple: Give me that which is best for me; for, he said, the gods
know best what things are good.’ The Platonic Apology speaks of ‘God’ or ‘the
gods’ in conventional terms, open to any interpretation. The attitude to
immortality is definitely agnostic. ‘To fear death is to think you are wise
when you are not; it is to think you know what you do not know. No man knows
whether death may not be the greatest good a man can have; yet men fear it, as
if they knew it to be the worst of evils.... Were I
to make any claim to be wiser than others, it would be because I do not think I
have any sufficient knowledge of the other world, when in fact I have none’.
Death may be either a .dreamless sleep or the migration of the soul to another
place. In either case it is certain that ‘no evil can happen to a good man, and
his concerns are not neglected by heaven’. If Socrates had professed any
definite belief in immortality, no motive could have induced Plato to convey a
false impression in the Apology. To Socrates this question, like every
other, was a question of knowledge; and an essential trait of his mind is the
clear sense where knowledge ends and ignorance, with its untested beliefs,
begins. That no evil can befall the good man is a rational conviction,
following from the definition of happiness. The only evil that can befall
anyone is the loss of moral goodness. The statement that the good man’s
concerns are ‘not neglected by heaven,’ expresses, in conventional terms, a
conviction that the world is so arranged that goodness does bring happiness. No
doubt Socrates believed this; but that ‘the gods’ had so arranged the world was
not even a generally accepted belief; and we are not warranted in ascribing to
Socrates either Plato’s theory of a designing Mind or Xenophon’s simple faith
in a busy Providence. The master might have thought that both his disciples
were in danger of thinking they knew what they did not know.
If conduct is
subject to no external authority, social or supernatural, what stands between
my will and the satisfaction of any desire whose end I can compass? Are not all
things lawful by natural right? Why not define ‘goodness’ as the effective
ability to do what I like? In the age of the Sophists and Socrates this
ultimate problem rose up to confront the discoverers of the inner world of
freedom. Science before Socrates had moved outwards into the physical world,
expecting, with innocent confidence, to surprise the secret of its birth and
nature, and unaware that it was discovering a pattern of its own contrivance.
This speculation seemed at first to have no bearing on conduct, which was
regulated by law, custom, and belief. But the unsettlement of tradition after
the Persian Wars turned some minds to explore the inner world, governed, as it
seemed, by other laws than those of the outer realm of necessity, or perhaps by
no laws at all. In sleep, said Heracleitus, every man
turns aside from the common world into a world of his own. When the speculative
mind turns inward, Nature will become appearance, the scenery of a
private dream: what more can be known of the alleged ‘nature of things,’ which
does not appear? Each mind, at the centre of its own dream, will claim freedom
and lordship of the inner realm. The restraints of religion and custom, imposed
by society, will be denounced as unnatural conventions. The individual will
identify his nature with the instincts, which disown artificial constraint.
Give him Gyges’ ring of invisibility, let him either elude or overpower the
watch-dogs of society, and he will do as he likes.
Protagoras,
who denied the Parmenidean world of unapparent Being and started this train of
thought, stopped far short of the conclusion (vol. v, p. 378). Plato was the
first to see all that was implied in what he called Sophistry, and to find an
explicit answer. Socrates’ answer was rather implicit in his life, a secret
that made him a riddle even to his own disciples. In his character seemingly
opposite tendencies were held in lightly balanced harmony. His rationalism
found the key to goodness in clear thinking, and claimed for the individual an
autonomy over-riding every recognized authority, divine or human. It was not
clear to his contemporaries why this assertor of individual freedom should not
be antinomian; why he should be indifferent to his own interests and pleasures;
why he should not repudiate, or try to subvert, social institutions. Yet he
challenged no conflict with received religion or with the demands of the State.
He conformed to the established cult, and his accusers could find no more
damaging charge than that he sometimes spoke of warnings received from a
‘divine sign.’ He did not, like the later Cynics, insult the decencies of
common life, or exalt a state of nature above the civilization of Athens.
Though he kept aloof from politics, he fulfilled the duties of a citizen, held
office, married, and brought up children. He was not a champion of natural
rights, but upheld positive law and accepted the duty of passive obedience. He
was content to find in Athenian society freedom enough to go about his chosen
business, avoiding any serious breach without the least compromise of
principle. Regarding pleasure, and even comfort, with complete indifference, he
had not that fear of pleasure which makes the ascetic. He could take pleasures
when they came; when they did not come, he never missed them. True, the
Socrates we know is the Socrates whom Plato and Xenophon knew, a man between
sixty and seventy. His self-mastery may have been won after a long struggle
with a passionate temperament; but, as we see it, the harmony is perfect. The
followers who founded the minor Socratic schools could not divine its secret;
Socrates had lived by a knowledge that he refused to call knowledge because he
could give no account of it. The Cynics mistook him for an ascetic, and fell
into anti-social extravagance. The Cyrenaics,
following another clue, sought peace of mind in a haven of agreeable
sensation1. Plato alone saw Socrates whole, and he set himself to give an
account of the knowledge his master had disclaimed, but must certainly have
possessed.
The inquiry
was to carry him further than he could then foresee. Aristoxenus,
the Peripatetic, had an anecdote of an Indian who met Socrates at Athens and
asked him about his philosophy. When Socrates said that he sought to understand
human life, the Indian replied that man cannot know himself without knowing
God. The story may show that the successors of Plato and Aristotle were aware
how far these two had travelled beyond their master’s explicit doctrine, when
they saw that the recognition of goodness demanded by Socrates could not be
separated from the recognition of Ultimate Being.
II.
PLATO:
THE EARLY DIALOGUES
Plato was
born (428—7 BC) of a family noble on both sides. In boyhood he must have
listened to the conversation of Socrates, and felt the effect described by
Alcibiades in the Symposium'. ‘No Corybant’s heart
ever throbbed like mine when I hear him; his words make the tears pour from my
eyes.’ As Plato grew to manhood, he came, deeply and irrevocably, under this
influence. The story goes that he burnt a tragedy which was to have been staged
at the Dionysia; Socrates had condemned the mere inspiration of the poet’s
genius, unable to give a rational account of its meaning. But Plato was not
only a student of philosophy. His mind was poignantly distracted by another
vocation, the life of active statesmanship, for which he was marked out by his
gifts and social position. He never ceased to acknowledge this claim upon
powers he could not contentedly suffer to fust in him unused.
After
Socrates’ death, Plato, with others of his closest friends, withdrew to join Eucleides at Megara, resolved to continue the master’s work
and defend his memory. The next twelve years Plato must have spent mainly at
Athens. He is said to have served in the Corinthian War of 395—86 BC; and
probably, at some time in this period, he visited Egypt and studied geometry
under Theodorus at Cyrene. Meanwhile he composed the Apology and the imaginary conversations which form the earliest group of his writings.
The order of the dialogues cannot be exactly determined. Plato may well have
written more than one at a time. The Republic must have taken several years;
others might have been composed in as many weeks. Happily, the methods of stylometry
have laid some check upon the caprice of subjective criticism. There is now a
general agreement to recognize three main groups, though the order within each
group is still disputed. To the early group we shall here assign the direct
defence of Socrates in the Apology and Crito; Laches, Lysis,
Charmides, Euthyphro, illustrating the true character of Socrates’ work;
the Shorter, and perhaps the Longer, Hippias, Protagoras,
Gorgias, in which the leading Sophists appear; and the Ion. Probably all
these were written, and the Republic begun, before Plato founded the
Academy. The Apology has already been mentioned. The Crito explains why Socrates, to the surprise of the public and possibly to the dismay
of his accusers, declined to escape from prison before his sentence was carried
out. The history of Plato’s thought begins in what are sometimes called the
Socratic dialogues.
The general
purpose of the Laches, Lysis, Charmides, and Euthyphro is still
apologetic: the first three show how far Socrates was from ‘perverting the
young men’; the last indicates his true attitude to conventional religion—the
other count in the indictment. But Plato is not merely echoing his master.
These dialogues are by no means realistic specimens of Socrates’ conversation;
they are closely knit works of art, grappling, sometimes obscurely, with
fundamental thoughts. Plato was himself trying to grasp the Socratic philosophy
of life and to make up his account with its implications. He was at this time
in painful hesitation, whether or not to yield to the importunities of
political friends, urging the claims of public life upon one in whom they must
have seen the Alcibiades of his generation, with the same social advantages and
far more brilliant intellectual powers. Alcibiades in the first of two
dialogues named after him, stands on the threshold of political life, and
Socrates convinces him that he will not be fit to advise his country until he
has gained self-knowledge, or the knowledge of good and evil. Plato may have
felt that the Socratic conception of the meaning and end of life had opened a
gulf at his feet. The Socratic dialogues were, perhaps, written partly to clear
his own mind before deciding whether he could hold true to this philosophy and
also serve Athens as an active statesman.
The four
dialogues are constructed on a uniform plan. The conversation arises out of a
scene of ordinary life described at some length. The theme is the definition of
a virtue: courage (Laches), self-control (Charmides), piety (Euthyphro),
friendship (Lysis). A series of definitions are elicited, criticized by
Socrates, and finally rejected. No conclusion is reached, and the reader is
left wondering what inference he is to draw. This peculiar form avoids making
Socrates lay down and defend any positive doctrine; but the inconclusiveness
is only apparent. At least one positive result is indicated—the central
Socratic principle that virtue can be reduced to wisdom or knowledge, with its
corollary that all virtues are one. The Laches, for example, disproves the
common view that a man can be brave and at the same time unjust or intemperate.
If virtue means a knowledge of what is good and bad, such insight will cover
every field of conduct, and determine all desire and action.
The Charmides shows Plato’s mind at work upon the problem which then faced him in a practical
form and never ceased to occupy his thoughts: the bearing of Socrates’
philosophy upon the government of society. The concept of self-knowledge leads
to the question, how a man can know the limits of his own and other men’s
knowledge and ignorance. What is this knowledge —Socrates had seemed to possess
it—which judges all other knowledge? It is not an omniscience embracing all the
special branches of science and art. If we could conceive the possessor of such
omniscience in supreme control, every department of life would be
scientifically directed; but it is not clear that true welfare and happiness
would follow upon increased efficiency. Pursuing the same ends as before, men
would be richer, healthier, stronger in war; but would they be better? The
ruler should possess, not technical omniscience, but ‘a single kind of
knowledge which has for its object good and evil’—a Sovereign Art, assessing
the values of minor ends and their contribution to the well-being of the whole.
The Charmides contains in germ the central doctrine of the Republic,
that the ills of society can be healed only when political power is combined
with knowledge of an absolute standard of value. The inference for Plato
himself was that he could not become a statesman until he had become a
philosopher.
Beside these
studies of Socrates’ identification of goodness with knowledge, Plato has set
some satirical exposures of the professed teachers of ‘goodness.’ In so far as
the Sophists merely supplied an education in advanced subjects, they did not
cross the path of Socrates, who sent them pupils; but their claim to teach the
conduct of life to young men who were to guide the destiny of Athens challenged
examination. Did they know themselves what was good or evil? Two dialogues
devoted to Hippias amusingly exhibit the professor of omniscience as unable to
follow the subtleties of a Socratic argument. In the Protagoras three of
the four great Sophists, Protagoras, Hippias, and Prodicus,
are present with their admirers in the house of a wealthy amateur; Gorgias is
reserved for another occasion. Their methods—the allegorical discourse,
exegesis of the poets—are parodied with the reserve of exquisite art. Socrates
maintains the unity of all the virtues; but the argument is interrupted.
