READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
CHAPTER XX.TENDENCIES OF EUROPEAN THOUGHT IN THE AGE OF THE REFORMATION.
WHEN the sixteenth
century opens, the West, with the exception of Italy, is still medieval,
distinguished by a superficial uniformity of mind, thinking ideas which it has
ceased to believe and using a learned tongue which it can hardly be said to
understand. When the century closes, the West, with the possible exception of
Italy, now fallen as far to the rear as she once stood in the van, has become
modern; its States have developed what we may term a personal consciousness and
an individual character, have created a vernacular literature and a native art,
and have faced new problems which they seek by the help of their new tongues to
state and to solve. In Spain, the land of ancestral and undying pride, the
humors of a decayed chivalry have been embodied in a tale which moves to
laughter without ever provoking to contempt. In Portugal the navigators have
created afresh the epic feeling; a new Iliad has been begotten, where swifter
ships plough a vaster sea than was known to the ancient Greeks, where braver
heroes than Agamemnon do battle against a mightier Troy, while travelers fare
to remoter and stranger lands than those visited by Odysseus. In France, where
the passion for unity is beginning to work like madness in the brain, Rabelais
speaks in his mother tongue the praises of the new learning; Montaigne makes it
the vehicle of the new temper and its cultured doubt; Clement Marot uses it to
sing the Psalms of the ancient Hebrew race; John Calvin to defend and commend
his strenuous faith; while Descartes, born in this century though writing in
the next, states his method, defines his problem, and determines the evolution
of modern philosophy, in the language of the people as well as in that of the
learned. In England the century began in literary poverty, but it ended
in the unapproached wealth of the Elizabethan age. In Germany, where the main
intellectual interest was theological and confessional, Martin Luther gave the
people hymns that often sound like echoes of the Hebrew Psalter; Kepler,
listening to the music which nature reserves for the devout ear, discovered the
unity which moves through her apparent disorder; and Jakob Boehme, though but a
cobbler, had visions of higher mysteries than the proud can see. The
Netherlands proved their heroism in their struggle for independence, and their
love of knowledge in the tolerant reasonableness that made them a home for the
persecuted of all lands. In Scotland William Dunbar, Gawin Douglas, and David Lindsay shed luster upon the early decades of the century,
while in its later years Reformers like Knox and scholars like Andrew Melville
trained up a people who had imagination enough to love and achieve liberty
without neglecting letters. The thought which at once effected and reflected so
immense a revolution can be here traced only in the broadest outlines.
We are met at the
threshold by a two-fold difficulty-one which concerns the included thought, and
another which concerns the thought excluded. The sixteenth century is great in
religion rather than philosophy, and stands in remarkable contrast to its
immediate successor, which is great in philosophy rather than religion. With
the latter, the great modern intellectual systems may be said to begin; and to
it belong such names as Bacon and Descartes, Hobbes and Locke, Spinoza and
Leibniz, Gassendi and Malebranche. But without the
earlier century the later would have been without its problems and therefore
without its thinkers. The preeminence of the one in religion involved the
preeminence of the other in thought; for what exercises the spirit tends to
emancipate speculation and raises issues that reason must discuss and resolve
before it can be at peace with itself and its world. Hence the thought whose
course we have to follow is thought in transition, dealing with the old
questions, yet waking to the new, quickened by what is behind to enquire into
what is within and foreshadow what is before. But, while the thought that is to
concern us may thus be described as moving in the realm of our ultimate
religious ideas, the thought that is not to concern us moves in the realm of
political and social theory. The two realms touch, indeed, and even
interpenetrate; yet they are distinct. The ideal of human society is a
religious ideal; but it is a consequence or a combination of religious ideas
rather than one of the ideas themselves. Hence, though certain of the most
potent thinkers of the sixteenth century occupied themselves with the
constitution and order of human society, with the actual or ideal State both in
itself and in relation to the actual or ideal Church, yet they must here be
rigorously excluded, and our view confined to the thought that had to do with
the religious interpretation of man and his Universe.
Latin and Teuton.
It is customary to
distinguish the Renaissance, as the revival of letters, from the Reformation as
the revival of religion. But the distinction is neither formally correct nor
materially exact. The Renaissance was not necessarily secular and classical, it
might be, and often was, both religious and Christian; nor was the Reformation
essentially religious and moral, it might be and often was political and
secular. Of the two revivals the one is indeed in point of time the elder; but
the elder is not so much a cause as simply an antecedent of the younger. Both
revivals were literary and interpretative, both were imitative and recreative;
but they differed in spirit, and they differed also in province and in results.
There was a revival of letters which could not possibly become a reformation of
religion, and there was a revival which necessarily involved such a
reformation; and the two revivals must be distinguished if the consequences are
to be understood.
The roots of the
difference may be found, partly, in the minds that studied the literatures, and
partly in the literatures they studied, though even here the qualities, the
interests, and the motives of the minds only stand the more clearly revealed.
The difference is better expressed by a racial than by a temporal distinction;
the term ‘race’, indeed, as here used does not denote a unity of blood, which
can seldom if ever exist, but unities of language, inheritance, association,
and ideas. In this sense, the Catholic South was in speech, in custom, in social
temper, in political and municipal institutions distinctly Latin; and for
similar reasons the Protestant North may be termed Teutonic. Now of
these two the Latin race was in thought the more secular, while the Teutonic
was the more religious; but as regards custom and institutions the Latin
peoples were the more conservative, while the Teutonic were the more inclined
to radical change. And this is a difference which their respective histories
may in some measure explain. The Latin race, especially in Italy, was the heir
of the Roman Empire, still a vivid memory and a living influence; its monuments
survived, its paganism had not utterly perished; its gods were still named in
popular speech; customs which it had sanctioned and dreams which it had
begotten persisted, having refused, as it were, to undergo Christian baptism.
Italy was to the Latins as much a holy land as Palestine had been to the
Crusaders, with graves and relics and shrines lying in every valley and looking
out from every hill; and these appealed all the more to the imagination since
ecclesiastical Rome was a reality and imperial Rome a memory and a dream. The
Eternal City was like a desolate widow who yet tarried and yearned for the
return of the Caesar who had been her spouse.
And if Rome lived
in the dust of her ancient roads and the ruins of her temples, the Italian
peoples and States seemed singularly suggestive of Greece. Their republics and
tyrants, their civic life and military adventurers, their rich cities with
their colonies and commerce, their rapid changes of fortune, their swift
oscillations from freedom to bondage and from bondage back to freedom, their
love of art and of letters, their mutual jealousies and ambitions were Greek
rather than Roman ; indeed at certain moments they might almost make us feel as
if ancient Greece had risen from the dead and come to live upon the Italian
soil. Here then the Renaissance could not but be classical : not the product of
some accident like the capture of a city or the fall of an ancient dynasty, but
the inevitable outcome of minds quickened by the Italian air and made creative
by the vision of a vast inheritance. The Teutonic mind, on the contrary, had no
classical world behind it; its pagan past was remote, dark, infertile, without
art or literature, or philosophy, or history, or any dream of a universal
empire which had once held sway over civilized man. In a word, its conscious
life, its social being, its struggles for empire and towards civilization, its
chivalry, its crusades, its mental problems and educational processes, all
stood rooted in the Christian religion. Behind this the memory of men did not
go, and into the darkness beyond the eye could as little penetrate as the
vision of the man can trace the growth of knowledge in his own infant mind.
Now these
differing conditions made it as natural that the Teutonic Renaissance should
concern itself with the early Christian ideal as that the Latin should with the
ancient classical literature; and, where they touched religion, that the one should
be more occupied with its intellectual side and the other with its
institutional; for where the Roman Empire had lived the Roman Church now
governed. The literature which the Teutonic mind mainly loved and studied and
edited was patristic and Christian; but the literature which the Latin mind
chiefly cultivated was classical and pagan. The Latin taught the Teuton how to
read, to edit, and to handle ancient books; but nature taught both of them the
logic that binds together letters and life. As a consequence, the Latin
Renaissance became an attempt to think again the thoughts, and live again the
life, embalmed in the literature of Greece and Rome; while the German
Renaissance became an attempt to reincarnate the apostolical mind. The Latin
tendency was towards classical Naturalism, but the Teutonic tendency was
towards the ideals of the Scriptures, both Hebrew and Greek. Among the Latins
almost every philosophical system of antiquity reappeared, though in an
instructively inverted order; but among the Teutons the field was occupied by
theologies based on Augustine and Paul, while philosophy began as an
interpretation, not of literary thought or societies, but of man, individual
and social, as he had lived and was living.
