CHAPTER VI.
THE NAPOLEONIC CODES.
The
codification of French law, if it was probably the most durable, was certainly
not the most surprising manifestation of Napoleon’s energy. It was the
fulfilment of an aspiration, as old at least as the fifteenth century, and
partially realised by the ordinances of kings and the textbooks of jurists, an
aspiration for the legal unity of France, for “one weight, one measure, one
law”. To this ideal the Revolution imparted a fresh and powerful impulse. The
birth of the new nation, the triumph of the new civic enthusiasm, the victory
of philosophic reason, seemed to demand a code of uniform laws suitable to an
enlightened people. At the same time, all those social obstacles which had
hitherto stood in the path of legal unity were swept away—provincialism and
feudalism, caste and corporation, the wealth and influence of the Church, the
power and prestige of the Crown. The whole law of property and of persons was
remodelled by the Revolutionary Assemblies under the stress of a democratic
theory as coherent as it was imperious.
The land was
liberated from feudal dues and tithes; and its freedom was secured by the
prohibition of all perpetual and irredeemable rents. The corporate property of
the Church and of the rural communities passed almost entirely into the hands
of the State, and was thrown piecemeal into the market. Again, as the land was
freed to guard against tyranny, so it was divided to promote equality. The
Roman law of succession, which was favourable to testamentary freedom and
therefore to inequality, was set aside; and the egalitarian tendencies of the Custumals were developed and sharpened. Wills were almost
entirely forbidden; the distinction between moveables,
acquisitions, and patrimonial property was abolished; and the inheritance,
considered as a uniform mass of property, was to be divided equally among the
heirs. Still further to promote territorial equality, representation was
declared to be infinite in the direct line ; donations were to be returned to
the donor ; natural children were recognised, and gifts to the rich prohibited.
Thus, while the law fortified the proprietor during his lifetime, it weakened
his influence after death.
Equally
sweeping were the changes which came over the law of persons. Under the
monarchy, sex and nationality, social status and professional calling, had
created legal inequalities between French subjects. In virtue of the droit d’aubaine, a foreigner could not inherit a legacy or
execute a will, or transmit his property save to children born in France. The division
of persons into three orders: clergy, nobility, and tiers état, carried with it fiscal and political inequalities
and also some differences of civil status. The monk was dead to civil life; and
in the mountains of the Jura there lingered a last remnant of serfdom. In
several Custumals, the rule of inheritance differed
according as the person concerned was noble or roturier. Religion, which gave
privileges to the Catholic, brought penalties to the Protestant and the Jew.
The civil disabilities of women were many. But all these intricate, manifold,
and unreasonable distinctions were swept away by the Revolutionary Assemblies.
The droit d'aubaine was suppressed ; the
division between the three orders was effaced; and monks were restored to civil
life. Religious toleration took the place of the intolerant privilege of the
Catholic religion. The clergy were permitted to marry; and marriage itself,
being declared a civil contract, passed into the domain of state control.
Divorce and adoption were introduced, to the scandal of the Catholic world; and
the care of the registers of births, marriages, and deaths was transferred from
the Church to lay officials. A secular State based upon a large peasant
proprietary, a civil law emancipated from religious influences, a system of
land-tenure devised to secure the maximum of equality, a law of persons, which
proclaimed that all men had equal rights—such were the main results of a period
of legislation unprecedented in history for its volume, its violence, its idealism,
its splendid achievements, and its deplorable mistakes.
An
atmosphere of great legislative fertility, of high passions and quick changes,
is unfavourable to codification; and the draft codes of the Convention and the
Directory received so little attention from the preoccupied Assemblies to which
they were successively submitted, that the revolution of Brumaire found France
still waiting for that body of simple and clear laws which had been promised in
the Constitution of 1791. Yet no one could doubt but that a code would
eventually be enacted, even if three successive drafts had been consigned to
limbo. Every Assembly had regarded the task as a solemn charge upon its
energies; and every sensible man felt—no one more than Cambacérès, the chief
draftsman of the Convention—that in the Revolutionary legislation there was
much to revise, to coordinate, and to secure. At the first calm moment the task
could be completed. Indeed, immediately after the revolution of Brumaire, a
committee was appointed to consider the reform of the Code and to report to the
Legislative Commission.
There is
perhaps no single document more significant of the temper of France upon the
morrow of Brumaire than the speech made by Jacqueminot in submitting his draft to the Commission. The reporter fully acknowledged that
the work of his committee had been hasty and imperfect, but urged in
extenuation that it was necessary to put an end to the scandal of the
Revolutionary divorce laws, to restore to parental power its lawful authority,
and to widen the liberty of testamentary bequest. So instantaneous was the
reversion from Revolutionary excesses to the old and pertinacious tradition of
French jurisprudence! The draft of Jacqueminot was in
itself of no consequence. Composed in the brief and unsettled interlude between
the fall of the Councils and the establishment of the Consulate, and far
inferior in elaboration and technique to the earlier work of Cambacérès, it was
not even discussed for five minutes. The Legislative Commission was confronted
with larger and more pressing problems; but it is well to remember that, before
their task had been completed, and while the lineaments of the Consular
Constitution were still under discussion, the spirit which was destined to
inform the Code Napoleon had spoken and revealed itself. The laws of France, as
they had been left by the Revolutionary Assemblies, were to be coordinated and
reduced to system; but philosophical idealism was to be corrected by juristic
tradition, and the political extravagance of the passing hour utterly effaced.
Law was to be the expression of settled national character, not of every
passionate and casual mood.
The Civil Code.
The desired
moment of calm came after the battle of Marengo had secured the frontier of
France, established the prestige of the Consulate, opened the avenue to an
honourable peace, and liberated the energies of Bonaparte for the civil
organisation of the State. On August 12, 1800, a committee of four lawyers, Tronchet, Portalis, Bigot de Preameneu, and Maleville, was
appointed to draw up a project of a Civil Code, with instructions to bring the
work to a conclusion in the following November. Every committee has a head and
a tail. Though Maleville was a capable lawyer and
afterwards distinguished as the first of a long line of commentators on the
Code, and though Bigot’s adroitness and pliancy were destined to be proved in
more fields than one, the driving power in this committee lay with Tronchet and Portalis. Of these
two men, Tronchet, the venerable president of the Cour de Cassation, stood for massive learning, sound
judgment, and conservative caution; while Portalis,
if less eminent in knowledge than “the Nestor of the aristocracy”, was
specially distinguished in the art of legal and philosophical exposition. “He
would have been”, said Napoleon, “the most eloquent orator in the Council if he
had known when to stop”; but, save for its fluency, the chastened eloquence of
the great Provencal jurist had little in common with the exaggerated rhetoric
of the Clubs. Portalis was a thinker, a Catholic, and
a conservative. A true parliamentarian, in the French sense of the term, he had
opposed legal unification in 1789 on the ground that a code would be the
precursor of despotism; and ten years later, when the Directory was tottering
to its fall, he expressed to a friend his earnest desire that a liberator might
be found to free France from the toils of Revolutionary legislation. It was
certain that he viewed divorce with aversion, and that his will would be cast
into the scale of moderate reaction towards the past. While Portalis and Maleville represented the legal traditions of the
land of written law, Tronchet and Bigot had been
trained in the Parlement and the Customs of
Paris; and the Civil Code, which was the result of their labours, exhibits many
traces of compromise between northern Teutonism and
the Latin inheritance of the south.
The draft of
the Civil Code was completed in four months and printed on January 1,1801. It
was then, by order of Bonaparte, sent to the law-courts, which were invited to
submit their criticisms and observations in the course of the next three
months. In the light of this commentary the draft Code was then examined and
revised by the legislative section of the Council of State, composed of Boulay,
Berber, Emmery, Portalis, Réal, and Thibaudeau; and, when
this process was completed, it was submitted title by title to the whole body
of the Council. It was at this stage that the provisions of the Code first came
under the notice of Bonaparte.
Eyewitnesses
have described the vivid and animated drama which was enacted whenever
Bonaparte came down to preside over the Councilchamber in the Tuileries. A clink of arms, a roll of the drum under the arcades, and
then, as the door opens, and the usher calls, and the councillors rise in
salutation, the master steps briskly up to his green table on the dais, nods to
Cambacérès on his right, to Lebrun on his left, signs to his Council to be
seated, and with his “Allons, Messieurs, commençons”,
sets the debate aflame. Under the Consulate, these discussions were free,
vivacious, and unembarrassed; and, when the First Consul presided in person,
and he presided over thirty-five of the eighty-seven sittings devoted to the
Civil Code, they were generally prolonged till a late hour in the evening. His
too was the most quickening spirit in debate. With little legal learning, save
what he had gathered from snatches of reading or from the talk of Tronchet and Portalis, and devoid
of the scholarly temper of the professional draftsman, he possessed so
luxuriant an intellectual nature, so lively a power of concrete vision, so keen
an instinct for the large issues of politics, that his contributions to the
discussion were a series of splendid surprises, occasionally appropriate and
decisive, occasionally involved in the gleaming tissues of a dream, but always
stamped with the mark of genius and glowing with the impulses of a fresh and
impetuous temperament. Lanfrey has indeed urged that
the official report of the proceedings drawn up by Locré, the clerk of the
Council, has imparted a correctness to Bonaparte’s language which did not
belong to it, and has effaced the eccentricities which would have betrayed the
novice in legislation. This is true. Bonaparte often talked at random, and some
of his warmest admirers in the Council complained that he fatigued the
attention of his audience by the confused abundance and the unexpected turns of
his thought. On the other hand, it is equally true to say that the grave and
chilly language of the official reporter has robbed the First Consul of all his
peculiar verve and most of his originality.
