![]() |
HISTORY OF ANCIENT GREECE |
![]() |
THE Hesiodic theogony gives no account of anything like a creation of man, nor does it seem that such
an idea was much entertained in the legendary vein of Grecian imagination;
which commonly carried back the present men by successive generations to some
primitive ancestor, himself sprung from the soil, or from a neighboring river,
or mountain, or from a god, a nymph, &c. But the poet of the Hesiodic
“Works and Days” has given us a narrative conceived in a very different spirit
respecting the origin of the human race, more in harmony with the sober and
melancholy ethical tone which reigns through that poem.
First (he tells us) the Olympic gods made the
golden race,—good, perfect, and happy men, who lived from the spontaneous
abundance of the earth, in ease and tranquility, like the gods themselves: they
suffered neither disease nor old-age, and their death was like a gentle sleep.
After death they became, by the award of Zeus, guardian terrestrial demons, who
watch unseen over the proceedings of mankind—with the regal privilege of
dispensing to them wealth, and taking account of good and bad deeds.
Next, the gods made the silver race,—unlike
and greatly inferior, both in mind and body, to the golden. The men of this
race were reckless and mischievous towards each other, and disdainful to the
immortal gods, to whom they refused to offer either worship or sacrifice. Zeus
in his wrath buried them in the earth; but there they still enjoy a secondary
honor, as the Blest of the underworld.
Thirdly, Zeus made the brazen race, quite
different from the silver. They were made of hard ash-wood, pugnacious and
terrible: they were of immense strength and adamantine soul, neither raising
nor touching bread. Their arms, their houses, and their implements were all of
brass: there was then no iron. This race, eternally fighting, perished by each
other's hands, died out, and descended without name or privilege to Hades.
Next, Zeus made a fourth race, far juster and better than the last preceding. These were the
Heroes or demigods, who fought at the sieges of Troy and Thebes. But this
splendid stock also became extinct: some perished in war, others were removed
by Zeus to a happier state in the islands of the Blest. There they dwell in
peace and comfort, under the government of Kronos,
reaping thrice in the year the spontaneous produce of the earth.
The fifth race, which succeeds to the Heroes,
is of iron: it is the race to which the poet himself belongs, and bitterly does
he regret it. He finds his contemporaries mischievous, dishonest, unjust,
ungrateful, given to perjury, careless both of the ties of consanguinity and of
the behests of the gods: Nemesis and Edo’s (Ethical Self-reproach) have left
earth and gone back to Olympus. How keenly does he wish that his lot had been
cast either earlier or later! This iron race is doomed to continual guilt,
care, and suffering, with a small infusion of good; but the time will come when
Zeus will put an end to it. The poet does not venture to predict what sort of
race will succeed.
Such is the aeries of distinct races of men,
which Hesiod, or the author of the “Works and Days”, enumerates as having
existed down to his own time. I give it as it stands, without placing much
confidence in the various explanations which critics have offered. It stands
out in more than one respect from the general tone and sentiment of Grecian
legend: moreover, the sequence of races is neither natural nor homogeneous,—the
heroic race not having any metallic denomination, and not occupying any
legitimate place in immediate succession to the brazen. Nor is the conception
of the daemons in harmony either with Homer or with the Hesiodic theogony. In Homer, there is scarcely any distinction
between gods and daemons: farther, the gods are stated to go about and visit
the cities of men in various disguises for the purpose of inspecting good and
evil proceedings. But in the poem now before us, the distinction between gods
and demons is generic. The latter are invisible tenants of earth, remnants of the
once happy golden race whom the Olympic gods first made: the remnants of the
second or silver race are not daemons, nor are they tenants of earth, but they
still enjoy an honorable posthumous existence as the Blest of the underworld.
Nevertheless the Hesiodic daemons are in no way authors or abettors of evil: on
the contrary, they form the unseen police of the gods, for the purpose of
repressing wicked behavior in the world.
