. |
DECLINE OF EMPIRE AND PAPACYCHAPTER XXIII.MEDIEVAL ESTATES
The
word “feudalism” is little more than a rough generalisation or formula under
which we try to include such conditions, economic, social, and governmental, as
are found to be common and uniform throughout the lands and peoples which were
once parts of the Western Roman Empire, in that obscure period of rapid change
between the dismembering of the Carolingian Empire and the growth of national
States.
In
a period so long as this, when conditions were changing so rapidly, it is
inevitable that many conflicting elements, forces, and tendencies should be
found together at every stage of the development, and still greater differences
between different historical stages of the growth even of a single common
institution or idea.
It
is fortunately not within the scope of this chapter to discuss the vexed and
disputed questions of the origin of these varying elements or of their relative
importance. From the establishment of the Frankish Empire a development may be
clearly traced which in time superseded the regime of the personality of law
resulting from the “wandering of the peoples”, and substituted for it the
restored Roman idea of territoriality; and later, when the cohesive force of
the Frankish Empire became weakened and that Empire again fell in pieces, these
pieces retained the main characteristic they had acquired under their Frankish
rulers, the principle of territoriality. The primitive Germanic conception of
law as tribal custom was by no means obliterated, but it was now the law of
peoples who had settled homes and determinate geographical boundaries, whose
jurisdiction was complete over all the inhabitants within those boundaries, of
whatever race, and limited only by those boundaries themselves. It was a period
of the complete territoriality of law, in the absence more or less complete of
all coercive central authority, a regime when small territories, each
practically independent of all the rest and of all central authority, and each
with its own customary law binding upon all within its boundaries, were the
rule; and for a time the process of subdivision was making these little
territorial units ever more numerous and more minute.
When
this process of subdivision reached its limit, and the counter-process began of
the gradual accretion of fiefs which was ultimately to develop into the great
national States of Western Europe, the course and direction of that development
were determined by the institutions and ideas which had become established
within the scattered territorial units from which the later States were ultimately
formed. Prominent among these institutions and ideas was that of law as the
custom of the people within a territory, the more utentium,
a ius non scriptum whose beginning was
beyond memory and whose transmission was by oral tradition. Since the law was the
usage of the people, it was the people alone who could know it. Hence, when
concrete cases arose requiring the application of the law, it was the people of
the district alone who could “find” it, and this became one of the chief
functions of the “courts” of the district. As Gneist points out, however, it was an equally marked characteristic of all these
assemblies or courts that there was in them no differentiation of functions,
such as we know in modern times, and no conscious distinction between finding a
law in general and administering it in an individual case. No doubt these
general duties had been performed in earlier times by all, or at least by all
who were regarded as qualified. But later there was a tendency everywhere to
restrict these duties to a smaller number, as in the scabini on the Continent, or the reeve, the priest, and the four men from each
township, as mentioned in English documents of the reign of Henry I. The
finding and the administering of law alike were then both communal and territorial,
and a survey of European procedure at this time shews how widely it differed
from the Roman procedure with its normal trial by a single index. This
difference is of fundamental importance and lies at the very roots of modem
constitutionalism. The Roman index was a real judge in our modem sense, even
though he was guided by the formula of a magistrate in his decision. He weighed
both sides of the case, and pronounced a real judgment upon the weight of the
evidence. The whole rationale of the judicial system of Western Europe in the
feudal period was strikingly different. In imitation of Rome, the suitors who
administered these courts might be called indices, as they are, for example, in
the Leges Henrici Primi, in the case of
England, early in the twelfth century; but their functions are in reality
markedly different. They weigh no evidence, for properly speaking there is no
evidence. They reach no judgment, for there is no place for any judgment. They
merely “award the proof”. Judicial discretion and a rational system of weighing
evidence are the marks of the matured judicial procedure of the Roman Empire,
and judicial discretion may be exercised by a single iudex as well as by a number, if not better. But the cruder law of the feudal age
knew no discretion, and very little rationalism. If ever there was “a government
of laws and not of men,” it was at that time. It was a formal, rigid, one-sided
procedure. Nothing was left to the discretion of any human judge, as is
immediately disclosed by an inspection of the tariffs of compositions in such a
“code” as the Lex Frisionum, or of the
mechanical list of formal essonia, or lawful
excuses for non-appearance at court, even as late as Bracton’s time. It was not the business of the members of these medieval courts to give a
judgment. It was not their discretion that was wanted; it was their knowledge,
the knowledge of the unwritten law of the district of which they alone were
possessed, or the acquaintance with the local reputation of an accused man,
which might affect the award of proof. That proof once awarded, whether it was
a trial by reputation, as in compurgation, or some form of the Indicium Dei, as
the ordeal or duel, the rest was mechanical. If the accused succeeded, he was
free; if not, he was guilty. There was an equal lack of discretion whether the
trial was civil or criminal, as we should say. Trial by witnesses, when
possible, was not, as now, the admission of witnesses to inform an impartial
arbiter; it was merely the introduction of persons who had been officially
present as formal witnesses when the original transaction took place. And their
introduction was as final and decisive as the result of an ordeal or of trial
by battle. Such witnesses swore only a formal oath. They were never sworn to
tell the truth on their consciences. They appeared to swear with the defendant.
They could not possibly be introduced to swear against him
In
this system the duties of the presiding officer were as mechanical as those of
the members of the court over whom he kept order, and whose findings he
pronounced. Not till a comparatively late period did he begin to acquire,
mainly, I think, by delegation from the king, a discretionary power, which in
time gradually developed into that of the Roman index or the modern judge.
The
judicial work of these medieval courts was performed by the members of the
community, or by a selected portion of them “representing” the community and
necessarily fairly large in numbers. Had their duties required discretion, one
“judge” might have been enough, but since instead they required knowledge—a knowledge
of the customs and of the people of the district—a considerable number became
necessary, and these had to be “representative” in the sense that they would be
persons of the district who knew their neighbours and were acquainted with the
customary law in force there from time immemorial, more utentium;
an acquaintance, as Glanville says of the Grand Assize in England in the
twelfth century, which they have gained from what they themselves have seen and
heard, “vel per verba patrum suorum et per talia quibus fidem teneantur habere in propriis.”
The
point is that the general business of these undifferentiated “courts” was
everywhere such that it could be carried on only by those acquainted with the
men and the customs of the country. Thus it was that when the inquisitio or inquest was in time introduced among
the older forms, at the instance of the king in England, it retained the old
communal basis. It still required, like the older procedure to which it was in
many respects closely akin, knowledge rather than judgment, and a knowledge
which could not safely be got from one but only from many. Though the true
jury, when it came, came from above and not below, as Maitland shews, and
though it implied an answer on oath to a question which unlike the older procedure
might be either Yes or No, still it was, as its name implies, like its communal
predecessors, a trial per patriam, per pais, by “the countryside.”
The
striking contrast between all these pieces of medieval judicial machinery and
the iudex of Rome lies in the fact that it was
knowledge, not judgment, that a medieval court wanted; and that knowledge of
the things needed for a decision required a considerable number of neighbours,
while judgment may be safely exacted from a single individual regardless of his
knowledge. Thus medieval procedure was based on a knowledge of the community by
the community, and this could safely be found only from that community. When
the practice arose of drawing this knowledge from a number selected from this
community pro omnibus, the earliest foundations of modern representative
institutions were laid. The great fact is that the procedure of the Middle Ages
required a fairly considerable number of “representatives” of the community to
make it really effective, under the ideas of law and of proof as they existed
at that time.
Early
in the eighth century the Lombard laws furnish an interesting illustration of
these Germanic ideas of fixed customary law and of the struggle for the mastery
between them and the Roman conception of the arbitrament of the iudex. Among the Lombards,
it is recited in the laws— “alii per consuitutinem,
alii per arbitrium iudicare aestimabant”;
and the resulting uncertainty was so great that it was found necessary to call
together the iudices et fideles in the fourteenth year of King Liutprand, “ut nullus error esse deberet, sed omnibus manifesta clariscere lex.” The Lombards, of course, were far in advance of
most Germanic nations in their legal development at this time.
These
general characteristics of medieval procedure are to be found in all parts of
Western Europe at this time and in all kinds of courts, feudal, seignorial,
communal, or royal. In some places the development of feudalism tended at times
to turn communal courts into seignorial ones, and often also to shift the
burden of attendance at the court from the community as a whole upon the
tenants of definite pieces of land within it. But, in any case, that burden of
suit remained, and in all the courts of whatever kind the procedure continued
to be one requiring the concerted action of a considerable number of the men of
the neighbourhood. Thus whether it was the custom of the manor or the feudal
law of the fief that was to be found, that law would be ascertained from a
sufficient number of men of the district who knew it.
Locally
this required, in the court of the district, “representatives” from the
community if they were not all present in person. The presence of these
representatives in early times does not, of course, imply their “election” in
our modern sense. Till a comparatively late date we know little of how they
were chosen, but it is as likely, if not more likely, that they were appointed
as that they were “elected”. Eligere is an
elastic word in medieval documents, from which too much should not be inferred.
Furthermore, these representatives of the community were chosen—however they
were chosen—to perform a duty, to acquit their community of a burden. It was no
privilege they enjoyed. Sometimes, indeed, this has been compared to modern
representative institutions, and it has something in common with them. But this
representing of the community was not then an honour. If it must be compared
with something modern to which it has little practical resemblance, it would be
fitter to compare it with our jury service than with membership in a modern legislative
body. Nevertheless, burden though it was, it contained and it continued the
practice, and even the theory, that lies at the roots of modern representative
institutions—not the practice alone, but the theory as well. A proof of this
exists in the wording of English official documents of the eleventh and early
twelfth centuries. We know absolutely that at that time, in both the hundred
and the county court, each township was “represented” by six persons at most.
Yet, for both hundred and hundred court, there was used but one word, the word hundredus: while in like fashion a single word,
comitatus, had to do duty alike for the shire and the shire court. In short,
the hundredus was both the hundred and the
hundred court— they were theoretically the same, though in actual fact widely
different; and the comitatus meant equally the county and the county court,
though but a small proportion of the whole county actually attended that court.
Theoretically the county and the county court were the same. Actually they were
not. The fiction of “representation” alone can explain this identity. There
must have been in existence some theory of representation as well as the fact.
Possibly
an even clearer indication of this may be seen in the statement made by the author
of the Leges Henrici Primi written in the
reign of Henry I of England. After a statement that a lord or his steward who
has a right to do so may acquit the lord’s demesne lands in the hundred of the suit in the hundred court due from them, he
goes on to say that if the lord or his steward is unable to be present, then
“prepositus et sacerdos et IIII de melioribus ville assint pro omnibus qui nominatim non erunt ad placitum submoniti.”
England.
When
the courts began in England to feel the strong hand of the Norman kings and the
process of administrative centralisation started, these germs of
representation, instead of dying out, developed a stronger growth. The
documents of this period prove that the kings retained the old communal courts
of the hundred and shire of set purpose. They also began the process of
unifying them, chiefly through the activity of the royally appointed sheriff
and later through the justices in eyre. With the
growth of the eyre system and largely through the
increasing practice of drawing cases by royal writ from other courts to the
King’s Court, it became increasingly necessary that these royal courts should
be certified of the proceedings already taken in the other courts from which
the cases were drawn away. The King’s Courts required a bringing up of the
“record” from the court, whether manorial or communal, in which the case had
begun. In the days before the proceedings of these courts were written, this
“record” was only in the minds of the men of the court, not in writing. Hence
the “bringing up of the record” was the bringing up of a man or men, not of a
written document.
So
section 4 of Henry II’s Assize of Clarendon, in 1166, prescribes that when the
sheriff brings violators of the assize before the itinerant justices for trial,
he shall bring along with them “from the hundred and the township where they
were arrested ‘duos legales homines ad portandum recordationem comitatus et hundredi,
quare capti fuerint’.”
Professor G. B. Adams has pointed out a number of cases of the same practice in Bracton’s Note Book, one in 1226 where four discreet
knights of the county and four of the king’s servientes were to come “ad certificandum Dominum Regem”; another in 1219 when the sheriff is directed
to have before the royal justices the record “per quatuor milites de comitatu qui recordo illi interfuerunt”;
another in 1220 when the knights are said to speak pro comitatu;
one in 1230 where three knights are said to come pro toto comitatu;
and several more. The number might easily be increased. “Here,” says Professor
Adams, “was certainly a direct line of connexion between the county court and
the king’s council, already established and in frequent use.” He sees in the
first recorded appearance of the knights of the shire in parliament, in 1254, a
repetition of this procedure in matters of parliamentary grant instead of in a
trial, and he finds in these earlier judicial practices the precedent and the
justification for the extra-feudal practice initiated in 1254 of summoning the
representative knights as well as the tenants-in-chief to a parliament. This
acute suggestion of Professor Adams, a suggestion amply supported by
contemporary records, really enables us to trace a continuous development of
the practice and the theory of representation in England from the end of the
Anglo-Saxon period through the fundamental reforms of William I, Henry I, and
Henry II, by which the royal administration was unified and extended, down to
the period of the appearance of the first surviving record of a summons of
representative knights of the shire to parliament in 1254. It is a matter of
the greatest consequence.
This
development, however, seems not to have been confined to the representative knights.
It appears, though considerably later and much less clearly, in the
representation of burgesses as well, long before the time of the Earl of
Leicester’s parliament of 1265, when we have the first record of the appearance
of representative burgesses in a parliament for the whole realm. In section 12
of John’s charter, after the promise that scutage and extraordinary aids should
be imposed only with the common assent of the realm, provision is made that in
case of aids from the city of London the procedure shall be simili modo. From the time of Sir Henry Spelman to the present, the meaning of simili modo has been an enigma. Spelman
himself seemed to think the words implied representation in the king’s Curia,
and was therefore surprised to find no appearance of any burgesses in the
records of the years following I215. Professor Adams, on the other hand,
believes that these words indicated merely that London and London alone of all
English towns had a commune, and therefore an independent feudal status which
placed it on a par feudally with the tenants-in-chief already mentioned in this
section of the document, and that this of course implies the necessity of
consent to aids, but apparently not necessarily any representative from the
city in any Curia where the collective consent of the tenants-in-chief was
obtained.