Protagoras holds the centre of the stage, discoursing of education as a
socializing influence. The vital question, on what philosophy of life sophistic
education is based, is not raised till near the end. The argument is so
cleverly turned that critics have been misled into imagining that Socrates here
defends hedonism. The real purpose is to lead the Sophists to confess that
their philosophy is the same as the ordinary man’s who believes that ‘good’
means ‘pleasant,’ or that pleasure is the only good. When he says that some
pleasures are bad, he only means that they are outweighed by future pains: he
has no standard of good save the amount of pleasure or pain. All errors of
conduct must, then, be errors of judgment in the use of the hedonistic
calculus. Socrates ingeniously claims this as a confirmation of his own
doctrine: All wrong-doing is due to ignorance. This ignorance, he blandly suggests,
the Sophists would cure, if only the public would send their sons to be taught.
Charmed with this conclusion, all the Sophists accept the whole argument: ‘the
pleasant is good, the painful evil’; right action can be defined as action that
secures a pleasant and painless life. Thus the professional teachers of
goodness are revealed as willing to fall in with popular hedonism. Their
function is to teach men how to pursue efficiently the only end they recognize.
If goodness can be taught at all, it is not taught by men to whom ‘the good’
means nothing but pleasure.4
If the Protagoras was too clever and gave the impression that Socrates could uphold hedonism, the Gorgias leaves no shade of ambiguity. Conceived in a wholly different
vein of passionate earnestness, this dialogue throws into sharpest contrast two
ideals of life. Rhetoric is treated as the weapon of political power in civic
assemblies, and so as including statesmanship. It claims to be the Sovereign
Art, but knows nothing of the true end of power; its aim is the autocracy of
the politician in control of a democratic machine. To Socrates tyrannical power
is at best unenviable. Better suffer wrong than do it; better be punished for
wrong-doing than escape chastisement. Callicles, a rich young aspirant to
political honours, protests that, if this be true, ‘the whole of human life is
upside down.’ He maintains the natural right of the strong to the lion’s share
and professes hedonism, which Socrates now openly refutes. The life of
self-asserting ambition, exalted by Callicles above the life of the
philosopher, ‘whispering with two or three striplings in a corner,’ is to
Socrates the life of the enemy of society. Socrates claims to be the only true
statesman; but if he should enter public life without stooping to flattery, he
would be put to death.
The bitter
passion of the Gorgias reveals Plato’s nature stirred to its depths by a
conflict that had not yet been solved. His Seventh Letter tells how,
before the revolution of 404 and later, he had been attracted to public life
and again repelled by the deeds of the men in power, culminating in the
execution of Socrates.
“The result
was that I, who had at first been eager to take part in public life, when I saw
all this happening and everything going to pieces, fell at last into
bewilderment. I did not cease to think how all these things, and especially the
general organization of the State, might be amended; but I was all the time
waiting for the right moment for action. At last I perceived that the
constitution of all existing States is bad and their institutions all but past
remedy without a combination of radical measures and fortunate circumstance;
and I was driven to affirm, in praise of true philosophy, that only from the
standpoint of such philosophy was it possible to take a true view of public and
private right, and that, accordingly, the human race would never see the end of
trouble until genuine philosophers should come to hold political power, or
those who held political power should, by some divine appointment, become
philosophers.
It was in
this mind that I first went to Italy and Sicily”.
III.
THE
ACADEMY. DIALOGUES OF THE MIDDLE PERIOD
In the
Gorgias Plato had resigned the hope of exercising the Sovereign Art in his own
city. There remained the possibility of intervening in some State which could
be reformed by a despot from above. This prospect opened before him on his
first visit to Sicily (389—8). A second, and (as it proved) more effective,
means was to found a school of philosophic statesmen. Plato’s own task would be
to direct this school and to work out the Socratic philosophy on lines now
taking shape in his mind, publishing his results in a form that would reach the
educated public throughout the Greek world and attract students. The Academy
was founded just after the first visit to Western Greece. At Syracuse Plato
thought he had found in Dion, the brother-in-law of the reigning Dionysius, a
young man who might become a philosopher-king; but to flatter a despot proved
as impossible as to flatter a mob; and Dion, now deeply devoted to Plato, had
to procure his escape by a ship which was conveying home the Spartan envoy, Pollis. According to Plutarch (Dion, Pollis,
acting on Dionysius’ instructions, sold Plato into slavery at Aegina. Redeemed
by a Cyrenian friend, Anniceris,
he returned to Athens, probably in the summer of 388. Anniceris,
it is said, refused repayment of the ransom, and the sum was used to buy a
garden in the grove of the hero Academus. Here the
school was founded on lines partly suggested by the Pythagorean societies Plato
had seen in South Italy. He also found in Pythagoreanism the clue to the
problem of knowledge. The discovery is unfolded in the dialogues of the middle
group: Meno, Phaedo, Symposium, Republic, Phaedrus. Some outlying works
may be mentioned here. The Euthydemus dissociates the dialectic of
Socrates from the barren disputation which was infecting the Megarian School.
The founder of this School, Eucleides, was an
Eleatic, who declared the Good to be one thing with many names—Wisdom, God,
Mind. The Zenonian dialectic of his followers was
called by their opponents ‘eristic’ or ‘anti-logic,’ and they have little to
their credit beyond the formulation of puzzles which gave an impulse to logical
theory. The Cratylus disposes of the notion that
philosophic truth can be deduced from the structure of language. The Menexenus (385 BC) contains a satire on the Periclean
ideal—a Parthian shot at Athenian democracy.
The
possibility of knowledge had become a problem when Parmenides condemned as
false the manifold world which ‘seems’ to the senses, and Protagoras had
asserted, on the contrary side, that what seems to every man is real or true
for him. Was there, or was there not, a world of true Being behind appearances
and capable of supporting them? Protagoras’ fellow-countryman, Democritus of
Abdera, whose long life must have nearly covered the century 450—350, gave the
materialist answer. The atomism he adopted from Leucippus is an ideally mechanistic system. True Being
consists solely of atoms of uniform quality and of the void in which they move.
Sensation is due to the impact of atoms from outside upon the atoms of the
soul. All sensible differences of quality must be consequences of the only real
differences between atoms—in shape, size, and position. These secondary
qualities are ‘conventional,’ not part of the objective reality which is
inaccessible to the ‘bastard knowledge’ of the senses. But the ‘genuine
knowledge’ that reveals the real nature of the invisible atoms is explained by
the same mechanism. The soul atoms, being diffused all over the body, can, by a
direct contact independent of the sense-organs, perceive the atoms outside as
they are. Democritus, of whom Aristotle remarked that he reduced all the senses
to touch, might be said to reduce all thought to an exceptional kind of
sensation. Such is the final outcome of Ionian science, seeking the real ‘nature
of things’ in the ultimate components of material bodies.
To a follower
of Socrates the problem of knowledge presents a different aspect; it is, in the
first place, the problem of that knowledge which is goodness. Plato was, at
this stage, no more interested than his master in the world of Nature. He held
to the doctrine, learnt in his youth from the Heracleitean Cratylus, that sensible things are always changing
and cannot be known. The primary aim of the Platonic theory of Forms or ‘Ideas’
is to provide for the inner world a law to save the individual will from the
nightmare of unlimited freedom. The sovereign knowledge of good and evil must
have for its object standards that are universally and absolutely valid.
Justice and the other moral conceptions that Socrates sought to define must be
eternal objects, to be known by thought, though not by sense. They are not part
of the furniture of anyone’s private world, but form a common world independent
of what ‘seems’ to any individual or to all. Plato did not reach this
conclusion solely by reflection upon the methods of Socrates and the formula,
Goodness is knowledge. Platonism, as Aristotle saw1, is a form of
Pythagoreanism, modified by Socratic influence. The Gorgias already
points in this direction, where Socrates describes justice and temperance as a
principle of order and law in the soul, and connects this principle with the
harmonious order of the universe and the structure of mathematical truth.
The Meno announces a further discovery: how knowledge of eternal objects, moral or
mathematical, is acquired. It cannot be derived by any process of ‘abstraction’
from the dream-world of appearance; it comes out of the soul itself by
Reminiscence. Perhaps through contact with the mathematicians of Cyrene and
South Italy, Plato came to recognize that the objects of the mathematical
sciences—the only organized bodies of knowledge that could be called
‘science’—were not concrete things, and that the truths of mathematics neither
hold good of sensible things nor can be proved by experience. To account for
the a priori discovery of fresh mathematical truth, Plato postulates an
impersonal memory, which, so far as it extends, is the same in all men, unlike
the personal memory that registers the peculiar experience acquired during
this life. All mathematical truth is stored in this impersonal memory, and,
since reality is a coherent system, the soul which recalls one truth can
proceed to rediscover all the rest, without recourse to experience. Unlike
historical information, such truths are recognized at first
acquaintance; they carry their own warrant of immediate certainty, and they are
linked in a necessary sequence. In the Meno Socrates establishes the
fact of reminiscence by experiment, eliciting from a slave, ignorant of
geometry, the solution of a rather difficult problem. The theory is supported
by further arguments in the Phaedo. In both dialogues it is associated with the
hypothesis of the soul’s pre-existence and the Pythagorean doctrine of
reincarnation.
Plato held,
moreover, that knowledge of the meaning of moral terms, such as Socrates had
tried to define, was reached in the same way. The meaning of ‘Justice’ is an
object of knowledge, as absolute and immutable as the meaning of ‘Triangle.’
Further, the world of moral truth, like the mathematical, is an intelligible
and necessary system, at the apex of which the Republic places the Form
(Idea) of Goodness itself. To trace out its structure was to be the function of
an ideal dialectic. This new conception of knowledge and its objects takes
Plato beyond Socrates, who had seen the ideal type of knowledge, not in
mathematics, but in the practical intelligence of the craftsman. It also points
to aristocracy. Theoretically, all knowledge is latent in every human soul; but
few will recover enough to justify their taking control of society. The rest
must be guided by ‘true belief,’ imparted by a philosophic lawgiver. This lower
form of goodness can be taught; the higher can be attained only by rational
intuition, after a long and laborious training of the intellect.
In the Phaedo the light of this discovery transfigures the meaning of life and death. The
life of the lover of wisdom is a meditation of death, and the death of Socrates
becomes a symbol of the death of every man. The objects of rational knowledge,
set in clear contrast with the experience that comes to the bodily senses, are
the unchanging Ideas, incomposite and indestructible. The immortal soul is akin
to the Ideas, and knows them when it withdraws from the body ‘to think by
itself.’ This withdrawal is completed by the severance of soul from body in
physical death; but, even then, only the philosopher’s soul is freed from all
taint of the earthly.
Towards the
end of the Phaedo, the theory of Ideas is formally stated for the first
time. Reminiscence accounts for our knowledge of mathematical and moral Ideas;
but here the theory has assumed a much wider application. It is announced as
superseding all earlier explanations of the becoming and change of concrete
things. At the same time it appears, at least to the modern reader, to be
intended as a logical theory of propositions in general. This logical aspect is
not distinguished from the metaphysical, and it must be remembered that no
science of Logic existed. Since, however, the two aspects of the theory appear
to lead to incompatible conclusions, of which Plato later became aware, it may
be well to present them separately.