Hence, in the
region of belief the Latins were the more critical and the Teutons the more
positive. The thought which the Latins studied was that of a world into which
Christ had not entered, though it was one in which Caesar had reigned; but the
thought which the Teutons cultivated had Christ as its source and God as its
supreme object. The Latin Renaissance thus produced two most dissimilar yet
cognate phenomena : intellectual systems affecting mainly the notion of Deity,
and Orders like the Society of Jesus, organized for the work of conservation
and reaction. On the other hand, the parallel phenomena produced by the
Teutonic Renaissance were attempts either to revive the religion of the
apostolic literature, or to found the Protestant Churches and States. What
concerns us here is the new thought, and not the new organizations; and these
preliminary distinctions and discussions will enable us to set the Latin, or
Classical Renaissance, in its true relation to the Teutonic or religious.
Influence of
Lorenzo Valla on the Reformers.
We begin with the
most obvious of the influences exercised by the Revival of Letters upon the
thought of the sixteenth century, viz., those concerned with
grammar and what it signified, and with language as the creation and the
interpreter of thought. It has often been said that the Church preserved the
knowledge of Latin as a living tongue; but Lorenzo Valla (1406-57) would have
said, if the tongue were still alive it were better dead. As a grammarian Valla
held grammar to be higher than dialectic, for it took as many years to learn as
dialectic took months; and he may be said to have discovered literary and
historical criticism by executing with its help judgment on three famous
documents, viz., the Vulgate, which he condemned as faulty in style and
incorrect in translation; the Donation of Constantine, which he proved by its
anachronisms to be late and false and forged; and the Apostolic Symbol, whose
terms and clauses he showed could not be of apostolic origin. His criticism of
these documents (we omit all reference to that of the pseudo-Dionysius) was
prophetic and more potent in a later generation than in his own. Erasmus
published in 1505 the Annotationes on
the Vulgate, and in a dedication which served as a preface he compared Valla as
a grammarian and Nicolas of Lyra as a theologian; and he argued from the errors
which had been proved to exist in the version which the Church had in a sense
canonized by use, in a way that was at once an apology and a call for his own
edition of the Greek New Testament nine years before it appeared. In 1517 a
copy of the De Donatione Constantini Magni came into the hands of Ulrich von Hütten, who published it, and with his usual careless
audacity dedicated it to the Pope, whom he straightway proceeded to denounce as
a usurper and robber. Later this was sent to Luther just as he was meditating
his De Captivitate Babylonien Ecclesiae; and it strengthened his trust in the German people, confirmed
him in the belief that the Pope was Antichrist, and fortified him for the
daring deed of burning the Pope’s Bull. The criticism of the Apostles’ Creed
indicated a method of discussing dogma which only needed to be applied to
become a theory of development capable of dissolving the vast systems of the
traditional schools. We need not be surprised that Calvin speaks of Valla as
“an acute and judicious man, and an instrument of the Divine Will”.
The Italian mind
was simple in spite of all its subtle complexity, and in the Renaissance it was
like the explorer who set out to find a new way to India and found a new world
instead. It had no more typical son than Giovanni Pico della Mirandola. He was, if we are to believe his nephew
and biographer, chivalrous, beautiful, radiant, a man it was impossible to see
without loving, an artist who loved art, a thinker who delighted in thought, a
seeker whose passion it was to find the truth, and who would gladly have sold
all he possessed to buy it. Born in 1463, he studied Canon Law at Bologna;
then, first at Padua, and later at Paris, he cultivated philosophy. When only
twenty-one he returned to Italy and read Plato in Florence under Ficino; three
years later he travelled to Rome, where he drew up nine hundred theses,
philosophical and theological, which he offered to discuss with the scholars of
all lands, promising, if they came, to bear the cost of their journey. But
heresy was discovered in some of the theses, and the disputation was
prohibited. Later he devoted himself to a contemplative life, renounced the
world, divided his goods between his nephew and the poor, saying that, once he
had finished the studies which he had undertaken, he should wander barefoot
round the world in order that he might preach Christ. He was a mystic; nature
was to him a parable, history was an allegory, and every sensuous thing an
emblem of the Divine. He magnified man, though he distrusted self; and as he
believed that truth came only by revelation he felt bound to seek it from those
who had thus received it from God. Hence he searched for truth, successively in
Aristotle, in Plato, in Plotinus, and in the pseudo-Dionysius, who seemed to
many, even after Valla had written, the source of the highest and purest truth.
But as Pico said, philosophy seeks truth, theology finds it, but religion
possesses it ; and the truth which religion possesses is God's. Man can best
discover it in the place where God has been pleased to set it.
Now, in his quest
for truth and its purest sources, Pico heard of the Cabbala, and conceived it
to be the depository of the most ancient wisdom, the tradition of the
aboriginal revelation granted to man. And just then John Reuchlin, German
mystic and scholar, found Pico. He was older in years but younger in mind. He
had studied philology in Paris, law in Orleans, and he had lectured on Greek in
Tübingen; he was then on his second visit to Italy, with all the mystic in him
alive and unsatisfied. The God whom he wanted, the logic of the Schools could
not give him; by their help he might transcend created existence, though even
then what they led him to was only the boundless sea of negation. In Aristotle
the impossible, in Plato the incredible, was emphasized; but in the region of
spirit things were necessary which thought found impossible or reason
pronounced incredible. The Neo-Pythagorean School saved Reuchlin from the
tyranny of the syllogism and restored his faith. In this mood he came to Pico,
and to his mood the Cabbala appealed; its philosophy was a symbolical theology
which invested words and numbers, letters and names, things and persons, with a
divine sense. But Reuchlin was more than a mystic with a passion for fantastic
mysteries; he was also a scholar; and the idea that there were truths locked up
in Hebrew, the tongue which God Himself had spoken at the Creation and which He
had then given to man, compelled him to learn the language that he might read
the thought in the words of Deity. So he put himself to school under a Jewish
physician, acquired enough Hebrew to pursue his studies independently, and, as
a result, published in 1506 his De Rudimentis Hebraicis. He himself named this book a monumentum aere perennius, and history has justified the name. It
helped to define and determine the religious tendencies in Teutonic humanism,
to change the fanciful mysticism that had begotten the book into a spirit at
once historical, critical, and sane. It practically made the Hebrew Scriptures
Christian, an original text which could be used as a Court of appeal for the
correction of the translation and of the canon which the usage of the Church
had accepted and endorsed. Knowledge of the language thus made the
interpretation of the Old Testament more historical and more ethical; it could
now be read as little through the Gnosticism of the Cabbala as through the
Roman associations of the Vulgate.
The event which took
the Old Testament out of the hand of phantasy turned it into an instrument of
reform; for if it is doubtful whether Protestantism could have arisen without
the knowledge of the Old Testament, it is certain that without it the Reformed
Church could not have assumed the shape it took. In all this, of course,
specific dangers might lie for the scholar who could no longer freely use the
allegorism of Alexandria to convey the New Testament into the most impossible
places of the Old, and who was therefore tempted to reverse the process and
employ the language and spirit of the Old Testament in the interpretation of
the New. But these dangers were still in the future; for the present it will be
enough to recall the story, told in an earlier volume, of the controversy
between Reuchlin and Pfefferkorn, and of the burning
of Reuchlin’s books by the Inquisition. In consequence of this unjust
treatment, the humanists addressed a series of letters, at once eulogistic and
apologetic, to Reuchlin, which were published in 1514 under the title Epistolae clarorum Virorum. (The second edition in 1519 substituted ‘illustrium’ for ‘clarorum’.)
This book
suggested to one of the younger and brighter humanists, John Jäger, better known as Crotus Rubeanus, Luther’s ‘Crotus noster suavissimus’, a
professor at Erfurt, a series of imaginary epistles written by vagrant students
in the execrable dog-Latin of the Schools, to Ortwinus Gratius, otherwise Ortwin de Graes, professor of belles lettres at Cologne, a man whom Luther in his most
emphatic and plain-spoken style described as ‘poetistam asinum, lupum rapacem, si non potiuscrocodilum’. The Epistolae,
while describing the experiences or adventures of their supposed authors, and
it is here where the characters so humorously reveal themselves, praise Gratius as well as the divines and divinity of the Schools,
and censure the ‘poetae seculares’
or ‘juristae’ who had eulogized Reuchlin. In their
composition various scholars collaborated, notably Ulrich von Hutten, then
ablaze with the enthusiasm for Germany and the passion against Rome which made
the strife a joy to his soul. “The prison is broken”, he cried, “the captive is
free and will return no more to bondage. O century when studies bloom and
spirits awake, it is happiness to live in thee!”.
Strauss thought
the Epistolae a supreme work of art,
and placed them alongside Don Quixote, since they were
pervaded by so excellent a humor as to be higher and better than any merely
satirical production. There is here ground for ample and radical differences,
but on one point there is none, the success of the satire. It deceived the very
elect; the friars who were satirized saw the truth of the portrait and did not
feel its shame, even though the men of serious mind, who could not be deceived,
were offended. Erasmus did not love it; nor did Luther, who said “Votum probo, opus non probo” and named the author “einen Hanswurst”; but it made the Schoolmen ridiculous,
and while they were laughed at Reuchlin was applauded. He died in 1522, six
years after the Epistolae had appeared, the
same year in which Luther published his New Testament, sorrowing over the lapse
from the Church and from letters of his young kinsman, Melanchthon, and over
the coming revolution which yet had in him a plain prophet and a main cause.