We may trace, I think, in this quintuple
succession of earthly races, set forth by the author of the “Works and Days”,
the confluence of two veins of sentiment, not consistent one with the other,
yet both co-existing in the author’s mind. The drift of his poem is thoroughly
didactic and ethical. Though deeply penetrated with the injustice and suffering
which darken the face of human life, he nevertheless strives to maintain both
in himself and in others, a conviction that on the whole the just and laborious
man will come off well, and he enforces in considerable detail the lessons of
practical prudence and virtue. This ethical sentiment, which dictates his
appreciation of the present, also guides his imagination as to the past. It is
pleasing to him to bridge over the chasm between the gods and degenerate man,
by the supposition of previous races,—the first altogether pure, the second
worse than the first, and the third still worse than the second; and to show
further how the first race passed by gentle death-sleep into glorious
immortality; how the second race was sufficiently wicked to drive Zeus to bury
them in the underworld, yet still leaving them a certain measure of honor;
while the third was so desperately violent as to perish by its own animosities,
without either name or honor of any kind. The conception of the golden race passing
after death into good guardian daemons, which some supposed to have been
derived from a comparison with oriental angels, presents itself to the poet
partly as approximating this race to the gods, partly as a means of
constituting a triple gradation of post-obituary existence, proportioned to the
character of each race whilst alive. The denominations of gold and silver,
given to the two first races, justify themselves, like those given by Simonides
of Amorgos and by Phokylides to the different characters of women, derived from the dog, the bee, the mare,
the ass, and other animals; and the epithet of brazen is specially explained by
reference to the material which the pugnacious third race so plentifully
employed for their arms and other implements.
So far we trace intelligibly enough the
moralizing vein: we find the revolutions of the past so arranged as to serve
partly as an ethical lesson, partly as a suitable preface to the present. But
fourth in the list comes “the divine race of Heroes” and here a new vein of
thought is opened by the poet. The symmetry of his ethical past is broken up,
in order to make way for these cherished beings of the national faith. For
though the author of the “Works and Days” was himself of a didactic cast of
thought, like Phokylides, or Solon, or Theognis, yet he had present to his feelings, in common
with his countrymen, the picture of Grecian foretime, as it was set forth in
the current myths, and still more in Homer and those other epical productions
which were then the only existing literature and history. It was impossible for
him to exclude, from his sketch of the past, either the great persons or the
glorious exploits which these poems ennobled; and even if he himself could have
consented to such an exclusion, the sketch would have become repulsive to his
bearers. But the chiefs who figured before Thebes and Troy could not be well
identified either with the golden, the silver, or the brazen race: moreover, it
was essential that they should be placed in immediate contiguity with the
present race, because their descendants, real or supposed, were the most
prominent and conspicuous of existing men. Hence the poet is obliged to assign
to them the fourth place in the series, and to interrupt the descending ethical
movement in order to interpolate them between the brazen and the iron race,
with neither of which they present any analogy. The iron race, to which the
poet himself unhappily belongs, is the legitimate successor, not of the heroic,
but of the brazen. Instead of the fierce and self-annihilating pugnacity which
characterizes the latter, the iron race manifests an aggregate of smaller and
meaner vices and mischiefs, It will not perish by suicidal extinction—but it is
growing worse and worse, and is gradually losing its vigor, so that Zeus will
not vouchsafe to preserve much longer such a race upon the earth.
The Works
and Days, earliest didactic poem.
I conceive that the series of races imagined
by the poet of the “Works and Days” is the product of two distinct and incongruous
veins of imagination,—the didactic or ethical blending with the primitive
mythical or epical. His poem is remarkable as the most ancient didactic
production of the Greeks, and as one of the first symptoms of a new tone of
sentiment finding its way into their literature, never afterwards to become
extinct. The tendency of the “Works and Days” is antiheroic: far from seeking
to inspire admiration for adventurous enterprise, the author inculcates the
strictest justice, the most unremitting labor and frugality, and a sober, not
to say anxious, estimate of all the minute specialties of the future. Prudence
and probity are his means,—practical comfort and happiness his end. But he
deeply feels, and keenly exposes, the manifold wickedness and shortcomings of
his contemporaries, in reference to this capital standard. He turns with
displeasure from the present men, not because they are too feeble to hurl
either the spear of Achilles or some vast boundary-stone, but because they are
rapacious, knavish, and unprincipled.