However
this may be, the fact is that there is no surviving record of the presence of
these borough representatives before the parliament of Simon de Montfort in
1265. But as in the case of the representative knights, there is a long local
history behind this first known appearance of burgesses in a central assembly.
For example, in 1231 the sheriff of Yorkshire is directed by writ to present
before the justices itinerant on their coming into the county, not only the
nobility and higher clergy, the knights and the free tenants of the county, but
twelve legal burgesses from each borough and all others “who usually are and
ought to be” there, to assist in the trial of the pleas of the Crown and others.
Cases might be multiplied, and it is clear that the words of Stubbs applied to
the knights of the shire are almost equally applicable to the townsmen as well:
“a consolidated body of men trained by a century and a half of common interests
and common work.”
In
recent years a tendency has appeared in certain quarters to criticise the
masterly account of these developments by Bishop Stubbs, on the ground that he
understates the importance of the clergy in shaping their course and attaches
“too much weight in comparison to the old communal institutions of England,
such as the attendance of the four men and the reeve at hundred and shire
court, and to the influence of the judicial procedure of Henry II.” The
reductio ad absurdum of Professor Barker’s temperate thesis on this subject is
found in a recent American study of representative government where it is
baldly declared that: “The Church originated representative institutions; the
State adopted them”. To make such a declaration one must either be totally ignorant
of the meaning and significance of the striking and continuous series of
evidences of representative ideas and institutions running back to the very
Conquest in England and even beyond, or he must consider himself able to
explain them as not really representative in character. One way of doing the
latter is to attempt, as Dr Barker does, to distinguish between the mere representation
“to give information” (ad recognoscendum) in the
earlier English instances and the true representation “to take action” (ad
faciendum), supposed to occur only at a later period and as the result of
clerical ideas and institutions.
But
against this view several serious objections may be urged. It implies a
distinction between central and local institutions which is too sharp and too
modern; it depends upon a sharp cleavage between the ideas of representation
for information and representation for action, for which there is little
contemporary evidence in the thirteenth century and before; and it is greatly
weakened by the fact that there were no Dominicans in England before 1221, yet
it is to the Dominicans that the institutions of representation are mainly
attributed. It is true enough, as has been urged in support of this view, that
our earliest surviving official record of the idea of representation on
anything like a national scale, the writ of King John in 1213 for the return of
“four discreet knights” from the counties of England, probably had no practical
result, since we have no record of their actual meeting; but the writ itself
nevertheless is evidence of the existence of the idea in 1213, some years
before the development of the Dominican constitution or its transfer to
England; and it is noteworthy that the four discreet knights were summoned not
merely ad recognoscendum, but ad loquendum nobiscum de negotiis regni nostri. In
local matters it is equally impossible to distinguish clearly between
information and action in numberless cases, and the distinction between the
local occurrence of representation and its use in a national assembly is one
that strikes us as it does only because we know its later developments; to
contemporaries it was insignificant and unimportant. The contemporary
chroniclers give no attention whatever to the first English case of borough representation
which we consider so epoch-making. To them it was only a slight modification of
ideas and practices long familiar to them in the county court. Knights and
burgesses had been co-operating for generations with the iusticiarii on their circuits throughout the counties of England, and these iusticiarii were in fact, if not in theory, members
of the king’s central Curia. The clergy no doubt contributed a large part of
the later development of representation; truly to assert that they “originated”
it is impossible in face of the overwhelming evidence to the contrary.
In
1254 in England, for the first time so far as we have evidence surviving, these
local practices and ideas were incorporated in the national assembly or Curia,
and in order to understand the working of the “estates” that resulted, a brief
review of the earlier history of the Curia itself is necessary.
Though
in an earlier period the English national assembly—and the local assemblies as
well—had in all probability been a real folc mote in the same sense and of much the same kind as the meetings of the warriors
of the civitas or tribe as described in the Germania of Tacitus, long before
the Norman Conquest it had turned into a select body of comparatively few
magnates, elders, or sapientes, a witenagemot,
in which the “wisdom” which constituted the supposed qualification for
membership was coming more and more to consist in royal favour and wide
estates. This body survived the Conquest and is frequently referred to in the
gradually expiring “Anglo-Saxon Chronicle” by the old names of Witan or Mickelgemot. But its character was changed. Even before the
Conquest, if we may accept the brilliant suggestions of Professor H. M.
Chadwick, feudal tendencies had long been at work upon it, and the Conquest at
a stroke completed the development. The drastic confiscation of the lands of
the greater English lords and the wholesale transfer of these lands by the
Conqueror to a completely new set of Norman tenants-in-chief are not only the
beginning of the English land law; they mark the complete transformation of the
English national assembly. It became completely feudalised. Tenure became the
single basis of the vassals’ obligation which entitled the king as their feudal
overlord to demand the services of such of them as he chose in the
administration of the fief, and the fief was a kingdom; hence the court was the
Curia Regis. The list from which he might choose in 1086 is the list of
tenants-in-chief set forth in Domesday Book, as printed in Sir Henry Ellis’
Introduction. In fact, he chose few, and some of these, for practical reasons,
he could not well omit. But the regularity of the summons to great officials,
such as the Chancellor or Treasurer, is owing, not to any constitutional rule
that gives them a “right” to be present, but only to the practical necessity of
their presence with their records and seals in order to get business done. No
one, in fact, had any right to attend. All tenants-in-chief were bound to do
so. It was the king’s right to summon them all, and he summoned whom he would
or whom practical necessity required.
The
Barons and the Council
Thus
the first and oldest medieval estate emerges in England. It is the estate of
the barones or feudal tenants-in-chief, both
spiritual and lay, a fraction of which, and not always the same fraction, was
summoned by the king from time to time to his Councils. Thus it remained in
general till the afforcement in 1254 by the
introduction of representative knights of the shire. But it would be premature
to attach the name “estate” to such a body in the Norman period. Such a term
was not applied, and could hardly be applied to the body of tenants-in-chief in
England, before that body began to act and to think collectively. In the
eleventh and twelfth centuries these tenants are referred to simply as barones. That word is not found in the singular, nor
is the collective noun baronagium or barnagium used as yet. Such barones were simply a number of persons who happened to be pares, because they held of
the same lord and of the same fief, convassalli,
and, at the same time, any one of them might hold other lands in other fiefs or
of other lords and thus be a member of other courts and the “peer” of other
bodies of men.
So
long as these centrifugal tendencies remained unchecked, the conception of
corporateness among the English tenants-in-chief was difficult to realise, and
history shews little collective action of a permanent kind. The feudal diffidatio by which a vassal repudiated his lord was
an individual thing, as were the original homage and fealty which it renounced.
In certain senses feudalism in its unchanged form was extremely
individualistic.
In
England it was not till the thirteenth century that the barons began to act as
a collective unit, but as early as the reign of John they are found doing so.
It is in that reign that we find the first royal recognition of the baronial
right collectively to coerce the king by force, in the final sections of Magna
Carta. From that reign, too, comes the first known instance of a “parliamentary
grant” to the king by the barons, acting in their collective capacity, and it
is but a few years afterward, as Matthew Paris tells us, that totius Angliae nobilitas, when importuned by the king for money, took
an oath each to the other that they would give the king no answer except a
communis responsio1, an early instance of “collective bargaining.”
An
indication of the absence of any idea of a definite corporate character in the
baronage may possibly be seen in section 14 of Magna Carta, in which it is
promised that an assessment of a scutage or extraordinary aid shall bind all
tenants-in-chief who have been summoned, even if all these have not appeared,
provided it is agreed to by those who are present. The tacit exception here
made of those who had not been summoned seems to indicate that assent is still
several rather than joint, though it is given when all are assembled together
instead of separately. Probably one not summoned was not bound by their action.
This provision as to summons had not been demanded by the barons in their
Articles; and it, together with the whole of the provisions of 1215 concerning
aids, was entirely omitted from all later reissues of the Charter, while
scutage was by the terms of the second reissue of 1217 to be thereafter imposed
as was the custom in the time of Henry II.
Professor Powicke has shown how John’s loss of Normandy had
resulted in the surrender of their Norman lands by the barons of England, who
were thus for the first time left “free to devote themselves to English
affairs.” There can be no doubt that this was a great impetus to the growth
among the English barons, not only of a feeling of nationality, but of their
corporate character as a real baronage or estate of the realm of England. John
was one of the first kings regularly to style himself Rex Angliae instead of Rex Anglorum,
in a few years we find the contemporary chronicler speaking of his barons also
as nobilitas Angliae.
It
is a commonplace that the units of political or legal thought in the later
Middle Ages are groups rather than individuals. When the barons then began in
practice to have common interests, aims, and actions, it was natural that they
should be regarded, first rather loosely, later much more definitely, as a
universitas or commune; and as such we may consider them as the first of the
communes which in time combined to form the English Parliament.
Up
to 1254 the commune of these barons or royal tenants-in-chief constituted the
only element in the national assembly, and up to the end of the first quarter
of the fourteenth century the only invariable and essential element. The basis
of the membership was military tenure tempered by royal summons. The greater
barons were entitled to a special summons, the lesser ones, whom Round has
shewn not to be the same as mere knights, must attend if merely summoned
generally by the sheriff’. Thus they assisted in the general business of the
Curia, which was at once consultative, administrative, and judicial; and it
included the promulgation of administrative assizes as well as the issuing of
original writs in judicial matters—until the increasingly onerous and technical
burden of the last of these was gradually delegated to the chancellor alone—and
the trial of such cases as found their way, on account of difficulty or
importance, to the whole Council for determination. On feudal principles, these
members collectively also gave judgment in cases involving any of their own
number, and each of them was entitled to such a indicium parium suorum in his own case. The growing definition of
the feudal incidents in feudal custom had made certain of these incidents a
matter of course which the lord might levy without consent when occasion arose,
but in all other or extraordinary cases no assessment of aids could be made
under feudal custom without the assent of the body of tenants upon whom it
would directly fall. This was as true of the tenants-in-chief of the English
king as it was of the vassals of any lord, and it was the meetings of these tenants
in the royal Curia and their consent to such aids, beginning on a national
scale apparently in 1207 in England, that must be considered the source of the
later parliamentary grants which played so large a part in the development of
English constitutionalism. The barons in 1215 formally demanded that all such
extraordinary aids as well as scutages should be imposed only “per commune consilium regni”—with the common assent of the realm—and in
conceding this demand the king promised in addition that all the
tenants-in-chief should be summoned to a meeting for the purpose, and that
those there present should be able to decide the matter even in the absence of
the rest who had not obeyed the summons. These provisions, their wording, and
other documents of this period, warrant us in assuming that the barons are by
this time in a sense acting as an estate of the realm and that their assent
alone is referred to as the assent of the realm; and elsewhere in documents and
chronicles of this time they are frequently spoken of and speak of themselves
and themselves alone as the populus. This is
the more significant when we remember that by this time the role of the Roman populus as the ultimate source of the authority of
Roman law was known in England through the law books of Justinian, as is shewn
clearly by statements made in the preface of Glanville’s treatise on the laws
of England, written before the end of the twelfth century, and repeated by Bracton. The meaning of populus was understood and the baronage was as yet the whole populus,
it was the only estate of the realm; its consent alone was the commune consilium regni. It was, however, an estate
in which there existed no representation in any definite constitutional sense.
To
such a meeting “for obtaining the common assent of the realm” all the
individuals to whom that assent directly applied were summoned; all barons upon
whom the burden of the aids or scutage there assessed directly fell were
actually present or had an opportunity to be present. The body thus represented
no one. Their decision was their own, it directly affected none but themselves,
and they alone were considered competent to make it.
It
may even be assumed that a baron, had he been omitted from the summons, would
not have been bound by their action; and we have some additional evidence that
this was the rule. But this is only the formal or legal aspect of the matter.
Though a baron who had failed to receive a summons was probably not bound by
the action of the rest, one who had received a summons and ignored it certainly
was, and this in itself is a striking evidence of the growing idea of
corporateness. Furthermore, though these barons alone were the whole populus whose assent would be enough to conclude all
others, at least for assessments whose original incidence fell upon them alone,
there was a vague sense in which even in these matters they did act for the
classes below them upon whom they were constantly shifting the actual burden of
these exactions.
An
illustration of this is found on the Close Rolls of Henry III in 1237, in which
the fact is recited that a colloquium had met at Westminster composed of “the
archbishops, bishops, abbots, priors, earls, and barons of our whole realm,”
and apparently none beyond these; yet there follows immediately the statement
that “the same archbishops, bishops, abbots, priors, and ecclesiastics holding
lands which do not belong to their churches, earls, barons, knights, and free
men, for themselves and their villani” had granted to
the king in aid a thirtieth of their movables.
And
a time was to come, and that before long, after the milites or “country gentry” had gradually grown to sufficient importance, strength, and
political self-consciousness, when the uneasiness aroused by these conditions
would force the barons to begin to doubt their own unaided ability, if not
their right, to consent to burdens whose chief weight must fall in the last
instance upon estates lower in the feudal hierarchy, and even to suggest to the
king that the estate of the knights should be consulted as well as their own in
the imposition of such burdens.
An
interesting example of such doubts on the part of the magnates occurs in 1290
in the case of an aid for the marriage of the king’s daughter. The lords did,
it is true, profess to make the grant “for themselves and for the community of
the whole realm,” but their growing doubts of their own unaided ability to do
so appear in the phrase immediately following: “quantum in ipsis est.” As a result of these doubts the king summoned representative knights of
the shire to consult on this matter, and in the writs he distinctly says that
he is issuing them at the special request of the magnates.