Erasmus.
In 1516, two years
after the first volume of the Epistolae,
Erasmus’ Novum Instrumentum appeared.
The man himself we need neither discuss nor describe. He was a humanist, that
is, his main interest was literature; but his humanism was German; that is, the
literature which mainly interested him was religious. In an age of great
editors he was the most famous; but he was not a thinker, nor a man who could
seize or be seized by large ideas and turn them into living and creative
forces. His greatest editorial achievements were connected not with the
classics, where his haste and his agility of mind made him often a faithless
guide, but with the New Testament and the Fathers of the Church. Religion he
loved for the sake of letters rather than letters for the sake of religion. He
had a quick eye, a sharp pen, a fine humor, and could hold up to man and
society a mirror which showed them as they were. He was fastidious and disliked
discomfort, yet he could make it picturesque and amusing. His letters are like
a crowded stage on which his time lives forever; and we can hear and see even
as his ear heard and as his eye saw. We are, indeed, never allowed to forget
that he is a rather too self-conscious spectator; and that while all around him
men differ and he is a main cause of their differences, yet there is nothing he
more desires than to be left alone to live as untroubled as if he had no mind.
He is ‘so thin-skinned that a fly would draw blood’; yet, or possibly
therefore, he is a good hater, especially of the ignorant mob, the obtuse and
vulgar men who could not see or feel the satire within the compliment or the
irony hidden in an ambiguous phrase.
He is one of the
men whose unconscious revelations of himself have a nameless charm; we see him
as a student whose very circumstances remind him of his origin, ortus a scorto as
his enemies said, impecunious, forced into an Order he did not love, thirsting
for a knowledge hard to obtain, seeking it at home or in Paris, where life is
fast while his clerical guardian is suspicious and his own temper
self-indulgent. Then we are touched by the early struggles of a scholar who
loved learning and good living, and neither liked nor acquiesced in the poverty
which seemed his destined lot, though we may be offended by his complaints,
which are too frequent to be dignified, and his appeals for help, which are too
urgent to be compatible with self-respect as we understand it. His pictures of
our gracious and spacious England, loved because it is so kind to the stranger,
the seclusion and erudition of Oxford, the repose and learned activity of
Cambridge, the regal Henry, the magnificent Wolsey, the devout Colet, the
genial More, the statesmanlike yet thoughtful Warham,
who can rule the Church and yet remember the scholars who serve it, are of a
sort which pleases the reader and which he loves to read. And if he desires first-hand
knowledge of the manners and morals of a picturesque day, the miseries of the
sea and the comforts of the shore, or the discomforts of continental travel
with its strange bedfellows, crowded inns, dirty linen, and unsavory food; or
of the dignified society and refined art of living to be then found in the
great Italian cities; or of Rome and Roman society under Julius II, where a
warlike Pontiff and cultured Cardinals, the spirit of the Borgia and the temper
of the Renaissance, make the capital of Christendom an epitome of the world; or
of the hopes, the disappointments, and the sorrows of an editor with a zeal for
letters and a passion for praise, who negotiates now with mean and now with
open-handed publishers, and stands between three publics, one sympathetic and
appreciative, a second suspicious and sore and critical, fearful lest he go too
far, and a third exacting and insatiable, determined to compel him to go much
further than he wishes; or of the Reforming men and movements, the strange and tempestuous
Luther, the audacious and restless Hütten, the
moderate and scholarly Pirkheimer, the conciliatory
and reasonable Melanchthon, the heroic and magnanimous Zwingli, the learned and
large-minded Oecolampadius,-then he will find this
knowledge superabundantly in this vivid and entertaining correspondence.
Yet, if we would
know Erasmus, he must be studied in his more serious works, as well as in his
letters. There we shall find the clergy of all grades from the friar and the
parish priest to the Pope, the superstitions and ceremonies, the pilgrimages
and fastings, the distinctions in dress and food, the
worship of relics and of Saints,-pilloried and satirized and killed, at least
so far as ridicule can kill. And his lighter moods express his graver mind; and
unless this mind be known there is no person in history to whom we shall find
it harder to be just. He is a proud and a strong man, when questions are at
issue for which he supremely cares; but he will seem to us indifferent or vain
or weak where the question is one for which he did not care, however much we
may wish he had. And, curiously, where his strength as well as his weakness
most appears is in his edition of the New Testament. The inaccuracies of his
text, the few and the poor authorities he consulted, the haste of the editor,
the hurry of the publisher, the carelessness of the printer, and the facility
with which he inserted in the third and later editions a text like 1
John V. 7, which he had omitted in the first and second, are all instances
of weakness familiar even to the unlearned.
But the sagacity,
which saw in the Epistle to the Hebrews a work instinct with the spirit but
without the style of Paul, which doubted whether John the Apostle were the
author of the Apocalypse, which discerned in Luke the Greek of a writer skilled
in literature, which perceived in the Gospels quotations from a memory which
could be at fault, or which inferred textual errors even where the authorities
were agreed, is characteristic of the honest scholar and indicative of the
courageous man. What is still more significant, is the deliberate way in which
as an editor and exegete he repeats the views and reaffirms the arguments of
his more occasional works. Stunica charged him with
the impiety of casting doubt on the claims and the authority of the Roman See
and of denying the primacy of Peter. The Church, Erasmus said, was the
congregation of all men throughout the whole world who agreed in the faith of
the Gospel. As to the Lord’s Supper, he saw neither good nor use in a body
imperceptible to the senses; and he found no place in Scripture which said that
the Apostles had consecrated bread and wine into the body and blood of the
Lord. Heathenism of life and Judaism of worship had come upon the Church from
the neglect of the Gospel. Ceremonies were positive laws made by Bishops or
Councils, Popes or Orders which could not supersede the laws of nature or of
God. The priest who wore a lay habit or let his hair grow was punished; but if
he became a debauchee he might yet remain a pillar of the Church.
These were brave
things for a man so timid as Erasmus and so desirous of standing well with the
authorities of the Church to say; and in saying them he was governed by this
historical idea : things unknown to the New Testament were unnecessary to the
Christian religion; what contradicted the mind of Christ or hindered the
realization of His ends was injurious to His Church. This idea determined the
attitude of Erasmus both to Rome and to Protestantism. He, indeed, honestly
believed that where Lutheranism reigned there literature perished; and that to
restore the knowledge of the New Testament was to bring back the mind of
Christ, who was the one teacher God had appointed, and therefore the sole and
supreme authority in His Church. Hence, his difference from Luther was as
inevitable as his difference from Rome, and more absolute, for in the one case
he differed from a man, in the other from a system. It has often been said that
his De libero arbitrio enabled him
to express his difference from Luther without expressing his agreement with
Rome, or recanting ‘his earlier criticism of ecclesiastical abuses’. This
judgment is both prejudiced and unjust. It is indeed certain that the book was
written in the desire to dissociate himself from Luther, as well as in response
to the appeal to write something against the new heresy; but it is no less
certain that the book expressed a point on which Luther’s scholasticism
offended the humanism of Erasmus. The saying “liberum arbitrium esse nomen inane” seemed to
him an “aenigma absurdum” and for this reason it was unknown to the New
Testament and the Apostolic Church. It might be Augustinian, it certainly was
scholastic; but it was neither Biblical nor primitive. Erasmus, in short, wrote
as a Greek and not as a Latin theologian, as a classical scholar and not as a
Western divine. He could not have selected a point more characteristic of his
own position. He would have the Christian religion known through its creative
literature; he would not have it identified with the philosophy or theology of
any school.
Spirit of the
Latin Renaissance.
So far we have
been occupied with the formal rather than the material side of thought; now we
must consider the latter, or thought in its objective expression as at once
evolved, governed, and served by the critical method.
We begin with the
Latin Renaissance. Its thought grew out of the study
of Classical literature, though it reversed rather than followed the sequences
of the Classical mind. The one began where the other ended, in an eclectic
Neo-Platonism, or a multitude of borrowed principles reduced by a speculation,
more or less arbitrary, to a reasoned unity which was yet superficial; but it
ended where the other began, in attempts to interpret the nature within which
man lived, with a view to the better interpretation of man. Though the order of
evolution was inverted, it was yet in the circumstances the only order
possible. For the mind which the voice of literature awakened could only
respond to a voice which was articulate and intelligible. The mind was old in
speculation, though its problems were new, and its age was reflected in the
solutions it successively attempted or accepted. It had been educated in
schools where theology reigned while Aristotle governed; and it revolted from
the governing minister out of loyalty to the reigning sovereign, whose
authority extended over regions of too infinite variety to be administered by
his narrow and rigid methods.