The daemons first introduced into the
religious atmosphere of the Grecian world by the author of the “Works and
Days”—as generically different from the gods, but essentially good, and forming
the intermediate agents and police between gods and men,—are deserving of
attention. They are the seed of a doctrine which afterwards underwent many
changes, and became of great importance, first as one of the constituent
elements of pagan faith, then as one of the helps to its subversion. It will be
recollected that the buried remnants of the half-wicked silver race, though
they are not recognized as demons, are still considered as having a substantive
existence, a name, and dignity, in the underworld.
The step was easy, to treat them as demons
also, but as demons of a defective and malignant character: this step was made
by Empedocles and Xenocrates, and to a certain extent countenanced by Plato.
There came thus to be admitted among the pagan philosophizers daemons both good
and bad, in every degree: and these daemons were found available as a means of
explaining many phenomena for which it was not convenient to admit the agency
of the gods. They served to relieve the gods from the odium of physical and
moral evils, as well as from the necessity of constantly meddling in small
affairs. The objectionable ceremonies of the pagan religion were defended upon
the ground that in no other way could the exigencies of such malignant beings
be appeased. The demons were most frequently noticed as causes of evil, and
thus the name came insensibly to convey with it a bad sense,—the idea of an
evil being as contrasted with the goodness of a god. So it was found by the
Christian writers when they commenced their controversy with paganism. One
branch of their argument led them to identify the pagan gods with demons in the
evil sense, and the insensible change in the received meaning of the word lent
them a specious assistance.
For they could easily show, that not only in
Homer, but in the general language of early pagans, all the gods generally were
spoken of as demons—and therefore, verbally speaking, Clemens and Tatian seemed to affirm nothing more against Zeus or Apollo
than was involved in the language of paganism itself. Yet the audience of Homer
or Sophocles would have strenuously repudiated the proposition, if it had been
put to them in the sense which the word demon bore in the ago and among the
circle of these Christian writers.
In the imagination of the author of the
“Works and Days”, the demons occupy an important place, and are regarded as
being of serious practical efficiency. When he is remonstrating with the rulers
around him upon their gross injustice and corruption, he reminds them of the
vast number of these immortal servants of Zeus who are perpetually on guard
amidst mankind, and through whom the visitations of the gods will descend even
upon the most potent evil-doers. His supposition that the demons were not gods,
but departed men of the golden race, allowed him to multiply their number
indefinitely, without too much cheapening the divine dignity.
As this poet, enslaved by the current
legends, has introduced the heroic race into a series to which they do not
legitimately belong—so he has under the same influence inserted in another part
of his poem the myth of Pandora and Prometheus, as a means of explaining the
primary diffusion, and actual abundance, of evil among mankind. Yet this myth
can in no way consist, with his quintuple scale of distinct races, and is in
fact a totally distinct theory to explain the same problem,—the transition of
mankind from a supposed state of antecedent happiness to one of present toil
and suffering. Such an inconsistency is not a sufficient reason for questioning
the genuineness of either passage; for the two stories, though one contradicts
the other, both harmonies with that central purpose which governs the author’s
mind,—a querulous and didactic appreciation of the present. That such was his
purpose appears not only from the whole tenor of his poem, but also from the remarkable
fact that his own personality, his own adventures and kindred, and his own
sufferings figure in it conspicuously. And this introduction of self-imparts to
it a peculiar interest. The father of Hesiod came over from the Eolic Kyme, with the view of bettering his condition, and settled
at Askra in Boeotia, at the foot of Mount Helicon.