In
like manner the “lords spiritual” were becoming less certain of their ability
by their assent alone to bind all the clergy. Thus the assembly of the clergy
which met at the king’s command at Northampton in 1282 to make a grant to the
king, though it contained proctors from the cathedral chapters, alleged, as a
cause of its failure to make any grant, the lack of consent by the parochial
clergy. As a result, in 1283 the writs to the archbishop to a second meeting
remedied this defect by directing that proctors of the parochial clergy should
be summoned, and the reason given was that at the previous convocation, “partly
through the absence of the greater part of the clergy who according to the
usual practice at that time prevailing had not been summoned, partly for other
reasons, ad plenum non potuit responderi.”
Thus
it is evident that the monopoly of the barones,
both ecclesiastical and lay, as the sole element in the populus,
was gradually wearing away, and that strong tendencies were at work which were
widening the basis of the State and rapidly creating the necessity for the
emergence of additional “estates” as sharers at least in the burdens imposed by
the increasing demands of the king. Later, a sharing of burdens must of
necessity lead to a sharing in other things as well.
Thus
new elements were in time added to the older Curia, but the Curia itself
remained through all the changes. This has been well expressed by M. Pasquet when he says, speaking of the House of Commons:
“That convocation is in short merely the extension to some of the new classes
of society—the bourgeoisie of the towns and the class of free tenants of the
country—of ‘the service of the court’ which had hitherto been demanded by the
king only from his barons. The delegates of the communautés then came to take their place in an organisation already in existence; for an
understanding of the real significance of the innovations which were made in
the reign of Henry III and of Edward I, it is necessary to recall the essential
features of that organisation.”
The
real motives behind these “innovations” of Henry III and more especially of Edward
I, and their immediate causes, have been the occasion of considerable
discussion in recent years. The traditional view, still generally held, and
admirably set forth in detail by Bishop Stubbs, attributes these new
developments almost solely to the increasing demands of the king for money, and
the participation of these additional “estates” in the parliamentary grants
which resulted. In recent years, several other alternative explanations have
been offered. In 1888 Ludwig Riess, the author of the
history of English parliamentary elections in the Middle Ages, contended that
the chief purpose of Edward I was not so much this, as the better control and
oversight of the county administration in the hands of the sheriffs, and the
centralisation of a system employing the aid of the knights of the shire in
local administration including the local assessment and collection of aids. M. Pasquet, while admitting the existence of all these causes,
would find the principal motive of Edward I in calling new estates to his
councils in his determination not only to be the suzerain of his vassals, but
the king of all his subjects; and he connects the king’s summoning of these new
elements with his inquests quo warranto and the statute of Quia Emptores, as all parts of a general design of
destroying the distinction existing in feudal custom between his tenants-in-chief and the mesne lords or arrière-vassaux. Professor Pollard sees in the
fact that in so many of Edward’s parliaments no financial supply was granted or
asked for, a proof that it was its judicial and not its financial activity that
must furnish the explanation at least of the frequency of its meetings, and he
believes this frequency to be due less to the king than to his subjects.
A
famous case of such a demand by the barons for reasons largely judicial occurs
in the twenty-ninth ordinance of the “Lords’ Ordinances” in 1311, where a
parliament is required once a year or oftener, and the reason given is that
defendants had alleged that they were bound to reply only coram Rege, and that the king’s ministers had been guilty of
acts of oppression against law, for which there was no redress without a
parliament. It was therefore ordained that a parliament should meet at least
once a year where these delayed cases might be terminated, as well as those in
which the justices were of conflicting opinions, and final action taken on
bills brought into parliament according to law and reason. But these
circumstances were to say the least exceptional, if not to be termed revolutionary.
Without
doubt there is much to be said for each of these factors, and this modern
discussion has considerably widened and deepened our understanding of the development
of parliament. If we confine ourselves to the beginnings of these innovations,
while Henry III was still alive, the contemporary evidence is strongly in
favour of Bishop Stubbs’ view that the original motive behind the beginning of
these changes was almost entirely fiscal. But the reigns of Edward I and Edward
II are a period of almost bewildering development, and new forces, unknown or
latent before, then began to operate. Certainly before 1327, the representative
knights who had originally come to parliament only to grant, were remaining to
do much more, and a part of this transformation must be placed in Edward I’s
reign if not attributed to his initiative. The Rolls of Parliament, which have
by this time begun, prove the activity of the representative estates in framing
petitions, and in 1322 the well-known statute of York provides that enactments
touching the estate of the whole realm must have their participation. In 1290,
when the statute of Quia Emptores was enacted, this had probably not been so,
and this rapid change may have been owing in part at least to Edward’s policy of
advancing the arrière-vassaux, or his attempts to consolidate the local administration
with the central. It seems probable that most of these great changes were in
the beginning at least the result of the king’s initiative—occasionally but
only in exceptional circumstances the barons’—rather than of the desires of the
new classes represented; but, even admitting this, the effect of the changes
upon those classes is not far different from what it would have been had they
originated with themselves. These classes do now in time gradually grow to be
an integral part of parliament, the parliament to which Fleta referred when he
said, “The king has his court in his council in his parliaments.” And they are
becoming something more than a mere addendum to the Curia as they seemed to be
at first, summoned only to participate in an aid demanded by the king and then
summarily sent home; they are now remaining to do many important things beyond
the granting of supply, though they continue to be in many things subordinate
to the lords. Edward I’s famous dictum of 1295, “quod omnes tangit ab omnibus approbetur,”
applied to them, and it cannot be wholly waved aside as the unimportant
verbiage of some minor official, as is sometimes done; but it originally
included only grants and nothing more. By 1322, however, it had come in effect
to include enactment as well as grant, and possibly in practice much besides.
Whatever then may have been the true proximate cause or causes of the beginning
of this important development, its remoter causes lie far back in the earlier
history, and the main features of the system of representation thus established
are fairly clear.
The
Knights
In
the first recorded instance of a summons of knights to a parliament, in 1254,
election in the county court is clearly referred to, as well as precise
instructions, and the clear principle that these representatives both act for
and can bind the whole body of the county; and it may safely be inferred that
these ideas and practices were already thoroughly familiar through long usage
in local matters in these courts. For certain specific things election was
employed at least as early as 1215. Chapter 18 of John’s charter had prescribed
the assistance of four knights elected per comitatum in the assizes of novel disseisin and more d’ancestor,
and chapter 48 had provided even more definitely that the twelve knights who
were to investigate the wrongdoing of the king’s foresters “ought to be elected
by the good men” in the county court. It is true, as M. Pasquet has pointed out, that the expedients of 1254 in one respect fall far short of
our modern complete idea of representation. The representatives are not
empowered by their constituents to represent them for a long period, and have
no authority to bind them in any matter that may happen in future to come
before them; they are definitely restricted to the matter of which the county
court has received notice in the king’s writ. As representatives, in their
consent in parliament they are confined ad hoc. This, however, does not mean
that they have no discretion, for they have power ad tractandum.
The limits of their discretion are probably fixed in their instructions, and
on this they are to have power to answer praecise,
but within these limits they are left free. This is, as M. Pasquet says, a system of procuration rather than one truly and entirely representative
in our modern sense, but many of the essentials of modern representation are
there, and of the others a beginning may be seen. The representatives bind
their constituents, they have a “mandate,” they have some discretionary power,
and before long they acquire a greater permanence. Medieval English parliaments
never lasted longer than a few weeks at the most, but we may easily see slight
but more and more definite indications of the growth of a more general
delegation of power, and for a longer time, in the writs of summons that we
find from time to time in the later years of the thirteenth century; and in the
next century these delegations of power become more extensive still, though it
was hardly before the Tudor period, with its parliaments occasionally lasting
several years and divided into several sessions, that the full modern idea can
be said to have become completely established.
Space
will not permit of a detailed examination of the growth of the different estates
of the knights, burgesses, cathedral and parochial clergy. When summoned to
parliament, the knights of one county in one writ of summons are directed to
treat with the representatives of the other counties upon the matters on which
the magnates shall have agreed. The matter thus agreed upon was of course a
grant, and the writ implies that all the knights were to deliberate together
upon it, and do so separately from the magnates, and there is other full
evidence that this was the practice. When burgesses were summoned, they too
deliberated together, but apart from the other estates, and the same was true
of the “communes” of the cathedral and the parish clergy, whether these were
present in person or by proctors, in the few cases of their presence in English
parliaments of the late thirteenth century.
Thus
the new representative element in the parliaments of that period really
consisted of several collective units or universitates, each consisting of
representatives who acted for the class as a whole from which it was drawn, and
no more. They were summoned ad tractandum, but
the “treating” was only in common with their fellow-representatives from the
same estate. Hence the answers of these several estates to the king’s request
for supply might be and usually were different. In the same parliament the
knights collectively might agree to grant a tenth, while the parochial clergy
might promise only a thirteenth, and so on. The lower clergy in a few years
disappeared as an estate in parliament but continued till the seventeenth
century to make grants in their convocations, a remarkable proof of the
separation of clergy and laity in the later Middle Ages, since a similar
tendency on the part of the merchants was successfully and permanently checked
by the House of Commons about the middle of the fourteenth century. Thus the
parliament in its deliberations upon the king’s requests was really not one
body, and in the early period not two bodies, but often three, four, or even
five, according as knights, burgesses, cathedral and parochial clergy were
present or not. Ad tractandum it was strictly
a combination of several separate communes or estates, deliberating apart from
each other and often returning different answers to the king’s demands, and
estates whose number actually varied widely from year to year. Before the reign
of Edward III it would be more accurate to call the representative portion of
the parliament a house of communes than a house of commons.
But
there is another side to all this. As M. Pasquet says,
the representatives are the delegates of separate communes, “but they come to
take their place in an organisation already in existence.” They did not take
this place at once. In the reign of Henry III, or even the early years of
Edward I, when they participated in grants and nothing more, it is questionable
whether they could properly be considered a part of that organisation; a few
years later there can be no question. True, the various communes continue to
deliberate apart, and for deliberation parliament remains a body of several
almost distinct parts. But by the end of Edward’s reign these communes have
taken their place as parts of one parliament. Organically it is one and they
have become members of it. At the solemn opening of parliament, when the king’s
demands are made known in the pronunciatio,
the representatives are present with the lords in the same chamber to hear it.
This was probably not the case so late as 1290; it becomes invariable in the
fourteenth century. It is only for deliberation that parliament is now
separated. For its formal acts it is one. Thus the estates continue, but they
have become merged in one official body. In 1297 Edward I had recognised that
new customs duties might be levied only with the assent of all the realm, and
that in parliament, for this touched all. In 1322 it was established that
common law as well as common grants needed the assent of “all,” and a statute
which enacted a common law required the assent of “all,” including the representatives
as well as the lords. By 1348 the Commons were able to assert their control
even over grants that appeared to touch not all but particular classes only,
and Edward III was compelled to desist from his attempts to treat for a grant
with assemblies composed of the merchants.
The
communes and the Commons
In
the meantime, Convocation had gone its separate way, and the communes of the
knights and the burgesses were gradually coalescing into a true “House of Commons,”
a process that was almost complete by the middle of the fourteenth century. By
1365 a chief justice of England could say, “Everyone is considered to know what
is done in parliament: for so soon as parliament has concluded anything, the
law presumes that everybody has notice of it; for the parliament represents the
body of all the realm.” The feudal estates have become the “body of all the
realm.” Edward I’s design of being king rather than mere lord has largely been
fulfilled. Modern political ideas are supplanting the medieval ones, and a
national “House of Commons” is rapidly replacing the medieval house of
communes.
The
above sketch of the development of the English communes is brief and
inadequate, but it was necessary to choose the growth of a single system as an
illustration, in order to bring out the fact that these institutions everywhere
were really the result of a gradual development, not of a sudden creation; and
the English system is best adapted to that purpose on account of the greater richness
of English records, especially of a local character, in the earlier period.
But
developments somewhat like this were by no means confined to England. Almost
everywhere in Western Europe, out of much the same original materials and ideas
and under the stimulus of circumstances generally similar though often
specifically different, a development not unlike this had taken place; and by
the end of the thirteenth century we find all over the Continent conditions and
ideas sometimes less developed than those of England, sometimes in some
respects apparently even more developed. These ideas and institutions are
neither of sudden occurrence nor the product of imitation to any great degree.
They are everywhere the result of a slow growth which no doubt might be
followed step by step elsewhere as we have tried briefly to follow it in
England, if other countries were as fortunate as England in the preservation of
the contemporary records of their earlier history. The universality of these
institutions is the sufficient answer to any theory of their exclusively
“Anglo-Saxon” origin and character. They are owing neither to English blood nor
to English political genius, but rather to the common stock of institutions
with which most of the Western nations started, and the operation of definite
historic events upon the development of these, which was in its larger aspects
much the same everywhere. The unique character of English constitutional
development began far back in English history, but its most striking manifestations,
as far as they are exclusively English, lie on this side of the thirteenth
century rather than on the other, and even they must be attributed to definite
historic conditions and events which demand only detailed knowledge to explain
them; they are not the result of some mysterious quality in the blood of
England. At the most, the factors are cultural rather than racial, but
historical rather than either.
By
the latter part of the thirteenth century, a development analogous to England’s
had produced institutions and ideas not fundamentally different from hers in
almost all parts of Christendom. From Scandinavia to the Adriatic they are
found, and in the east of Europe as well as the west; in Hungary, Poland, and
Bohemia, no less than in Italy, Spain, and the Low Countries. Those of Eastern
Europe treated in other chapters in this work are not included in this sketch,
but even in the West alone their wide distribution is sufficiently remarkable.