The literature
which enlarged the outlook changed the mind; it could not think as it had
thought before or believe as it had believed concerning the darkness and error
of pagan antiquity. The light which dwelt in ancient philosophy broke upon it
like an unexpected sunrise, which it saw with eyes that had been accustomed to
a grey and creeping dawn. And this means, that Classical thought was seized at
the point where it stood nearest to living experience, and yet formed the most
expressive contrast to it. This point was where philosophy had done its best to
become a religion, and had tried out of its school to make a Church. Hence, the
new mind in the first flush of its awaking turned from its ancient master,
Aristotle, and threw itself into the arms of the Neo-Platonists. Gemistos Plethon, who took part
in the Council of Florence, 1439, was intellectually the most potent of the
Greeks who helped in the Renaissance. He regarded Aristotle as a westernised Mohammadan rather
than as a Greek, a man who had indeed once lived on the Hellenic soil, but who
had become an alien in race and an enemy in religion, speaking in the Latin
schools ideas which he owed to a Moorish interpreter. So Plethon expounded to the awakening West Plato as the Neo-Platonists understood him,
‘the Attic Moses’, the transmitter of a golden tradition which the secular
Aristotle had tried to break and which ran back through Pythagoras to Zoroaster
on the one hand and Abraham on the other. His philosophy was at once
monotheistic and polytheistic; God was one and infinite, but He acted by means
of ideas or spirits, or minor deities who filled the space between us and Him.
As first and final cause He ordered all things for the best, and left no room
for chance or accident. Providence was necessity and fate providence, the world
in all its parts and life in all its elements were vehicles of a divine purpose.
The soul of man was immortal ; the doctrine of reminiscence proved that it had
lived before birth and so could live after death.
Plethon emphasized in every possible way the differences between Plato and
Aristotle, refusing to allow them to be reduced to a mere question of
terminology. This teaching lifted men above the arid syllogisms of the schools,
enriched their view of themselves and nature, of God and history, and gave
reality to the ancient saying ‘ex oriente lux’.
For it came more as a religion than as a philosophy; even the apparatus of
worship was mimicked; ceremonies were instituted, holy or feast days were
observed; celebrities became saints, before the bust of Plato a taper was
ceremoniously burned. The neophytes underwent a species of conversion; Marsilio
Ficino (1433-99) was said to have been called in his youth to be a physician of
souls, and designated as the translator of the two great masters, Plato and
Plotinus. Man was conceived as like unto God, and was named divine; his destiny
was to seek eternal union with the God from whom he came. That God was the
archetype of the universe, its unmoved mover and orderer,
the ground of all our reasoning, the light of all our seeing. He knew the world
from within when He knew Himself, for creation was only the expression of the
divine thought, God as it were speaking with Himself, and man overhearing His
speech.
The circle of
those devoted to the study of this philosophy contained the most distinguished
scholars of the day. Besides Ficino there stood his friends or converts, Angelo Poliziano, though his fame is mainly philological;
Cristoforo Landino, the exponent of Horace, of
Virgil, and of Dante, who has given us a picture of Florentine society which
recalls Plato’s Symposium; Girolamo Benivieni,
the poet who sang in praise of Platonic love; the architect, painter and man of
letters, Leo Battista Alberti; Pico della Mirandola, of whose faith and fame and achievements we have
already spoken; and above all the men of the Medicean House who founded the so-called Platonic Academy of Florence. This was rather a
Society than a School, not an equipped and organized college, but an
association of like-minded men who cultivated philosophy and professed to live
according to the philosophy they cultivated. It added lustre to the reign of the Medici, helped to define its character, to fix upon it name
and distinction. Under Cosmo and his son Piero, and especially under his
grandson Lorenzo, it became the centre and sum and
even source of Florentine culture. But the patronage of the House proved fatal
to the thought for which the Academy stood; with the House it rose, lived in
its smile, fell in its fall. Yet it did not fall before it had accomplished
things that could not die. It revealed the world which the Church had
extinguished and the Schoolmen superseded; it raised the reason that could
speculate concerning truth above the authority that would legislate in its
behalf; it taught men to believe that the truth lived in the soul rather than
in books, that nature was beautiful and man was good, and that truth existed
before Church or Councils and stood outside them both, and that man attains to
the larger humanity by the study of that literature in which the truth adapted
to his nature is best expressed. These were indeed notable contributions to the
thought of the century.
But though Plato
lived in the New Academy, Aristotle still reigned in the older Schools. He had
been too efficient an instrument in education to be easily pushed aside; but
the thought which is to shape living mind must not itself be dead. Hence the
men, who were by birth as well as by discipline Aristotelians, set themselves
to rejuvenate the ancient Master and change his obsolete speech into the
language of the day. Three tendencies at once showed themselves, one which
interpreted Aristotle in the sense and manner of Averroes; a second which
construed him by the help of the Greek commentators, especially Alexander of
Aphrodisia; and a third which labored to reconcile him with Plato, some of the
last-named going to Aristotle for their physics, but to Plato for their
metaphysics. It soon became evident that the philosophical questions involved
theology and raised issues affecting certain dogmas of the Church. These issues
were more sharply defined in the Aristotelian than in the Neo-Platonic Schools
and seriously alarmed the Church. How this was and with what reason, Pomponazzi (1462-1524)-Peretto,
or little Peter, as he was affectionately named-will help us to understand.
Reverence for
Aristotle had become in him a second nature; and though he writes poor Latin
and knows no Greek, and is, as he said, in comparison with his master but an
insect beside an elephant, yet he desires to serve truth by interpreting his
philosophy. He frankly emphasized its opposition to faith; and narrowly escaped
being burned for his pains, though his books were not so fortunate. He said :
“The thinker, who inquires into the divine mysteries,
is like Proteus. In face of consequences he neither hungers nor thirsts, eats
or sleeps; the Inquisition persecutes him as a heretic; the multitude mocks him
as a fool”. Doubt is native to him, and like Descartes he doubts that he may
know; but, unlike Descartes, his doubt is more critical than speculative, more
literary than philosophical. And if he has a doubt to express he dearly loves
to express it in another name than his own, or shield himself behind some noted
authority. Religions he conceives as laws instituted by lawgivers, like Christ
or Mohammad, for the regulation of life. They are governed in their coming and
going, in their bloom and decay, by time and space; and their horoscope can be
cast just as if they were mortal beings. Christianity is proved true by its
miracles, which are not impossible, though they have now ceased to happen and
fictitious marvels have taken their place. Since religions are laws, they must
promise to reward the righteous and threaten to punish the wicked; and as
conduct rather than knowledge is their end they may use parables and myths,
which, of course, need not be true. Man is like the ass which must be beaten
that it may carry its burden; to teach him deep mysteries would be but to waste
our breath. Nor are we to esteem him too highly or exhort him to become
godlike, for how can man resemble a God whom he cannot know? As it is
impossible to have natural grounds for a supernatural faith we must be content
to hold it without reason, though it may be a gift of grace. If religion be
moral then man must be free. And though his freedom may be incapable of
rational proof yet it is a matter of conscious experience. This, indeed, may
seem incompatible with Providence, which Aristotle conceived as general rather
than particular, though we conceive it as a general made up of all particulars;
but where philosophy is blind revelation may see, and it is better to trust it
than to walk in darkness. The God who governs has created, and creation was
willed in eternity, but happens in time, for Aristotle's idea of an eternal
creation is sophistical. As the workman loves his handiwork so God loves all
His creatures and wills their good. He has given to every being, not perhaps
the absolutely best, but the best for it and for the universe, viewed in their
complementary and reciprocal relations. For men supplement each other; what
seems in and by itself a defect may become an excellency when seen from the
standpoint of the collective whole. Man lives in humanity, humanity within
nature, nature in God; and we ought to know all together before we judge any
separately.
This is what would
be called today a system of philosophical agnosticism, where man's ignorance
becomes a plea, if not a reason for faith; but what it signified to Pomponazzi we shall best understand by turning to his
famous treatise on the Immortality of the Soul. The treatise is at once an
attempt at the historical interpretation of Aristotle and a serious independent
discussion. It is practically concerned with the question : How did Aristotle
conceive immortality, as personal or as collective? It is as little soluble by
the natural reason as the cognate question whether the world is eternal or
created; in each case the problem as to the beginning holds the key of the
problem as to the end. The Aristotelian Schoolmen had argued that the capacity
of the soul to think the eternal and will the universal implied its
immortality. But what is the soul? We cannot define it as thought percipient of
the universal reason, for there can be no thought without ideas and no ideas
without sense. The soul which lives within nature must develop according to
natural law and in obedience to it. Now, we never find soul without body; and
hence we must ask : how are these related? Not as mover and moved, else their
proper analogies would be the ox and the wagon it draws, but as matter and
form, i.e. without the body the soul could not be, for only through the body
does man take his place in nature and realize his rational activity. Hence the
human soul cannot exist without the human body, and must therefore be liable to
the same mortality. And this conclusion is worked out in connection with the
moral doctrine that man is bound to act from love of virtue and horror of vice,
and not from any hope of reward or fear of punishment, and so to act as to make
all nature the better for his action. Reason, then, must conclude that the soul
is mortal; but religion comes to our aid, and by teaching us to believe in the
resurrection of the body resolves our doubts. Of this doctrine philosophy knows
nothing, and so we can hold it only as an article of faith. This is in effect
all Pomponazzi can teach us; religion and reason
occupy opposite camps; neither can hold intercourse with the other. The truths
of religion are the contradictions of the reason; the processes of the reason
cannot serve the cause of religion. The new scholasticism was a philosophy of
reasoned ignorance where the cardinal verities of religion were the inconceivabilities of thought.