In Logic, the
‘Form’ or Idea (eidos) is a common character of any number of things
called by the same name; for every common name there is a Form (which is, in
one sense, the meaning of the name), and a corresponding class of things. The
theory states (1) that there are Ideas such as Beautiful, Good, Large, etc. ‘just
by themselves,’ and (2) that ‘if anything else (i.e. any individual thing) is
beautiful, it is so for no other reason than that it partakes of that
“Beautiful.”’ Logically construed, this amounts to an analysis of the
proposition ‘This thing is beautiful' into (a) this thing (a
particular subject), (b) Beautiful (a universal or predicate), and (c) is (the
subject-predicate relation, ‘partaking,’ which every particular has to some
universal). The proposition means the same as ‘This thing -partakes of (the)
Beautiful (itself)’. Considered simply as an analysis of the type of
proposition which has a particular subject and a universal predicate, this
theory marks a brilliant discovery in Logic. Unfortunately it is extended to other
types of proposition, such as ‘A is larger than B’, which do not in fact
contain a predicate or the subject-predicate relation. It is probable also that
a confusion of the proposition ‘This thing is beautiful’ with ‘This
beautiful thing exist’s, partly accounts for the
failure to distinguish the logical theory from a metaphysical explanation of
the causes of existence, becoming, and change in time.
Under this
other aspect, the theory is stated in the same context as follows: ‘What makes a thing beautiful is nothing but the presence of that “Beautiful” or its communication,
however it may occur; for I do not insist on that, but only say that it is by
the Beautiful that all beautiful things are beautiful’. This appears to mean
that the fact corresponding to the proposition ‘This thing is beautiful’ is the
presence in the thing, either of the Idea (eidos) ‘Beautiful’ itself, or
of a character (idea, morphi) imparted by the
Idea to the thing. When a beautiful thing begins to exist, or a thing becomes
beautiful, what happens is that the Idea somehow either comes to be present in
the thing or imparts its own nature to it. When the thing ceases to exist or to
be beautiful, this presence or character is withdrawn, for neither the Idea
itself nor the character can cease to exist or change. Thus the theory becomes
a metaphysical account of ‘the causes of becoming and perishing,’ which is to
supersede all mechanical and materialistic doctrines.
When we try
to reconcile the two aspects of the theory, difficulties at once occur. In
Logic common names, such as ‘red’ or ‘dirty,’ are on the same footing as ‘just’
or ‘triangular’; but can we suppose that redness and dirt are eternal Ideas, to
be known a priori without reference to sensible experience? How, again,
can an eternal and unchanging Idea impart its character to a thing at some
moment of time and withdraw it at another? The metaphysical relation between
the supersensible Idea and the perceptible thing,
whether called ‘partaking’ or ‘presence’ or ‘communication,’ does not appear to
us to be the same as the logical relation between subject and predicate, and it
remains mysterious.
Elsewhere
Ideas are often described as ‘models’ (paradeigmata)
or types, which are copied or reflected in sensible things; and it is suggested
that the imperfect things of sense are striving to realize in themselves the
perfection of their models. On this view, the moving cause which makes the
thing (imperfectly) like the Idea lies, not in the Idea, but in the thing
which, as it were, desires to reproduce its character. This suggestion bears fruit
in Aristotle’s doctrine of the Form as moving and final cause. An alternative
suggestion is latent in the earlier passage where Socrates calls for a
teleological explanation of existence, recognizing an Intelligence which
designs the world, in all its parts, ‘for the best.’ What exists in time is not
to be accounted for by mechanical antecedents or by an analysis of things into
material elements. The ground of all existence must be sought in the real world
of perfect Ideas. These may be conceived as the models, with reference to which
the divine Artist fashions an imperfect world of appearance. A cosmology of
this type, in which the moving cause is the divine Mind, was to be outlined
later in the Timaeus.
Meanwhile
Plato’s thought was still bent upon the reform of society. What were the least
changes which would enable a Socrates to replace the Callicles of the Gorgias
and to put in practice the sovereign art of philosophic statesmanship? The Republic studies the problem of harmonious organization in the analogous cases of the
State and of the individual soul. Conflict and disharmony arise because the
competing motives characteristic of groups of men in society and of ‘parts’ of
the soul—love of knowledge and goodness, love of power, and love of
pleasure—are not reconciled, and their relative values are not determined. A
perfect society can exist only where the men who know what is really good are
in complete control. In the perfect character the discord of motives must be so
resolved that it cannot break out again, because all ends are seen in true
proportion and no part of our nature is thwarted of its true satisfaction. The
social and individual problems are intertwined throughout the Republic. Their
solutions meet in the doctrine that political power must rest with the perfect
character, the philosopher.
The
commonwealth described is a reformed city-state, whose citizens are classed
according to their natural dispositions and abilities. The lowest class
minister to economic needs; next comes the executive and fighting class; and
above them the philosophic rulers, who possess true wisdom and virtue. The
cardinal virtues, which in the Socratic dialogues had all been reduced to
wisdom, are now separately defined. Justice and Temperance are virtues of the
citizen as such, and pervade the whole community. The principle of justice,
that each should do the work he is naturally fit for, replaces the principle of
‘equality’ in existing democracies, where every man was held to be capable of
all social functions. Temperance unites all classes in harmonious agreement on
the question where power should lie. This principle of government by consent
replaces the democratic ‘freedom’ of everyman to do as he likes. To understand
the secret of this harmony we must turn to the economy of the individual soul.
The division
of the soul into three ‘parts’—reflective, spirited, and appetitive—is not
meant as an exhaustive classification of faculties. It is established by
analysing states of mind containing a conflict of motives; and, as Aristotle
observes, the element of desire is distributed among all three parts, each of
which has its own desires and pleasures. The reflective part desires knowledge;
the spirited, honour; the appetitive, money as a means to sensual enjoyment. There
are three corresponding types of character, each preferring its own kind of
pleasure. The pleasures of knowledge are the truest; but the lower parts, by
following reason, find the truest pleasure they can have; they are not
sacrificed. The three forms of desire are characterized by differences in their
objects, as if desire were a single energy which can be diverted from one channel
to another. This analysis corrects an impression left by the Phaedo,
which was concerned with the significance of death and opposed the soul, as the
thinking thing, to the body, as the seat of emotion and desire. From that
standpoint, an ascetic type of morality treats the inward conflict as a
struggle between passionless reason on the right side and naturally evil desire
on the wrong. The Republic recognizes the element of desire as appearing
in all three parts of the soul. Desire is not to be crushed as evil in itself;
the moral problem is to be solved by bringing the competing desires into a
stable agreement. Hence Temperance is defined as ‘a harmony and solidarity of
all three parts of the soul, when they all consent to the rule of the
reflective part, and there is no faction among them’.
This
conception of desire (Eros) as the single moving energy of the soul is
developed in the discourse which Socrates, in the Symposium, says that
he heard from Diotima, a wise woman of Mantinea. The name Eros has been
misappropriated to one species of desire; but the love of honour and the love
of truth are manifestations of the same energy, which in itself is neither good
nor evil, but takes its value from its object. ‘All are in love with the same
thing always,’ namely with a happiness that consists in the possession of
beauty and goodness, and the possession of them for ever. Thus Eros is a
passion for immortality, reaching out beyond the individual life and its
pleasures. Even in sexual desire the mortal creature seeks the immortality of
the race. The love of honour aims at undying glory, for which the individual
will sacrifice enjoyment and life itself. A third form is the passion to beget
spiritual children, seen in the creative artist and in the educator, who plants
his thoughts in living minds.
Such an
educator was Socrates himself. Diotima here pauses to tell him that, though he
might be initiated into these Lesser Mysteries of Eros, she doubts if he is
capable of the perfect revelation. Plato may wish to imply that the vision of
the eternal world, in the Greater Mysteries that follow, was denied to the
historic Socrates, unless we should rather say, the Socrates of the earlier
Platonic dialogues. Immortality in the three forms above mentioned is the
immortality in time attainable by the mortal creature, who can only perpetuate
his race, his fame, his creative work, his thoughts, in other mortal creatures.
In the higher stages, next described, Eros is detached from the individual
object and from physical beauty. It passes on to moral, and then to
intellectual, beauty, becoming the philosophic passion for eternal truth. The
final object, embracing all these forms, is an absolute and divine Beauty. The
soul united with it in knowledge becomes divine and immortal. The energy which
wings the soul to this highest flight is the same that appeared in the instinct
to perpetuate the race and in the lower forms of ambition. It is the single
moving force of the soul; and in the Phaedrus soul is defined, no longer
as the thinking thing, opposed to the body with its emotions and desires, but
as the self-moved source of all motion. If Eros is the energy of the
self-moving soul, the division of the soul into ‘parts’ may be understood as
the temporary diversion of some of this energy from its proper object to ends
incidental to incarnation in a mortal body. The temperate harmony of the
perfect character is to be reached, not by the suppression, but by the
re-orientation, of desire.
The
conversion of Eros from its lower forms to the passion for wisdom lifts the
philosophic natures, whose training for the government of society is described
in the Republic VI—VII, above the lovers of sensible beauty, immersed in
the dream-world of appearance. The virtue they must possess consists in a knowledge
whose object is Goodness itself, the principle of all truth and being, as the
sun in the visible world is the source of all light and life. The discovery of
the world of Ideas has immeasurably deepened Plato’s conception of the
knowledge which is virtue. It means no longer a rational art of conduct, but a
recognition of the final significance of the universe. The supreme object of
knowledge, which ‘every soul seeks after, divining that it exists, but unable
to say what it is,’ lies beyond even the intelligible world. The eye of the
soul must be turned away from the idols of the Cave—a symbol of the world of
appearance—and accustomed to the light of intelligible truth, until it can
bear to look upon the Sun.
The faculty
exercised is the Reason; and Plato here distinguishes two complementary phases
of its activity: Intellect (dianoia) and Intuition (noesis). The
procedure of Intellect is that deductive and discursive reasoning which
operates in the mathematical sciences. Geometry, for example, assumes certain
premisses, as if they were self-evident, and proceeds to deduce an indefinite
series of necessary conclusions. But the Reason is also capable of a movement
in the reverse direction, upwards from the consequence to the premiss that
implies it. The assumptions of Geometry are not really ultimate. The branches
of pure mathematics form a single chain of necessary truths, deducible from the
ultimate premiss of the science of numbers (arithmetic), which we may perhaps
formulate as ‘the existence of unit’y. Unity is one
aspect of the Good. The upward movement is due to a power (as it were) of
divination, which apprehends a prior truth by an immediate act of Intuition.
The Reason is
first to be trained in the deductive arguments of mathematics. But mathematical
concepts are not the only objects of knowledge, nor is unity the only aspect of
the ultimate principle. There are the other Ideas, which culminate in the same
principle under its aspect as the Good, though they also share with the
mathematical structure the attributes of beauty and truth. From mathematics the
philosophers will pass to Dialectic, the study of moral concepts, with a
technique developed from the Socratic conversation aiming at the definition of
moral terms. Here the deductive reasoning of Intellect has only a subordinate
place, being employed in the criticism of ‘hypotheses’, the tentative
definitions advanced by the respondent and tested by the consequences to which
they lead. The ‘hypothesis’ is reached by an effort of Intuition to perceive
the content of an Idea. If the consequences prove the suggestion to be
one-sided, too narrow or too wide, it will be rejected, and the respondent will
frame a new definition, which should more nearly coincide with the true
meaning. The criticism of Intellect will again be applied, and so the process
will be continued by Intuition and Intellect in alternating rhythm, until the
Idea, which has all along been dimly in view, is fully apprehended. Even when
an Idea is known, however, this knowledge is only a part of the whole system of
truth. Intuition must mount higher still to the summit, from which the partial
truth can be seen in relation to all the rest of truth—the knowledge of
Goodness itself. If this unconditional principle can ever be reached, the Intellect
may then proceed to a complete deduction of the structure of reality. The
philosopher, could he ever achieve this quest, would see the world as God might
see it, and become as God, knowing good from evil. If virtue is knowledge,
nothing short of this is perfect knowledge; and the man who can reach it should
be enthroned as absolute lawgiver. Then the perfect commonwealth might see the
light of day.