“He spoke”,
says Thibaudeau, “without embarrassment and without
pretension. He was never inferior to any member of the Council; he often
equalled the ablest of them by the ease with which he seized the point of a
question, by the justice of his ideas and the force of his reasoning; he often
surpassed them by the turn of his phrases and the originality of his
expression”. At one moment he would embark upon the most adventurous of
intellectual cruises; at the next he would propound some prim legal definition.
Here would be a flash of anger ; here a string of anecdotes; here a friendly
passage of badinage punctuated by snuff-taking; here a flight of gaudy
rhetoric. But the prevailing impression left on the reader of these debates is
the union in the mind of the chief debater of hard-headed common sense with
imaginative vision. He thinks, not in legal rules but in concrete cases, keeping
always in sight the gain and loss to the whole State, the political advantages
and disadvantages to France. “You act as law-makers”, he cried once, “not as
statesmen. It is by speaking to the soul that men are electrified”. He was in
fact the amateur of genius, learning as he went along, throwing off opinions as
sparks fly from the anvil, shaking himself free from the views of yesterday if
they embarrassed him or were plainly overpowered, but always capable of making
a contribution to the discussion by his sheer power of seeing principles as
they would work themselves out in the life of the individual or the State. “I
first thought”, he confessed, “that it would be possible to reduce laws to
simple geometrical demonstrations, so that whoever could read and tie two ideas
together would be capable of pronouncing on them; but I almost immediately
convinced myself that this was an absurd idea”; and in one of the last sittings
of the Council he pronounced what legal opinion has felt to be the trite
criticism on the Code itself. “I often perceived that over-simplicity in
legislation was the enemy of precision. It is impossible to make laws extremely
simple without cutting the knot oftener than you untie it, and without leaving
much to incertitude and arbitrariness”. Yet Bonaparte’s appreciation of the
complexity of the task was only equalled by his impatience to despatch it
without delay.
As each
Title of the Code passed the Council, it was submitted successively to the
Tribunate and the Legislative. The spirit of these two assemblies was in the
early days of the Consulate tolerably independent; and the debates of the
Tribunate were often distinguished by eloquence and courage. As the Tribunes
had been provided with copies of the first draft, they had ample leisure to
mature their objections ; and it was expected that they would assail the Code
for its lack of originality, its deference to tradition, and its departure from
some of the Revolutionary innovations. To disarm criticism of this kind, Portalis pointed out that the Prussian Code had respected
historic forces and even local custom; that moderation was a quality essential
to the legislator; and that the temporary laws of the Revolution were like
piles wavering in a stormy sea. Nevertheless, the Tribunes proceeded to level a
volley of well-aimed criticism against the first two “Titles”, or laws, which
were presented to them. It was objected against the First—which dealt with the
publication, the effects, and the application of laws in general—that its scope
was too wide; that its character, consisting largely of moral and legal maxims,
was inappropriate; and that the arrangement of the clauses was incoherent.
These objections were so strongly felt that the law was thrown out by a
majority of sixty-five to thirteen in the Tribunate, and by a hundred and
fifty-two to a hundred and thirty-nine in the Legislative. The Second Title, on
the enjoyment and loss of civil rights, shared the same fate; and the Council
was obliged to withdraw both laws. The First Consul was deeply chagrined. “When
I see a man like Simeon”, he said, “doubting if persons born in the colonies
are Frenchmen, I ask myself whether my head has turned”; and, announcing that
the time had not yet come when one could “import into these great discussions
the calm and unity of intention which they demanded”, he decreed (April 1,
1S02) a revision of procedure. An end was put to open debate in the full House.
The Titles of the Code were henceforward to be submitted to the legislative
section of the Tribunate, which was invited to tender its comments to the
section of the Council responsible for that portion of the draft. In case of
non-agreement, a conference was held under the presidency of Cambacérès; and,
when the clauses had been there settled, they were referred back to the whole
body of the Council, discussed anew, and then in their final shape expounded to
the silent legislature by three selected Councillors. Under the new
arrangement the work proceeded swiftly; and on March 21, 1S04, the Civil Code
in its entirety passed into law.
It has been
often said that the spirit displayed by the Tribunate in these legal debates
was captious and unsteady, and that it was well for France that the
rhetoricians were silenced. This view is untenable. The speeches of Andrieux and Simeon, who took the lead in opposition, are
serious and weighty ; and nearly all the criticisms of the Tribunes were
well-founded. One speaker protested against the droit d’aubaine,
another against civil death, a third against confiscation. All three have the
verdict of posterity on their side. When Simeon, the brother-in-law of Portalis, urged that there was no pressing hurry, and that
every effort should be made to bring the Code to perfection, he was only
talking common sense. But Bonaparte was impatient of delay; and, through no
fault of its own, the action of the Tribunate was bound to wear the aspect of
obstruction. By an inept clause of the Constitution, that body was debarred
from proposing amendments to the laws which were submitted to it. If, then, the
Tribunes were to give practical effect to their criticism of an article, they
were forced to throw out the whole Title of which that article formed perhaps
only an inconsiderable part. The alternative was one which no self-respecting public
men could accept; and, refusing to accept it, the Tribunate was deprived of the
power of publicly debating the Civil Code.
The First
Book of the Civil Code treats of “Persons”, the Second of “Goods and the
various kinds of Property”, the Third of “The various modes in which Property
is acquired”.
The French
Revolution was justly charged with having disturbed the foundations of family
life. In order to stimulate the subdivision of property, it had, by its
encouragement of adoption and its recognition of natural children, introduced
new members into the family, while, with the same clear intention, it had
restricted the testamentary powers of the father, equalised the sexes in
marriage, and facilitated divorce. In the strong reaction which had set in
against these ideas Bonaparte fully participated. He held that the legislator,
far from encouraging the indefinite subdivision of property, should aim at
securing a nation of moderate fortunes. He was a keen advocate of the
subjection of women. He thought that it was the function of law to chasten
loose morals, to exhibit the solemnity and sanctity of marriage, to strengthen
the authority of the father, and to maintain the cohesion of the family group.
All these views—and they were by no means the exclusive property of
Bonaparte—are reflected in the provisions of the Code. If adoption was
retained, the institution was accompanied by so many precautions that it could
no longer be regarded as a deterrent to matrimony or a menace to family life.
The adopter must be childless and over fifty years of age; and the adopted is
not to sever the ties which bind him to his natural family. Nor can adoption
take place so long as the adopted is a minor. Again, a clear line of separation
was traced between the lawful and the natural child. “Natural children are not
heirs. The law only accords them a claim upon the goods of their deceased
father and mother when they have been legally recognised”. Even so their share
is reduced to a third, a half, or three-fourths of what it would have been had
they been born in wedlock; a third if the father and mother have left lawful
descendants; a half, if they have only left ascendants, brothers or sisters;
and three-fourths where there are neither descendants nor ascendants, to claim
the inheritance. In vain Cambacérès pleaded that in certain cases the parent
should be compelled to recognise the child. “Society”, replied Bonaparte, “has
no interest in the recognition of bastards”; and he set his face against
facilitating investigations into questions of paternity. Save in one
eventuality, la recherche de la paternité is
forbidden in the Civil Code.
In one of
those large moral precepts, which are plentifully sown about the Code, it is
laid down that the “child at every age owes honour and respect to his father
and mother”. The power of the father was restored, and the despotism of the
State repeated in the structure of the family. While the mother has no voice in
the control of her children, the father is absolute. He can imprison his child,
if under sixteen years of age, for a period not exceeding one month; if between
sixteen and twenty-one, for a period not exceeding six months. In neither case
is any writing or judicial formality required. The president of the Court of
the arrondissement is bound to grant the order for detention. The father is not
even required to state his motives. It is merely demanded of him that he shall
sign an undertaking to pay all the expenses, and to furnish a suitable support
to the prisoner. There is no more significant tribute to the continuity of
French jurisprudence than this curious revival of the lettres de cachet, which, in the later half, at any rate, of the eighteenth
century, were almost exclusively used to protect family honour by enabling a
parent to incarcerate his troublesome offspring, without any disagreeable
process of washing dirty family linen in open court. In the south of France, no
doubt, where the Roman law bad always been a living force, the paternal power
was the corner-stone of society; but all over the country, partly owing to the
pride of the aristocracy, partly owing to a delicate sensitiveness which is a
feature of the national temperament, and partly owing to the general dislike of
the royal tribunals as intrusive novelties, the strongest prejudice existed
against dragging family affairs into court. Indeed it is a singular fact that
many of the cahiers of 1789, while denouncing the lettres de cachet, express a hope that some less objectionable provision may be
made for maintaining domestic discipline. To this aspiration the Code responds.
Nor are
these the only stones in the edifice of domestic monarchy. A marriage may not
be contracted without consent of the parents by a son who has not reached his
twenty-sixth year, or by a daughter who has not reached her twenty-first. The
parents have the usufruct of their children’s property until they have entered
upon their nineteenth year. They have the right to choose a guardian without
the intervention of the relations or of a magistrate; and, if the father may
not disinherit his son, he is given a larger power of devising his property by
will. “Even in the most absolute governments”, said Bonaparte, “despotism stops
short at the threshold of the home. It weighs upon the head of the household;
and, as the head of the family is absolutely at the disposition of the
Government, so is the family absolutely at the disposition of its head.”