But here certain
new forces which seriously affected the course and the development of Latin
thought must be referred to and analyzed. The ecclesiastical situation began to
change, and the temper of the Renaissance changed with it. Thought had revived
without conscious antagonism to the Church, though with the clear sense of
opposition to the Schools and their methods. Churchmen had been forward in
cultivating the new spirit, had encouraged and studied its literature,
appreciated and promoted its art. But the Reformation, with its attendant
incidents, made the Church suspicious of movements which might contain the
seeds of revolt, while the Renaissance, always sensitive to outer conditions,
lost its spontaneity, becoming self-conscious and critical. Italy after 1525
became what the Moorish wars had made Spain, sullen in temper and jealous in
disposition; she imitated Spanish methods and developed the Inquisition; in
Rome, once careless and happy, the Holy Office was founded.
One of the
earliest fruits of this change of feeling was the revival of Scholasticism and
the increased influence of the Spanish mind upon the Italian. This revived
Scholasticism, which was bred mainly in two Orders, both of Spanish origin, the
Dominican and the Jesuit, and introduced by them into schools and universities,
pulpits and Courts, learning and literature, was used to prove the necessity of
the Church to religion, of the Pope to the Church, and of all three to society
and the State. It had the learning which the Renaissance created, but was
without its knowledge of antiquity, its sympathy with it, or its belief in
finding there virtue and truth. Its purpose was indeed quite specific : to
prove not that the Church was the mother of culture or mistress of art, but
that she was the sole possessor of truth, the one authority by which it could
be defined, authenticated, and guaranteed. The line of defence was bold : the Church was the creation of God, its government His express
design, its rulers instituted by His immediate act. Secular rulers were but
mediate creatures of God, appointed through the people and responsible to them;
but spiritual rulers were His immediate creation and responsible to Him alone.
And since the Church was the sole custodian of truth, it was not permissible to
seek it without her or outside her; to profess to have found it independently
was to be heretical; to obey what had been so found was to fall into the
deadliest schism. The argument may have been narrow, but it was clear and
strenuous; it may not have converted opponents, but it convinced friends. The
Church became conscious of her mission; she was the guardian of thought, the
guide of mind. She alone could judge what was truth and what error, what men
ought to do or ought not to know. And as she believed so she acted, with
results that are broadly written upon the face of history. The new Scholastics converted
their own Church from the Catholicity which encouraged the Renaissance to the
Romanism which suppressed its thought.
Bernardino Telesio.
This, then, is
what we have now to see; and so we resume our discussion of the thought which,
as it faced the second quarter of the sixteenth century, began to feel the
creeping shadow of the future. The change came slowly, for mind loves a violent
catastrophe as little as nature, still it came and was marked by the rise of
physical in succession to metaphysical speculation. The Neo-Platonic school had
tended to a mystical and allegorical conception of the world, which implied a
doctrine of the divine immanence and looked towards Pantheism. The
Aristotelians, on the other hand, emphasized the ideas of cause and Creator,
conceived the universe as manufactured and limited, and God as transcendent,
the two being correlated in the manner of the later deism. The one school was
inclined to read nature through Deity, the other Deity through nature; but in
each case nature took its meaning from the temper and fundamental postulates of
the school. The traditional ideas were Aristotelian; the universe was
geocentric; its main fact was the opposition of heaven and earth, with the
involved antithesis of the higher or celestial element, and the four lower
elements, earth, air, fire, water, all movement being explained from their
attempts to effect a change of place.
This theory could
not satisfy men who believe in a philosophy of immanence; and efforts were soon
made to dislodge it. One of the earliest and most notable of these stands
associated with the name of Bernardino Telesio (1508-80). He was a devout son of the Church as well as a zealous student of
nature, and he disliked Aristotle for two reasons : first, because his philosophy
knows neither piety nor a Creator; and, secondly, because he tried to interpret
nature without questioning herself. Telesio’s fundamental principle was this : nature must be explained in her own terms
according to the method of experience and by the instrument of the senses. He
conceived matter as a substance incapable of increase or decrease, more or less
passive, yet susceptible of being acted upon by two forces, heat and cold,
which, as causes, respectively, of expansion and contraction, produce all
motion and all change. The heavens are the home of heat, and the earth of cold;
and the constant effort of heat to illumine the dark and quicken the cold issue
in a conflict whence come all the movement and variety of nature. The whole
proceeds according to immanent laws and without the intervention of God. Nature
is self-contained and self-sufficient; which however did not mean that she is
without intelligence; on the contrary, there is a soul in things; each
supplements and serves the other; mind lives in each, and works through the
whole. Bacon saw in Telesio a return to Parmenides;
others have seen in him an anticipation of Kant; others again have construed
his principle ‘non ratione sed sensu’ as
if he were the first of modern empiricists, the forerunner of the sensuous
philosophy, both English and French. In all these views there is a measure of
truth. He clothed his doctrines in a guise more or less mythical ; he could
best conceive natural forces as personal, and he was never so ideal as when he
meant to be most realistic. But he intended to be true to his principle, to
construe nature not through metaphysics or theology, but from herself alone. It
is this that makes him so significant in the history of thought, anticipating
so much of what Bacon achieved, and places him, in spite of his crude and
allegorical nomenclature, amid the forefathers of modern physics.
The speculations
of Telesio did not stand alone; they were
characteristic of his race and time. Italy, during what remained of the
century, seemed to forsake philosophy for science, but the science she
cultivated was only disguised philosophy. A distinguished contemporary, a
critic and a Platonist, was Francesco Patrizzi (1529-97), who agreed with the Telesian physics, but
differed in his metaphysics : arguing that, as both the corporeal and spiritual
light emanated from one source, each was the kin and correlate of the other,
the effects being reduced to unity by the unity of the cause. Another and
younger contemporary, who loved to think and speak of himself as Telesio’s disciple, though he only saw the master after
death, was Tommaso Campanella (1568-1639). His career has something of the
tragedy which belongs to another and even more distinguished contemporary,
Galileo Galilei (1564-1642), for whom he wrote while suffering imprisonment a
noble though unsuccessful Apology. Like Galilei, Campanella lived after
Copernicus, and was attracted by his sublimer and
vaster view of the universe; and, like Copernicus, he was accused of heresy in
consequence, spending, partly on account of his religious and partly on account
of his political views, twenty-seven years of his life in prison. He was at
first, and he probably remained, in spite of all the persecutions he endured, a
faithful Catholic. While he followed Telesio, he was
yet a most independent disciple. His science evolved into a philosophy of
existence, whose highest truth is the Deity, and whose fixed first principle is
the thought, the ‘Notio abdita innata’ which is man. He was praised by
Leibniz as one who soared to heaven, in contrast to Hobbes who groveled upon
the earth. Then as Telesio anticipated Bacon,
Campanella anticipated Descartes. Though he does not use the formula he holds
the principle of the ‘cogito ergo sum’. Both are rooted in Augustine who said :
“As for me, the most certain of all things is that I exist. Even if you deny
this and say that I deceive myself, yet you do confess that I am, for if I do
not live how could I deceive myself”. One of the strangest things in connection
with the Catholic Campanella is the State, as described by him in his Civitas
Solis. It is an echo of the Platonic Republic, without private
property or family, with sexual intercourse publicly regulated and children
owned and educated by the State, without a priesthood or public and positive
religion, with philosophers as rulers and workmen as the true nobility. It was
a noble dream, and shows how little physical speculation had killed ethical
passion; the best interpreted earth was empty till it was made the home of
happy and contented men.