In
France, the historic connexion of these remarkable constitutional developments
with the earlier institutions of the Frankish monarchy is fairly clear. The
tradition of the old Frankish regime, its royal power, its enactments, and its
assemblies had remained; but in the tenth and eleventh centuries the powerlessness
of the kings and the parcelling out of royal authority among great lords, whose
dependence was little more than nominal, had gone so far as to make this
scarcely more than a memory. With Louis VI, as Luchaire points out, this striking contradiction between the king’s great claims and his
actual feebleness began to grow less, and a new tradition was founded which was
ultimately gradually to grow into the absolutism of Louis XIV. In France,
however, conditions were at first less favourable for its rapid development
than in England. The twelfth century was in reality the critical period for
both countries, and England was then able to lay the foundations of later
constitutionalism in her national system of administration, while in France
similar conditions were hardly approximated before the reign of Philip the
Fair. These things gave to England and Normandy an administrative development
in advance of France by more than a century, and that difference in time
determined the difference between England’s subsequent constitutionalism and
the absolutism of France. Otherwise, conditions were roughly much the same on
both sides of the Channel. As in England, though more rarely than in England,
the French king from time to time assembled in his Curia varying numbers of the
great feudatories owing him suit, and by the reign of Louis VII their activity
often resulted in administrative enactments or établissements of considerable importance. Such enactments, except in the crises of war or
invasion, Beaumanoir says, must, however, be for
sufficient cause, for the common profit, not against God and good customs; and
they must be made par grant conseil.
It
was to the appearance of a great national emergency, together with the
continuance of these earlier institutions and practices, that we must attribute
the unusual developments in France in the time of Philip the Fair, which
resulted in the first assembling of the feudal estates on a national scale; and
the inclusion in these assemblies of the bourgeoisie was, in the first instance
at least, due to the enfranchisement of so many of the communes during the
thirteenth century, which thus brought them within the feudal hierarchy and
imposed upon them the burden of the suit generally incident to feudal tenure
whenever it was demanded of them by their feudal overlord, together with the
other customary obligations of auxilium and military service. In common with
the other vassals of the king they owed him counsel and they owed him aid, and
these, or the second of them at least, had been demanded and received by the
kings of the thirteenth century from their villes, in
assemblies of which the great lords had formed no part. The rapid differentiation
in the central administration of the latter part of the thirteenth century is no
doubt an important cause of this separate action. The judicial function of the
old Curia had already passed in large part to the Parlement,
while consilium had become one of the chief functions
of the king’s private council, though this was, as Viollet says, a matter of fact rather than of legal definition. When the communes were
summoned, it was usually auxilium and that alone that was wanted, and before
the opening of the fourteenth century, in all cases where it was demanded from
them collectively, it was in assemblies to which no other feudatories were
summoned. No doubt the reason why they had been summoned at all was the force
of the feudal principle that all specific aids beyond the few accustomed ones
could be assessed only with the consent of the vassals upon whom they fell.
Instances of these separate assemblies of representatives of the villes are to be found a good while before the opening of
the fourteenth century, and separate they might have remained much longer but
for the great national questions brought up by the conflict between Pope
Boniface VIII and Philip the Fair. For such a national emergency the old feudal
revenues were inadequate. Feudalism was dying and its revenues drying up none
the less surely, even if more gradually, than in England, and, as in England,
the national power was rising and with it a national activity that required for
its support a larger revenue than could be drawn from sources strictly feudal
in character. The king was driven to treat on extra-feudal terms with his
vassals, the barons and the enfranchised villes. Thus
the estates are feudal, but they are extra-feudal also. Philip probably called
to him in 1302 none who did not owe him feudal suit, but he did it in a way
unprecedented in feudal custom. The departure from precedent might seem less
striking in the occasional assemblées de notables to
which none but great nobles lay or spiritual were summoned, but the greater
assemblies of Philip the Fair were certainly an innovation, though their feudal
basis is evident; and later meetings mark a far more radical departure from
feudal institutions and ideas.
Early
French representation
The
first instance seems to have been in the year 1301 at an assembly held by
Philip at Senlis, in which was demanded the counsel “clericorum et laicorum, doctorum et aliorum proborum virorum”, on the
difficult question raised by the king proceeding against the Bishop of Pamiers for breach of faith and lèse-majesté.
But
other differences arose between the Pope and the French King which finally
became so serious that on 10 April 1302 Philip called a great meeting of the
Estates at Paris. This assembly is usually regarded as the beginning of the States General, and the documents edited by the late M.
Georges Picot enable us to draw with some confidence certain conclusions as to
the character, powers, and activities of its members. The assembly was composed
of tenants-in-chief of the king, lay and spiritual, as had long been the
custom; and it also included arrière-vassaux, “representatives” of enfranchised villes. All these arrière-vassaux were bound in a
general way by the fealty they owed their liege lord, but direct negotiations
with them were an addition to feudal custom which could be made regular only by
the assent of their overlords who held of the king in capite.
In England, an aid had already been asked of the mesne lords, as we have seen,
but “at the instance” of their feudal superiors. This was now done for France
by Philip in 1302, and it illustrates the gradually widening basis of the State
on both sides of the Channel, a process observable earlier in England than in
France. In both, fealty is gradually becoming wider, more national, and less
feudal, as wealth, power, and political self-consciousness diffuse themselves
beyond the circle of the greater land-holders. But the development is a gradual
one which proceeds without any distinct break with feudal custom. The mesne
lords—a term including communes outside the royal demesne—are now summoned, but
it is on account of an obligation which may be called as much feudal as
national, and the innovation of summoning the is softened by obtaining the
assent of the direct vassals who had hitherto concluded their tenants by their
own unassisted decisions. This assent was forthcoming no doubt because the
participation which was now first extended beyond the immediate circle of the
king’s tenants-in-chief was not a privilege to be guarded, but rather a burden
which might be borne more easily when more widely shared.
Changing
economic and social conditions were making increasingly difficult the older
shifting of the incidence of the burden of auxilia sanctioned by regular feudal
custom. The consent of the tenants-in-chief was necessary if such a change was
to be made, but it was a consent probably not hard to obtain in view of the
crisis which faced the nation in 1302. Thus it is clear that the basis of the
membership of the first Estates was obligation and not right, an obligation
arising out of fealty; while the growing forces of nationalism were now
imposing upon it the necessity of direct negotiations between the king and his
arrière-vassaux, hitherto unnecessary but now accepted by the chief tenants in
the prospect of unusually heavy demands for aid in the impending struggle with
the Pope, and accepted the more willingly no doubt because of their decreasing
confidence in their ability longer to shift these burdens from their own
shoulders to those of their tenants. That the real basis of the summons was
obligation rather than right is made plain by the surviving summonses to the
Estates themselves. In the very first of these, addressed by the king to the
seneschal of Beaucaire on 15 February 1302, the
purpose of the meeting is set forth in language which echoes the famous phrase
of Edward I of England seven years before—“quod omnes tangit ab omnibus approbetur”.
Since on “many difficult matters” which touch in no small degree the status and
liberty of himself and his realm no less than of the churches, ecclesiastics,
nobles, secular persons, and all and singular the inhabitants of the said
realm, the king wishes to “treat and deliberate” with his prelates, barons, and
others the subjects and lieges of him and of the said realm, he commands to be
summoned under their obligation of fealty and any other obligation whatsoever
by which they are bound to him to appear at Paris on 8 April then next ensuing,
the “consules et universitates civitatum et villarum praedictarum”
(in this case seven villes) through two or three “de maioribus et pericioribus singularum universitatum predictarum” who are to have full power from the aforesaid
consuls and communes among other things “to hear, receive, and carry out, and
to consent to everything ordained by the king in this regard without the excuse
of a referendum,” their presence being for the purpose “of treating and
deliberating upon these matters, of hearing, receiving, and carrying out” all
of them, and of giving their assent “in the name of the consuls and communes
aforesaid” to all those things ordained by the king in the premises or
connected therewith. The document here summarised clearly indicates that this
summons grew out of the obligations incident to fealty. There appear also the
instructions to “representatives” such as are to be found a generation earlier
in England, but there is no definite reference to any election.
But
an important question arises at the outset in regard to those things which
touch the status and liberty of all the inhabitants of the realm. Must all
actually approve of what touches all? Whom must the king include when he asks
assent in matters thus touching all? How far beyond the prelates and barons
does the obligation of fealty extend; or the additional phrase quocumque vinculo? How much of this “representation” is
only “virtual”? Shall we translate the important words “aliis nostris et eiusdem regni fidelibus et subjectis” with M.
Picot, as “les autres sujets du royaume,” or with the late Professor Esinein, as “d’autres fidèles sujets du royaume”, thus including among the “others” none beyond the
inhabitants of enfranchised villes? How far is this important
experiment of Philip “national” and novel, how far is it merely feudal and
traditional? It is a difficult question. There can be no doubt that there was a
great development of these matters between 1300 and the great meeting of the
Estates in 1484 for which Masselin’s journal gives us
such detailed information, but on the whole, though the paucity of documents
for the first meeting makes certain conclusions impossible in regard to it, if
we may judge from the history of earlier assemblies in France and elsewhere,
the more conservative interpretation of Esmein seems
to offer an explanation of these important transactions more in accordance with
the facts and the political habits and ideas of the time than the “consequences exagerées” of M. Picot. It is important, however, to
bear in mind that this applies wholly only to the earliest meetings of the
Estates.
Several
times in 1303, at Paris, Montpellier, Nimes and Carcassonne, and again in 1308
in the struggle with the Templars, the Estates were called together; and many
of the documents have survived from which some conclusions may be drawn as to
the general character of the assemblies in the early fourteenth century. They
met again in 1314, in 1356, when there were two assemblies, one for the South at
Toulouse and one for the North at Paris; in 1413, and in 1484, and several
times between; often in times of national defeat and civil disorder which make
their actions seem more revolutionary than constitutional. The last meeting
before the fateful one of 1789 was in 1614.
In
the beginning the prelates and barons were required to appear in person, and
such of the members of these assemblies as were ordered to come and gave their
assent only nomine consulum et universitatum doubtless lacked many of the powers
characteristic of the more fully developed representatives of modern times. The
attendance of both classes was sub debito fidelitatis and under threat of punishment for failure.
But even the prelates and barons owing personal attendance might find it
impossible to answer the summons in person, and in such cases they might appear
by attorney, as was possible in all the royal courts at this time in both
England and France, provided the royal licence could be had. The reasons given
for these procurations or letters of attorney issued by the clergy for the
meeting in Paris in 1303—here suspiciously numerous—which M. Picot has printed,
shew conclusively that this appearance by attorney was at the time of that
meeting regarded as an exception to be admitted only when sufficient cause was
shewn. So one abbot prays this privilege “propter infirmitatem”,
the Prior of Saint-Leon of Sens is prevented from coming “gravi proprii corporis infirmitate”.
“We have started on our journey,” says another, “though very weak, but are not
strong enough to appear in person, as God is our witness, without grave danger
to our health.” Another is so poor and so burdened with his duties at home that
he begs to be excused. Another has got as far as Troyes but the journey is too
much for a man of almost eighty, wherefore he begs “vestre regie maiestati quatenus super hoc pro excusato dignemini me habere.”
Another is so ill that he is not able to ride. The Abbot of Chantoin cannot come because his monastery is so poor that he must come afoot, which he
could not do without grave danger to his health. Another has broken his leg,
“as is well known in the whole neighbourhood”. Another is deaf. In these
exceptional cases, the attorney was usually given power first of all to present
the excuses of his principal, which were probably not always acceptable—“full
power to excuse our absence from your presence for the reasons aforesaid, and
to take oath on the excuse given”, as in one instance. This was accompanied by
a grant of authority to the attorney to conclude his principal as fully as
though he himself were present in person, sometimes in all the king’s demands,
but quite as often with important reservations; “salva fide”, in the case of the Abbot of Longuay, and in
another instance only so far as the acts agreed to should be done “de iure”, and even then with the proviso that they must be
referred to the principal for ratification. One letter limits the attorney’s
consent to those things alone to which the majority of the prelates shall have
agreed. Sometimes the attorneys are empowered to consent, “if necessary”, or
“to consent” and if necessary “to affix their seals.” Others are only to give
assent subject to ratification by the superior of the Order to which the
monastery belongs. In one case power is given merely to excuse and to take oath
that the excuse is genuine, but no power whatever to act. The Bishop of Rodez expressly delegates authority to join in all acts
against Boniface, “quondam papam octavum,”
while the Abbot of Villemagne and the Prior of
Sainte-Énimie are careful to except always the
status, honour, and revenue of the Holy See. The persons designated in these
letters of procuration are usually referred to as “procurator ac nuncius specialis”, “exhibitor presencium nostrum”, “latores presencium”, “excusator specialis”; and in some cases several are appointed, in
others a single individual. When several are chosen, usually any one of them
may act for the whole. Most of the appointments of these proctors were made
directly by abbots or priors, but in one case it was by a chapter, in another
by the dean and chapter, and in another, where the abbot of the monastery was
absent, it was authorised by the prior and monks.
In
July 1303 an assembly was held at Montpellier which marks some notable
developments in representation beyond those of a few months before. The summons
addressed to the viguier of Beziers prescribes the
attendance of all prelates and barons of the district, together with chapter’s, collegia, the conventus as well as the priors of important collegiate and conventual as well as
cathedral churches, together with “syndicos et
universitates civitatum et castrorum aliarumque villarum insignium”. Of these the prelates, barons, priors, and
consults must appear in person, the rest by suitable proctors with adequate
power and instructions. The notices of the choice of proctors in the cities,
chateaux, and villes are particularly interesting. In
one, the Chateau d’Aimargues near Nimes, the
universitas of the men of the Chateau were summoned by the trumpet and the
public crier, and they or a majority of them “as appears and is declared,”
“nobles as well as non-noble,” “representing that universitas,” proceeded to
elect (fecerunt, constituerunt,
et elegerunt) four men, two noble, two non-noble, to
act “on behalf of the universitas and everyone of the
said universitas,” its authority inhering in all or each of the proctors in
such way that anything begun by one or more of them might lawfully be carried
on and determined by the others, one or more; an authority, too, which extended
far beyond the narrow mandates earlier in the year, to include generaliter everything the universitas could do,
say, treat of, and accomplish, if all its members were present in person. Even
where the election was the act of the consoles alone, as in the Château de Capdenac, the representative was sometimes “general” as
well as special, and was empowered to do not only the things specified but “all
others.” The procuratores are in one mandate
designated as “our certain general and special proctors”, in others authority
to prosecute and defend legal actions against the commune is specifically
mentioned. At Lunel “the people of the university of
the men” of the ville, three hundred and thirty-six
in number, were called together by crier and trumpet in the churchyard where it
was the custom of the people to assemble, and there, “all and singular and each
of them” appointed four proctors, with “full, general, and liberal power” to
act, two of them noble, one a lawyer, and one a draper of Lunel.