In
accordance with these principles, the civil status of woman was carefully
depressed. A woman cannot be accepted as a witness to the acts of the Civil
State, nor can she act as guardian or form part of the family council unless
she is the mother or one of the ascendants. As a wife she is subject to her
husband, and has no voice in the administration of their common property. She
cannot give, sell, or mortgage; she cannot acquire by sale or gift without the
husband’s written consent. Only if she is carrying on a separate trade can she
make a contract without her husband’s authority. The woman of the Civil Code is
regarded as a fickle, defenceless, mindless being; and her lapses from virtue
are punished more severely than those of a man. “A husband”, said Napoleon,
“ought to have the right to say to his wife: you shall not go out, you shall
not go to the play, you shall not see such and such a person”. When a
Councillor asked whether wifely obedience had been prescribed in the old laws
of France, the First Consul turned upon him sharply: “What a question!” he
cried. “Do you not know that the angel told Eve to obey her husband?... Morality
has written this article in all languages. A fortiori should it be written in
French in our Code”.
A law of
September, 1792, had abolished judicial separation and admitted divorce, not
only by mutual consent, but also for incompatibility of temper upon the
allegation of one of the parties. That a contract should be abolished at the
will of one of the parties was in itself an anomaly; and in this instance it
was clearly subversive not only of religious tradition but of the most
elementary principles of social order. Some of the law-courts, when consulted
upon the first draft of the Code, declared against divorce altogether, and
asserted that, as a matter of fact, no recourse had been made to it in the
provinces. With the single exception of the Tribunal of Paris, every Court in
France rejected divorce for incompatibility; and the Tribunal of Paris
stipulated that incompatibility should be proved in court. It was a question
upon which Bonaparte himself was profoundly interested. On the one hand, with
his strong views as to the subjection of the weaker sex and the value of family
cohesion, he was averse from any provision which might encourage the levity or
augment the liberty of woman; and so powerful was this feeling in him that he
subsequently prohibited divorce for members of the imperial family. On the
other hand, he recognised that divorce might serve his own turn, and that
within certain prescribed bounds it was necessary to society. As he said at St
Helena, “to make marriage indissoluble is to provoke ennui, and to put the
village cure above the law”. The Council too was substantially agreed upon the
necessity of admitting the principle of divorce, though it was willing to yield
to Catholic susceptibilities so far as to restore judicial separation (omitted
in the first draft) as an alternative. Nor was there any doubt that, while
divorce for grave specific causes should be admitted, divorce for
incompatibility at the demand of one of the parties should be eliminated from
the Code. The main contest raged over divorce by mutual consent; and, but for
the strong advocacy of the First Consul, this would not have been received into
the Code. Bonaparte’s contention was that divorce for specific causes would not
be sufficient. The offences contemplated were not only difficult to prove, but,
in the attempt to prove them, the wronged and the wrong-doer were alike dragged
into publicity. “Few men are so lost to shame as to proclaim the turpitude of
their wives. It would be scandalous and against the honour of the nation to
reveal what passes in some households”.
Practical
and political considerations therefore concurred in suggesting that this form
of dissolving the marriage union should be supplemented by an alternative
expedient which should be at once more private, more honourable, and more
popular. Bonaparte was willing to concede that unions should not be dissolved
after they had endured ten years; he was willing to prevent the same person
from divorcing twice; he urged that the law should forbid divorced persons from
remarrying within five years. But, hedged round by these safeguards, divorce by
mutual consent for incompatibility of temper was in his view essential to
marital happiness. Girls married young; and, though he had succeeded in raising
the age from thirteen to fifteen, he had not raised it as high as he wished. In
most cases, a young girl fresh from school or convent could not know whether
her husband would prove congenial; in most cases a marriage was an affair of
convenience. It was well that, when mistakes had been made, they should be
capable of being corrected without noise or scandal. Accordingly he proposed
that the affair should be brought before a family council presided over by a
magistrate; that the relations on both sides should be unanimous; and that with
their consent the Court should pronounce the divorce without examination. “I do
nothing against the married persons”, he said, “since I require mutual consent.
I do nothing against marriage, since I demand the adhesion of the relations”.
Judicial separation was in his view a bad expedient, for it involved publicity
and favoured immoral conduct. At St Helena he added, with penetration, that it
was “a mezzo termine which could only be
applied to the upper classes”. All things then conspired to commend the
adoption of some provision for divorce by mutual consent. After long debate the
First Consul prevailed; and, surrounded with a large number of restrictions,
divorce by mutual consent passed into law.
No less
jealous was the attitude of the Council towards divorce for “specified
motives”. The possible causes were reduced from seven to three: adultery, cruelty,
and the conviction of one of the parties for a grave criminal offence; and the
investigation into the facts was transferred from the family council to the
law-court. It is a curious fact in human nature that the experiment of
entrusting these delicate enquiries to the family council broke down, not so
much by reason of the incompetence of its members as because of their sheer
indifference to an issue in which their sentiments should have been most
closely involved.
The
sentiment of equality, which had shaped the family law of the Revolution, had
also moulded its conception of civic rights. The Constituent Assembly, in a
fit of cosmopolitan generosity, had unconditionally abolished the droit d'aubaine, and the droit de detraction, a ten per cent,
succession duty levied by the Treasury upon the property of foreigners. But the
clouds of war had obscured the clear sky of philanthropy; and the draft Code
proposed a return to the earlier system of reciprocity, which secured to the
alien in France just such treatment as was accorded to the Frenchman in the
alien’s country. Though sharply attacked in the Tribunate, this clause passed
into the Code. In favour of the change it was argued that the generous policy
of the Constituent Assembly had failed to induce other countries to relax
their alien laws, and that, by retaining something to give away in return for
concessions, France could secure better terms for her emigrants. Animated by
the same spirit of traditional nationalism, the framers of the draft Code had
proposed to accord civil rights to such persons only as were born in France and
were the children of French parents. This proposition seemed to Bonaparte far
too narrow. On political and on military grounds, he held that the privileges
and duties of French citizenship should be as widely diffused as possible. He
insisted that civil rights should be granted to the children of an alien father
if they were born in France, and to the children of a French father born
abroad. So too he urged that the child born abroad of a French father who had
renounced his nationality should always be able to recover his French
citizenship. “As for me”, he said long afterwards when recalling his share in
this debate, “I desired that a Frenchman by origin should find himself a
Frenchman again even if his family had been for ten generations abroad. If he
should appear on the further bank of the Rhine, saying, ‘I wish to be a
Frenchman’, I desired that the barrier should fall before him and that he
should return triumphant to the bosom of the common mother”. It is also due to
the First Consul that special dispositions were inserted in the Code to
facilitate the registration of births, marriages, and deaths occurring in the
French army while it was serving beyond the frontiers. Où est le drapeau, là est la France.
The
fundamental principles of the Revolutionary law of property were too clearly
based on sound economic principles to be shaken by the lawyers of the
Consulate. Nobody dreamed of restoring feudalism or the dead hand of the great
corporations. A proposal to revive the rentes foncières, a contract resembling the Roman
emphyteusis by which a proprietor may let out waste land at a perpetual and
irredeemable charge, was indeed discussed, but only to be rejected. The First Consul
saw no advantage in it; and Portalis urged that,
however useful it might have been in days when there was much waste to be
reclaimed, such a contract would now create “inextricable embarrassment”. But,
while the law of tenure underwent no sensible modification, the law which
regulated the transfer of property was modified in several important
particulars. A sale of immoveable property could be rescinded pour cause de lésion, if the seller had been defrauded of more than
seven- twelfths of the price; and that, too, even if he had expressly renounced
his right to take action for the rescission of the contract. Such a provision
implies that there is a just price, the result of common opinion; and that, if
property is sold for less than it is worth, the State should step in to protect
the ignorant vendor. The doctrine had been repudiated by the Convention, which
had abolished the action for rescission in 1795; but it was hotly championed by
the First Consul, whose hatred of the Stock Exchange and of army contractors
led him to welcome any expedient for repudiating a contract.
With a
similar aim of defeating the machinations of financiers, it was intimated in
the Code that the rate of interest would be fixed by law. “Interest”, so runs
the text, “is legal or contractual. Legal interest is fixed by law. Contractual
interest may exceed legal interest whenever the law does not prohibit”. It was
urged in defence of the principle of regulation that, ever since the Convention
had declared money to be merchandise, it had been loaned out at usurious rates.
Nevertheless, it was not until September, 1807, that the rate was actually
fixed—by a law which, as Napoleon remarked to Mollien, did not belong “to the
system of your idéologues”.
Two
questions arose with regard to liens and mortgages. Should the law require them
to be publicly registered? Should the law require them to be specially attached
to a particular piece of immoveable property? The Convention, which desired to
facilitate land-transfer to the furthest extent possible, decided on 11
Brumaire, year VII (Nov. 1, 1798) both for the principle of publicity and for
that of specialty. But these rules seemed too violent a departure from previous
custom. It is true that in the Low Countries mortgages had long been publicly
inscribed and specially allocated; but in France the secretiveness of an
embarrassed aristocracy had resisted so obvious a method of facilitating
credit. Of thirty Courts of Appeal consulted upon the point, only nine were in
favour of maintaining the Law of Brumaire. The legislative section of the
Council was divided, and two plans were submitted. It was alleged that the Law
of Brumaire violated family secrets, destroyed credit, and injured the
circulation of wealth; that inscription was costly and ineffectual ; that the
principle of specialty was inconsistent with the rights of property, because
the debtor was bound to fulfil his engagements upon all his property and not
upon some special part of it. But the most valid practical objection to the law,
as it stood, was the injury which might be inflicted upon wives and minors who
had not taken the step of inscribing their legal claims upon the property of
their respective husbands or tutors. The division of opinion pointed to a compromise
; and, while the publicity and specialty of liens and mortgages were
recognised, a particular exception was made in favour of women and minors who
had omitted the formality of registration.