In the Phaedo and the Republic the sensible and intelligible worlds are sharply
distinguished, and the relation between them is obscure. If Dialectic is
concerned wholly with Ideas ‘apart from all the senses,’ how does the power of
thought gain its first foothold to ‘mount upon and spring from’? The theory of
Reminiscence replies that the memory of an Idea seen before birth is awakened
by the perception of its imperfect copies in the world of sense. The mythical
encomium of Eros, delivered by Socrates in the Phaedrus, identifies this
act of reminiscence with what we might call a process of ‘abstraction.’ Man,
and man only, has Reason, enabling him to ‘understand by way of the Form
(Idea), a unity gathered by reflection from many acts of perception; and this
is recollection of the things formerly seen by the soul, when it travelled in
the divine company, despising the things we now call real and looking upwards
to true reality’. Further we are told that, of the three aspects of the divine—Beauty,
Goodness, and Truth—Beauty alone is visible through the bodily eyes, as an
‘indwelling light’ in its likenesses on earth. The perception of Beauty in the
individual causes the distraction of Love, a form of ‘divine madness’ compared
to the inspiration of prophecy, religious enthusiasm, and poetry. This madness
is exalted above rational sobriety; the influx of Beauty causes the wings which
Psyche must receive from Eros to grow for the higher flights of philosophic
intuition.
The theory of
Reminiscence is here set in a new light. The Idea, a unity shared by a
manifold, is intuitively discerned as beauty; as if the perfect type were
revealed within, or through, the imperfect copy. The first apprehension is dim
and confused. It is clarified by Dialectic, which, in the Phaedrus, is
described as consisting of two complementary processes, Collection and
Division, ending in the Definition. The Definition is a complete and explicit
statement of the content of the ‘indivisible species’. For this procedure the
Ideas are conceived as forming a hierarchy, in which a higher term is related
to the lower as genus to subordinate species. Collection is an act of
Intuition, ‘surveying together’ the specific Form to be defined and a number of
others that may be ‘widely scattered’, and divining the single generic Form under
which they must all be gathered. Everything will depend upon the correctness of
this intuition; but it is an act of insight, not a method for which rules can
be given. The genus is then systematically divided ‘where the joints naturally
come’, down through intermediate classes and sub-classes, each with its
specific difference, to the indivisible species. This lowest term is a Form
which cannot be further divided, because it has nothing below it but an
indefinite number of individual things whose Form it is—the members of the
species, unknowable in so far as they contain anything more than their common
specific Form. This is the very Form that was dimly apprehended in the initial
act of intuition. What is gained by the dialectical process is an explicit, statement
of its content; and, moreover, the Form so defined is set in its proper
relations to kindred Forms. The definition consists of the generic term and all
the specific differences of the intermediate classes. This method is later
illustrated at length in the Sophist and Statesman. It exhibits
the alternating rhythm of Intuition and Intellect, which in the mathematical
sciences are employed to divine the premisses and to deduce the conclusions of
demonstrative proof.
This
description of Dialectic indicates that the intelligible world of Ideas
includes a hierarchy of natural kinds, or ‘types fixed in Nature’. Such a
structure points to a possible object for a science of Nature; and we learn
from a fragment of Comedy that the method of Division was applied in the
Academy to the classification of natural species. The belief in the existence
of a limited number of eternally existing real kinds was perpetuated as a
fundamental postulate in the philosophy of Aristotle.
Towards the
end of the Phaedrus, the written word is disparaged as no better than
the bastard brother of the living and breathing word that can be written with
understanding in the learner’s mind. Plato speaks as if the dialogues we have
reviewed were pastimes to amuse the leisure of the head of the Academy, whose
serious work lay elsewhere, in living intercourse with his students. He may
have laid aside his pen for some years. His time was also to be taken up by
another essay in practical reform. On the accession of the younger Dionysius at
Syracuse in 367 BC, Plato was led by a sense of duty and by the more sanguine
hopes of Dion to attempt once more the conversion of a despot to philosophy. This
unsuccessful journey may have interrupted the composition of the series: Parmenides,
Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman.
IV.
THE
LATER DIALOGUES
The newly
discovered world of Ideas had yet to be explored and conquered. Complete
conquest would mean the deduction of a rational and coherent system of the
universe from an absolute principle. If Plato had moments when the way seemed
clear, he could not communicate a finished result. The Parmenides opens
with a searching criticism of his own theory of Ideas, formulating difficulties
ignored in the Phaedo and perhaps brought to light by discussion in the
Academy. (1) Can an Idea, like a thing, be the subject of propositions and have
many predicates without loss of unity? (2) The extent of the world of Ideas
becomes a problem, if Logic is to recognize universals such as ‘mud’ or ‘dirt,’
which Metaphysics can hardly admit to be eternal forms of reality. (3) No
intelligible account of the relation between an Idea and its group of
synonymous things has yet been found. The problem cannot be evaded by regarding
Ideas as mere thoughts in our minds, or by recognizing only the relation of
likeness between Idea and thing. The gap between the Ideal world and the
sensible threatens to remain unbridged. Modern critics dispute whether the
exercises in abstract dialectic which fill the rest of the dialogue offer more
than some hints towards an answer to these problems. But .the necessity of some
answer is stated with emphasis: Ideas are indispensable to thought.
This
conclusion is negatively reinforced in the Theaeletus,
by a proof that knowledge is not to be found in sensation or senseperception, or in ‘true belief,’ which can be
produced or shaken by persuasion. Sensation is infallible, but does not
apprehend reality, the immediate objects of the senses are qualities which only
arise in a process taking place between the sense-organ and the physical thing.
Nor can it yield truth; for this is a property of judgments, and every judgment
must contain at least one term which is not a sense-object. The discussion of
the claims of true belief shows that empiricist views of the mind as a mere
passive receptacle of impressions from without cannot explain how we can ever
make a false judgment. Incidentally Plato refutes the doctrines he ascribes to
Protagoras: that what appears real to each man is real for him, and what he
thinks true is true for him. He also rejects the extreme Heracleitean view which denies any stable Being, though he still holds that sensible objects
are in perpetual change and cannot be known. The dialogue defends the old
position that there can be no knowledge without the Ideas.
This
criticism of the world of appearance and its champion, Protagoras, is followed
by a dialogue defining the Sophist as a denizen of that world and himself a
creator of illusions. The attempt involves a discussion of what is meant by an
unreal appearance and by falsehood in speech and thought. The treatment of the
former question does not solve the problem of the relation between an Idea and
the things described as partly unreal copies of it. We find only a review of
theories of the real, leading to a criticism both of the materialists, who
believe only in tangible body, and of the ‘friends of Ideas’, who admit only
the reality of ‘intelligible and bodiless Forms’. It is asserted that at least
some perfectly real things must be capable of life and intelligence, and
therefore of change. The friends of Ideas must not suppose that immutable Forms
can be the whole of reality. Plato seems here to provide for the reality of the
divine Mind, of that element in the human soul which knows truth, and, perhaps,
of non-human intelligences, such as govern the movement of the stars.
The logical
discussion which follows clears up some fallacies about negative propositions,
and deals, for the first time, with propositions about Ideas, which are here
treated as ‘kinds,’ arranged in a hierarchy. The dialectician, by means of
Collection and Division, will make out their relations. All discourse depends
on the combination of Ideas with one another. False speech and judgment are now
explained. A judgment (doxa) is the conclusion of the process of
thought, the silent dialogue which the mind holds with itself. Speech is the
utterance of a judgment in a significant combination of words. It is false when
it states about its subject something other than what is. ‘Appearance’ (phantasia), in the psychological sense, is defined
as ‘a mixture of sensation and judgment,’ with the implication, apparently,
that the element of falsity it may contain is due to the judgment. This
demonstration of the possibility of false speech, judgment, and appearance
justifies the definition of the Sophist as a species of image-maker, practising
an art of deceit.
The Statesman continues the conversation begun in the Sophist. It defines the scope of the
sovereign art of statesmanship, dismissing theocracy as not for this world. The
ideal is still the philosopher king, ruling without laws; but, in his absence,
laws such as he would approve must be framed. Plato undertook this task in the
Laws, his last work. He there finds the practical solution in a mixture of
constitutional monarchy and democracy.
The series of
critical dialogues is inconclusive: problems are raised that are not solved.
The Sophist and Statesman seem to promise a further dialogue, the Philosopher, in which Socrates would have taken the lead once more. If
projected, it was never written. In its place we have another unfinished
trilogy. The Timaeus opens with the creation of the world and of man;
the Critias (a fragment) was to exhibit a
commonwealth like that of the Republic, identified with pre-historic
Athens, saving the Mediterranean world from an invasion of the inhabitants of
Atlantis, and then swallowed up by flood and earthquake. The Hermocrates (never written) would, perhaps, have
described the rise of existing society after the catastrophe, and the
establishment of a second- best constitution. Plato may have abandoned his
scheme as too vast, and recast his material in the Laws.
The cosmology
of the Timaeus is a preface to the projected survey of human history and
social institutions; it culminates in the description of the moral and physical
nature of man. It is framed in conscious opposition to the mechanism of the
Pre-Socratics and Democritus. Plato held that motion can be originated only by
the principle of life, or ‘soul,’ and that the soul, or souls, which cause the
motions of the universe must be governed by Reason, purposing ends that are
good. The Laws declares that on these two discoveries rests the faith,
indispensable to society, in gods whose providence is concerned with the good
and evil of mankind. Thus metaphysical, religious, and moral considerations
combine to dictate a type of cosmogony which is creational, rather than
evolutionary, though nothing is created, in the later sense, out of nothing.
The world is the work of a divine Artist, who, being good, desired that all
things should be, so far as possible, like himself. An artist works upon
existing material, and with reference to a model. The divine model is at first
presented as the eternal world of Ideas, the existence of which is asserted
throughout the Timaeus with all the old emphasis. The material is described as
the visible principle of Becoming, whose orderless movement is reduced to order and harmony by the fashioning of a living universe
with a reasonable soul and a body.
The
World-soul itself is a compound of the two principles of Being and Becoming, or
‘the Same and the Other.’ It is ordered in the numerical ratios of a musical
harmony; and its substance is divided into the two circles, equatorial and
ecliptic, of the celestial sphere. The circle of the Other is subdivided into
the planetary orbits. Here the allegorical or mythical form of exposition masks
an inexplicable transition from the purely logical order to the physical, which
is characteristic of this part of the Timaeus and recurs in the
construction of the body of the universe. Visible and tangible body is reduced
to atoms, with the forms of four of the regular geometrical solids; these forms
themselves are decomposed into elementary triangles, and triangles can be
expressed in relations of number. Matter appears sometimes as an indeterminate
substance bounded by these forms, sometimes as mere Space. Elsewhere it seems
to be ultimately reduced to a logical principle of ‘Otherness’ or multiplicity,
as if the physical dispersion of objects in space were derived from the logical
Form of Otherness, which (as the Sophist showed) separates the Ideas
themselves, since each of them is not (is other than) all the rest. Thus the
cosmogony, which cannot here be followed in detail, still leaves in obscurity
the old problem, how to relate the eternal world of Ideas to the mutable things
of time and space. The mechanism of the visible heavens and the living
creatures of earth emerge from a mysterious background of logical entities,
itself concealing the Power whose word becomes flesh.
That this
scheme is, in some sense, ‘mythical’ has always been recognized; and it is
commonly assumed that the mythical form is an allegorical disguise which can be
stripped off, so as to unveil a coherent theory of the universe. Plato, it is
believed, chose to wrap in misleading, and even contradictory, imagery, a
rational doctrine which might have been set forth in literal and prosaic terms.