After his death his two sons divided the family inheritance: but Hesiod
bitterly complains that his brother Perses cheated
and went to law with him, and obtained through corrupt judges an unjust
decision. He farther reproaches his brother with a preference for the suits and
unprofitable bustle of the agora, at a time when he ought to be laboring for
his subsistence in the field. Askra indeed was a
miserable place, repulsive both in summer and winter. Hesiod had never crossed
the sea, except once from Aulis to Euboea, whither he went to attend the
funeral-games of Amphidamas, the chief of Chalcis: he
sung a hymn, and gained as prize a tripod, which he consecrated to the muses in
Helicon.
Probable age of the poem.
These particulars, scanty as they are,
possess a peculiar value, as the earliest authentic memorandum respecting the
doing or suffering of any actual Greek person. There is no external testimony
at all worthy of trust respecting the age of the “Works and Days” Herodotus
treats Hesiod and Homer as belonging to the same age, four hundred years before
his own time; and there are other statements besides, some placing Hesiod at an
earlier date than Homer, some at a later. Looking at the internal evidences, we
may observe that the pervading sentiment, tone, and purpose of the poem is
widely different from that of the Iliad and Odyssey, and analogous to what we
read respecting the compositions of Archilochus and the Amorgian Simonides. The author of the “Works and Days” is indeed a preacher and not a
satirist: but with this distinction, we find in him the same predominance of
the present and the positive, the same disposition to turn the muse into an
exponent of his own personal wrongs, the same employment of Aesopic fable by way of illustration, and the same unfavorable estimate of the female
sex, all of which may be traced in the two poets above-mentioned, placing both
of them in contrast with the Homeric epic. Such an internal analogy, in the
absence of good testimony, is the best guide which we can follow in determining
the date of the “Works and Days”, which we should accordingly place shortly
after the year 700 BC. The style of the poem might indeed afford a proof that
the ancient and uniform hexameter, though well adapted to continuous legendary
narrative or to solemn hymns, was somewhat monotonous when called upon either
to serve a polemical purpose or to impress a striking moral lesson. When poets,
then the only existing composers, first began to apply their thoughts to the
cut and thrust of actual life, aggressive or didactic, the verse would be seen
to require a new, livelier, and smarter metre; and
out of this want grew the elegiac and the iambic verse, both seemingly
contemporaneous, and both intended to supplant the primitive hexameter for the
short effusions then coming into vogue.
THE sons of the Titan god Iapetus, as described in the Hesiodic theogony,
are Atlas, Mencetius, Prometheus, and Epimetheus. Of
these, Atlas alone is mentioned by Homer in the Odyssey, and even he not as the
son of Iapetus: the latter himself is named in the
Iliad as existing in Tartarus along with Kronos. The Homeric Atlas “knows the depths of the whole
sea, and keeps by himself those tall pillars which hold the heaven apart from
the earth”.
As the Homeric theogony generally appears much expanded in Hesiod, so also does the family of Iapetus, with their varied adventures. Atlas is here
described, not as the keeper of the intermediate pillars between heaven and
earth, but as himself condemned by Zeus to support the heaven on his head and
hands; while the fierce Menoetius is pushed down to
Erebus as a punishment for his ungovernable insolence. But the remaining two
brothers, Prometheus and Epimetheus, are among the most interesting creations
of Grecian legend, and distinguished in more than one respect from all the
remainder.
First, the main battle between Zeus
and the Titan gods is a contest of force purely and simply—mountains are hurled
and thunder is launched, and the victory remains to the strongest. But the
competition between Zeus and Prometheus is one of craft and stratagem: the
victor does indeed remain to the former, but the honors of the fight belong to
the latter. Secondly, Prometheus and Epimetheus (the fore-thinker and the
after-thinker) are characters stamped at the same mint, and by the same effort,
the express contrast and antithesis of each other. Thirdly, mankind are here
expressly brought forward, not indeed as active partners in the struggle, but
as the grand and capital subjects interested,—as gainers or sufferers by the
result. Prometheus appears in the exalted character of champion of the human
race, even against the formidable superiority of Zeus.