Curious as
was the debate upon mortgages, as revealing unsuspected depths of timid
conservatism, it was far less important than the discussion provoked by the law
of inheritance. The theory of the French Revolution had been that the State,
having conferred testamentary rights upon the individual, could abridge or
expand them at will; and that in the interests of social equality it was
necessary to abridge them. Consequently entails (substitutions) were
forbidden; the devisable portion was limited to a tenth; and equality of
division was prescribed. The Code exhibits a sensible but cautious modification
of this extreme position. The devisable portion was augmented, rising to a half
if the testator had but one child, and never falling below a fourth. The father
may bequeath all or any of this portion to one of his natural heirs, or give it
to a relation in trust for children who may be yet unborn. Entails, owing to
the vigorous advocacy of Bonaparte, are permitted to one degree. The arguments
used in debate were both economic and moral. On economic grounds, urged Maleville, it was undesirable that property should be
excessively divided, especially in the poorer departments where corn and
moveable wealth were scarce. On moral grounds, urged Portalis,
it was well that the father should be placed in a position in which he “could
punish and recompense his children, redress inequalities between them, and
satisfy obligations of gratitude towards strangers.” While Bonaparte was fully
in accord with the spirit of these contentions, he proposed, as an alternative
plan for giving effect to them, that the devisable portion should be graduated
according to the amount of the heritable property rather than according to the
number of the children, in such a way that, the wealthier the testator, the
less should be the ratio which the devisable portion should bear to the sum
total of his property. This suggestion, however, was overruled, as entailing
expensive and inquisitorial researches; and the First Consul acquiesced in his
defeat. The concession could be afforded; for, though the Code favours the subdivision
of property, it is far more lenient to inequality than was the Convention,
whose doctrine still numbered some vigorous exponents in the Council of State.
Napoleon
once said at St Helena that his glory consisted, not in having won forty battles,
but in the Civil Code and in the deliberations of his Council of State. Judged
by external tests, the fortunes of the Civil Code have indeed been brilliant,
and its influence has been wide. Yet it has been subjected to much severe
criticism. Savigny, the founder of the historical school of European jurists,
and Austin, the chief exponent of the analytical school in England, attacked it
with vigour and knowledge. The Civil Code, said Savigny, was drafted at an
unfavourable epoch, at a time of uncertainty and conflict, when the ideas of
the Revolution were fast passing away and the ideas of the Empire were secretly
growing; and this uncertainty is reflected in its provisions. To take one
instance—the system of entails, rejected in 1803 was restored in 1806, and
included in the Code in 1807. The Council of State had no part in the technical
discussion of the Code, which was left to the four draftsmen, who were ignorant
of Roman law. The judicial literature of France, consisting almost entirely of Pothier, from whose treatise three-fourths of the Code were
extracted, was pitiable; and the selection of subjects was not determined by
experience and practical knowledge, but by the Institutes of Justinian. The
Code was incomplete; it had to be supplemented by external authority, and, far
from being an organic product, was but a mechanical mixture of the results of
the Revolution and the old regime of Roman law and the customs. Austin, too,
condemned the haste and ignorance of the draftsmen, the absence of definitions
of technical terms and of any provision for amendment. The Council of State, he
pointed out, often devoted great attention to points of no importance, while
neglecting many vital questions of arrangement and expression. The Code must
not be regarded as a body of law forming a substantive whole, but as an index
to an immense body of jurisprudence existing outside itself.
The Civil
Code has also been criticised, upon economic grounds, as too favourable to the
subdivision of property. From this cause some have deduced the lack of
commercial enterprise, the fondness for safe investments, and the stationary
census returns which they regard as characteristic of France. Thus Le Play
contended that, before the reign of Louis XIV, the French peasantry made use of
their testamentary freedom to keep their properties together; and that these
habits resulted in an admirable social organisation and great agrarian
prosperity. By degrees, however, the old traditions of work and economy
declined; and it was found more difficult to make pecuniary endowments for the
younger children. The habit of territorial subdivision acquired strength ; and
it was intensified by the legislation of the Revolution and the Consulate. It
may be sufficient here to point out that the economic criticism is more
properly directed against the Revolutionary law of succession than against the
Civil Code, which travelled as far back on the road to testamentary freedom as
public opinion would then allow.
The
criticisms of the jurists are no doubt largely true; but some of them would be
equally applicable to any code framed at any time. The most elaborate system of
legal casuistry is poor beside the inexhaustible power of life to produce new
combinations; and no code can be more than a legal alphabet. It is doubtful
whether the Civil Code has reduced the bulk of French case-law, or materially
lightened the labours of French judges. On the other hand, it has diffused the
knowledge of law, and made it comparatively easy for the ordinary Frenchman to
become acquainted with the leading principles which govern the law of his own
country. Again, its simplicity and elegance of form have made it a convenient
article of exportation; and these qualities have perhaps helped to secure for
it a wider acceptance outside the frontiers of France than upon its intrinsic
merits it deserves. In France, the Code has perhaps commanded an excessive
deference and stood in the way of useful legislative changes. There the glamour
which attaches to it is due not only to the circumstances of its production, to
the fact that it is at once the summary and the correction of the French
Revolution, as well as the legal formula of the most dazzling period of French
national history, but also and more especially to the circumstance that it is
the abiding symbol of that unity of law which was first made possible by the
meeting of the States General in 1789. So long as law
was unified, it did not so much matter whether the text was scrupulous or clumsy,
whether the principles were collected in a code or left to be inferred from
legislative acts, custom, and judicial decisions. The Civil Code was a hasty
piece of work; and the First Consul imported a strong gust of passion and of
politics into the laboratory of legal science. Civil death, a superannuated,
unjust, and immoral fiction, confiscation, and the position of women, are bad
blots upon the page. Could anything be more monstrous than that a widow should
not be allowed to succeed to her husband, until all his relations, even his
natural children, have taken their share ? There is also much disproportion and
omission. There are instances of a subject being discussed in the Council, then
forgotten and allowed to lapse. The law of contract is taken almost bodily from Domat and Pothier. But,
when all deductions have been made for haste, negligence, and political
perversion, it remains a great achievement. It was a single code for the whole
of France, substantially based upon the broad historic instincts of the race,
while preserving the most valuable social conquests of the Revolution. It is
vain to say that the moment was unfavourable. Ideally favourable it certainly
was not, but it was the one moment which had never occurred before and would
never occur again. A few years earlier, the Code would have been steeped in
Revolutionary extravagance; a few years later, it would have borne the hard
imprint of despotism. Fortunately for France, the Code was composed at the only
time since the Revolution when the government of the country had been both
glorious and even-handed. And to the strictures of the chair it is at least
some reply, that the Code has proved adequate to the needs and congenial to the
temper of France.
The share
taken by Bonaparte himself in the construction of this famous monument has been
variously estimated according to the political prepossessions of historians. Lanfrey believed that, if the First Consul advocated
divorce and adoption, this was because he was thinking of his own possible
requirements; and that his interference with the legal discussions of the
Council, being dictated in the main either by strictly political or by strictly
private considerations, was a positive disservice to French law. Such a view is
a great exaggeration. It is perfectly true that the quidnuncs of Paris were
speculating upon a possible divorce of Bonaparte even then regarded the divorce
as a conceivable and odious contingency. But his attitude upon the question is
quite explicable without reference to any dishonourable hypothesis; and the
safeguards with which he proposed to surround adoption clearly show that in
that matter at least he was not thinking of his own case. Again, it would be a
wild paradox to assert that the Code gained nothing by Bonaparte’s slashing
intrusions. That he had little interest in the technical side of law; that he
had none of that patient and trained sagacity which slowly worries out the
heart of an intricate subject; that he was often grossly irrelevant; that he
took no part whatever in the composition of the Second Book of the Code and
only an intermittent part in the composition of the Third; that he was mainly
interested in the larger social and political aspects of every legal problem
which came before his notice—all this may be admitted. Nor can any fair
apologist deny that Bonaparte was directly responsible for some of the worst
features of the Code; that he admitted without a word of censure other features
which were hardly less objectionable; and that, if he had always had his way,
some provisions would have been inserted which every sound lawyer and statesman
would have deplored. He was solely responsible for the admission of
confiscation; he was largely responsible for the gross inequality of treatment
meted out to the two sexes. If his will had prevailed, all émigrés would have
been declared civilly dead, and their marriages regarded as null and void by
the law.
All this
notwithstanding, the Civil Code owes much to Bonaparte. Without his driving
power it would certainly not have come into existence so soon, and it might not
have come into existence at all. To his glowing imagination and fertile
intelligence are due several small changes of a humanitarian character and some
technical improvements. “Would you allow a father to drive a daughter of
fifteen from his house or to thrust out his heir into misery? A well-to-do
father always owes maintenance to his children”, he cried; and this eloquent
protest against the doctrine that alimony was not due to majors was embodied in
the Code. In another passage he argued that the deaf and dumb should be
permitted to marry. “He has known through his father and mother the marriage
union. He can declare his will to live like them. Why then aggravate his
misfortune?”. And here again the argument went home. He suggested several
improvements in the law of absence; he framed the definition of “domicile”
which has found its way into the Code; he advocated, in the interests of the
race, that the age at which marriage could be legally contracted should be more
advanced than that sanctioned by the old French law. But, over and above these
specific contributions, the presiding intelligence of Bonaparte gave scope and
dignity to the work. Professional lawyers may easily lose sight of the wider implications
of their professional studies; though perhaps this was not the greatest danger
in a Council where men like Berber and Treilhard championed at every turn the
large political faith of the Revolution. Yet it was a danger; and to
Bonaparte’s presence we may ascribe the fact that the civil law of France was
codified, not only with more scrupulosity than other portions of French law,
but also with a livelier sense of the general interests of the State. What
those interests were, Bonaparte knew. They were civil equality, healthy family
life, secure bulwarks to property, religious toleration, a government raised
above the howls of faction. This is the policy which he stamped upon the Civil
Code.