Later in the day fifty-three more of the inhabitants ratified the action
already taken.
At Viviers “those men of the universitas who were
present declaring that they constituted two parts and more of the men of that
universitas, as seemed very probable”, proceeded in the name of the whole
universitas to elect their two representatives and to promise ratification of
their acts. At Lodève the assembled inhabitants, five
hundred and forty-four in number, whose names are all set down, after hearing
the letters of convocation translated for them, “as a universitas and in the
name of the universitas of Lodève,” unanimously chose
three syndics to represent them. Occasionally procuratores were empowered to substitute others for themselves, and there is at least one
case in which this was actually done. In 1308, for the assembly at Tours, two
proctors were to be chosen at Beaucaire, one “pro parte nobilium,” the other “pro parte popularium personarum,” and
the election of the latter occurred in an assembly of the “burgenses et homines populares,” who
chose a doctor of laws as the representative “pro popularibus personis et nomine universitatis earum.”
Such
specific instances as these indicate far more clearly than any amount of
detailed comment the nature and the extent of representative institutions and
ideas in France at the opening of the fourteenth century. Several points seem
clear. The attendance is not a right but a duty, and a duty imposed primarily
by the obligation of fealty. Those summoned to appear in person must do so, at
the beginning of the century at least, unless they have an excuse, of whose
sufficiency the king will judge. With the king’s permission they may in such
cases appear by an attorney. This Esmein considers
exceptional and existing only in 1302. Normally, he says, they might appear by
proctor if they chose. This was certainly not the case, however, at the first
meeting in 1303, but obviously soon became the general practice. Such proctors
when appointed were attorneys or mandatarii,
and usually little more. They represented in most cases no one but their
principal. They were his personal agents and bound none beyond him by their
acts. “Each appeared in virtue of an obligation that was personal.” Collective
bodies such as villes or chapters of necessity had to
appear by a proctor or proctors, who were likewise regarded oftentimes as
little more than mandatarii, as is indicated among
other things by their being occasionally allowed to appoint substitutes, a
power hardly consistent with the existence of the discretionary power
necessarily incident to representation in any developed sense. But many cases
go far beyond this. There were other proctors who were general as well as
special, empowered in advance legally to bind their principals in any way
whatsoever, and there were cases where several prelates or barons agreed to
employ the same proctor in common, and one instance at least where several bishops
of a single province are authorised to choose one of their own number “to act
as representative in place of all and to have the full power of all.” In the villes the developments are particularly interesting. For
purposes of representation they are conceived in the usual manner of the time
as collective wholes, universitates or communes, and the proctors they chose
represent the universitas. Apparently the franchise is wide, and the decision
is sometimes made by the vote of a majority. This body of the ville usually includes nobles and non-nobles, but in one
case in 1308 there are two communes in a single ville,
the nobles and the populares personae,
the second of which separately chose a proctor for their own universitas.
Seemingly none but the inhabitants of the towns are represented in these
assemblies of 1303 and 1308. The inhabitants of the open country are not
mentioned till long afterward.
In
fact, the most striking difference between France and England in the local
representation at this time and before undoubtedly lies in the continuance of
the old county court in England and the absence of anything comparable to it
in France. Thanks to the circumstances of the Conquest, the vigour of William I
and Henry I, and the obvious advantage to them in continuing the older system
of the hundred and the shire, it became the settled policy of the Norman Kings
of England to retain them. Thus in England the sheriff, the king’s chief local
officer, remained a part of the court over which he presided. He remained the
shire-reeve to the end, and though he was the king’s praepositus,
his authority increasing in proportion to the increasing growth of royal power
itself, yet he never became detached from his county or its court or
independent of it. Its authority as a whole did not decline as his advanced,
though his authority was partly gained at the expense of the old suitors of the
court itself. And when in turn the sheriff’s authority gave way to that of the
justices itinerant, the vigorous communal life of the shire was not affected.
The justices were strong, but they were active in and through the machinery of
the county court. In France, on the contrary, the praepositus,
in developing into the prévôt as royal power increased, tended to lose touch
with the community and become more a royal minister than a local officer, and
the later baillis were even more markedly so. Neither the prévôté nor the bailliage ever came to be the full equivalent of the English county.
The difference is profound, and it had results no less decisive on the
development of the rural representative institutions in the two countries. In
the early fourteenth century the only local representation in France is in the
universitates of the villes. In England at the same
time, and probably until the passage of the forty-shilling freehold act, the
participation in elections of representatives extended to all the members of
the county court, including much of the agricultural population of the open
country, as seems the better opinion, supported by Homersham Cox, Riess, and Stubbs.
For
the towns, on the other hand, though there is a vast practical difference
between the frequent meetings of an English Parliament and the rare and
exceptional assemblies of the French Estates, the theory and practice of
representation in France certainly seems no less advanced than in England in
the early fourteenth century; and in the period following, at times of great
political excitement, it occasionally advanced far beyond the earlier
precedents. In fact there were several significant changes whose results were
of the greatest importance.
Gradually
the nobles and the prelates ceased to attend the meetings of the Estates in
person or to be required to do so. It became their practice, contrary to that
of England, to appear only by deputy; and a further step of the greatest
importance followed when the prelates and the nobility of a general district
began regularly to elect a small number of proctors to represent them all.
Equally important was the extension of the franchise to the people of the whole
bailliage including the open country as well as the villes,
as is found in 1484 at the meeting of the Estates at Tours. This was no doubt
exceptional, but it seems to indicate the existence, temporarily at least, of
conditions in some respects not greatly different from those in the English
shire. Unlike England, however, the representatives of each order in the French
districts were chosen, not by all the electors together as in the county court
but separately, each of the orders, clergy, nobility, and “third estate”
choosing deputies to represent none but their own order in the bailliage at the
general meeting of the Estates. In 1484, in the case of the third estate, the
suffrage for these elections seems to have been almost universal; but, taking
the later Middle Ages in general, the basis remained on the whole municipal
rather than general, though at times of crisis it was occasionally extended in
theory at least to cover the whole bailliage. So, as Augustin Thierry says, however
restricted may have been the representation of the third estate on account of
its exclusively municipal character, it nevertheless had the merit of feeling
itself charged with the duty of pleading the cause, “not of this or that
fraction, nor of this or that class of the people, but the cause of the whole
body of the non-nobles, of the people without distinction of free or serf, of
bourgeois or peasant.”
There
were thus in 1484 deputies for and from each order or estate, but all
represented one “electoral district”; and the bailliage for which they all
appeared included the villes and, theoretically at
least, the campaniae as well. For electoral
purposes these were not separate and distinct as were the boroughs and the
counties in England. Jean Masselin speaks of the
assembly of 1484 as disposed “per nationes et turmas,”and specifically mentions the representatives of
Paris, Picardy, and Normandy, the “chief nations” of France in the University
of Paris. In the famous oration given in the assembly by Philippe Pot, he
speaks of “his nation”, by which he undoubtedly means Burgundy, in which there
were nine bailliages, no doubt the turmae or subdivisions of that “nation”, from whom representatives were returned. As a
general rule, says Masselin, each bailliage returned
one deputy for each of its three estates, the Church, the nobility, and status plebeius, but occasionally from places of great
size or dignity there were two or three and in rare cases fewer than one for
each estate, though this he felt was inadequate. From the bailliage of Senlis there was but one, from a few others two. But this
inequality is of less significance because the votes in the assembly were not
by individuals but by the bailliages as collective units.
The
Estates in Parliament
In
most national assemblies of the later Middle Ages a distinction should be noted
more clearly than is sometimes done between their formal acts and the less
formal proceedings of which the formal acts are often only the preliminary or
the result, a distinction roughly analogous to the difference between a regular
session of the House of Commons and a committee of the whole House in our own
day. The difficulty in distinguishing the two was one cause of the momentous
struggle with which the French Revolution opened. It was probably the chief
cause of the series of conflicts between the two English Houses of Parliament
in the seventeenth century. In more recent times it has led to serious misapprehension
and frequent misstatement of the relations of the various parts of these
medieval assemblies one to the other. Professor Pollard in his Evolution of
Parliament has emphasised the fact, well known but often insufficiently
attended to, that organically the English Parliament was a single body; only
informally and for deliberation did it gradually become bicameral during the
Middle Ages. In the formal sessions with which it opened and closed, the only
ones in which the king was present in person or by deputy, the whole body was
present in one room there to hear the formal pronunciatio in which the subjects were laid before them for their separate deliberation, or
to learn at the end which of their decisions had obtained the royal favour and
were to be made effective by the final sanction of the king. Not till the reign
of Edward VI did the Commons have an official “House” set aside for their
exclusive use in the Palace of St Stephen, and their journals begin only at the
beginning of the same reign.
At
the formal opening of parliament, while the Council sat on the woolsacks in the
middle of the house and the Lords along the sides, the whole body of the
Commons stood uncovered at the foot of the room below the bar, their speaker at
their head. This over, the Commons withdrew for deliberation apart on this medieval
“speech from the throne” to wherever they could find a suitable place, usually
the chapter house of the Abbey across the street, and only returned when they
were ready for the final formal ceremonies of the royal assent and dissolution.
The
practice was somewhat the same in the early French assemblies. Masselin’s detailed description of the assembly chambers in
1484 shews that the third estate were segregated in the lower part of the room,
though they were probably seated. The meeting was opened as in England by a
speech of the Chancellor announcing the reasons for their summons and the
action expected of them. Then the deliberation followed, all the Estates
remaining at times where they were, as they seem to have done in 1467, contrary
to the English practice; or sometimes separately, as is indicated at times in
the Assembly of 1484, until a decision (conclusio)
was reached on each part of the king’s demands, which seems then to have been
reduced to writing. There was thus a considerable difference between the French
practice in which the three estates at times deliberated together but never
really fused, and the English, in which the knights of the shire and the
burgesses regularly withdrew together and apart from the lords for common
discussion.
The
French Estates in times of crisis exercised unusual and enormous power, as in
1420, and Glasson believes that it was the very extravagance of their acts at
such times that caused their later weakness. But the reasons for this weakness,
and for the long intervals between their meetings as compared with the frequent
parliaments in England, lie much deeper, and have their roots, some of them, in
a past already distant in the fifteenth century. Some of the results of these
same causes were clearly seen by Sir John Fortescue, and they are closely
connected with the ones with which we are concerned. The French king, he says,
has taken upon him “to sett tayles and other imposicions upon the commons without the
assent of the III estates; but yet he wolde not sett any such charges, nor hath sette, uppon the nobles for fere of rebellion”. The growth
of these impôts permanents which the
king might take without consent is a sign of the increasing tendency toward
absolutism in practice and theory; and this, together with the exemption of the
nobility from such burdens, is at once a striking difference, noticeable to
Fortescue between England and France in his day, and ail argument in favour of
the more limited monarchy which he believed to exist at home. The great
difference between the two countries in these two things, whether itself a
cause or only the result of deeper differences, certainly was a practical
factor of increasing importance in determining the future difference between
parliamentary and constitutional England and the absolutism of
eighteenth-century France. The Estates in 1484 struggled against this fatal
tendency, but in vain. The theory insisted upon by the Estates survived in part
in Bodin’s Six Livres de la Republique, but the
practice became far otherwise. As Esmein sums it up:
“In a word, the institution of the States General had
proved abortive. They had no regular time of meeting but came into existence as
the last resort of the royal government in times of crisis. As for their
powers, the king demanded of them the vote of subsidies which he might impose
without them, and the giving of counsel which he was free to disregard....But
the absolute monarchy, with an instinct that was sure, mistrusted the States
General even when so weakened: it had a sense of the existence in them of
latent forces, which favouring events might well let loose. Hence, without
abolishing the institution, it carefully refrained from calling them together.
Their whole activity occurred under la monarchie temperée, between 1302 and 1614. The meeting of 1614
was the last before the Revolution.”
If
the States General are the most interesting French parallel with English
constitutional development, probably the history of the provincial estates
would furnish the most interesting French analogy to the development of
representative institutions in countries such as Germany and Italy, where the
postponement of political unity to more modern times restricted the activity of
their representative bodies to local affairs during the Middle Ages. These
provincial estates were for single provinces what the States General were for
the whole realm; and in general, where they were suffered to remain, they
retained the form, the powers, and the general procedure found in the general
estates of the fourteenth century. Varying in origin in the different provinces
before their absorption in the Crown domains, some of these estates remained,
particularly on the borders of the kingdom, long after the States General had
fallen into abeyance; but since the ideas and practices to be found in them, as
well as the general conditions out of which they grew, do not differ
essentially from those already described for the realm as a whole, our limited
space might better be employed by a brief consideration of representative
institutions elsewhere in Western Europe.
Spain
In
no country, not even excepting England and France, are these developments
illustrated more clearly than in the Spanish peninsula. The remarkable
development and maturity of representative institutions and ideas found in
Spain, arising in the thirteenth century or before, reaching their climax in
the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, and declining during the late fifteenth
century and the sixteenth, might well furnish the material for many volumes.