In the primitive or Hesiodic legend,
Prometheus is not the creator or molder of man; it is only the later additions
which invest him with this character. The race are supposed as existing, and
Prometheus, a member of the dispossessed body of Titan gods, comes forward as
their representative and defender. The advantageous bargain which he made with
Zeus on their behalf, in respect to the partition of the sacrificial animals,
has been recounted in a preceding chapter. Zeus felt that he had been
outwitted, and was exceeding wroth. In his displeasure he withheld from mankind
the inestimable comfort of fire, so that the race would have perished, had not
Prometheus stolen fire, in defiance of the Supreme Ruler, and brought it to men
in the hollow stem of the plant called giant-fennel.
Zeus was now doubly indignant, and
determined to play off a still more ruinous stratagem. Hephaestus, by his
direction, molded the form of a beautiful virgin; Athene dressed her, Aphrodite
and the Charites bestowed upon her both ornament and
fascination, while Hermes infused into her the mind of a dog, a deceitful
spirit, and treacherous words. The messengers of the gods conducted this
“fascinating mischief” to mankind, at a time when Prometheus was not present.
Now Epimetheus had received from his brother peremptory injunctions not to
accept from the hands of Zeus any present whatever; but the beauty of Pandora
(so the newly-formed female was called) was not to be resisted. She was
received and admitted among men, and from that moment their comfort and
tranquility was exchanged for suffering of every kind. The evils to which
mankind are liable had been before enclosed in a cask in their own keeping;
Pandora in her malice removed the lid of the cask, and out flew these thousand
evils and calamities, to exercise for ever their
destroying force. Hope alone remained imprisoned, and therefore without
efficacy, as before—the inviolable lid being replaced before she could escape.
Before this incident (says the legend) men had lived without disease or
suffering; but now both earth and sea are full of mischiefs. Maladies of every
description stalk abroad by day as well as by night, without any hope fox man
of relief to come.
The Theogony gives the legend here
recounted, with some variations—leaving out the part of Epimetheus altogether,
as well as the cask of evils. Pandora is the ruin of man, simply as the mother
and representative of the female sex. And the variations are thus useful, as
they enable us to distinguish the essential from the accessory circumstances of
the story.
“Thus (says the poet, at the
conclusion of his narrative) it is not possible to escape from the purposes of
Zeus”. His myth, connecting the calamitous condition of man with the
malevolence of the supreme god, shows, first, by what cause such an unfriendly
feeling was raised; next, by what instrumentality its deadly results were
brought about. The human race are not indeed the creation, but the protected
flock of Prometheus, one of the elder or dispossessed Titan gods. When Zeus
acquires supremacy, mankind along with the rest become subject to him, and are
to make the best bargain they can, respecting worship and service to be
yielded. By the stratagem of their advocate Prometheus, Zeus is cheated into such
a partition of the victims as is eminently unprofitable to him; whereby his
wrath is so provoked, that he tries to subtract from man the use of feeling of
fire. Here, however, his scheme is frustrated by the theft of Prometheus: but
his second attempt is more successful, and he in his turn cheats the unthinking
Epimetheus into the acceptance of a present (in spite of the peremptory
interdict of Prometheus) by which the whole of man’s happiness is wrecked. This
legend grows out of two feelings; partly as to the relations of the gods with
man, partly as to the relation of the female sex with the male. The present
gods are unkind towards man, but the old gods, with whom man's lot was
originally cast, were much kinder—and the ablest among them stands forward as
the indefatigable protector of the race. Nevertheless, the mere excess of his
craft proves the ultimate ruin of the cause which he espouses. He cheats Zeus
out of a fair share of the sacrificial victim, so as both to provoke and
justify a retaliation which he cannot be always at hand to ward off; the
retaliation is, in his absence, consummated by a snare laid for Epimetheus and
voluntarily accepted. And thus, though Hesiod ascribes the calamitous condition
of man to the malevolence of Zeus, his piety suggests two exculpatory pleas for
the latter; mankind have been the first to defraud Zeus of his legitimate share
of the sacrifice—and they have moreover been consenting parties to their own
ruin. Such are the feelings, as to the relation between the gods and man, which
have been one of the generating elements of this legend. The other element, a
conviction of the vast mischief arising to man from women, whom yet they cannot
dispense with, is frequently and strongly set forth in several of the Greek
poets—by Simonides of Amorgos and Phokylidis,
not less than by Euripides.