The Code of Civil Procedure.
By turn
feudal and ecclesiastical, royal and democratic, civil procedure in France has
earned, in its successive phases, the bad opinion of laymen. The venality of
judges, the costliness, the delays, and the cumbrous forms of the law have been
denounced or satirised by a long succession of writers, from Theodulf of Orleans to Rabelais, Montaigne, Moliere, and
Saint-Pierre. In its feudal stage, procedure was public and oral; its proofs
were characterised by extreme rigidity and formalism, and also by the barbarous
method of the combat. But, in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, the Church
began to extend her influence over the whole realm of legal forms, softening
the rigour of the old Germanic codes, introducing written proofs and secret
enquiry, and appealing to reason rather than to force. In the thirteenth
century, the usage of secret inquest, diffused specially through the medium of
the Inquisition, found its way into the “Olim” and
the official registers of the Parlement of
Paris; and the influence of St Louis, who in 1260 suppressed judicial combat in
the royal domain, was exerted to promote this tendency.
The triumph
of the Canon Law invested the civil procedure of France with a higher degree of
unity than existed in the department of Civil Law. The Custumals,
at any rate in their later stages, generally contained no rules relating to
forms ; and, although each Parlement had its own
“style of procedure”, there was a large measure of uniformity through France,
always excepting those provinces which had lately been conquered. When,
therefore, in the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries, the Kings of
France undertook the task of correcting the vices which had crept into the
administration of justice, they were able with comparatively little trouble to
secure general acceptance for their ordinances. Several important partial
reforms were effected in the sixteenth century, as for instance by the
Ordinance of Villers-Cotterets in 1539, which
prescribed the use of the French language in legal documents, simplified
procedure in cases of default, and restrained the number of dilatory
exceptions; and by the Ordinance of Orleans (1561), which introduced into lay
Courts the canonical distinction between ordinary and summary affairs. But all
these ordinances were welded together in the Grand Ordinance of 1667, which
aimed at establishing a uniform “style” in all the Courts of the kingdom,
public, feudal, and ecclesiastical. Supplemented by local usages, this
elaborate code, for code it was, ruled France till the Revolution. It abolished
some abuses; but, since its object was rather to codify existing rules than to
introduce reforms, it was often subjected to sharp criticism. The eighteenth
century was filled with complaints of the delays, the costs, and the
technicalities of justice; but, unfortunately for legal progress, the aversion
from formalism characteristic of the age was unaccompanied by an accurate
knowledge of forms. With the exception of d’Aguesseau’s two Ordinances of 1737 and 1738, no definite ameliorations were proposed. The
works of Lange and Bornier, who had commented upon
the Ordinance of 1667 in the reign of Louis XIV, were reprinted; and the reform
of French judicial procedure failed to attract a single mind of high quality.
Indeed, it is well to note that the eminent Pothier,
whose lectures had so large an influence on the Civil Code, left only one
unimportant treatise upon the subject of civil procedure, and that composed
only in extreme old age. Thus, when the Revolution broke out, the lawyers,
whose gaze was restricted within the four corners of seventeenth century
formalism, were confronted with a public that wished all formalism at the
bottom of the sea. The public said in effect, “Let justice be speedy,
unprofessional, governed by natural laws, divested of technicalities, affording
large facilities for arbitration”; and what the fashionable theory proclaimed
the Revolutionary Assemblies enacted. The Constituent Assembly promised a code,
organised the procedure to be followed before the newly created juges de paix, and
curtailed some judicial expenses. In the Constitution of 1793 it was decreed
that public arbitrators were to decide upon verbal pleadings without formality
or expense; and this principle was translated into practice by a law passed in
October of that year, which suppressed attorneys, and enjoined that procedure
should be simple and inexpensive, “founded upon a verbal defence or on a simple
memoir read to the Court by one of the judges”.
The attempt
to infuse simplicity and sentiment into transactions which are necessarily
complicated and dry is unlikely to command success. Treilhard said that justice
was never so costly as during the temporary eclipse of the legal profession,
when every litigant was making large and irregular payments for underhand and
unauthorised advice. Nor was this the only vessel in the fleet of amiable
intentions which suffered shipwreck. While theory proclaimed the juge de paix as
“arbiter”, “father”, and “angel of conciliation”, practice too often exhibited
him as a venal, violent, and ignorant politician. The conciliatory procedure,
from which Voltaire had hoped so much, failed for a reason which a man of
letters could not have been expected to foresee. If it was a means of averting
litigation in tranquil country districts, it broke down in the exciting
atmosphere of the towns; and, so early as 1800, it was clear that the belief in
trained legal intelligence and settled formality had experienced a revival. The
attorney was reestablished by law; the old procedure
was restored pending the preparation of a new code; and men of weight held
conciliation to be a thing of proved futility and a specious source of delay
and expense.
While the
Council of State was elaborating the Civil Code, a Commission was at work upon
civil procedure. Nominated on March 24, 1802, this Commission was composed of
Treilhard, President of the Court of Appeal of Paris; Try, substitute of the
Commissioner of the Republic in the same Court; Berthereau,
President of the Court of First Instance of the Seine; Seguier,
government Commissioner in the same Court; and Pigean,
formerly a practitioner in the Court of the Châtelet and a recognised expert
upon procedure. The work of the Commission was published in 1804, submitted to
the Courts of Appeal and the Cour de
Cassation for their observations, amended by the Commission, examined by
the legislative section of the Council of State, and then, after a discussion
in full Council, communicated privately to a section of the Tribunate, and
finally voted on in the Legislative Body (April 14-29, 1806). In the case of
the Civil Code, far the most interesting stage in the proceedings had been the
debate in full Council; but this cannot be predicated of the Code of Civil
Procedure. Most of the Councillors were unversed in minute technicalities; and
the Commission, composed as it was of practising judges and lawyers with little
sense of philosophical or literary finish, presented their work in a somewhat
abstruse and forbidding shape. Once only, on February 22,1806, was Napoleon
present; and his personal influence was restricted to obtaining the insertion
of two clauses which modified the law relating to the inscription of mortgages
in the interests of the Treasury. So languid, indeed, was the interest of the
Council, that a code containing no less than 1042 articles was despatched in
twenty-three sittings (April 20,1805, to March 29, 1806).
The
Commission decided to exclude from its purview all questions affecting judicial
competence. It did not attempt to settle the procedure of the commercial
Courts, for this would properly belong to the framers of the Commercial Code;
nor that of the Cour de Cassation,
which still substantially follows, in civil cases, the regulation issued by the
Conseil des Parties in 1738. It was also determined to leave the settlement of
a tariff of judicial costs to subsequent regulation, rather than to include it
in the Code. Nevertheless, the task of Treilhard and his colleagues was
sufficiently arduous. They had to bring the civil procedure of the ordinary
Courts into harmony with the Civil Code, to simplify and amend the ancient
forms, and to review the Revolutionary legislation as to the juges de paix,
conciliation proceedings, and the various processes of distraint. Yet, when all
allowance has been made for the difficulty of the task, it must be confessed
that the arrangement of topics is singularly illogical and disorderly. The
first part is entitled “Procedure before the Courts,” and the second “Diverse
Procedures.”
The former
is by no means a model of systematic treatment; while the latter, as its title
implies, comprises a miscellaneous assortment of regulations dealing with such
varied subjects as offers of payment by a debtor, judicial separation, and the
procedure incidental to arbitrations or the opening of a succession.
Yet, however
faulty its arrangement, the Code of Civil Procedure contains some useful
innovations upon the law as d’Aguesseau left it. The
provisions in the First Book as to the procedure to be followed before the juge de paix are
substantially based upon the law of 1790, but comprise a few marked
improvements in detail, such as a simplification of procedure on appeal, and
the prohibition of viva voce objections to witnesses after evidence given. It
was decided to take over from the Revolution the principle that access should
not be given to the lawcourts until all attempts at conciliation had been
exhausted; but the exceptions to the general rule of obligatory conciliation
were multiplied. The law of 1790 had decided that affairs which interested the
State, the communes, and public order need not in the first instance be brought
before the juge de paix for conciliation. The Code extends the privilege, exemption from nugatory
proceedings is nothing else, to minors, to commercial affairs which admit of no
delay, to actions incidental to pending suits, and to actions directed against
.two persons. Even these concessions have been regarded as insufficient. The
Commission on the revision of the Code of Civil Procedure in 1893 revealed the
presence of considerable dissatisfaction with compulsory conciliation. It was
described as a formality “useless in three-fourths of the cases which arise,
and always long and burdensome”. It was pointed out that the number of cases
settled by conciliation was only 23 per cent, of those brought before the juge conciliateur;
that ten or twelve days were consumed by the process; and that, where
conciliation had failed, the record of the proceedings was often prejudicial to
the interests of bona fide litigants in the Court to which the case was
subsequently removed. It would, however, have been folly in 1806 to reject a
promising experiment simply because it had broken down under the stress of
abnormal circumstances. The Commission rightly held that conciliation
proceedings had never had a fair trial; and that the conditions in regard to
the temper of the country and the qualifications of the Bench were so far
changed as to admit of these proceedings being continued with a good prospect
of success.