These developments abundantly prove the careful statement of Professor
Merriman: “The claim of the people to a share in the government was
considerably more fully recognised, theoretically at least, in Spain than in
England, at that stage of their development. The difficulty is to deal with so
large and so important a subject in small compass. This difficulty is increased
by the fact that the great constitutional age of Spain preceded the union of
the crowns and must therefore be studied separately for Castile and Leon, and
for the eastern kingdoms, while even among the latter there are often found
differences that are fundamental. In such circumstances the only course open—
though one rather unsatisfactory—is to choose the representative institutions of
one kingdom for treatment and indicate the chief differences found in other
kingdoms as variants from this. For this purpose the institutions of Catalonia
will here be taken, because, as Professor Memman says, “the Cortes of Catalonia in this period resembled a modern legislative
body perhaps more closely than any other in the peninsula”; and since the main
purpose of this chapter is to make clear medieval representative institutions
and ideas in general, rather than to trace their history in detail, it would
seem better to choose as an illustration the more perfect forms of Catalonia
rather than those of Castile, though the latter probably had an earlier
beginning and certainly exercised a greater influence upon subsequent
institutions and events. Catalonia is chosen instead of Aragon because the
documentary history of its Cortes is now fully covered for our period in the
Cortes... de Aragon y de Valencia, y Principado de
Cataluña, whose magnificent volumes, still in process of publication by the
Spanish Royal Academy of History, have not yet included any of the records of
the kingdoms of Aragon and Valencia.
The
assemblies in Christian Spain had come down from Visigothic times and were in
their earlier development not unlike those of the same early period in England
or France, especially in the fact that they included none beyond the nobles and
the clergy. Conflicting statements have been made by Spanish historians early
and modern as to the first appearance of representatives from the towns, but
the first official mention of such representatives seems to have been in the
decrees promulgated in the kingdom of Leon in 1188, where the presence of the
archbishop, the bishops, and the magnates of the realm is noted—“cum electis civibus ex singulis civitatibus.” It is
almost a century after this before certain indications are found of the
appearance of such additional representatives in the other kingdoms, but by the
end of the thirteenth century they are found in all.
Before
the middle of the fourteenth century these representative institutions had
assumed a form in Catalonia which is impressive in its definiteness and
maturity, as well as in its completeness. In the case, for example, of the
Cortes or Curia Generalis which met at Tortosa
in 1331, we find summonses requiring the personal attendance of seven high
secular ecclesiastics, of nineteen abbots, and of the Prior of the Order of Hospitallers
in Catalonia, together with several members of the royal family and the King of
Majorca. In addition to these, forty-three “nobiles”
are summoned, thirty-eight of whom must appear in person and five are permitted
to appear by proctor; forty-two “milites,” one of
whom may appear by proctor. To six cities, Barcelona, Lerida, Tarragona,
Gerona, Vich, and Manresa instructions are given to
send syndics or proctors with full powers, and similar instructions are given
in twelve towns to “probis hominibus ex universitate Cervarie,”
as in the case of Cervera, or to “iuratis probis hominibus.”
There
were three estates or brazos in the Cortes of
Catalonia as in Castile, instead of four as in Aragon: the clergy, the “nobiles” and knights, and the proctors of the cities and
towns. The nobles—in Castile usually called ricos hombres (richi homines)—corresponded
rather closely to the barones in England (the
word ricos as used here retaining its original
meaning in all Indo-European languages, of “powerful”, “mighty”, “exalted”,
“noble”, rather than our modern “rich”). The “milites”
or caballeros, like the magnates, received individual summonses to appear in
person, and when they did so, joined with the ricos hombres as one brag, or estate. This is a difference of great consequence
from the practice at this time growing up in England by which the knights of
the shire were associating themselves not with the barons but with the
burgesses, in the discussion of the matters they were called together to treat.
And even in Aragon, where there was a separate brazo de Caballeros, it never coalesced with the burgesses as in England.
The
obligation of personal attendance in Catalonia, and apparently elsewhere in
Spain, was as in England more lasting than in France. Though attendance in
person was required in France by Philip the Fair, the magnates both lay and
clerical were soon able to substitute an attendance by representatives, and
regularly absented themselves, thus no doubt greatly weakening the influence of
the Estates. In England this was avoided by the greater power of the king in
the earlier period, and later by the greater importance of parliament, in which
it gradually became an advantage and in time an honour to be present. In
Catalonia it is clear that personal attendance was rigidly insisted upon
except when a sufficient excuse could be given and sworn to. In the Cortes of
1331, for example, the king on learning that the Bishop of Barcelona intended
to be represented by a proctor for reasons “non bene sufficientibus,”
separately commanded him to appear in person, especially because he was “bound
to take part in person” in the making of constitutions by the Cortes.
The
representative element in the Cortes of Catalonia in 1331 consisted of syndics
or procuratores chosen by the deans and
chapters of the seven cathedral churches and the representatives from the
cities and towns. Abbots were required to be present in person and were the
sole representatives of their abbeys, since no summons issued for the
attendance of monastic proctors. There was none for representatives of the
parish clergy. Thus the practice in Catalonia in 1331 differed from that of the
Estates in France to which monastic proctors were summoned, and from similar
assemblies in England to which the parish clergy were summoned in the praemunientes clause in 1295 and occasionally
thereafter until Convocation became separate from Parliament. But the most
interesting and important feature of the Catalan and other Spanish Estates is
in the representation of cities and towns—in 1331 respectively six and twelve
in number in Catalonia—and in the peculiarities of this representation when
compared with those of France and England in the same general period.
Mention
of the presence of a third estate appears in Leon, as we have seen, as early as
1188, and about a century later references to the hombres buenos become common in
all the kingdoms. “Many good men” of Barcelona are recorded as attending the
Cortes in Catalonia as early as 1251, but, as it was to a meeting in Barcelona
itself, and as no other burghers are mentioned, its significance might easily
be overrated. By the year 1283, however, from two to four representatives were
summoned from each of the cities and from “many” of the towns throughout Catalonia,
and among the constitutions enacted and sealed by the king at that meeting, one
provides that in future no general constitution for Catalonia shall be made by
the king without the consent of the elves of Catalonia, as well as of the
barons and knights, “vel maioris et sanioris partis eorundem.”
Another provision promises that in future the king and his successors will
convene a meeting of the Cortes in Catalonia once in every year in which to
treat of the condition and reform of the country with the clergy secular and
regular, with barons, knights, and “cum... civibus et hominibus villarum.”
Though
“just cause” may often have been found for less frequent meetings, the latter
of these provisions is remarkable, and it precedes by more than a quarter of a
century the first similar enactment in England in the famous ordinances of
1311, assented to by the king only under compulsion. England can shew nothing
comparable to the Catalan provision for the assent of the burgesses to new
constitutions before the year 1322 in the well-known statute of York by which
the ordinances of 1311 were repealed.
Thus
from the opening of the fourteenth century and before, the regularity and the
constitutional character of municipal representation is established by law in
Catalonia, and all existing evidence seems to point to an actual practice
conforming with the law. In 1300 it is distinctly stated that the ordinances
made in the Cortes of that year are made with the counsel and assent and at the
request not only of nobles and knights but of the citizens and men of the towns
as well; it is further provided that no interpretation of the constitution
should be made in future except with the help of jurists and in the presence of
four ricos hombres and four citizens;
and provision is made even for local committees consisting of one knight, one
man of the law, and one citizen, to keep watch for breaches of the constitution.
In
the summonses of this period in Catalonia, the procuradores of the towns are to
have full power from their constituents, “tractandi, consenciendi, faciendi, et firmandi,” in all that shall be ordained there. In 1322 it
is recorded that such differences of opinion arose in the Cortes that nothing
could be agreed to, but nevertheless that the proctors of the cities and towns
made a grant. It is this participation of the third estate alone in grants that
marks one of the greatest of the differences between Spain and France on the
one hand and England on the other, and this important difference played no
small part in the great contrast between the continuance of representative
institutions and the further development of constitutional principles in
England a little later, at the same time that Spain and France, from beginnings
often even more remarkable, were gradually lapsing into absolutism.
It
seems clear from a general survey of the official documents of the Catalan
Cortes of the fourteenth century that the representation of the cities and
towns was very uniform from year to year. Thus the cities and the towns as well
as the individual clergy, barons, and caballeros, obtained what might be called
a prescriptive right to be summoned, a right which seems to have been respected
by the king and prized by the burgesses. There is not in Catalonia at this time
such a variation in the towns summoned as may be found in Castile or in
England, where the king’s discretion alone seems to have determined what towns
should send deputies. There is ample justification for Professor Merriman’s
statement that the Catalan assemblies more nearly resembled a modern
legislative body than any other in the Peninsula. One is tempted to substitute
for “the Peninsula,” “the world.”
In
definiteness of organisation and regularity of procedure neither the English
Parliament nor the French Estates can compare with the Cortes of Catalonia at
this time. Their nearest rival seems to have been in the sister kingdom of
Aragon, in which a right of attendance similar to that in Catalonia was
recognised by the king. A proof of this definiteness is found in the
elaborateness of the procedure of habilitación,
or determination of the qualification of members, which fills many pages of the
records of the Cortes, in striking contrast with the Rolls of Parliament in
England at the same period. Those summoned individually could substitute a
proctor only in exceptional cases and for “just cause”; while chapters of
churches and the universitates of towns, which of necessity appeared by deputy,
were under obligation to see that their proctors were both idonei and entrusted with sufficient power to bind their principals in all the matters
of which they were called together to treat, or for which their common consent,
enactment, and confirmation were necessary. This formal determination of the poderes (credentials and instructions) of the
members regularly preceded the principal business of the Cortes, and its importance
and minuteness seem to prove that the representative constitution of the
Catalan Cortes had no rival for definiteness in any national assembly outside
the Spanish peninsula at this time. In the Cortes held at Perpignan in 1350 and
1351, for example, a committee of twelve was elected by the Cortes to examine
the poderes of the members in conjunction with
two jurists of the royal council, consisting of two bishops, two nobles, one
abbot, one canon, two knights, a doctor of laws of Barcelona, another of
Perpignan, and one citizen from each of the two cities of Lerida and Gerona.
It
is true that this third estate in Catalonia, and in fact in all the Spanish
kingdoms, seems to be in composition more closely allied to the third estate of
France than to the “commons” of England. No Spanish procuradores represented
such a body of constituents as we find in the English county court. They were
all deputed as in France by the universitates of the cities and villes, and none came as in England from the body of a
rural county. This difference is fundamental and its results are of great
consequence. “There were two essential defects in the constitution of Castile,
through which perhaps it was ultimately subverted,” says Hallam. “It wanted
those two brilliants in the coronet of British liberty, the representation of
freeholders among the commons, and trial by jury. The Cortes of Castile became
a congress of deputies from a few cities, public-spirited indeed and intrepid,
as we find them in bad times, to an eminent degree, but too much limited in
number, and too unconnected with the territorial aristocracy, to maintain a
just balance against the crown”. In Catalonia the cities represented were not
so few in relation to the size of the realm as they became in Castile, but in
neither is there anything like the English county court whose representatives
were probably chosen by all the suitors in common whether they were knights or
of lower status. While this is undoubtedly true and of an importance not easily
overestimated, a part—though only a part—of the significance of this contrast
loses its sharpness from the fact that the jurisdiction of the cities and villae of all the Spanish kingdoms, as in the
banlieue of the towns in France, extended in most cases far into the campaniae beyond their walls, often including many
hamlets as well as much open country. From such an extended jurisdiction it
would be rash and probably incorrect to assume that the rural inhabitants had
any such direct participation in elections as the members of an English county
which included all the territory as far as the boundaries of the next shire.
Many parts of the open country in Spain, as in France and unlike England, must
have been wholly unrepresented. But there still remained considerable portions
of it, within the jurisdiction of the greater towns, for which this was not the
case, formally at least. And beginning early in the thirteenth century in
Castile, the hombres buenos were often directed to appear por personeros de los concejos,
not only de las ciudades et de las villas but de
los lugares as well. What amount of actual
participation the inhabitants of a lugar may
have had the words of these formulae are far from making clear. It may have
been very small, and was probably greater in the early fourteenth century than
later. Colmeiro’s opinion that the choice of the town
was construed as the act of all the inhabitants under its jurisdiction, which
most of the French parallels seem to corroborate, may be accepted as the most
probable explanation; but these expressions are not wholly without
significance. In Catalonia, the ordinances of the Cortes of 1307 were made in
an assembly that included none below the syndics of the cities and villae, but their ordinances were expressly extended not to
these cities and towns alone, but “civitatibus et villis et locis nostris Chatalonie, et habitatoribus eorundem”; while in
the Cortes of Barcelona in 1311 both the presence and the advice, as well as
the approbation and consent to the ordinances made, extended to the syndics of
the cities, the villae, “et locorum Chatalonie, qui ad nostram generalem curiam predictam pervenerunt.”
The
procuradores from the Catalan towns varied in number, Barcelona usually having
a larger deputation than any other, but as in the French Estates the voting
units in the Cortes of Catalonia and the other Spanish kingdoms were towns and
not individual proctors. There were of course many differences in the mode of
electing these proctors between the cathedral chapters and the universitates of
the cities and towns, and even among the latter alone. The actual power of the
Cortes in the Spanish kingdoms in the great constitutional age were very great,
and nowhere so great as in Aragon and Catalonia.