Punishment of Prometheus
But the miseries arising from woman,
however great they might be, did not reach Prometheus himself. For him, the
rash champion who had ventured “to compete in sagacity” with Zeus, a different
punishment was in store. Bound by heavy chains to a pillar, he remained fast
imprisoned for several generations: every day did an eagle prey upon his liver,
and every night did the liver grow afresh for the next day’s suffering. At
length Zeus, eager to enhance the glory of his favorite son, Heracles,
permitted the latter to kill the eagle and rescue the captive.
Such is the Promethean myth as it
stands in the Hesiodic poems; its earliest form, as far as we can trace. Upon
it was founded the sublime tragedy of Aeschylus, “The Enchained Prometheus”,
together with at least one more tragedy, now lost, by the same author.
Aeschylus has made several important alterations; describing the human race,
not as having once enjoyed and subsequently lost a state of tranquility and
enjoyment, but as originally feeble and wretched. He suppresses both the first
trick played off by Prometheus upon Zeus respecting the partition of the
victim—and the final formation and sending of Pandora—which are the two most
marked portions of the Hesiodic story; while on the other hand he brings out
prominently and enlarges upon the theft of fire, which in Hesiod is but
slightly touched. If he has thus relinquished the antique simplicity of the
story, he has rendered more than ample compensation by imparting to it a
grandeur of ideal, a large reach of thought combined with appeals to our
earnest and admiring sympathy, and a pregnancy of suggestion in regard to the
relations between the gods and man, which soar far above the Hesiodic level,
and which render his tragedy the most impressive, though not the most
artistically composed, of all Grecian dramatic productions. Prometheus there
appears not only as the heroic champion and sufferer in the cause and for the
protection of the human race, but also as the gifted teacher of all the arts,
helps, and ornaments of life, amongst which fire is only one: all this against
the will and in defiance of the purpose of Zeus, who, on acquiring his empire,
wished to destroy the human race and to beget some new breed. Moreover, new
relations between Prometheus and Zeus are superadded by Aeschylus. At the
commencement of the struggle between Zeus and the Titan gods, Prometheus had
vainly attempted to prevail upon the latter to conduct it with prudence; but
when he found that they obstinately declined all wise counsel, and that their
ruin was inevitable, he abandoned their cause and joined Zeus. To him and to
his advice Zeus owed the victory; yet the monstrous ingratitude and tyranny of
the latter is now manifested by nailing him to a rock, for no other crime than
because he frustrated the purpose of extinguishing the human race, and
furnished to them the means of living with tolerable comfort. The new ruler
Zeus, insolent with his victory over the old gods, tramples down all right, and
sets at naught sympathy and obligation, as well towards gods as towards man.
Yet the prophetic Prometheus, in the midst of intense suffering, is consoled by
the foreknowledge that the time will come when Zeus must again send for him,
release him, and invoke his aid, as the sole means of averting from himself
dangers otherwise insurmountable. The security and means of continuance for
mankind have now been placed beyond the reach of Zeus—whom Prometheus proudly
defies, glorying in his generous and successful championship, despite the
terrible price which he is doomed to pay for it.
As the Aeschylean Prometheus, though retaining the old lineaments, has acquired a new coloring,
soul, and character, so he has also become identified with a special locality.
In Hesiod there is no indication of the place in which he is imprisoned; but
Aeschylus places it in Scythia, and the general belief of the Greeks supposed
it to be on Mount Caucasus. So long and so firmly did this belief continue,
that the Roman general Pompey, when in command of an army in Colchis, made with
his companion, the literary Greek Theophanes, a
special march to view the spot in Caucasus where Prometheus had been
transfixed.