This was the
boundary beyond which the influence of the French Revolution was not permitted
to pass. The rest of the Code is founded on the rules of the ancien régime,
though some useful additions were made with a view to curtailing expenses,
reducing formality, and abridging delay. The Court was given power to disallow
the right of a party to conduct his case in person, whenever it had reason to
believe that the course of justice would suffer from the passion, the
inexperience, or the obscurity of the pleader. In order to defeat fraudulent
attempts to win a judgment by default by intercepting the summons, it was laid
down that execution could not be taken save “after an act necessarily known to
the defaulting party”. Some excellent provisions were added concerning the
examination of experts; but, save for two slight changes, the whole procedure
to be followed when the genuineness of a document was questioned in a civil
trial (faux incident civil) was taken from d’Aguesseau’s Grand Ordinance of 1737. Indeed the First Book of the Code of Civil Procedure
may be roughly described as a reissue of the Ordinances of 1667 and 1737 with
some improvements and such additions as were rendered necessary by the
institution of conciliation and other proceedings before the juge de paix. Like
the Civil Code, the Code of Civil Procedure was a synthesis of old and new law;
but the old law was here the dominating factor. The rules relating to the
examination of witnesses direct that they shall be examined in camera, but in
the presence of the parties to the suit. The secrecy of 1667 is substantially
preserved. The witnesses are not examined in each other’s presence; nor is the
public admitted to hear the examination. But the presence of the parties is a
guarantee that the judge will not tamper with the depositions. In the
compilation of the Second Book, the Commission found less guidance in the great
code of the seventeenth century; and recourse was had to the “edicts and
declarations of kings, to local statutes, and case-law”. Here some considerable
changes were effected, partly in order to bring the procedure into harmony with
the Civil Code, and partly to correct some suspected tendencies of
Revolutionary legislation. Whether these changes were always wise is a matter
of grave doubt; and it has been alleged that the Code, by too sharply reacting
against the easy Revolutionary law of distraint (November 1, 1798), has damaged
credit and rendered property almost impregnable.
In the main,
then, the Code is an almost literal reproduction of the ancient ordinances and
of the practice of the Chatelet. Even the most conservative lawyers criticise
the luxury of precautions, the profusion of documents, the extreme slowness and
costliness which it enjoins or entails. It may be regarded as a blemish that it
reverts to imprisonment for debt, though, in view off the fact that the contrainte par corps en matière civile et commerciale was not abolished
till 1867, this step was clearly in accordance with opinion and manners. That a
bolder and more drastic treatment was not applied to civil procedure is a
matter for regret, but readily admits of explanation. The writers of the
eighteenth century were either too vague or else too satirical to afford any
practical guide to the reformer. There was no French Jeremy Bentham, nor had
the Revolutionary Assemblies produced a draft code of civil procedure which
might serve as a corrective to the Grand Ordinance of 1667; and a reversion to
the cautious formalism of that and other legal monuments of the ancien régime seemed especially imperative to men just escaped from a period of turbulence
and corruption, when judges were ignorant and venal, and justice was frequently
perverted to political ends. Personal influence may have contributed its quota;
something may have been due to the absence of Napoleon and to the activity of Pigean, a conservative Châtelet lawyer whose Court had been
abolished by the Revolution, and who now took a modest revenge by importing the
practice of the Chatelet into the Code. But though public and lawyers alike
have grumbled over the Code of Civil Procedure, though the Academy has offered
prizes for the best suggestions for reforming it, though two commissions have
reconstructed it on paper, and nine statutes have amended it in detail, the course
of business in a French civil Court is still substantially determined by the
work of Napoleon’s commission.
Criminal Procedure and Penal Laws.
As in civil,
so in criminal procedure, the jurists of the Consulate and the Empire were
presented with two sharply contrasted systems, the one the product of the
monarchy, and the other of revolution. The salient features of the older
criminal procedure, as first tabulated in 1539 by the Ordinance of Villers-Cotterets and afterwards incorporated in the Grand
Ordinance of 1670, were, first, that the procureur of the King or the lord is a
party to every criminal proceeding; next, that the case is divided into two
parts of unequal length, the instruction, a long secret enquiry before a single
judge, and the jugement, given in secret by
the whole Court upon the written evidence submitted to it; thirdly, that the
accused is not permitted to be represented by counsel or to see the charges
brought against him; and lastly, that he is on oath to answer all questions
truly. In other words, the procedure was secret, inquisitorial, and highly
unfavourable to the accused; and many flagrant violations of justice drew attention
to its obvious defects. Towards the end of the eighteenth century, the movement
in favour of a reform of criminal procedure spread through the whole educated
class in France. It had been preached by Beccaria, Voltaire, and Dupaty; it was encouraged by Louis XVI, who carried through
some elementary but precious reforms, such as the abolition of torture; and it
led to some remarkable and comprehensive changes during the Revolution.
The lines
upon which these changes were effected were English rather than French. All the
legal reformers were loud in praise of the English system: the English jury,
the English public trial, the English practice of allowing the prisoner to
employ counsel, the English principle that no prisoner is to be examined on
oath. The Constituent Assembly therefore addressed itself to the task of a
radical reform of criminal procedure upon English lines. Two juries were
introduced: the jury d’accusation,
corresponding to the English grand jury, and the jury de jugement,
corresponding to the English petty jury. The secret preliminary instruction,
which had been the longest and most important part of the proceedings under the ancien régime,
was whittled down to a summary examination by the police-officer, to the
possible hearing of witnesses by the jury de accusation, and to the
interrogation of the accused by the director of the jury, who was always one of
the judges of the district Court. Further, although the instruction was held
with closed doors, the public were now represented by the accusing jury, which
examined the documents submitted to it by the juge de paix, and decided whether to bring in or to
throw out the bill. Greater facilities were given to private persons to
initiate criminal proceedings; there was more oral examination and less
writing. An important change also comes over the second stage of the
proceedings, the trial proper. The procedure is oral and public instead of
written and private. The accused has the assistance of counsel; the judge reads
out the charge to him; he is put upon oath only if he wishes to advance charges
against the witnesses. He is condemned or acquitted by the verdict of a jury of
twelve men, but he is given a practically unlimited right of rejecting jurymen.
The criminal prosecutions are no longer exclusively initiated by the
Government; and no prosecution proceeds to the second stage unless the accusing
jury sees fit to draw up an acte d'accusation. In a word, the system of the Constituent
Assembly was as favourable to the defence as the Ordinance of 1670 had been
favourable to the prosecution.
During the
Revolution these rules proved unworkable. At the best, a system so alien to
French tradition, and making such large drafts upon the judicial temper of the
populace, could only have succeeded in quiet times. As it was, the jury was
introduced into the country during the one decade of its history in which it
was almost certain to be valueless. The excesses of Revolutionary law-courts
and the prevalence of crimes of violence exhibited the weakness of the new
procedure; and Merlin’s Code of Delicts and Penalties (October 25, 1795),
heightening the importance of the written instruction, marks an early stage in
reaction.
The rise of
Bonaparte sharply closed the epoch of generous excursions and airy latitude.
Anarchy, rife in many departments, supplied pretexts congenial to a soldier’s
temperament. An article of the Constitution of 1799 decreed that the public
prosecutor was to be the agent and the nominee of the executive power. A law,
of January 27, 1801, provided for the appointment of government prosecutors in
every arrondissement, gave them power to imprison pending the report of the
accusing jury, restored the secret examination of witnesses in the absence of
the prisoner, and substituted written for oral procedure before the jury
accusation. On Jan. 7, 1801, in spite of the terms of the Constitution which
guaranteed trial by jury for all crimes, special criminal tribunals were
established exempt from the restraint of jury or appeal. The orators of the
Tribunate were loud in their indignation. These new Courts, they said, were
only the Cours prévôtales of 1670
revived; it was vain to urge that they were limited as to function, space, or
time. In a short time all France would be covered with these tribunals; and
what kind of tribunals were they? They denied the prisoner time and opportunity
to prepare his defence; they deprived him of the right of being heard on
questions of importance, of objecting to his judges, of being released on bail.
Since the Bench was relieved of the necessity of explaining the grounds of its
judgment, there was no guarantee that the judgment would be reached by any
competent intellectual process at all; and, since the law denied the right to
appeal, there was no redress if the procedure should be tainted by informality
or injustice. To these criticisms the government orators replied that the
disorder of the country demanded exceptional measures; that the Courts were to
be abolished two years after the conclusion of peace; that the procedure was to
be public and oral; that the prisoner was to have the benefit of counsel and to
be acquainted with the act of accusation; that it was impossible to obtain a
verdict of guilty in the west or the south, where the jury had become the “safeguard
of brigands”; that military tribunals had been established to deal with
brigandage under the Convention and the Directory; that exceptional Courts were
generally demanded by the prefects; and that the Constitution itself had
sanctioned the suspension of the jury in case of armed revolt. The measure was
carried in the Tribunate by 49 votes to 44, and in the Legislative by 292 to
88.
Meanwhile
(May 28,1801) a Commission had been appointed to draw up a criminal code. Their
labours resulted in a draft comprising both penal law and criminal procedure (Code criminel correctionnel et
de police), which preserved the jury and was still prevailingly English in
character. But no sooner was this draft submitted to the law-courts than it
became clear that Anglomania was falling out of fashion. Of the seventy-five
Courts whose observations were published, only twenty-six pronounced in favour
of the retention of the jury; twenty-three did not refer to the subject; while
twenty-six, mainly from the south of France, were adverse. Of the Courts of
Appeal, twelve were adverse, and seven favourable. The problem of the jury
became a burning question.