As
in all representative bodies found in the developing national States of the
West in this great constitutional period from the thirteenth to the fifteenth
century, the ordinary powers of the Cortes in the Peninsula were exhibited most
strikingly, on the one hand, in their control over enactments of law, less
frequently in the necessity for their assent to measures of national policy;
and on the other, in the great practical power involved in their theoretical
right of making voluntary grants of supply in support of government. To these
might be added an exceptional authority as in times of national crisis or of
royal minority. No doubt it was largely this control over grants that brought
about their control over enactment, and for a time the latter is found probably
more explicitly recognised in Aragon and Catalonia than in any other Western
State. Its gradual disappearance there, as in France in the later Middle Ages,
is to be accounted for chiefly by the inability of the Cortes permanently to
retain their earlier control over the national finances, and by the gradual
growth of impôts permanents, which the
kings were more and more collecting without their assent. Though the Cortes of
the Peninsula at the height of their power were able to exact from their kings
more striking formal recognition of their legal rights and powers than even
England can show in this period, they were eventually stripped of these powers
mainly because of their inability to make permanent the financial dependence of
the Crown upon them, as the English Commons were able in the long run to do,
chiefly on account of the continuous association of the gentry and burgesses in
parliamentary grants from which all were exempt in Spain and France except the
representatives of the towns. This fundamental difference in turn resulted
mainly from the peculiar nature, extensive powers, and wider constituency of
the county courts in England, which have no parallel on the Continent; a
peculiarity which goes back in its historical causes to the character of the
Norman Conquest of England itself, and the resulting consistent and astute
policy of the strong Norman Kings and Henry II of retaining the old machinery
of the county courts as a part of their scheme of establishing a vigorous and
centralised royal administrative system at the expense of the power and
jurisdiction of the feudal lords.
But
if the powers of the Spanish Cortes were short-lived, they were impressive in
their extent while they lasted. In Catalonia as well as in Aragon no laws were
valid to which their assent had not been given, and they were able repeatedly
to exact from their kings formal recognition of extensive popular rights of
which even the concessions of Magna Carta fall short. To these they regularly
required the king to promise his adherence under oath and seal, and this was
done in Aragon and Catalonia, though probably not in Castile, at the formal
session with which the Cortes closed. A consideration of the fueros ratified in
these assemblies, and the constitutions enacted and included in the records of
the Cortes, shews that the rights to which they were able to compel the king’s
assent were in general more extensive and far more popular than any similar
concessions then found in England, and the assumption is warranted that the
proctors of the towns had a more direct and influential part in obtaining them
than any such representatives had in England until a period considerably later.
An illustration of their power in this respect is to be found in varying forms
in an institution of the greatest importance common to all the greater kingdoms
of Christian Spain, known in Catalonia as the Diputación General, a
committee chosen in the Cortes to keep watch in the intervals between their
sessions over the administration of the grants and constitutions to which they
had assented, and consisting of members from each of the Estates.
In
matters of grant the powers of the Cortes were as extensive as in the enactment
of law. The principle was recognised as fully as in England that no new or
unaccustomed dues could be levied by the king without the consent of the Cortes,
and much of the revenue of the government came in the form of the grant or donativo made by the Cortes. The burden of it fell,
however, on the towns alone, as the nobles and knights were supposed to acquit
themselves of their obligation by personal service, and this in time proved one
of the greatest points of practical weakness in the Spanish constitutions and
contributed in large measure to the later development, so fatal to the
liberties of the Peninsula, by which the kings were able gradually to obtain
money without consent of the Estates and thus to dispense with their regular
sessions.
But
in the great age of Spanish constitutionalism this right was jealously guarded
by the Cortes, and the grants were accompanied by petitions for redress of
grievances—gravamina or greuges—of
which the king was prayed to give redress, which are closely analogous to the
cahiers of the French Estates and the petitions of the Commons in England.
These were often complaints of particular nobles or towns and sometimes came
from the whole brazo of the nobles and
knights. Frequently they disclose serious contentions among the different
Estates between which the king had to mediate. The king, as in England, gave
separate responsiones to the several
gravamina, and seems to have had much the same latitude in his replies as is
found in the similar responsiones on
the English Rolls of Parliament.
In
the fifteenth century these great powers of the Spanish Cortes began to
decline. In Castile the number of towns summoned to the Curia rapidly shrank,
and the privileged classes were sometimes not summoned at all. The differences
between the orders were cunningly used by the kings, and revenues were obtained
from other sources which rendered the meetings of the Estates less and less necessary.
Thus after the union of Castile and Aragon a development which had begun before
was rapidly accelerated, and without formally destroying the various Cortes as
institutions the sovereigns were at length able gradually to dispense with them
as the Kings of France did with the Estates. “All in all, the Catholic Kings
had managed to drive the Cortes of their various realms a long way on the road
to destruction; but with all their efforts they were unable entirely to exterminate
the ancient Spanish love of freedom and democracy, as the revolt of the comuneros in the succeeding reign was to prove in
dramatic fashion.”
Germany
While
the Estates in England, France, and Spain are probably the most instructive in
the later Middle Ages to a student of the growth of political institutions in
general, on account of the relatively early development of centralised and
national monarchies, some of the other Western European States where
centralisation came later than the period included in this chapter furnish
remarkable instances of similar institutions and ideas, of a few of which space
remains only for briefer mention.
As
might be expected from the place and the man, it is in Italy and in the time of
the Emperor Frederick II that we find what has been called the “first example
of the modern representative system”. In 1232 he summoned two representatives
of the “third estate” from each city and Castello to an assembly to treat
concerning “the utility of the realm and the common good.” Two years later, in
1234, he ordained that a curia should be held in each of the provinces of the
realm twice in the year, in which should be present, in addition to nobles and
prelates, from each great city four men “de melioribus terre, pro parte universitatis,” and two from each of the smaller cities and castelli,
for the purpose of presenting gravamina or complaints of injuries done by any
official. Another instance similar to that in 1232 is found in 1240. Early in
the fourteenth century instances of representation of the third estate became
fairly common in many parts of Italy. In Savoy, beginning with the fourteenth
century or a little before, assemblies both general and provincial are found
which include representatives of the third estate. Before the end of the
thirteenth century and frequently during the fourteenth and fifteenth in the
States of the Church, meetings of provincial estates were held to which towns
owing fealty to the Pope were bound to send syndics with their mandates; and
even as early as the papacy of Innocent III (1207) there is mention of a
summons to Rome of consults from cities within the papal jurisdiction.
So
general had representation of the third estate become by the middle of the
fourteenth century that Bartolus in his commentary on
the term “consilium,” occurring even in a
constitution of the year 392, assumes it as a matter of course. “Note”, he
says, “that the heads of provinces assemble a council or universal parliament
of the province. Which you must understand is not that all from the province
are bound to go to it... but from all the cities certain persons are deputed as
ambassadors or syndics who represent the city”.
In
Naples and Sicily the tradition of Frederick II was revived under the Spanish
monarchs by the transfer to them as well as to Sardinia of a representative
system on the model of the Spanish Cortes.
In
Germany, during the Middle Ages, the development of representative institutions
was delayed by the persistence of feudal decentralisation and by the autocracy
of the separate princes and nobles, but many indications are found of the
activity of representatives, both as parts of the Landstände and on a wider scale in the Reichstag. In the Landtag, the vassals of the
princes, including the towns, were often able to enforce against their lord the
customary law of the district, and to make good their right of consent to
impositions and to important questions of policy. In the Reichstag, from the
time of William of Holland (1247-56), the towns were at times represented. In
1254 the promise was made that in future assemblies both lords and cities
should send four “sollempnes nuncios” with full
power, and in the next two years several colloquia generalia were held in which these were included, the royal confirmation of the great Landfriedensbund of the Rhenish cities in 1255
formally acknowledging the unanimous consent of nobles “et eciam civitatum.” In the troubled times that followed, the
death of William and in the reign of Rudolf of Habsburg, there is little
evidence of any representation of the third estate as contemplated by William.
In fact it was not until the great struggle between Lewis of Bavaria and Pope
John XXII that this element of the nation was called upon in general to give
support to the imperial claims, as Philip IV of France had done against
Boniface VIII thirty-six years before. In the call to the assembly at Frankfort
in 1338, in which Lewis issued his famous law Licet Iuris,
are included not merely secular and ecclesiastical princes, comites,
and barones, but civitates et communitates, the latter to appear by two
representatives “with sufficient mandate.” Such instances, however, are the exception,
that of 1338 being the result of a crisis in the history of the Empire, as the
first French Estates were of a similar conflict between the Papacy and the
French kingdom; and complete recognition of the claims of the German cities to
representation was not obtained within the period covered by this chapter, and
in fact hardly before the Ewige Landfriede of Maximilian I in 1495 and the great Regiments-Ordnung of 1500—provisions which were not unlike the ordinances obtained by the French
Estates in 1357 after the battle of Poitiers, not only in their both containing
unprecedented recognition of the rights of the towns, but in the fact that both
were followed by periods of reaction toward an absolutism greater than any
which had preceded.
Scotland
Further
illustrations of developments similar in many ways to those in the countries
already mentioned might be given from various other parts of Western Europe
within our period, particularly from Sweden, with its system of four estates,
from the other Scandinavian kingdoms and Iceland, the peculiar institutions of
the Isle of Man, or the “States” of Jersey and Guernsey which have preserved a
surprising number of their medieval institutions even to our own day, from
Switzerland, the Netherlands, and locally from many others. The medieval
Estates of the Irish Parliament, composed as they were exclusively of
Anglo-Irish, were probably modelled too closely upon English precedents to
furnish independent characteristics worth noting here, but, in closing, brief notice
must be taken of a few of the peculiarities of the Estates of medieval
Scotland, some of which were unusual if not unique.
The
contrast in parliamentary institutions north and south of the Tweed is
striking, but the chief difficulty in coming to a real understanding of the
former for the medieval period lies in the constant influence of English
constitutional ideas upon those of Scotland and the regular employment,
especially after the reign of James I, in Scottish official documents of words
and phrases borrowed from England. Are such phrases to mean what they mean in
England, or are they mere formulae little more than meaningless, foreign importations
never really naturalised in Scotland, probably little understood at the time,
and never now to be given the full meaning they undoubtedly have for England.
The latter is the view of the leading present-day historian of the Scots
Parliament. In Scotland the strength of the kings was never as in England great
enough to check the power of the feudal lords in the medieval period and thus
to establish a strong administrative system as a foundation of constitutional
development. Nationalism when it came in Scotland took other forms than
constitutional; it was concentrated neither in the king as in France nor in
parliament. Its first real organ was the Kirk. The earlier parliaments in
Scotland were of the type usual in feudal Europe at that time, composed of the
king’s tenants-in-chief. Innes believed that the addition of burgesses is to be
dated from the Parliament of Cambuskenneth in 1326,
but Professor Rait holds that this is not borne out
by the records. At all events, they were occasionally present before the end of
the fourteenth century, frequently in the fifteenth, and invariably in the
latter half of it. Originally the smaller tenants of the king were bound to
attend his councils as fully as the greater ones, but it is a sign of the
weakness of the Scottish monarchs that they were never able to compel them to
attend. James I attempted to secure their attendance by representatives without
result; about the middle of the fourteenth century the lesser of them were
exempted by law, and at least from that time they practically ceased to come
and their influence is negligible in the Scottish Parliament. This is one of
the greatest of the differences between its constitution and the institutions
of England, and for Scotland one of the most unfortunate. In their powers, the
Scottish Parliaments differed little theoretically from those of the other
European national assemblies, including enactment of law and the grant of
supply, but in the exercise of these powers they were greatly weakened, not
only by their incompleteness of personnel but by the peculiarities of their
procedure. Medieval parliaments everywhere were in the beginning regarded by
their members as a burden, and attendance was only obtained by rulers strong
enough to compel it.
Thus
the king in Scotland had found it impossible to force his lesser tenants to
appear, and even such members as did appear would not remain long enough to do
the necessary business of a parliament. From the second of these facts arose
one of the most peculiar and most unfortunate of Scottish institutions, the
Lords of the Articles. In 1367 the Estates chose certain persons “to hold the
parliament” (ad parliamentum tenendum)
and the rest obtained leave to go home for the harvest. This precedent was
followed with increasing frequency and by the early sixteenth century the only
functions left to the Estates as a whole were the choosing of the Lords of the
Articles at the opening of a parliament and the perfunctory ratification of
their work as a matter of course at the end. Thus the parliament willingly and
regularly handed over its whole power, even at times in the matter of voting a
grant, to this committee. While they sat at all, the whole of the Estates met
together in one house, but these sessions were so short, though they were
fairly frequent, that nothing of importance could be done. Compared with the
national assemblies of England, the Scottish Parliaments throughout the Middle
Ages in general are utterly insignificant in importance, though of considerable
interest on account of their peculiarity. “We possess no writs summoning a
Parliament, no report of a debate in the Scottish Estates... Between 1437 and
1513 it is not easy to discover any single token of definite constitutional
development, either in the direction of absolute government or in that of
popular liberty. Not only does Scotland fail to produce a constitutional movement
like that which characterizes the history of England; she does not develop any
kind of constitution at all. No absolute monarch, no oligarchical council, no
democratic parliament occupies the stage of her history for any length of time,
nor does she know any free cities or any independent duchies. This constant
condition of unstable equilibrium is not precisely analogous to the history of
any other European country, and least of all is it like that of England, where
we are apt to judge of national, by constitutional progress. Yet advance there
certainly was, if not unbroken, still persistent, and persistently unconnected
with questions relating to the constitution.”
The
fate of these representative institutions, so widely spread and so surprisingly
alike, was very different in different parts of Western Europe. In some, as in
Germany, the continuance of feudal decentralisation and the long-belated
appearance of an effective central authority caused these feudal Estates to
remain with many of their essential features unchanged, and prevented their
fusion into the national assembly of a State, often until modern times. In
others, when the like feudal decentralisation gave way or was absorbed in a
strong central authority at a comparatively early period, that authority was
the authority of a monarch who soon made himself practically absolute and
excluded the representatives of the people from all direct participation in the
government of the State. This happened in Spain and France, where the Cortes
and the Estates disappeared entirely, or became so occasional that their
importance was lost as a regular organ of government. England is no doubt the
most striking and far the most important instance of a third development, in
which feudalism early gave way not to absolutism but to constitutionalism;
where the representative Estates remained but became national instead of
feudal, and were never so far weakened by monarchy that they could be
suppressed by it, or prevented from exerting a strong and continuous influence
which preserved the participation of the people in government and consequently
limited the power of the monarch and protected his subjects from the arbitrary
exercise of that power.