Giordano Bruno
(1548-1600) is of all the thinkers of the Latin Renaissance the most modern; in
him science becomes philosophical, and philosophy speaks the language of
science, confronts, defines, and enlarges its problems. As a man he is
passionate, explosive, impetuous, vain, intolerant, and indomitable; and where
these qualities are allowed freely to mix and express themselves it is very
difficult indeed to be just. He himself says that “if the first button of one’s
coat is wrongly buttoned all the rest will be crooked”; and the event which set
his whole life awry happened when, as a lad of sixteen, he entered the
Dominican Order. He early thought himself into heresy, and in his nature were
fires which “all the snows of Caucasus” could not quench. In the effort to
unfrock himself he became a wanderer, tried Rome, roamed over Northern Italy,
crossed the Alps, and settled at Geneva, where he found neither the discipline
nor the doctrine of the Reformed Church to his mind. He then emigrated to
Toulouse, where he studied the New Astronomy, tried to be at home and to teach
the fanatical Catholics of southern France in a city where the Inquisition had
an ancient history. He next moved to Paris, where he attempted to instruct the doctors
of the Sorbonne and to make his peace with the Church; and, failing, he crossed
to England, where he lived for a while, wrote and published in London, and at
Oxford claimed with much literary extravagance the right to lecture. To his
Italian soul England was an uncongenial clime; he praised Elizabeth, as the
Inquisition remembered later to his hurt; but he despised the barbarians over
whom she ruled, and the ostentatious wealth and intellectual impotence of
Oxford in her day.
From England he
wandered back to France and thence to Germany, where he lectured at Wittenberg
and eulogized Luther, who had “like a modern Hercules fought with Cerberus and
his triple crown”. He was elected to a professorship at Helmstedt;
which he soon forsook for Frankfort. But the home-sickness which would not be
denied was on him, and he turned back to Italy where bloomed the culture which
was to him the finest flower of humanity, where dwelt the men who moved him to
love and not to hate, whose speech and thought threw over him a spell he could
not resist. He was denounced to the Inquisition; spent eight years in prison,
first in Venice and then in Rome; and, finally, on February 17, 1600, he was
sent to the stake. Caspar Scioppius, a German who had
passed from the Protestant to the Roman Church, and who loved neither Bruno nor
his views, tells us that when the prisoner heard his sentence he only said,
“You who condemn me perhaps hear the judgment with greater fear than myself”.
And he adds that at the stake Bruno put aside a crucifix which was held out to
him, and so entered heaven proclaiming how the Romans dealt with “blasphemous
and godless men”. A modern admirer sees, in the eyes uplifted to the blue, a
spirit that would have no dark image stand between him and the living God.
It is customary
now to describe Bruno’s system as a form of pantheism. The term was not known
then, or indeed for more than a hundred years after his death, which means that
the idea is as modern as the term. Bruno was roundly named, just as Spinoza was
later, an atheist, for men thought it was all one to identify God with nature
and to deny His independent existence. The systems were indeed radically
unlike; for while the one was a theophantism or
apotheosis of nature, the other was an akosmism or a
naturalization of God : in other words, Bruno started with nature and ended
with Deity, but Spinoza began with Deity, his causa sui, substantia,
or ens absolute infinitum, and
reasoned down to nature. The antecedents of the one system were classical and
philosophical but those of the other Semitic and religious. The historical
factors of Bruno’s thought were two, ancient or Neo-Platonic, and modern or
scientific. His system, if system it can be called, may be described as an
attempt to state and to articulate the ideas inherited by him in the terms of
the universe which Copernicus had revealed.
He conceived this
universe as infinite, and so rejected the ancient scholastic idea of a limited
nature with its distinctions and divisions of place, its here and there, its above and below, its cycles and epicycles. But the
universe, which has no centre and therefore no
circumference, has yet a unity for consciousness, and wherever consciousness is
its unity appears. And this unity signifies that order reigns in the universe;
that its phenomena are connected; that individual things are yet not insulated;
and this coherence implies that all are animated by a common life and moved by
a common cause. And this cause must be as infinite as the universe; for an
infinite effect can proceed only from an infinite cause, and such a cause can
be worthily expressed only in such an effect. But there is no room for two
infinities to exist at the same moment in the same place; and so the effect
must be simply the body of the cause, the cause the soul of the effect. Hence
the cause is immanent, not transcendent; matter is animated, the pregnant
mother who bears and brings forth all forms and varieties of being. And the
soul which animates matter and energizes the whole is God; He is the natura naturans, Who is not above and not outside, but
within and through, all things. He is the monad of monads, the spirit of
spirits, carried so within that we cannot think ourselves without thinking Him.
There are, indeed,
other expressions in Bruno; God is described as ‘the supersubstantial
substance’, as ‘the supernatural first principle’, exalted far above nature,
which is only a shadow of divine truth, speaking to us in parables. And this is
possible, because in every single thing the whole is manifested, just as one
picture reveals the artist’s power and promise. But these things signify that
he refused to conceive God as a mere physical force or material energy, and
held, on the contrary, that He must be interpreted in the terms of mind or
spirit. He hates, indeed, the notion that nature is an accident, or the result
of voluntary action ; and he labors to represent it as a necessity, seeking by
a theory of emanation or instinctive action to reconcile the notions of
necessity and God. Yet he does not conceive the best as already attained.
Everything in nature strives to become better; everywhere instinct feels after
the good, though higher than instinct is that which it seeks to become, the
rational action that wills the best. Thought rises, like sense and instinct,
from lower to higher forms. Heroic love, which desires the intuition of the
truth, drives us ever upwards, that we may attain the perfect rest where
understanding and will are unified.
Bruno’s
speculations were those of a poet as well as a philosopher; and were in various
ways prophetic. His death by fire at Rome signified that Italy had neither the
wit nor the will to understand men of his kind; that for her the Renaissance
had run its course, so that men must pursue its problems elsewhere in the hope
of a more satisfactory solution. Descartes’ de omnibus dubitandum est was but
the negative expression of Bruno’s positive effort after emancipation from
authority, the freedom without which thought can accomplish nothing.
Spinoza’s substantia, with its twin attributes of thought and
extension on the one hand, and Leibniz' monadology on the other, carried into
more perfect forms the quest on which he had embarked. But to us he has an even
higher significance ; he is the leader of the noble army of thinkers who have
tried at once to justify and to develop into a complete system of the universe
the dreams and the doctrines of modern science. It is this which makes him the
fit close of the movement, which began by waking the old world from its grave
and ended by saluting the birth of the thought that made the whole world new.
The French
Renaissance. Rabelais and Montaigne.
We have not as yet
approached the French Renaissance, which has indeed an interest and character
of its own. It was, while less philosophical, more strictly educational,
literary, and juristic than the Italian; and may be described as both Teutonic
and Latin in origin. It entered the north and penetrated as far as Paris with
the Adagia of Erasmus, published in
1500; but it reached the south from Italy, crossing the Alps with the gentlemen
of France who accompanied their Kings on those incursions which had, as
Montaigne tells us, so fateful an influence on the French morals and mind.
Correspondent to this difference in origin was a difference in spirit and in
the field of activity. In the north the Renaissance made its home in the
schools, and worked for the improvement of the education, the amelioration of
the laws, and the reform of religion, as names like Bude, Pierre de la Ramée, and Beza, may help us to realize; but in the south
it was more personal and less localized, its learning was nearer akin to culture
than to education, and it loved literature more than philosophy. Hence the
forms it assumed in France can hardly be said to call for separate discussion
here. Especially is this true of its more northern form; a better case might be
made out for the southern. To it belong the great names of Rabelais and
Montaigne; but their place is in a history of literature rather than of
thought, though both affected the course of the latter too profoundly to be
left unmentioned here.
Coleridge has said
that Rabelais was “among the deepest as well as boldest thinkers of his age”;
that the rough stick he used yet “contained a rod of gold” ; and that a
treatise could be written “in praise of the moral elevation of his work which
would make the Church stare and the conventicle groan, and yet would be the
truth, and nothing but the truth”. These may seem hard sayings, utterly
incredible if portions of his work are alone regarded, but accurate enough if
the purpose and drift of his teaching as a whole be considered. It has been
well said that the confession of faith of the curé of Meudon has far more moral reality than that which
Rousseau puts into the mouth of his Savoyard vicar. He believes that the
universe needs no other governor than its Creator, whose word guides the whole
and determines the nature, properties, and condition of each several thing.
Pascal’s famous definition of Deity, “a circle whose centre is everywhere and whose circumference is nowhere”, is but an echo from
Rabelais. And he can, with the wisest of the ancients and the best of the
moderns, speak of the “great Soul of the universe which quickens all things”.
La Bruyère described his work as “a chimera; it has
the face of a beautiful woman, but the tail of a serpent”. Yet surely the man
who had to wear the mask of a buffoon that he might preach the wisdom of truth
and love to his age, well deserves the epigram which Beza wrote in his honor :
“Qui sic nugatur, tractantem ut seria vincat,
Seria cum faciet din, rogo, quantus erit?”