But the interpreters who reverse this proceeding arrive at conflicting and
arbitrary results. In Plato’s thought about God, the universe, and the soul
there is an irreducible element of myth. This word has more than one sense. ‘Mythos’,
meaning ‘account,’ ‘story,’ is used by Timaeus himself to describe the physical
theories which fill a large part of the dialogue. These seem to embody the best
results of contemporary speculation in astronomy and medicine. But for Plato
‘the actual physical world, just because it cannot be completely analysed into
combinations of logical concepts, but involves a factor of irrational sensible
fact, is incapable of being an object of science proper. Any conclusions we may
form as to its structure and history must be put forward not as proved results
of science, but as, at best, a “probable account”’ (mythos). Such an
account might be in the plainest prose; the element of falsity lies, not in the
mode of exposition, but in the object described, which is only a fleeting image
of the real. This sense of mythos does not imply the use of poetical
imagery. Plato also recognizes an allegorical type of myth. The Guardians of
the Ideal State will fabricate myths to convey to the unphilosophic citizens
religious truths beyond the reach of their intellects. Here the element of
falsity resides in the allegorical form; but the truth it contains is assumed
to be known and deliberately disguised. Now, the myths in Plato’s dialogues are
partly allegorical; but those which deal with God and the soul cannot be
completely transposed into rational and prosaic terms. They contain an element
of that non-rational poetic thought, which the Phaedrus acknowledged as
yielding intuitions of truth inaccessible to the sober intellect. When the
imagery of Timaeus’ creation myth is dissolved by the allegorical method of
interpretation, with it disappears the element which Plato in his old age valued
more and more—the belief in ‘a Maker and Father of this universe,’ who not only
designed the world but cares for the destinies of man.
The Philebus contains Plato’s last word upon the nature
of human happiness, occasioned perhaps by an Academic controversy between
Plato’s colleague Eudoxus, a hedonist, and others who
denied that pleasure was a good at all and identified happiness with wisdom.
Happiness is declared to consist in a mixed life combining all forms of
knowledge with innocent and pure pleasures. The mixture owes its goodness to
the qualities of beauty, truth, and measure. Judged in respect of these
qualities, pleasure is declared, on metaphysical grounds, to be inferior to
Reason and knowledge.
From
Aristotle we learn something of a latest phase, in which Plato developed the
Pythagorean doctrine that all things represent numbers. He distinguished the
numbers Two, Three, etc., which are Ideas, not only from collections of so many
things, but also from an intermediate kind of numbers which occur in
mathematical propositions, such as 2 + 2 = 4. An Ideal Number is unique,
cannot be added to itself, and does not consist of units. Such Numbers are
derived from a formal principle, the One, and a material, the ‘great and small’,
or ‘Indeterminate Duality’, so called because ‘the indefinite is held to
proceed to infinity both in the direction of increase and in that of diminution’.
The principles are called, in the Philebus, by
the Pythagorean names, Limit and Unlimited. In the physical world the Unlimited
is exemplified by ‘hotter-and-colder,’ or ‘higher-and-lower’ in sound. The
Limit is represented by ‘whatever has the ratio of one number or measure to another’.
The union of the two principles produces ‘a mixed being which has become’, e.g.
health, musical harmony, temperate seasons, etc. Plato seems to have held that
Numbers themselves can be analysed into corresponding principles. Ideal spatial
magnitudes form a class of more complex Ideas, in which Numbers serve as the
formal principle, and the material is space. Below these again are the
mathematical numbers and magnitudes, and finally physical atoms in actual
space. It appears, further, that Plato regarded all Ideas as in some sense
‘Numbers,’ composed of corresponding principles. Here the formal principle may
be identified with the One in its aspect of the Good. The material is the
principle of multiplicity in the Ideal world. Ideas so formed serve as the
principle of Limit to sensible things.
We hear also
of an unpublished lecture on the Good; but if the notes preserved by Plato’s
pupils had come down to us, it is not likely that we should understand them.
Indeed, we have Plato’s own assurance that we should not. On his last visit to
Syracuse (361 BC) he had told Dionysius something, but by no means all, of what
was in his mind with regard to the ultimate questions of philosophy. Dionysius
afterwards composed a treatise and gave it out as his own doctrine. Of this
essay and others like it Plato writes that their authors could not understand
anything of the matter.
“There is
not, nor shall there ever be, any writing of mine on this subject. It is
altogether beyond such means of expression as exist in other fields of
knowledge; rather, after long dwelling upon the thing itself, in a common life
of philosophic converse, suddenly, as from a leaping spark, a light is kindled,
which, when it has arisen in the soul, thenceforward feeds itself. Yet of this
I am sure: that, if these things were to be written down or expressed in words,
I could express them better than anyone; I know too that if they were set down
in writing badly, I should be the person to suffer most. If I thought they
could be adequately set forth to the world in speech or writing, in what nobler
business could I have spent my life than in writing a work of great service to
mankind and revealing Nature to all eyes under the light of day? But I do not
think that a statement of what has been attempted in this field is a good thing
for man, unless it be for the very few who can be enabled, by a slight
indication, to make the discovery for themselves. Of the rest, some would be
puffed up with an entirely offensive spirit of false superiority; others, with
a lofty and presumptuous conceit of understanding some great matter”.
From these
words we may infer that there were moments when Plato seemed to himself to have
gained a luminous vision of reality, in which the claims of logical intellect
and poetic intuition were reconciled, and the world appeared both rational and
harmonious. All that he could give to others was a ‘slight indication,’ such as
might enable a few to discover for themselves the knowledge which, as Socrates
had said, cannot be taught.
V.
ARISTOTLE
Aristotle
joined the Academy in his eighteenth year (367 BC), about the time of Plato’s
second visit to Sicily, and worked there till Plato died in 347. He was born at Stagirus in the Thracian peninsula, a Greek colony
from Andros and Chalcis, the home of his mother’s family. His father, Nicomachus, was a physician, attached to the court of Amyntas II of Macedonia. The intellectual influences of
Aristotle’s early years came from medical and physical science, untouched, in
that quarter of the Greek world, by the philosophic revolution begun by
Socrates at Athens. The natural bent of his mind was always towards the study
of empirical facts; he collected them with enormous industry and sought to fit
them into an encyclopaedic system of the universe. But during the twenty years
he spent at the Academy, as the pupil and colleague of Plato, he became, once
for all, a Platonist. His life-work was a gigantic effort to force the
apparatus of Platonic thought to account for the natural world revealed by
observation.
It is
impossible as yet to trace closely the development of Aristotle’s thought. Of
the dialogues he wrote at the Academy, only fragments survive. His collections
of material have perished almost entirely. The extant works form a corpus of
treatises, mainly intended for the School and little known outside it until they
were published by Andronicus of Rhodes in the time of Cicero. Some parts
consist of lectures written out in more or less summary form; others seem to be
compilations of essays, of various dates, collected either by Aristotle himself
or by his pupils after his death. When criticism has made out the
stratification of these writings, it may go on to construct the history of
Aristotle’s thought. A great advance has been made by W. Jager, whose Aristoteles supersedes earlier biographies. Other scholars are pursuing the same line; but
some of the results are still in dispute, and a long controversy may be
expected before agreement is reached.
The dialogues
written at the Academy were, like Plato’s, intended for the educated public.
Some, it would seem, were closely modelled, both in style and contents, upon
the works of Plato’s middle period. In others the dramatic manner was dropped;
and a new form, later used by Cicero, appears, in which a series of speeches
are made upon some theme proposed by a chairman, who sums up at the end. The
treatment of immortality in the Eudemus, dated
by the death of the Platonist Eudemus of Cyprus in
354 BC, reproduced the conception of life and death expressed in the Phaedo.
At this date Aristotle regarded the soul as a substance, not as a form
inseparable from the matter of the body, and still held the theory of Ideas—a
proof, incidentally, that the doctrines of the Phaedo had not been
abandoned by their author. Another work of this period, the Protrepticus,
reveals Aristotle’s sympathy with that impulse which tempted Plato throughout
his life to withdraw from the tasks of practical reform into religious
contemplation of truth. It was an exhortation, after the pattern perfected by
Isocrates, recommending the philosophic life to a reigning prince, Themison of Cyprus.
After Plato’s
death and the appointment of his nephew, Speusippus,
to preside over the Academy, Aristotle may have felt that he could not continue
his work under a man of inferior powers. With Xenocrates,
who was later to succeed Speusippus, he withdrew to Assos in the Troad, where two
Platonists, Erastus and Coriscus of Scepsis, were in
friendly relations with the local despot, Hermeias of Atarneus, himself a former member of the Academy.
Aristotle married Hermeias’ niece, Pythias. In this
Platonic circle he stayed for three years, and then taught for a short time at Mitylene in Lesbos, the country of his collaborator and
successor, Theophrastus. In 343 he was invited by Philip of Macedon, who may
have known him as a boy, to undertake the education of Alexander, then thirteen
years of age.
In this
second period of his life, Aristotle still called himself a Platonist; but
death had freed him from the duty to respect the feelings of a venerable
master; and, as the leader of an independent school, he was bound to formulate
his own doctrine. The native bent of his mind now asserted itself in clearer
antagonism to the mystical metamathematics of Plato’s latest thought. The lost
dialogue Concerning Philosophy, perhaps the programme of the School at Assos, attacked the Platonic Ideas, and, in particular, the
theory of Ideal Numbers, distinct from the numbers of mathematics. It opened
with a review of ancient wisdom, oriental as well as Greek, fragments of which
Aristotle believed to have survived the catastrophes that, from time to time,
had overwhelmed civilization. The cosmology set forth at the end had a
theological character as marked as that of the Timaeus. The mythical Creator
and his ideal model are, however, eliminated. The world is without beginning or
end. The movement of the stars is the voluntary motion of their directing
intelligences. God is already conceived as the Unmoved Mover, a pure
unchanging Form, separate from the world. Some of the oldest parts of the
extant treatises must date from this period.
VI.
FORM
AND MATTER, THE ACTUAL AND THE POTENTIAL
With
Aristotle’s rejection of the Platonic Ideas, the centre of reality is shifted
back to the natural world of time and change. A science of Nature, such as Plato
could not recognize, is possible, if the world given in experience contains
objects that are real in the fullest sense. For Plato the world of immaterial
Forms contained the true ‘nature of things’ and the objects of knowledge. In
the hierarchy of Ideas, the method of Division led to the definition, by genus
and differences, of the lowest object of knowledge—the indivisible essence of a
natural kind. The problem was to find an intelligible relation to link the
specific Form in the Ideal world to the individual members of the species.
Aristotle tried to evade it by denying independent reality to the Idea. The
specific Form, actually realized in each individual, is primarily real, and is
the nature of the things possessing it. The real world, then, is no longer a
world of universals, but of concrete things which we perceive. Although these
things become and perish in time and suffer change, they contain a constant
reality. Nature is, in the first place, a kingdom of specific Forms realized in
matter; and every such Form is an invariable and limited set of
characteristics, which can be defined and known. The main purpose of science is
to define these essences and to demonstrate universal truths about them. The
Aristotelian philosophy has its centre here. Its apparatus of concepts is
designed to explain the nature of the individual substance, and how it can come
into existence and undergo change.
The objects
of physical science are things which have sensible matter and movement. These
two characteristics distinguish them from the objects of the other theoretical
sciences, mathematics and metaphysics, the objects of mathematics do not,
indeed, exist apart from sensible matter; number and geometrical form exist
only as determinations of physical things, though they are studied by
mathematicians in abstraction from them. But, as thus abstracted, they are
incapable of motion, and possess only ‘intelligible matter’, a principle of
individuation distinguishing entities that are conceptually identical (e.g. two
circles). This ‘intelligible matter’ is geometrical space, which is not
imaginary, but an abstraction of the same kind as mathematical objects. The
study of objects which are not only incapable of movement, but wholly
immaterial, is the field of metaphysics, also called theology, because the
chief among such objects is God. Since Aristotle’s theology is an appendix to
his philosophy of Nature, we must seek the kernel of his thought in the
analysis of the central objects of physical science.