The Criminal
Code first came before the Council of State on May 22, 1804. The Emperor, in
order to clear the ground, ordered the legislative section of the Council to
prepare and print a list of fundamental questions relating to criminal law and
procedure which might be debated before the articles of the draft Code came to
be discussed in detail. Accordingly, on June 5, fourteen questions were
submitted. Should the jury be preserved? Should there be a jury of accusation
and a jury of judgment? How should the jury be constituted? On what grounds
should objection be taken to a juror? Should the instruction be purely oral, or
partly oral and partly written? Should several questions be put to the jury of
judgment, or one only—“Guilty or not guilty?” Should the verdict be given by
unanimity or majority Should there be criminal circuits? Should the
penalty of death be preserved? Should there be life penalties? Should
confiscation be admitted in certain cases? Should the judges have a certain
latitude in the application of penalties? Should condemned persons who have
finished their term of punishment be placed under supervision? Should condemned
persons of subsequent good conduct be rehabilitated?
The debate
extended over three days, and was characterised by great ability and acuteness.
Capital punishment and imprisonment for life were passed without discussion.
Confiscation was contested, but advocated by Napoleon and carried through. The
main debate centred round the Jury; and here Napoleon, after listening to a
number of speeches, most of them adverse to the retention of the institution,
unfolded his views with characteristic decision. A tyrannical government, as
the experience of the Revolution showed, could influence a jury more easily
than it could influence a judge; and, given public trial and counsel for the
defence, the jury was a superfluous guarantee. Besides, a jury would always
acquit a man who could afford an advocate, and always condone an offence
against the gendarmerie. Still, if it were well composed, and provided that
counsel should not be permitted to address it, a jury might be allowed; but
exceptional Courts would always be needed to chastise organised crime. If,
however, a jury were allowed, the verdict should be given by a majority vote,
for so the chance of escape would be diminished. In these views the Council
only partially concurred. The retention of both Juries—that of Accusation and
that of Judgment—was voted in principle; but it was decided that they should be
named by the prefect from the Electoral Colleges, and that the verdict should
go by an absolute majority. If injustice were done, it might be remedied by the
right of pardon.
With these
large principles determined, the Council, under the presidency of Cambacérès,
settled down to discuss the draft Code. Twelve sessions were held; and the work
was proceeding fast, when it was disturbed by an intervention of the Emperor.
In the great June debate, Napoleon had argued, for the establishment of large
Courts like the old Parlements in order to
give greater authority to the magistrature. “Did one not”, he said, “see
judges, even of the Cour de Cassation, dine with advocates, and contract habits of familiarity with them which
destroyed the moral independence and prestige of their office?”. But his idea
found no favour with the Council. On October 30, however, the legislative
section was presented with a draft law on the amalgamation of civil and
criminal justice which was to give effect to Napoleon’s intention. The Council
of State was again summoned to Saint-Cloud; and five days were devoted to the
discussion of the Emperor’s plan in his presence. “It is necessary”, urged
Napoleon, “to form great corporations, strong in the reputation conferred by a
knowledge of civil law, strong in numbers, above private fears and
considerations, in order that they may cause the guilty to turn pale and may
communicate their energy to the prosecution. It is necessary, in fact, to
organise the prosecution of crime. At present there is no such thing”. It was
argued on the other side that it had been difficult enough to gather the
departmental juries, and that under the proposed plan of wider judicial areas
the Jury would be impossible. Napoleon replied that his Court might send judges
on assize; but this did not satisfy the Council, whose view was shared and
supported by the magistrates then present in Paris for the Imperial coronation.
They reported that the proposed change would extinguish the Jury, and that the
Jury was working better every day. At this Cambacérès confessed his surprise;
and Napoleon tacitly withdrew his plan. After December 20 the work of the
Commission was mysteriously intermitted. Twenty-five sittings of the Council
had been held, over eleven of which Napoleon had presided ; but opinion was not
yet ripe for the changes which he had in mind, and he was content that opinion
should ripen. Thus all the questions relating to criminal law and procedure
which had engaged the public, the law-courts, the Institute, and the Council,
were allowed to fall into oblivion for three years.
It was not
till January 23, 1808, that the legislative section of the Council of State was
commanded to resume its labours on criminal procedure. Their recollection of
past proceedings was confused and unrefreshed; and the great questions which
had excited so much controversy in 1804 were debated anew as if they had never
arisen. A close and crushing criticism from Napoleon settled the fate of the
Jury of Accusation; but the Jury of Judgment successfully weathered the storm.
Napoleon himself advanced arguments in its favour, provided that it were
properly constituted. “The real interest of the accused”, he said, “is to be
judged by enlightened and not by ignorant men”; and this object would be
obtained if the jurors were drawn from the Judges of First Instance and the
Electoral Colleges. There remained the great question of the amalgamation of
civil and criminal justice; and into this Napoleon threw himself with
passionate energy. He had to vanquish an old prejudice against itinerant
judges, and a suspicion that the scheme might revive the Parlements of the ancien régime in a new shape. Never did he wield the rapier of controversy with a more
persuasive brilliance. He touched on the need of curtailing the powers of the
prefect, already excessive; on his desire for a vigorous local life, for more
decentralisation; on the respect due to the magistrature, which was now to
receive greater dignity; on the sheer necessity of coercing crime; on the
humanising influence which a turn at civil business would exert upon the
temperament of a criminal judge. Nor was Napoleon rich in principles only; he drew
from his pocket two draft laws for consideration, and presided day after day
till the scheme passed through.
The system
of Assize Courts once safely secured, Napoleon could afford to admit the Jury,
and to allow the Code of Criminal Procedure to proceed quietly on its way. In
thirty-seven sittings (Jan. 30 to Oct. 30, 1808), the Council cut the Gordian
knots over which they had fumbled in 1804.
In the Code
of Criminal Procedure (Code d’Instruction criminelle) the jury of accusation is suppressed. The depositions
of witnesses are taken secretly in the presence of the juge d’instruction and his clerk, and in the absence of
the prisoner; and all the guarantees of 1789 disappear. The defence cannot
contest the choice of an expert made by a judge; the juge d’instruction is not compelled to hear the
witnesses for the defence; and, during the whole of the instruction, the
prisoner may remain in complete ignorance of the steps which are being taken
against him. The regulations as to bail are so illiberal as to be almost
prohibitive; and they were contested in the Council. And yet, with this
exception, this portion of the Code, utterly subversive though it was of the
Revolutionary law, was passed almost without discussion. So great a change had
been wrought by the advancing palsy of despotism.
But while
the Code of Criminal Procedure borrows from the Ordinances of 1670 almost all
its rules of preparatory instruction, the rules for the trial in court were
based upon the legislation of the Revolution. The accused was to be tried in
public; he was allowed to produce witnesses, to be assisted by counsel, and to
be heard in his own defence. A jury of well-to-do persons was permitted to
return a verdict by a majority vote. The Code however maintained the special
Courts which were authorised to decide without recourse to a jury upon cases of
rebellion, false coinage, assassination if committed by armed bands, and armed
smuggling; nor was any resistance offered in the Council of State to the
permanent incorporation within the judicial system of France of these tyrannous
and autocratic tribunals.
It cannot be
denied that the apparatus set up in the Code for performing the preliminary
business of penal judicature was, though complicated, highly effective as an
instrument of exploration. Whereas in England no judicial functionary was then
obliged to attend to any evidence except such as was voluntarily offered to
him, in France the power of the State was at once put in motion to search out
everything that could illuminate the case. On the other hand, the rule which
required every question to the witnesses to be put through the medium of the
presiding judge sacrificed much of the extractive force of the English
cross-examination. The questions framed by the judge for the jury admitted a
more delicate consideration of circumstances than the mere alternative “guilty”
or “not guilty”. But the Code of Criminal Procedure, though on the whole well
adapted for the detection of crime and for the speedy trials of prisoner’s,
presented hardly any barrier against the arbitrary use of executive authority.
There was no adequate machinery to correspond to the English proceedings upon a
writ of habeas corpus, the juries were nominated by the prefects; the prefect
might act as a juge d’instruction;
and, in the secrecy of the preliminary instruction, a case might be prepared
for the jury which the innocent prisoner would find it difficult to rebut.
The Penal Code.
The Code of
Criminal Procedure could not be put into force until the completion of a Penal
Code; and on October 4, 1808, this task was taken in hand. Some fundamental
questions had already been decided in the June debate four years earlier. It
had been settled that there should be capital punishment and imprisonment for
life; that discharged convicts might be placed under police supervision; that a
convict might be rehabilitated; that a minimum and a maximum penalty should be
fixed for each crime, with latitude of choice within the boundary. It remained
to revise the Code of 1791 in detail under the influences of the moral climate
of 1808. The work was accomplished in forty-one sittings; and the Penal Code
was decreed on February 2, 1810. On the single occasion upon which Napoleon
presided, he expressed his desire for short laws, which left a large discretion
to the judges and the Government, on the pretext that “men had bowels and the
law had not”; but his general views of penal law did not err on the side of
clemency. In 1801 he had advocated with enthusiasm the penalty of branding, especially
for forgery. “The forger is generally rich”, he remarked. “If only condemned to
irons, he returns to society, keeps a fine salon, and people dine with him.
This would not happen if he were branded by the hand of the executioner”. And
his defence of confiscation was equally characteristic; it would, he said,
tempt the relatives of a conspirator to betrayal.
“Punishment”,
said Target, “is certainly not vengeance. It is not the object of law that a
guilty man should suffer, but that crimes should be prevented”. This theory of
punishment had recently been made famous in Bentham’s Treatise on Legislation
which was once alluded to in the course of the discussion. It is not however
probable, considering the prevailing Anglophobia of the time, that the
influence of Bentham upon the Commission was great; and such influence would
never have been acknowledged. The memory of the crimes of the Revolution and
the administrative needs of a strong despotism were far more potent influences.