Montaigne is of
all Frenchmen most thoroughly a son of the Renaissance. He loves books,
especially the solid and sensible and well-flavored books written in the
ancient classic tongues, the men who made and those who read them, and he loved
to study man. He says : ‘Je suis moi même la matière de mon livre’ (I
am, myself, the subject of my book). And he does not understand himself in any
little or narrow sense, but rather as the epitome and mirror of mankind. The
world in which he lived was not friendly to the freedom of thought which was
expressed in affirmative speech or creative conduct, and so he learned to be
silent-or skeptical. He had seen men hate each other, willingly burn or be
burned, out of love to God; and he was moved by pity to moralize on the
behavior of those who were so positive where they could not know, and so little
understood the God in whom they professed to believe that they never saw what
the love of Him bound them to be and to do. The man that he studied and
described was not abstract but concrete man, with all his foibles and failings,
limited in his nature but infinite in his views, differing without ceasing from
his fellows, and not always able to agree with himself. And man, so conceived,
dwells amid mystery, has it within him, and confronts it without. Custom may
guide him but not reason; for reason builds on arguments, whose every position
depends on another, in a series infinitely regressive. “Les hommes sont tourmentés par les opinions qu'ils ont des choses, non par les choses mêmes”
(Men are afraid of their own opinions about the things, not of the self of the
things). Where man is so ignorant he ought not to be dogmatic; where truth is
what all seek and no one can be sure that he finds, i.e. where it is nothing
but a mere probability, it is a folly to spill human blood for it.
God is unknown
even in religion; as many as the nations of men so many are the forms under
which He is worshipped. And when they try to conceive and name Him, they
degrade Him to their own level. God is made in the image of man rather than man
in the image of God; to the Ethiopian He is black, to the Greek He is white,
and lithe and graceful; to the brute He would be bestial and to the triangle
triangular. Man, then, is so surrounded with contradictions that he cannot say
what is or is not true. Wisdom was with Sextus Empiricus when he said : “Il n'y a nulle raison qui n'en ait une contraire, dit le plus sage
parti des philosophes” (every single thing has its contrary, say the
philosophers). Where man so doubts he is too paralyzed to fight or to affirm.
Montaigne’s sympathies might be with those who worked and suffered for a new
heaven and a new earth; but his egoism inclined to the conventional and
followed the consuetudinary. Prevost-Paradol termed him “une perpétuelle leçon de tempérance et de
modération” (always searching for moderation and fortitude). But this is a lesson which men
of culture may read contentedly; while those who struggle to live or to make
life worth living will hardly find in it the Gospel they need.
The Teutonic
Renaissance.
We turn now to the
Teutonic Renaissance. Like the Latin, it began as a revolt against the
sovereignty of Aristotle; but, unlike the Latin, its literary antecedents were
patristic and Biblical rather than classical. They were, indeed, so far as
patristic, specifically Augustinian, and, so far as Biblical, Pauline. With
Augustine, the underlying philosophy was Neo-Platonic, with a tendency to
theosophy and mysticism; with Paul, the theology involved a philosophy of human
nature and human history. This does not mean that other Fathers or other
Scriptures were ignored, but rather that Paul was interpreted through
Augustine, and Christ through Paul. This fundamental difference involved two
others. In the first place, a more religious and more democratic temper, the
religious being seen in the attempt to realize the new ideals, and the
democratic in the strenuous and combatant spirit by which alone this could be
accomplished. The thought which lived in the Schools could not resist the
authority that spoke in the name of the Church and was enforced by the
penalties of the State; but the thought which interpreted God to the conscience
was one that bowed to no authority lower than His. In the second place,
Teutonic was more theological than Latin thought. The categories, which the
past had formulated for the interpretation of being, it declined to accept; and
so it had to discover and define those which it meant to use in their stead.
The God with whom it started was not an abstract and isolated but a living and
related Deity; and man it conceived sub specie aeternitatis, as a
being whom God had made and ruled. The very limitation of its field was an
enlargement of its scope; its primary datum was the Eternal God, and its
secondary was the created universe, especially the man who bore the image of
his Maker. This man was no mere individual or insulated unit, but a race, a
connected, coherent, organic unity. The human being was local, but human nature
was universal; before the individual could be, the whole must exist; and so man
must be interpreted in terms of mankind rather than mankind in the terms of the
single and local man. And this signified that in character, as well as in
nature, the race was a unity; the past made the present, the heir became as his
inheritance; and so any change in man had to be effected by the Maker and not
by those He had made. And here Augustine pointed the way to the goal which Paul
had reached : the will of God had never ceased to be active, for it was
infinite; and it could not cease to be gracious, for it was holy and perfect;
therefore, from this will, since man’s nature was by his corporate being and
his inevitable inheritance evil, all the good he could ever be or achieve must
come.
This fundamental
idea was common to the types most characteristic of the Teutonic Renaissance.
It was expressed in Luther’s Servum Arbitrium, in Zwingli’s Providentia Actuosa, in Calvin’s Decretum Absolutum. These all signified that the sole
causality of good belonged to God, that grace was of the essence of His will,
and that where He so willed, man could not but be saved, and, where He did not
so will, no amelioration of state was possible. But this must not be
interpreted to mean that man had been created and constituted of God for darkness
rather than light; on the contrary, these thinkers all agree in affirming a
universal light of nature, i.e. ideas implanted in us by the Creator, or, as
Melanchthon phrased it, “Notitiae nobiscum nascentes divinitus sparsae in mentibus nostris”. In this position they were more influenced by
Paul than by Augustine; with the Apostle, they argued that the moral law had
been written in the heart before it was printed on tables of stone, and that
without the one the other could neither possess authority nor be understood.
But they also argued that knowledge without obedience was insufficient; and
therefore they held God’s will to be needed to enable man both to will and to
do the good. But their differences of statement and standpoint were as
instructive as their agreements. When Luther affirmed the absolute bondage of
the will and Calvin the absolute decree of God, the one looked at the matter as
a question of man’s need, the other as a question of God’s power; and so they
agreed in idea though they differed in standpoint. Yet the difference proved to
be more radical than the agreement. And so, when Zwingli said “he would rather
share the eternal lot of a Socrates or a Seneca than that of the Pope”, he
meant that God willed good to men who were outside the Church or the covenants,
without willing the means which both Luther and Calvin conceived to be
necessary to salvation. It is through such differences as these that the types
and tendencies of Teutonic thought must be conceived and explained.
Jakob Boehme.
Luther’s Article
of a Standing or Failing Church, Justification by Faith alone, is the positive
side of the idea which is negatively expressed as the bondage of the will; and
the idea in both its positive and negative forms implies a philosophy of
existence which may be stated as a question thus : How is God, as the source of
all good, related to man as the seat and servant of evil? God and man, good as
identical with God and evil as inseparable from man, are recognized, and the
problem is : how is the good to overcome the evil? The man who frames the
problem is a mystic; God is the supreme desire and delight of his soul; and he
conceives sin as a sort of inverted capacity for God, the dust which has
stifled a thirst and turned it into an infinite misery. Now, Luther has two
forms under which he conceives God’s relation to man, a juristic denoted by the
term “justification”, and a vital denoted by the term “faith”. Justification is
the acquittal of the guilty : faith is nothing else than the true life realized
in God. The one term thus describes the universe as ethically governed, while
the other describes man as capable of participating in the eternal life; and
the two together mean that he can realize his happiness or his end only as he
shares the life of God and lives in harmony with His law. The philosophy here
implied is large and sublime, though its intrinsic worth may be hidden by the
crudity of its earliest forms. The Lutheran doctrine of the communicatio idiomatum attempts,
for example, to establish a kind of equation between the ideas of God and man.
The person of Christ is a symbol of humanity; in it man can so participate as
to share its perfections and dignity. Christ's humanity is capable of deity;
God lives in Him now openly, now cryptically, but ever really ; and His
humanity so penetrates the Deity as to touch Him with a feeling of our
infirmities and make Him participant in our lot as we are in His life.
This is the very
root and essence of German mysticism, which gives to the German hymns their beauty
and their pathos, which inspired the speculations of Brenz and Chemnitz, and which later determined Schelling’s doctrine of “indifference”
or the “identity of subject and object”, and Hegel's “absolute idealism”. If we
read Boehme from this point of view, how splendid his dreams and how reasonable
his very extravagances become! We are not surprised to hear him speak of the
necessity of antitheses to all being, and especially to the life and thought of
God, of evil being as necessary as good, or wrath as essential as love in God,
who is the fundament of hell as well as of heaven, both the everlasting No, and
the eternal Yes. He dwells in nature as the soul dwells in the body; there is
no point in the body where the soul is not, no spot in space and no atom in
nature where we can say, “God is not here”. The man who is His image, who is
holy as He is holy, good as He is good, is of no other matter than God. This
may be Pantheism, but it is not rational and reasoned like Bruno’s; it is
emotional and felt, a thing of imagination all compact. It is born of the love
that loses the sense of personal distinctness and identity in the joy, not of
absolute possession, but of being possessed. Boehme says that the processes of
nature conceal God, but the spirit of man reveals Him; and how can it reveal a
God it does not know? But the spirit that has never seen and touched Deity has
never known Him or been so one with Him as to know Him as he knows himself.