In the Physics ‘natural objects’ are declared to be ‘animals and their parts, plants, and the
simple bodies—earth, fire, water, and air’. Inorganic Nature consists of the
simple bodies and lifeless compounds of them; organic Nature, of the living
creatures, grouped in species. The individual living creature can be analysed,
in the first place, into its specific Form, its other attributes, and its
Matter.
The specific
Form is an immaterial principle of structure, which cannot exist apart from the
appropriate matter embodying it. Its content is conceptually identical in all
the individuals, and is expressed in the definition by genus and differences.
It is the true ‘nature’ or ‘essence’ of the thing, or ‘what it is to be’ a
thing of that kind. It constitutes, as it were, the permanent and invariable
core of the individual’s being. Round it are grouped the other attributes,
divided into properties and accidents. A property is an attribute which belongs
to all members of a given species and only to them, but is not part of the essence;
thus the capacity for laughter is confined to men, but not essential. An
accident is an attribute which may or may not belong to a thing, and may belong
also to things of other species.
All these
determinations, essential or not, are, in a wider sense, the Form of the
individual substance at any given moment; but the substance is not simply the
sum of them. It also contains an element determined by them, an unknown
something which has the qualities and undergoes the changes that occur in the
thing. This element is called ‘Matter.’ Matter and Form, however, are relative
terms. In relation to the essential nature, the matter of a living creature is
its body; but relatively to the organs of the living body, the tissues
composing them are matter; relatively to the tissues, the simple bodies are
matter; and these bodies themselves are logically analysable into the primary
contrarieties (hot and cold, dry and fluid) and ultimate Matter. Ultimate or
pure Matter is an abstraction of thought, not any kind of thing that can exist
by itself. The lowest level on which Matter exists is the simple bodies. The
name ‘Matter’ is applicable to anything indeterminate, but capable of
determination. The history of this conception goes back through Plato’s
Indeterminate Duality, to the Pythagorean ‘Unlimited’—the void womb of
becoming, informed by the principle of ‘Limit’.
It is,
further, a given fact of experience that individual substances begin and cease
to exist. Natural objects, as distinct from artificial things, are defined as
having in themselves a source of movement or rest. A living creature is born,
grows to its full development and then ceases to grow, produces another
individual of the same kind, and at last decays and dies. These phenomena
cannot be accounted for either by the unimaginable operation of a changeless
Platonic Idea, or (as the Pre-Socratics had supposed) by mechanical interaction
of the lowest forms of matter. Aristotle sees the moving cause in the goal of
development—the specific ‘nature’ realized in each individual. In the highest
types of living creatures—and the lower is to be explained by the higher—the
Form is impressed by the male parent, in the act of generation, on matter
supplied by the female. From its latent condition in the germ it develops to
full perfection, this stage being marked by the capacity to reproduce the Form
in another individual. Thus the cycle begins again, the perfection or ‘end’ of
one individual acting as the ‘beginning’ of another. The ‘final cause’ and the
‘moving cause’ coincide with the ‘formal cause.’
The impulse
of life, manifested in the growth of the living organism from the germ to
perfection, is often spoken of as if it were an impulse of desire directed to
the end, analogous to the artist’s desire to produce in his material the form
he has before his mind. In the language of personification, ‘Nature’ is said to
work to an end. But ‘Nature’ is not a soul, capable of desire or purpose, but
merely a collective name for the natures of all natural things. The personification
is only a literary device, expressing the given fact that the development of
the living germ follows a definite course that seems to be predetermined: it
can develop into the specific Form of its own kind and of no other. This fact
is conveniently conceived by the analogy of conscious purpose, but not
explained; for Aristotle’s system admits neither a designing Creator nor a
World-soul which might be the seat of such purposes.
The same fact
is also expressed by saying that the germ has the power to develop into its
destined perfection, or is ‘potentially’ what it later comes to be actually. In
connection with processes of becoming and change Actuality (energeia)
and Potentiality (dynamis) correspond to Form
and Matter, and are similarly relative terms: what is actually bronze is
potentially a statue. The notion of potentiality is obscure. Dynamis is the substantive answering to the
auxiliary verb ‘can,’ and covers several meanings: (1) the mere
'possibility of anything that may or may not be; (2) capacity to pass
through a change of quality, quantity, or locomotion; (3) the potential
existence of something that may develop into actual existence; (4) the power to
effect a change, the faculty of producing something or of manifesting activity.
Energeia has the corresponding senses: (1) reality, (2) actualization, (3) actuality,
(4) activity. These ambiguities sometimes cover a confusion, and often render
the thought obscure. What, for instance, is meant by saying that the seed is
‘potentially’ a tree? In relation to the full-grown tree the seed is matter,
but not, of course, pure matter capable of any determination. It has the capacity
of becoming a tree, if nothing hinders it; and this capacity must be due to the
actual Form it already possesses—certain properties confining its development
to the course that will end in the perfect Form of its own species. But this is
not all; a lifeless piece of bronze has actual properties which fit it to be
made into a statue, but it will never become a statue of itself. The seed, as a
natural object, must contain ‘a source of movement within itself’—a force that
will carry it to its fulfilment. But, though ‘power’ is one of the meanings of dynamis, this moving force resides, not in matter,
but in the specific Form. Usually the ‘moving cause’ is said to be the specific
Form as actually existing in the fully developed parent; but, in the act of
generation, transmitting this Form to a new individual, the power or force must
also be transmitted. Hence we must say that the specific Form, bearing this
force, exists already in the seed; and since it does not exist in full
actuality until the new tree is grown, it is said to exist ‘potentially’, and
conceived as containing a latent power, whose energy will effect the development. Finally, when the actualization of the Form is complete, this
‘first entelechy’ is endowed with faculties, to be further expressed in the
activities or functions of life, such as nutrition and reproduction.
In this
analysis the word dynamis shifts through all
its meanings. The whole is a description, rather than an explanation, of the
mysterious force of life, whose operation we witness but cannot understand.
Characteristic of Aristotle is the notion that this force resides in the
specific Form, conveying it in unbroken succession from one perishable
individual to another. His merit lies in the caution which keeps him from going
further beyond the observed facts of life to seek an ‘explanation’ in
unverifiable and insufficient hypotheses. On the other hand, the specific
Forms, considered as everlasting and invariable constituents of the natural
order, arc a metaphysical heritage from Plato, involving the dogma that the
natural order itself is without beginning or end. A new species cannot be
created or ‘evolved’ from another species; though, when a species becomes
extinct, on Aristotle’s principles the natural order must be impaired—a
consequence he never faces.
The concepts
of Matter and Form, Potentiality and Actuality, above illustrated from their primary
application to living creatures, are used as master-keys to explain all
phenomena. A few examples must suffice. In order to make the Form the moving
cause in artificial production, the Form of a statue is declared to pre-exist
in the sculptor’s mind and to set in motion the desire leading to its
realization. The material is moved by the tool, the tool by the craftsman’s
hands; his hands are moved, in an appropriate way, ‘by his knowledge of his art
and by his soul, in which is the Form’. In the analysis of changes other than
the generation of substances—changes of quality, quantity, and place—the same
concepts are used; and motion generally is defined as ‘the actualization of
that which is potentially.’ In this context ‘matter’ figures as the subject which
undergoes and persists through change. Aristotle tries to solve the old
problem, How can what is come out of what is not? by remarking that Form (A)
cannot come simply out of its privation (not A) but
only from privation in a substrate (x) which has the new form potentially. Even
in the case of locomotion, Aristotle speaks of ‘local matter,’ which is to be
found, without the matter presupposed in other kinds of change, in the capacity
for rotation of the heavenly spheres. Beyond this is ‘intelligible matter’ or
spatial extension, and finally ‘ultimate matter.’ In the conceptual world, the
genus is called ‘matter’ in relation to the species, which has a higher degree
of determination. Aristotle can hardly be defended against the charge that
concepts of such bewildering ambiguity are chiefly useful for making his system
appear more complete and coherent than it is.
VII.
THE
OBJECTS AND METHODS OF SCIENCE
The belief,
inherited from Plato, in the indivisible specific Form as the kernel of reality
carried with it the old problem of the relation between the universal objects
of knowledge and the particular things existing in time. Aristotle held to the
doctrine that only the universal can be defined and known; but the most real
things in his world are not universals, but individual substances, for the
independent existence of the Platonic Ideas has been denied. When the specific
Form is thus transferred from the intelligible world to actual existence in
sensible matter, what it gains in substantial reality is offset by the danger
that it may cease to be knowable. If the Platonic Idea is a universal, it can
be known, but cannot exist; if it exists, it is an individual, and cannot be
known. But the Aristotelian Form is open to the same dilemma. The world revealed
to experience consists of individual existents. If these constitute the real,
and the individual is indeed unknowable, the problem of finding real objects
for knowledge, which the Theory of Ideas was to solve, seems to become inoluble.
On the other
hand, if the problem appeared in this light to Aristotle, to us the reality of
the specific Form may seem more doubtful than its knowableness. These
invariable Forms, which are to stiffen the unstable world of Heracleitean change with a structure of constant fixity,
are metaphysical figments. The actual Form of an individual substance is
declared to be the most real of entities; but this Form, numerically different
from the Form of any other individual, perishes; it is not transmitted to
descendants. The alleged specific Form which never begins or ceases to be, but
only comes to be ‘actualized’ in fresh individuals, and exists ‘potentially’ in
the germ, is not a thing that really persists and travels unchanged through the
succession of individuals. Though Aristotle attacks Plato for giving
independent existence to Ideas, he is in fact guilty of the same offence; the
difference is that he makes the Idea exist within and throughout the flow of
time and change. It is still the Platonic Idea, with a better claim to be
knowable than to be real; for it retains the essential of an object of
knowledge—a determinate, unvarying, definable content. Having persuaded himself
that it exists everlastingly in the natural world, Aristotle is left with the
problem, how to make this object of knowledge accessible to experience which
must enter through the gate of the senses. The senses show us individual
things, each with a numerically different Form of its own, involved with a mass
of necessary or accidental attributes. It remains to give some account of the
process by which the universal is disengaged from the particular.
Aristotle’s
term Epagoge, though usually rendered by ‘Induction’, rather denoted a
process of abstraction. Starting from the animal faculty of perception, ‘the
first stage in the development from sense to knowledge is memory, the
“remaining of the percept” when the moment of perception is over. The next
stage is “experience,” or the framing, on the basis of repeated memories of the
same kind of thing, of a conception, the fixation of a universal’. It appears,
further, that by a similar process we ascend from particular judgments to
universal judgments and to the first premisses (definitions, axioms etc.) of
all science. Aristotle recognizes, throughout all the stages, the operation of
Plato’s faculty of intuition (noesis). It is ultimately this highest
human faculty that guides the entire procedure by its power of penetrating to
the Idea and to ultimate truths. Induction is ‘the process whereby, after
experience of a certain number of particular instances, the mind grasps a
universal truth which then and afterwards is seen to be self-evident. Induction
in this sense, is the activity of intuitive reason’. It is ‘a process not of
reasoning but of direct insight, mediated psychologically by a review of
particular instances’. In Plato intuition ‘collects’ the generic Idea from a
review of the species; in Aristotle it also arrives at the specific Form from a
review of individuals; Plato, indeed, had already made the sensuous intuition
of beauty in the individual the starting-point of philosophy. On the lowest
level of knowledge, in perception itself, there is an element of intuition,
grasping the whole nature of the individual in a single immediate act.