Space
will not permit the detailed examination of the later development of all the
medieval Estates, even for the west of Europe alone. It is probably more
important to try to determine the general factors at work on the Estates by a
comparison, in greater detail than would be otherwise possible, of two
countries whose development was strikingly different but where these
developments occurred nearly enough together, and therefore amid general
surroundings sufficiently alike to enable us to discover the real causes of
their dissimilarity.
For
such a purpose the contrast of France and England is the most valuable. In
both, the transition from feudal to what we usually call modem conditions took
place before the Renaissance. In both, the changes are nearly enough
contemporary to be comparable; and though the results were very different in
the two countries, they were brought about amid conditions of the same age and
of the same general kind. In no other country, with the possible exception of
Spain, do these fundamental changes come early enough safely to illustrate by their
peculiarities the factors that created the modern out of the medieval political
world, and the constitutional history of Spain has not been sufficiently
studied.
“England,
after the Norman Conquest, began in a monarchy almost absolute; and it is perhaps
for that reason that in the seventeenth century it emerged as a monarchy
representative. Feudal France began with a royal authority almost totally powerless;
and it is probably on that account that she ended in the seventeenth century in
the monarchy absolute.” In these words the late Professor Esmein has pointed out the first and greatest of the factors which turned the
institutions of France and England into channels so different from each other.
But this statement is an apparent paradox whose profound truth becomes
apparent only when examined in greater detail. Elsewhere the same author
indicates another of these factors in the growing community of interest between
the feudal nobility in England and the rising “middle class.” But the second of
these factors with all its vast importance came in part as a result of the
first. The broadest lines of distinction in constitutional development between
France and England lie ultimately in the fact that in the former kingdom the
feudal monarchy passed into the absolute monarchy while in England it became a
constitutional monarchy. Why did one become absolute while the other became
constitutional? It was because the English monarchy became national before it
ceased to be feudal, at a time when the French monarchy still remained feudal
only. When then the feudal element disappeared, as it ultimately did in both
kingdoms, in England its place was taken by a government in which the Estates
had already begun to share; in France there was no power in existence to replace
the feudal monarchy but the uncontrolled power of an absolute king. The
difference is owing to the regular participation of the Estates in England before
the feudal monarchy disappeared, a participation which existed in that period
of French history, with one exception, only on the rare occasions of popular
unrest. On the decline of feudalism in France there was no authority, and no
body of men, politically prepared permanently to take over or even to share
with the king in the centralised government that was replacing feudal
decentralisation. That place could be taken only by an authority that was at
once centralised and national, and the only one then in existence to do it was
a strong, national, but practically absolute monarch. To put it otherwise, in
England there was participation and there was representation while feudal
conditions still remained, and therefore when these conditions disappeared the
strong centralised national power which emerged was one which retained the
participation of the Estates. In France, since this participation had not begun
during the period when feudal conditions flourished, so it could not continue
when they began to decline, and the feudal monarchy was replaced by one
practically, even if not theoretically, absolute. These results are inherent in
feudal monarchy itself, and partly owing to the unusual strength of the feudal
monarchs in England after the Norman Conquest, partly to the circumstances of
that conquest itself. As Professor Dicey says, “A King who is forced to receive
advice, means, at the present day, a King who is a King in name alone, who ‘
reigns but does not govern.’ According to the ideas prevailing in the eleventh
century, it was rather the King’s privilege than his duty to receive counsel
from the great men of his kingdom... The more powerful the monarch, the more
frequent the conventions of his barons. In England these assemblies were
constantly held, whilst in France, where the royal power was feeble, they
became more and more rare. The reason of this is clear. A feudal monarch had to
dread the isolation, not the union, of his liege men. A feudatory who threw off
his sovereign’s rule, withdrew from his counsels. The Dukes of Burgundy, or
Normandy, gradually dropped attendance at the royal court. For once let the
barons attend their lord, and his authority was secure, since attendance was an
acknowledgement of his sovereign rights...”
The
decisive factor in determining these results for England was the early
centralisation of administration, a centralisation which came far sooner there
than elsewhere. It was this that made England the only Western country with a
common law little influenced by Rome, and this too ultimately made her a
constitutional instead of an absolute monarchy. The great founders of this
strong central administration, William I, Henry I, and Henry II, were the first
great builders of modern constitutionalism. They laid in their administrative
reforms the foundation on which the superstructure of the English
“representative monarchy” was later to rise. Save for the permanent foundations
they laid, the outbursts of popular discontent at arbitrary rule would have
been as ephemeral in England as the protests of the French États Généraux in the fourteenth century.
It
was not so much mere centralisation that had these important results, it was
early centralisation. France became centralised too, but too late to save
constitutionalism or to secure for her a common law based almost wholly on the
customs of the land. England, on the other hand, received at the strong hands
of her kings before the eleventh and twelfth centuries were over an
administrative system so extensive, so strong, and so uniform, that it created
the immediate necessity for a uniform procedure and ultimately for a system of
legal principles common to the whole realm, and this at so early a period that
the gradually recovering Roman Law was not yet strong enough to make its bid to
be that common system. When the law of Rome had again become strong enough in
Western Europe, for England the opportunity had passed, and England was already
inoculated against it; she already had a common law of her own, which Rome was
never afterwards able to replace. England had been forced by her early
centralisation of judicial administration to build a general system of common
law from materials then at hand, and at that early time it was not yet Roman
but English materials alone that were at hand. England and her descendants
alone of all the Western nations have today a common law almost entirely
independent of Rome, on account of the great centralising work of her kings in
the eleventh and twelfth centuries; and mainly for the same reason, England
alone preserved for the Western world the continuity of the development from
feudalism to constitutionalism. This could not have been merely because England
became centralised, for other nations became centralised too. It was because
she became centralised early, earlier than any of the other national States of
the West. It was in part the consequences of the nature of the Conquest itself
and in part the masterful character of the line of kings the Conquest gave to
England, that led to this early centralisation of administration at the expense
of the jurisdiction of the feudal lords; and the monarchy that resulted, though
in character feudal, was the strongest of its day. But the strength resulted
not only in the earliest centralisation of jurisdiction, procedure, and law; to
it we must attribute that other characteristic which Professor Dicey considers
the chief badge of royal authority in feudal times, the regularity of the
attendance of the barones in answer to the
royal summons to the Curia Regis. Thus the barones became the first “estate”; and, thanks to the strength of the king, an estate
which was never suffered long to absent itself from the work of his councils.
And it was with this estate, when the populus was extended to include the milites and the
burgesses, beginning with the thirteenth century, that the representatives of
these classes gradually merged, as new parts “dans une organisation préexistante.”
In
the beginning it was the feudal obligation of the barons to attend their lord’s
court, and it is the unusual vigour with which the English king was able to
exact it with regularity, rather than the strength of these barons or their
independent spirit, to which we must trace back the causes of English
constitutionalism. But in order to make the whole of this development clear, it
is not only necessary to understand its beginnings, but its results as well.
The work of the early kings may be summarised as: (1) a centralisation of
administration stronger and earlier than any found elsewhere, (2) a regularity
in the meetings of the Curia, which the strength of the English king made
unique in Western Europe, (3) a consequent sharing in the tasks of
administration between king and barons, which in time became continuous,
permanent, and regular. And this sharing in the burdens of administration
became of greater and greater constitutional importance the more closely it
brought the members of the King’s Council, as iusticiarii itinerante, in closer and closer touch with the
knights in the county courts, whose political development had been steadily
going on locally side by side with that of the central Curia. Thus began the
rapprochement of the estate of the barons and those knights who were later to
be incorporated with them as an added estate in a representative parliament.
It
was the encroachment of a centralised authority upon the powers and
jurisdiction of the feudal lords that marked the development of both England
and France in the later Middle Ages. But in England this had started earlier
and was becoming national and constitutional even while it yet remained in many
respects feudal. The individual barone became
a baronagium, an estate of the realm, though
still feudal vassals of a common lord, while their feudal auxilia gradually
became parliamentary grants, without wholly losing at once their original
feudal character; and the nature of these gradual transitions is typical of the
whole development from feudalism to nationalism, and in this case to
constitutionalism.
Originally
the king was both dominus and Rex. In the Norman period he had been able
largely to “live of his own”. These strictly feudal revenues as dominus
sufficed for most of his needs. But every advance of the central administration
tended to increase his revenues as Rex, and an increase of these revenues was,
we may suspect, as often as not the real reason for administrative reforms,
rather than any desire for justice. In general, the extension of this central
administration meant a corresponding transformation of the king’s revenues: it
was more to the king as Rex and less and less as mere dominus that they were
coming. The fact is that on its economic side feudalism was declining, and the
ordinary revenues properly to be called feudal were gradually drying up. It was
partly resentment against this that led to the baronial uprising which produced
Magna Carta. The barons rightly attributed part of this result to the reforms
of Henry II, and among their demands were included several which would have
undone some important parts of his work if the designs of the barons had been
fully realised.
This
drying-up of feudal revenue necessarily affected the king, whose demesne was
involved, no less than the lands in the hands of tenants. Thus John and Henry
III were driven more and more to depend on grants, which as we have seen were
truly national in scope even though their origin is to be traced to feudal
custom. The strong kings of the eleventh and twelfth centuries, in adding to
their strength by extending their claims as Rex, could hardly have foreseen
that in this nationalising the necessity of taking the nation into partnership
in that administration. But the proof that they were actually doing so is seen
in the baronial claims in the reign of Henry III, as well as the baronial
demand for a control of administration in the Provisions of Oxford, and the
ordinances of the barons in 1311, in the concessions of Edward I in the
confirmation of the charters of 1297, in the distinction made in the reign of
Edward II between the king and the Crown, in the extension of baronial control
over the Exchequer and even over the King’s Wardrobe, and finally in the rapid
enlargement of the powers and claims of parliament which reached their height
at the time of the Lancastrians.
By
making English administration national, the kings of the eleventh and twelfth
centuries also made inevitable national participation in that administration,
just so soon as the nation should become conscious of itself, and just so far
as classes or “estates” of the people strong enough and politically
self-conscious enough should arise to demand their proper share in this
participation. This consciousness of nationalism began to be effective in the
thirteenth century, particularly in the long weak reign of Henry III, and by
the fourteenth century it had extended down from the barons to knights and
burgesses who, in theory if not entirely in fact, had become the commons of the
whole realm—communa totius Angliae.
Thus
constitutionalism in England took the place of feudalism and gradually grew out
of it. In France, on the contrary, the original estate of the barons never
became so closely connected with the administration of the kingdom as in
England, largely because the king was unable to compel them regularly to attend
him. Neither was there in France that early strengthening and centralising of
administration to be seen in England, nor the equally important linking up of
the central Curia and the local courts by a systematic and periodical
employment of itinerant members of the Curia. Without this encroachment of
royal power as in England, feudal decentralisation in France remained longer
and while it remained was less affected by the growing tendency toward
nationalism. Thus when feudalism finally did decline in France, the royal power
that replaced it was the power of a king who did in fact become national, but
in doing so did not to the same degree become constitutional as in England. No
Estates were in France so closely interwoven with the royal administration that
they could not be dispensed with without endangering that administration itself
or destroying its national character. In the seventeenth century Loyseau could say of the French monarchy that it was a
monarchy royal and not seignorial, “a perfect sovereignty in which the estates
have no part.”
Elsewhere,
for local reasons, the developments were somewhat different. In Scotland, for
example, no powerful kings appeared during the earlier development, as in
England, and in later times no constitutional monarchy really worthy the name.
But the latter result was not, as in France, owing to the growth of an absolute
monarchy, but rather to the longer continuance of feudal anarchy. To the very
end of the Middle Ages and long afterward, the kings of Scotland were both
irresponsible and weak. Though parliaments were frequent, they were too little
representative of the nation to impose any constitutional limitations upon the
king of lasting importance, while at the same time the monarchy was so completely
at the mercy of factions of the nobles that it was never able to establish
itself on an independent basis. Scotland produced neither strong monarchy nor
constitutionalism; she retained feudal anarchy so long that neither of these
had a chance to develop in the Middle Ages. Even locally her constitutional
life was weaker than in most continental countries, though by no means
non-existent. The representative institutions of the burghs, particularly in
the conventions of the royal burghs, have no doubt been given an exaggerated
importance by some Scottish constitutional writers of modern times, and a
greater antiquity has been attributed to them than contemporary evidence seems
to warrant. Nevertheless, before the Reformation, there can be little doubt
that it was in these burghs that Scotland’s chief constitutional life was to be
found, and the burghs are at last beginning to receive the attention from
constitutional historians that they have long deserved.
In
most other Western States, where neither royal absolutism nor constitutional
monarchy developed, this lack of development was the result of the lateness of
the unification. Effective centralised administration and a common law go hand
in hand as a rule. Germany, for example, got neither of these before the late
fifteenth century. This meant, however, merely that the communes remained
local; they were never merged in an effective centralised but constitutional
monarchy as in England nor destroyed by an effective centralised absolutism as
in France. These institutions survived, but survived only locally, until modern
times. In many places, however, the local constitutional life remained strong
and vigorous and outlasted the Middle Ages to contribute to an important
degree, when later combined with parliamentary institutions borrowed from England,
to Continental constitutionalism in modem times and under modern conditions,
when central authority had finally become established and revolution had
destroyed the most important remnants of feudal particularism which had
burdened it hitherto.
The
later history of the medieval Estates thus varied widely from country to
country. In some they remained merely local, in others they for a time shewed
promise of combining with the growing centralised power of the nation, only to
be later suppressed by the monarchy. In England, circumstances were more
favourable, and constitutional monarchy resulted. But amid all these
variations, it may be said that, whenever constitutionalism arose out of an
earlier feudalism, its rise and its continuance alike were conditioned upon a
corresponding appearance and participation in government of the medieval
Estates or their descendants.
PEASANT LIFE AND RURAL CONDITIONS(c. 1100 to c. 1500)
|