Here lives the very soul of Luther and the essence of all his thought. Boehme’s
friend and biographer describes him as a little man of mean aspect, thin voice,
snub nose, but eyes blue as heaven, bright and gleaming like the windows of
Solomon’s temple. And he lived in harmony with lines which he wrote with his
own toil-stained hand :
Wem Zeit ist wie
Ewigkeit Und Ewigkeit
wie Zeit,
Der ist befreit
Von allem Streit.
Of course, such a
change as Luther instituted could not but powerfully affect the minds of men.
But certain concomitants must not be set down as effects; and the Peasants’ War
had its causes in centuries of German history, though among its occasions must
be reckoned the ideas which the Reformation had thrown as it were into the air.
But quite otherwise was it with the Anabaptist movement. While it sprang up and
flourished in provinces and cities where Zwingli was potent as well as in
places more expressly Lutheran, yet it belonged more specifically to the
Lutheran than to the Reformed Church. To discuss its causes and forms would
carry us far beyond our available space. It is enough to say : the principle of
parity which it emphasised was more antagonistic to
the one Church than to the other. Luther created his Church by the help of
Princes; Calvin founded his on the goodwill of the people. The system that
claimed fullest freedom for the individual could find less fault with the
latter than with the former. And it is significant that the heresies which
troubled the Lutherans were largely political and social, while those that
afflicted the Reformed were mainly intellectual and moral. In nothing is the
character of a Society more revealed than in the heresies to which it is most
liable.
Zwingli and Calvin
alike conceived God under the category of will, and construed man and history
through it. Both held faith to be a consequence of, rather than a condition
for, election; man believed because God had so decreed, and into His will every
step in their upward or downward progress was resolved. Now, this emphasis on
the will of God necessarily threw into prominence the ideas of God and will,
with the result that the main varieties of opinion in the Reformed Church concerned
these two ideas. If the will of God was the supreme and sole causality in all
human affairs, and if the will always was as the nature was, it became a matter
of primary consequence to know what kind of being God was, and what His nature
and character. This question was early and potently raised, and in a most
significant quarter. Zanchius, himself an Italian,
who so emphasized the will of God as to anticipate Spinoza and represent God as
the only free Being in nature and the sole cause in history, wrote in 1565 to
Bullinger warning him against being too easy in the matter of credentials of
orthodoxy, as he had many heretical compatriots. And it is curious that the
attempts to find a simpler conception of God than Calvin’s, or to modify his
notion of the will by the notion of the Deity whose will it was, came mainly
from men of Latin stock. Servetus was the son of a Spanish father and a French
mother; Lelio and Fausto Sozzini,
uncle and nephew, the one the father of the doctrine, the other of the sect, which
respectively bear their name, were Italians, as were also Bernardino Ochino, who wrote a once famous book concerning the freedom
and bondage of the will, “the Labyrinth”, in which he argued that man
ought to act as if he were free, but when he did good he was to give all the
glory to God as if he were necessitated, and Celio Secondo Curione, who desired to enlarge the number of
the elect till it should comprehend Cicero as well as Paul; while Sebastian Castellio, who is described by some contemporaries as
French, though by others as Italian, as a matter of fact he was born in a
Savoyard village not far from Geneva, argued that as God is good His will must
be the same, and if all had happened according to it there could have been no
sin. These views may be regarded as the recrudescence of the Latin Renaissance
in the Reformed Church, and are marked as attempts to bring in a humaner and sweeter conception of God. They failed,
possibly because of the severity and efficiency of the Reformed legislation, or
possibly because they did not reckon with the Augustinian sense of sin, or most
probably for reasons which were both political and intellectual. It is indeed
strange, that positions so strongly rational and so well and powerfully argued
should not have been maintained and crystallized into important religious
societies; but as Boehme helps us to see, the man who knows himself to be evil
expects and appreciates wrath as well as mercy in God. This may be the reason
why the attempts made by some of the finest minds in the sixteenth century to
soften the severer ideas of Deity seemed to their contemporaries heresies, and
seem to the student of history ineffective failures.
The problem was
soon attacked from another side. The field in which the will of God was exercised
was the soul of man. That will concerned, therefore, him and his acts; if these
acts were done because God had so determined, then two consequences followed;
the acts would show the quality of the will, and the man would not be
consciously free, would know himself an instrument rather than an agent. The
criticism from these points of view was mainly northern; those who urged it did
so in the interests of man and morality. In Calvin’s own lifetime the doctrine
of foreordination, or of the operation of the Divine will in its relation to
human affairs, was assailed by two men, Albert Pighius,
a Catholic from the Netherlands, and Jerome Hermes Boisée,
a Parisian, an unfrocked Carmelite monk, who had turned physician, and had for
a time been closely attached to Calvin. The former argued that if God was the
absolute cause of all events and acts, then to Him we owed, not only the
goodness of the good, but the wickedness of the wicked; the second, that if
faith is made the consequence rather than the condition of election, then God
must be charged with partiality. But towards the end of the century a more
serious movement took place. The question of the Divine will had exercised the
Reformed theologians, especially as criticism had compelled them to consider it
in relation to sin as well as to salvation, i.e. both as to the causation of
the state from which man was to be saved, and as to his deliverance from it.
Certain of the more vigorous Reformed divines, including Beza himself, said
that the decree in date precedes the Fall, for what was first in the Divine
intention is last in execution; the first thing was the decree to save, but if
man is to be saved he must first be lost; hence the Fall is decreed as a
consequence of the decreed Salvation. But the milder divines said that the
decree of God takes the existence of sin for granted, deals with man as fallen,
and elects or rejects him for reasons we cannot perceive, though it clearly
knows and regards. The former were known by the name of supralapsarians, and the
latter by the name of sublapsarians. In the
seventeenth century an acute and effective criticism was directed against both
forms of the belief, which, although it falls beyond our scope, must receive
passing notice here. Jacobus Arminius (Jakob Herman), a Dutch preacher and
professor, declined to recognize the doctrine as either Scriptural or rational.
He held that it made God the author of sin, that it restricted His grace, that
it left the multitudes outside without hope, that it condemned multitudes for
believing the truth, viz. that for them no salvation was either intended or
provided in Christ, and it gave an absolutely false security to those who
believed themselves to be the elect of God. The criticism was too rational to
be cogent, for it was, as it were, an assertion of the rights of man over
against the sovereignty of God. And it involved the men who pursued it in the
political controversies and conflicts of the time. The Arminians were most successful when the argument proceeded on principles supplied by the
conscience and the consciousness of man; and the Calvinists when they argued
from the majesty and the might of God. But if the Arminians were dialectically victors, they were politically vanquished. The men who
organized authority in Holland proved stronger than those who pleaded and
suffered for freedom.
There are still
large fields of thought to be traversed before we can do even approximate
justice to the mind of Protestantism; but our space is exhausted. All we can
now do is to drop a hint as to what was intended; we should have wished to
sketch the Renaissance that followed the Reformation as fully as the literary
Revival which preceded it. Theodore Beza is a man whose fame as a Genevan
legislator and divine has eclipsed his name as a scholar and educator; but it
ought not to be forgotten that he was an elegant humanist before he became a
convinced reformer and his most fruitful work was done in the provinces of
sacred learning and exegesis. The Estiennes, Robert
and Henry, are potent names in the history of Greek and Roman letters; they
accomplished much for the languages and the literatures which they loved;
Robert, in particular, standing out as a devoted friend of religion and of
science, for both of which he made immense sacrifices. Our textus
receptus and its division into verses are witnesses to his zeal.
Joseph Scaliger and Isaac Casaubon had the merit of awakening the envy, which
was but inverted admiration, and the supple hate, which was like the regret of
the forsaken, of the society whose mission it was to roll back the advancing
tide of the freer thought that had come to quicken interest in letters; while
Gerard Jan Vossius construed the classical mythology
through religion, and both through Old Testament history in a way that contributed
to form comparative science in the regions of thought, religion, and language.
Protestant scholars had a larger and more realistic way of looking at classical
problems than the men of the earlier Renaissance, and by its dissociation from
polity and custom Teutonic thought even while it seems narrower in scope, is
yet far wider in outlook and interest than Latin. It goes into a more distant
past, and rises to higher altitudes. It came as a revolt, but it grew into a
development; it continued free from the authority that would have suppressed
it, and used its freedom to achieve results which the more fettered Latin mind
panted after in vain. France continued in the seventeenth century the literary
activity of Italy in the sixteenth; but speculation loves freedom, and refused
to live where it could not be free. The events, which emancipated England from
monotonous uniformity in religion, set the problems that have been the main
factors in her historical development, and the chief causes of her philosophical
activity and her literary greatness, Modern thought is the achievement of
Northern and Central Europe, but it is the possession of universal man.
THEHISTORY OF THE REFORMATION |