Possessed by
intuition and ‘induction’ of its universal objects and premisses, demonstrative
science can proceed to its task of proving universal truths. Since the belief
in the primary reality of the specific Form is as much the kernel of
Aristotle’s logic as of his metaphysic, the typical purpose of science is to
define such Forms and to show why they possess properties which are necessary
but not parts of their essence. Definition, as in Plato, is by genus and
specific differences; but Aristotle does not accept the Platonic method of
Division. An indivisible species is to be defined by collecting attributes
common to all individuals of the species, and separately, but not collectively,
shared by other species of the same genus. Since we cannot examine every
individual, we are once more thrown back upon intuition; and it is not clear
how essential attributes can be distinguished from the properties which
demonstration will prove to be necessarily derived from the essence.
Aristotle’s whole discussion of this subject is obscured by two
pre-suppositions. In the first place, he takes the existing structure of the
mathematical sciences as the pattern of all science; and in geometry, for
instance, ‘having angles equal to two right angles’ is taken to be a demonstrable
property of the triangle, but not part of its definition. The other source of
confusion is his belief that the syllogism—a discovery of which he was proud—is
the structure common to all reasoning, and he tries to force the processes of
scientific enquiry into this mould. The perfect syllogism, to which other
‘figures’ are to be reduced, is the figure with a universal affirmative
conclusion. It is assumed that every proposition in a syllogism contains the
subject-predicate relation, and the predicate in one premiss must be a term
which can stand as subject in the other. An account of the process of reasoning
which is subject to these limitations is necessarily incomplete and distorted.
Further, when
the subject of inquiry is the cause of a class of events (such as eclipses of
the moon), Aristotle tries to reduce this to an inquiry for the definition of
an attribute. An eclipse is regarded as an attribute of the moon, and the ‘cause’ (the interposition of the earth) becomes the middle
term of a syllogism: ‘Loses its light’ is always true of a body which has
another body between it and its source of light; being such a body is true of
the eclipsed moon; therefore ‘loses its light’ is true of the eclipsed moon.
This can be recast into the definition: Eclipse of the moon is loss of light
due to the earth’s interposition. Aristotle did not, however, imagine that the
causes of events could be discovered by demonstration. The discovery of the
‘middle term’ stating the cause is made, after a number of experiences of the
fact, by an ‘instantaneous guess’ of intuition. He admits that the syllogistic
statement does not even prove that the cause we have guessed is the true cause.
What lies behind these logical contortions is the conviction that the ‘cause’ of a thing or of an event is to be found in its
essential nature or Form. Aristotle holds true to the tradition that the aim of
science is, not to establish laws of succession among phenomena, but to
discover the ‘nature of things.’ Hence the relation of cause and effect is
replaced by the notions of Form and Matter, or actuality and potentiality. An
effect is a potentiality actualized by its cause, or ‘Matter’ of a certain kind
determined by a certain Form. The Matter individualizes the Form, which in
itself is universal.
The method of
definition by genus and specific difference implies the acceptance of Plato’s
hierarchy of Forms, extending upwards from the indivisible species, through
intermediate kinds, to highest genera, which must be simple and indefinable.
The genus and intermediate kinds are less determinate than the lowest species,
and so related to it as ‘Matter’; every difference adds an element of Form.
Accordingly, as we move upward towards the highest genera, we are not, as Plato
supposed, approaching the ultimate cause of all existence, but receding ever
further from the primary reality of the concrete thing. The highest genera
appear to be identical with the ‘categories’ which figure everywhere in
Aristotle’s works, but are nowhere formally deduced. The authenticity of the
treatise called Categories is disputed. It contains the famous list of ten;
substance, quality, quantity, relation, place, date, position, state, action,
passivity—apparently an inventory of the ultimate classes of things that are
meant by words. They are the terms arrived at when we push the question, what a namable thing is, to the last point. But they stand
at the farthest remove from the reality of the individual substance. To find
anything that can rank as a higher kind of reality, we must look in another
direction. There we find certain Forms which are declared to be without Matter,
though they are all individuals. They are: the active Reason in man, which has
no bodily organ, but is eternal and immortal or ‘divine,’ and enters the body
‘from without’; the Intelligences which move the spheres; and God, the Prime
Mover. The divinity of the active Reason is a dogma inherited from Plato and
earlier religious thought. The Intelligences and God are required to explain
the motion of the universe. The First Heaven is moved directly by God; the
other spheres, having different motions, are moved by subordinate immaterial
Intelligences.
VIII.
COSMOLOGY
Aristotle’s
universe is a system of concentric spheres, with the earth at rest in the
centre, and at the outside the ‘First Heaven’ of the fixed stars. The
mathematical spheres, imagined by Eudoxus and Callippus to account for the apparent motions of the sun
and moon and the five known planets, were converted by Aristotle into a
mechanism of actual rotating spheres, each moving by contact the sphere next
inside it. The number of spheres down to the moon was raised to 55. The
heavenly bodies consist of a fifth element, incapable of any change except
circular motion.
The existence
of God is deduced from the eternity of the world and of motion. It is
necessary, and sufficient, to suppose one eternal source of motion; but this
cannot be itself moved. Already in the treatise Concerning Philosophy,
Aristotle had declared God to be incapable of change; he is not a soul, or a
creator, or even conscious of the world’s existence; the activity in which his
life consists can be nothing but intuitive contemplation, without any element
of desire or action. He is without parts or magnitude; and although in one place
he is said to be outside the universe, he cannot really be in space. He can
cause motion only as the final cause, or object of desire, which moves without
itself being moved. The subject of this desire must presumably be the soul
animating the body of the First Heaven; but the operation of the Intelligences
is left in obscurity. Aristotle’s God thus holds a position like that of the
Good in the Republic, and his efficacy is still illicitly imagined not
merely as a source of mechanical motion propagated throughout the spheres, but
also as an attraction to which life responds with its mysterious impulse to
rise from the potentiality of Matter to the actuality of Form. The tendency to
think in this way appears where personified Nature is represented as striving
towards perfection. But, as we have seen, the system admits no soul in Nature
that might be the seat of such desire. Aristotle’s mind is still haunted by the
Platonic doctrines of the Good and of Eros; but his God is the object of a
desire for which he provides no subject.
A striking
feature of the cosmology is the distinction between the celestial region and
the sublunary, to which all becoming and all change, other than rotatory
locomotion, are confined. Here are the four elements, which, as natural objects,
‘contain within themselves sources of motion,’ manifest in their tendency to
move towards their natural places in four spheres—a notion which goes back to
Anaximander. Each element contains two of the primary qualities (hot, dry,
cold, fluid), whose interaction explains the transformation of the elements
into one another and the production of intermediate natures by combination. The
elements are the material cause of the generation of substances. The efficient
cause, as we have seen, resides in the specific Forms; but the alternation of
birth and growth, decay and death, in the life of individual creatures is due
to the rhythmical approach and retreat of the sun in its annual course, causing
transformation of the elements and the seasonal alternations of heat and cold,
drought and rain. The Meteorologica contains a
further study of the combinations and mutual influences of the four elements,
and deals with the ‘meteoric’ phenomena of the sublunary region.
IX.
BIOLOGY
AND PSYCHOLOGY
Biology is
the department of science in which Aristotle’s characteristic concepts are most
at home, and the treatises on natural history are still admired by those men of
science who are aware that they exist. They contain a large collection of
observations of the structure and habits of some five hundred animal species.
The theory of classification is carried to a point beyond which, it is said, no
advance was made before Linnaeus. The principle observed in explaining organic
Nature is teleological, in the sense that the process by which an organism and
its parts come into being is to be explained by the Form of the perfect
creature—‘becoming is for the sake of being’—and the Form itself by its
function or ‘activity.’ The phenomena cannot be accounted for by the casual play
of mechanical causes, though these may suffice to produce some characters which
are not essential. This teleology has, however, no firm metaphysical basis; it
is an inverted mechanism, which cannot show how the end is to cause the
beginning.
Natural history
culminates in Psychology, for this science has for its object the specific
Form, the vehicle of life. What has so far been studied morphologically as the
structure characteristic of a species is now seen as the living essence
embodied in the individual, informing its material parts. It is nothing else
than the soul, which is related to an organic body of a certain constitution as
Form to Matter. Thus soul and body are two inseparable aspects of one thing,
and soul is defined as ‘the first entelechy (or actuality) of a natural organic
body,’ the second, or further, actuality being the activities it displays in
waking life. This interesting view of the relation of soul to body avoids the
difficulties that arise when soul and body, or mind and matter, are conceived
as entities of different orders, whose interaction has to be accounted for. All
psychic phenomena which occur in plants and animals generally are not merely
accompanied by physiological changes; they are the formal aspects of these
material processes. Anger, for example, is on the physical side, a boiling of
the blood; on the mental, a desire for retaliation. The mental aspect gives
this phenomenon the Form of anger, which distinguishes the physical change from
boiling that might be mechanically produced by the application of heat. Neither
aspect can strictly be called, in the modern sense, the cause or the effect of
the other; each is a ‘cause’ in the Aristotelian
sense, the one formal, the other material. The psychologist, in defining anger,
must mention both.
From this
definition of soul it follows that no individual soul can exist apart from the
body it informs from the moment of generation to the moment of death. On the
other hand, the human soul contains an element, the active Reason, which is
declared to be pure Form with no bodily organ, and to exist eternally. This is
none other than that ‘true self’ which Socrates had believed in and Plato had
held to be the rational part of the soul, whose impersonal memory contains all
knowledge of reality. In Aristotle, as in Plato, it is immortal or ‘divine,’
and includes no element of personality, such as distinguishes one individual
from another. More than once in the Ethics Aristotle explicitly calls it the
‘self.’
As life rises
in the scale of Nature, one layer of soul is superimposed on another. The
lowest form of life, in the plant world, consists of the faculties of nutrition
and reproduction. To this is added in animals the sentient life, including
sensation and perception, feelings of pleasure and pain, desire and consequent
movement, and at least some rudimentary emotions. On the physiological side
sense-perception involves the assimilation of the organ to the objectively
existing qualities perceived; this reception of the Form without the Matter’
has its mental aspect in the awareness of the quality. Imagination (phantasia) is the faculty which preserves images of
former objects of perception, on which depends memory—the complex act of
recognizing an image as the image of some past object. Imagination is also
active in free imagery and in dreams.
In addition
to these animal faculties, man has Reason, making him capable of thought and
moral action. This faculty, though it can exist and exercise its activity of
pure contemplation apart from the mortal soul, combines with the soul during
life in such a way that its activity penetrates the lower functions. Even on
the level of perception, while the senses receive only the Form of the sensible
qualities, Reason, by its peculiar power of intuition, apprehends the essential
nature of the individual. It thus receives the ‘intelligible Form’ of the
indivisible species, in an immediate act occupying an undivided time. Again, we
are told that the Reason ‘thinks the Forms in the images’ which, Aristotle
holds, are present to the mind in all thinking. The Reason has thus the same
function as in Plato: it is the power which apprehends the primary realities.
Aristotle finally draws his distinction of Form and Matter, actual and
potential, within the Reason itself: there is an active Reason and a passive.
Some of his expressions suggest that, like Plato’s rational part with its
impersonal memory, the active Reason is always in possession of all truth,
which it recovers by an act of recognition. In the process of gaining
knowledge, potential knowledge is raised to actuality. This seems like a
translation into Aristotelian terms of Plato’s theory of reminiscence.