The Penal Code is severe, suspicious, and in places barbarous. The penalty of
confiscation, which had been condemned by Montesquieu and excluded from the
Code of 1791, was restored. The Legislative Section agreed almost unanimously
to restore the penalty of branding, on the ground of “political reason and the
general interest.” The parricide was to lose his hand before undergoing the
penalty of death. Men condemned to forced labour were to be employed upon the
most painful tasks. “They shall drag a ball at their feet, and shall be tied
two and two with a chain when the nature of the work on which they are employed
shall permit.” The penalty of death was to be inflicted for murder and arson,
for theft and brigandage endangering life and personal security, for corruption
and false witness in cases which imperil the life of the innocent. Penal
servitude for life was meted out to those who organise and command associations
of malefactors against persons or property, even where no actual crime has been
committed; against unprovoked acts of violence which were of a nature to cause
death; and against rebellion, armed gatherings, and “grave crimes”. Deportation
for life was assigned to “state crimes due to false political ideas, the spirit
of party, or an ill-understood ambition”, as well as to grave cases of forgery
and peculation. So great was the suspicion of political meetings that it was
provided that “no association of more than twenty persons, whose aim is to
unite every day or on certain fixed days to occupy itself with religious,
literary, political, or other objects, can be formed, except with the consent
of the Government or under such conditions as public authority may impose”.
The Penal
Code and the Code of Criminal Procedure bear very strongly the imprint of the
times in which they were composed. Unlike the Civil Code, they belong to the
later epoch of the Empire, when despotism had assumed its harsher forms, and
the ideals of the Revolution had ceased to be serious factors in political
life. Napoleon intervened only in the most crucial questions; but his attitude
was understood, and his purposes were fulfilled. No despotism could have wished
for a more powerful or terrible instrument than the combination of these two
branches of penal law. It has been truly said of the compilers of the Penal
Code that “they were far less concerned with devising means of repression
sufficient for public safety, than with compensating the horror of crime by the
horror of punishment.” And, while the Penal Code displays its long catalogue of
terrible penalties for offences against public order or the political
principles of the Empire, the Code of Criminal Procedure furnishes the
Government with the most ample means for the exploration of criminal charges
and for the packing of the juries by whom these charges are to be tried.
The Commercial Code.
A Commercial
Code crowns the ordered structure of Napoleonic law. This was in the national
tradition; for, ever since the days of L’Hôpital, France had possessed separate
commercial Courts established “for the public good and the shortening of all
suits and differences between merchants”. Two great Ordinances, due to the
initiative of Colbert, had fixed the outlines of French commercial law—the
Edict of 1673 touching inland, and the Ordinance of 1681 touching marine
commerce. So excellent was the Ordinance of 1681 that it became the common
maritime law of Europe.
A commission
was sitting in 1789 to investigate the commercial law of France. Commerce had
grown; new wants were urgent; and the two great edicts of the seventeenth
century, variously interpreted and overspread with a luxuriance of local
custom, needed pruning and adaptation. Bonaparte commanded the suspended task
to be resumed; and on April 3, 1801, a committee of six was appointed to
prepare a Code. Their draft was submitted not only to the law-courts but also
to the commercial councils and tribunals, and duly revised in the light of
their comments. By some mistake, however, this revised Code was handed in, not
to the legislative section of the Council of State, but to the section of the
Interior, where it slumbered peacefully in its pigeonhole for several years. A
curious incident served to disinter it. In the autumn of 1806, while the
Emperor was campaigning in Germany, Paris was startled by a scandalous and
signal case of fraudulent bankruptcy. The firm of Recamier had failed. A
rescript came from the camp demanding a severe law; and an answer went back
that such a law would properly form part of the Commercial Code. The Code then,
replied Napoleon, must be instantly pushed forward. Accordingly, the draft was
produced, and submitted to all the processes employed in the case of the other
Codes. The discussion began on November 4, 1806, occupied sixty-eight sessions,
and ended on August 29, 1807. The Emperor was absent during the greater part of
this period; but, on his return, he demanded a general account of the
proceedings, and held four sessions at Saint-Cloud (July 28, 29, August 1, 8,
1807) which began at 7 a.m. and lasted till the evening.
Two points
riveted his attention; and on these he poured out his rich and effervescent
eloquence. The first concerned the question whether the commercial Courts
should take cognisance of all cases arising out of promissory notes, where the
signatories had declared their intention of being bound by the law of commerce.
Napoleon argued strenuously that no one, save a merchant, should be liable to
imprisonment for failing to meet an obligation contracted by a promissory note.
The obligations of private individuals were not so precise as those of
merchants; for the former, credit was a misfortune and a lure to dissipation.
For his part, he was unwilling to see bills of exchange or other negotiable
instruments used by those who were not in business. Such a practice would lead
to the mobilisation of fortunes, and spread alarm among the fathers of
families. “A courtesan who had extorted a promissory note from a young man
might drag him before the commercial Court and get him sent to prison”. This
vehement advocacy, inspired by a hatred of speculation and of the free transfer
of land, produced its due effect upon the Code; and, by Clauses 636 and 637,
uncommercial persons and uncommercial transactions were exempted from the
severe penalties by which the commercial Courts were empowered to enforce the
payment of negotiable instruments.
The second
point which specially interested Napoleon was bankruptcy. The old law had
assumed misfortune until fraud was proved; and in other respects it was
characterised by objectionable laxity. The Council proposed, in the first
instance, to expropriate the bankrupt and to vest the administration of his
property in the hands of provisional syndics; then, to subject his conduct to
strict examination; after which he might be brought before a correctional or a
criminal Court according as his offence was one of negligence or fraud. In any
case, action was to be taken by the public prosecutor and not by the creditors.
These proposals were severe, but they were not severe enough for Napoleon.
“Bankruptcies”, he said, “take away men’s fortunes without destroying their
honour; and that is what it is important to destroy”. He argued in favour of
incarceration in order to prevent the bankrupt flaunting his triumph of
indifference. The creditors could not be trusted to humiliate the bankrupt, for
their sole interest was to recover their debts as soon as possible But prison
would do it, even if it were but for an hour. It was also desirable that in
every case the woman should share the misfortune of her husband. It was pointed
out by more than one member of the Council that the proposals were too severe;
and that to suppose every failure to be the result of fraud until the contrary
had been established would injure credit, and bear harshly upon merchants and
traders in the country districts. The clauses in the Code represent a somewhat
softened version of Napoleon’s views. The administration of the debtor’s
affairs is entrusted first to agents named by the Court of Commerce, and then
to syndics named by the creditors; and the magistrate must be kept fully
informed of the proceedings, so that on any indication of misconduct or fraud
he may send the bankrupt before the correctional or the criminal Court.
Pardessus has
complained that the Code of Commerce was more carelessly drafted than any of
the other Codes; and yet it was the Code for which there existed the most
abundant materials. In the First Book, entitled Du Commerce Général, the whole question of purchase and sale is
disposed of in a single unimportant clause. There is not a word concerning
price, promise of sale, or earnest money; nothing upon the conditions of
weights, measures, and assay; nothing on patents or copyrights, on contracts of
apprenticeship, or contracts between workmen and manufacturers or shopkeepers,
on bank commissions or on the various kinds of loans which are used in
commerce. The Second Book, Du Commerce Maritime, being copied from the
Ordinance of 1681 with little alteration save what was derived from later
experience or later laws, is pronounced to be the best Book of the Code, though
here again several topics are omitted, for instance, quays and ports,
shipwrecks, and fishing. The Third Book, on bankruptcy, is said by Pardessus to contain some excellent dispositions, with
others so full of objectionable matter that it is difficult to believe they
could have passed uncorrected; and this verdict is confirmed by Locre, who shows how the Law of Bankruptcy broke down. The
Fourth Book, on the competence and procedure of the commercial Courts, is far
from being either clear or precise, and is distinguished by the curious
omission of any clause dealing with imprisonment for debt. No part of the
Napoleonic legislation has required or received more amendment.
The Five
Codes, a Sixth: the Code Rural, was drafted but never passed, represent a great
idea, the unity and comprehensiveness of French law. When it is remembered that
a task demanding the most massive learning, the calmest and most scrupulous
enquiry, was accomplished in the midst of unparalleled excitement and strain;
that it was begun in the reverberation of a great war, when all the organs of
government were being simultaneously recreated; and that it was continued and
brought to a close while the country was involved in a series of gigantic and
perilous foreign enterprises, we need not wonder that the expert has detected
signs of perfunctory work and political passion. The print of despotism is
stamped harsh and deep on the Penal Code, the subjection of woman on the Civil
Law. It was left for future generations to make adequate provision for the
needs of an industrial society, to regulate labour contracts, to protect the
interests of the working classes against the tyranny of capital, and to expand
the sphere of company law, so jealously contracted by the middle-class
individualism of the Civil Code. Nevertheless, the Codes preserve the essential
conquests of the revolutionary spirit—civil equality, religious toleration, the
emancipation of land, public trial, the jury of judgment. Original they were
not, but rather a hasty amalgamation of royal and revolutionary legislation,
governed by the genius of Napoleon, divining, traversing, and penetrating all
complications in order to make law subservient to his rule. But, if in France
herself the Codes were a symbol of a strict but enlightened despotism, in
Germany and Italy they stood for liberty. Here they were the earliest message,
as well as the most mature embodiment, of the new spirit. In a clear and
compact shape, they presented to Europe the main rules which should govern a
civilised society.
THE CONCORDATS.