Aristotle, however, is embarrassed by his conviction that the objects of
knowledge exist in the physical world, so that the intelligible Forms must pass
into the soul through the channel of sense-perception and imagination, and be
received from that quarter by the ‘passive Reason.’ The obscurity of this part
of his psychology is, perhaps, due to his having to combine this doctrine with
a conception of Reason and knowledge that was more like Plato’s than he cared
to admit.
X.
ETHICS
AND POLITICS
Aristotle’s
theory of Ethics is dictated, no less than other parts of his philosophy, by
his central doctrine of the specific Form. The first object of ethical inquiry
is to discover the good or final cause of man’s existence. It is a foregone
conclusion that this will be found among the activities of man’s specific Form
or essential nature, which the Psychology has identified with his soul. The
‘good for man’ or happiness (as all agree to call it) must be some activity of
soul, in which his peculiar nature finds its fullest realization. Every other
species has a corresponding ‘good’; but man’s business is to realize his own
nature. The moralist, however, cannot admit that all activities of life are
good in themselves or ethical ends. Aristotle’s only discussion of the meaning
of ‘good’ is confused and contradictory;
but he recognizes that some things are good in themselves and such as ought to
be desired, whether they are desired or not. He further holds, with Socrates
and Plato, that the divine Reason or ‘ true self’ has the power to discern what
is really good, and always ‘wishes’ for it; its judgment is the only guide and
is infallible. Happiness, then, must consist in activities recognized by this
faculty as good in themselves. Aristotle describes such activities as those
which are ‘in accordance with virtue (goodness)’ adding (without justification)
‘or, if there be several virtues, in accordance with the best and most
perfect.’ But since the goodness or excellence of anything is that condition
which enables it to perform its function well, virtue may equally well be
defined in terms of good activities; it is a state of the soul from which good
activities result, and analogous to bodily health.
Man’s nature
is complicated by the presence in his soul of the divine Reason—the part which
‘possesses a rational principle (or rule)’, by virtue of its power of directly
and infallibly perceiving what is good and ‘wishing’ it. In moral conduct, good
or bad—an activity peculiar to man, since neither God nor the lower animals are
capable of it—the operation of Reason is combined with the instinctive
mechanism of action, namely the group of faculties we share with animals;
sensation, perception, feelings of pleasure and pain, and the consequent
desires and motions. The desires of this part, when left to itself, have for
their object pleasure, or ‘what appears good’; having no rational principle,
this part cannot tell good pleasures from bad. In man, however, the lower
faculties are interpenetrated by Reason, and hence this part is amenable to
Reason. In the perfect character the harmony is complete; but there are less
perfect types, in whom a conflict of the higher and lower motives still occurs;
according as the higher or the lower usually prevails, they are called
‘continent’ or ‘incontinent.’ In perfect vice, the battle has been finally won
by the lower nature.
Moral Virtue
is acquired by habituation. Children are still irrational, and conduct judged
to be right by their rational elders is imposed upon them from without. As the
habit of acting in certain ways is established and the Reason develops, the
conduct becomes virtuous in the full sense: besides acting from a fully formed
habit, the agent is then aware of the nature of good action and acts from his
own deliberate choice. He is now governed by the rational principle within
himself. The ends of action are intuitively determined by the Reason, and
Aristotle speaks as if this process involved no deliberation about the relative
values of alternative ends. Deliberation is only the process of thinking out
the chain of means which will lead to an end, and the object of ‘choice’ is the
first link in this chain—an act we can at once perform. Choice thus involves a
decision reached by deliberation, affirmed by desire, and issuing in
corresponding action. Upon the question of free will Aristotle makes no clear
pronouncement.
The famous
doctrine that Virtue is a mean state between two vices, of excess and defect,
is derived from the medical analogy of health, as a balanced or ‘proportional’
mixture of contrary physical qualities, which may be upset by extremes of heat
or cold, dryness or moisture, etc. This was itself an application of the
Pythagorean view of ‘goodness’ as due to the imposition of Limit on an
Unlimited. In moral Virtue the ‘unlimited’ factor is emotion, the affective
phase of the instinctive mechanism. Emotion is held to vary in degrees of
intensity; physiologically, it actually is a change in the amount of a quality
in the direction of one or the other extreme. The habit which is Virtue or Vice
is, from this standpoint, a certain range, somewhere in the scale, which
determines the intensity of emotional reaction. If it is fixed too high or too
low, the reaction will habitually be too intense or not intense enough. The
mean state, which will be ‘relative to us’ (i.e. vary somewhat with differences
of temperament), is Virtue. There are obvious objections to this theory; but
the doctrine of the mean has attracted more attention than it deserves; and
Aristotle himself recognizes that quantitative differences of emotion are only
one factor in the determination of right conduct. We must feel and act ‘on the
right grounds, at the right time, towards the right persons, for the right
end.’ Under all these heads the Reason of the virtuous man is the sole and
infallible judge of what the occasion demands.
After a long
analysis of the particular moral virtues, Aristotle passes to the intellectual
virtues of the rational part. They fall under two main heads: theoretical and
practical wisdom. The first includes scientific knowledge of necessary truth,
the intuition of first principles and demonstration. The highest form of
activity is, not discursive reasoning or the discovery of truth, but the
contemplation of truth already possessed—the only activity possible to God or
to the disembodied Reason. The life of the philosopher has foretastes of this
mode of consciousness, which possesses every attribute of felicity and answers
to the definition of happiness as the activity of the soul in accordance with
the best and most perfect of virtues. It is, however, a divine, rather than a human,
activity, for the animal part of our nature has no share in it. Accordingly,
the ‘good’ or happiness of man as a composite being lies in the other mode of
activity peculiar to man, moral action. This involves the lower intellectual
virtue of practical wisdom, exercised by Reason in its control over the
instinctive nature. Though Aristotle quarrels with the statement of Socrates’
doctrine, ‘Virtue is knowledge (or wisdom),’ he accepts it in substance; for he
declares that all the moral virtues are one, and that they cannot exist apart
from practical wisdom, nor practical wisdom apart from them.
The Nicomachean
Ethics opens with a picture of. human activity portioned out into the
several ‘arts’, each with its end. Some of these ends are only means to the
ends of higher arts; at the head of all is the art of Statesmanship (Politics),
with its ultimate end, human happiness. Thus Aristotle inherits Plato’s view of
Statesmanship as the sovereign art, controlling all the other branches of human
activity by virtue of its knowledge of good and evil. Ethics, which defines the
supreme end and indicates the way to attain it, is ‘in a sense’ this very
science or art; and the treatise on Politics, or the study of man in
society, follows immediately. It consists of a collection of writings which
were never welded into a consecutive whole. The earliest stratum may be the
theory of the Ideal State, since this is closer to Platonic tradition; the later
parts are enriched by the industry of Aristotle and his School in compiling
studies of 158 Greek constitutions. The Constitution of Athens alone
survives. The political doctrine is discussed elsewhere.
The three
books on Rhetoric and the fragment of the Poetics complete the Aristotelian
corpus.
XI. THE
PERIPATETIC SCHOOL AT ATHENS
Soon after
the accession of Alexander (336 BC), Aristotle, now fifty years old, returned
to Athens. At the Academy Xenocrates had succeeded Speusippus in 339. Aristotle rented some buildings just
outside the city in the grove of Apollo Lyceus and
founded a rival school. The name ‘Peripatetic’ was derived from the walks (peripatoi), where the master discussed philosophy
with his students. A large library was collected, with maps and a museum of
objects to illustrate the lectures. Aristotle discoursed on the more abstruse
subjects in the morning, and delivered popular courses to a wider public in the
afternoon. He was also engaged in revising and adding to the writings of the previous
period, and in organizing research. He ranks as the creator of a new kind of
science of observation and description, amassing collections of facts of human
and natural history, descriptions of animals, plants and minerals, materials
for chronology in lists of the victors at the Pythian games and the Athenian
Dionysia, the studies of 158 Constitutions, and innumerable smaller monographs.
The first history of science was compiled by Theophrastus, Eudemus of Rhodes, and Meno, who respectively undertook physics and metaphysics,
mathematics, and medicine.
A passage
from the introduction to The Parts of Animals, shows that young men
accustomed to the discussion of abstract ideas and formal rhetoric were not
easily induced to study the anatomy of worms and insects.
“It remains
to treat of the nature of living creatures, omitting nothing (so far as
possible), whether of higher or of lower dignity. For even in the case of
creatures, the contemplation of which is disagreeable to the sense, Nature, who
fashioned them, nevertheless affords an extraordinary pleasure to anyone with a
philosophic disposition, capable of understanding causes. We take delight in
looking at representations of these things, because we observe at the same time
the art of the painter or sculptor which created them; and it would be strange
and unreasonable that the contemplation of the works of Nature themselves
should not yield a still greater satisfaction, when we can make out their
causes. Accordingly, the consideration of the lowlier forms of life ought not
to excite a childish repugnance. In all natural things there is something to
move wonder. There is a story that, when some strangers who wished to meet Heracleitus stopped short on finding him warming himself at
the kitchen stove, he told them to come boldly in, for there also there were
gods. In the same spirit we should approach the study of every form of life
without disgust, knowing that in every one there is something of nature and of
beauty. For it is in the works of Nature above all that design, in contrast
with random chance, is manifest; and the perfect form which anything, born or
made, is designed to realize holds the rank of beauty”.
This manifold
activity was cut short by an outbreak of antiMacedonian feeling at Athens upon the death of Alexander in 323 BC. The conqueror’s former
tutor was assailed with the usual charge of impiety and withdrew to the home of
his mother’s family at Chalcis, leaving the school to the charge of
Theophrastus. Aristotle may have hoped to complete his life’s work by a final
revision of his writings; but in the next year he died, at the age of 63. After
the death of Theophrastus the intellectual supremacy passed from the Academy
and the Lyceum to Alexandria.
Aristotle’s
best work was done in the fields of Biology and Ethics, where teleology is more
illuminating than mechanism. Our brief review of his system has shown how it
revolves round the doctrine, inherited from Plato, of the specific Form of the
natural kind. In this context his apparatus of concepts possesses its full
meaning. The farther he moves from this central point, the less appropriate the
concepts become. When he passes below the level of the living organism to
penetrate the constitution of the inorganic, the notions of Form and Matter, the
actual and the potential, are strained till they trail off into verbal
distinctions, all but meaningless save for illicit associations with their
proper use. His work is inferior to that of the Atomists, whose strength lay
precisely here, while their weakness was that they levelled down the phenomena
of life to the plane of the inanimate. Again, when he passes upward from the
sublunary sphere of living Nature to the celestial region, the Intelligences,
and the first source of motion, he becomes a doctrinaire, ready to prove a
priori that there cannot be more than one world or five elements, or that
the earth must be at rest in the centre of the universe. Several causes
combined to hold him back from reaching the standpoint of modern science. For
better or worse, he could never shake free from the commanding influence of
Plato, though in later life his natural inclination towards the study of
empirical fact carried him ever farther from the Academy. He had, moreover, an
exaggerated respect for tradition, founded on the notion that fragments of
ancient wisdom had survived the cataclysms which destroyed civilization from
time to time, and were embedded in proverbial thought or in the sayings of the
older sages. Finally, he inherited the Pythagorean and Academic tendency to see
the pattern of all science in mathematics and to believe that the divine
faculty of Reason can, with unerring intuition, ascertain the premisses of all
knowledge and deduce the whole structure of reality. This faith in the
infallibility of the soul, when she ‘withdraws to think by herself,’ was to
cost the scientific world many centuries of illusion and disillusionment.
ALEXANDER:
THE CONQUEST OF PERSIA
|