HAVING briefly enumerated the gods
of Greece, with their chief attributes as described in legend, we come to those
genealogies which connected them with historical men.
In the retrospective faith of a
Greek, the ideas of worship and ancestry coalesced. Every association of men,
large or small, in whom there existed a feeling of present union, traced back
that union to some common initial progenitor; that progenitor being either the
common god whom they worshipped, or some semi-divine person closely allied to
him. What the feelings of the community require is, a continuous pedigree to
connect them with this respected source of existence, beyond which they do not
think of looking back. A series of names, placed in filiation or fraternity,
together with a certain number of family or personal adventures ascribed to
some of the individuals among them, constitute the ante-historical past through
which the Greek looks back to his gods. The names of this genealogy are, to a
great degree, gentile or local names familiar to the people,—rivers, mountains,
springs, lakes, villages, demes, &c.,—embodied as persons, and introduced
as acting or suffering. They are moreover called kings or chiefs, but the
existence of a body of subjects surrounding them is tacitly implied rather than
distinctly set forth ; for their own personal exploits or family proceedings
constitute for the most part the whole matter of narrative. And thus the
genealogy was made to satisfy at once the appetite of the Greeks for romantic
adventure, and their demand for an unbroken line of filiation between
themselves and the gods.
The eponymous personage, from whom
the community derive their name, is sometimes the begotten son of the local
god, even if it could be ascertained, we must at once set it historical aside,
if we wish to look at the genealogy in the point of view of the Greeks. For to
them, not only all the members were alike real, but the gods and heroes at the
commencement were in a certain sense the most real; at least, they were the
most esteemed and indispensable of all. The value of the genealogy consisted,
not in its length, but in its continuity; not (according to the feeling of
modern aristocracy) in the power of setting out a prolonged series of human fathers
and grandfathers, but in the sense of ancestral union with the primitive god.
And the length of the series is traceable rather to humility, inasmuch as the
same person who was gratified with the belief that he was descended from a god
in the fifteenth generation, would have accounted it, criminal insolence to
affirm that a god was his father or grandfather. In presenting to the reader
those genealogies which constitute the supposed primitive history of Hellas, I
make no pretense to distinguish names real and historical from fictitious
creations; partly because I have no evidence upon which to draw the line, and
partly because by attempting it I should altogether depart from the genuine
Grecian point of view.
Nor is it possible to do more than
exhibit a certain selection of such as were most current and interesting; for
the total number of them which found place in Grecian faith exceeds
computation. As a general rule, every deme, every gens, every aggregate of men
accustomed to combined action, religious or political, had its own. The small
and unimportant demes into which Attica was divided had each its ancestral god
and heroes, just as much as the great Athens herself. Even among the villages
of Phocis, which Pausanias will hardly permit himself to call towns, deductions
of legendary antiquity were not wanting. And it is important to bear in mind,
when we are reading the legendary genealogies of Argos, or Sparta, or Thebes,
that these are merely samples amidst an extensive class, all perfectly analogous,
and all exhibiting the religious and patriotic retrospect of some fraction of
the Hellenic world. They are no more matter of historical tradition than any of
the thousand other legendary genealogies which men delighted to recall to
memory at the periodical festivals of their gees, their deme, or their village.
With these few prefatory remarks, I
proceed to notice the most conspicuous of the Grecian heroic pedigrees, and
first, that of Argos.
Argeian genealogy-Inachus
The earliest name in Argeian antiquity is that of Inachus,
the son of Oceanus and Tethys, who gave his name to the Argeian river flowing under the walls of the town. According to the chronological
computations of those who regarded the mythical genealogies as substantive
history, and who allotted a given number of years to each generation, the reign
of Inachus was placed 1986 BC, or about 1100 years
prior to the commencement of the recorded Olympiads.
The sons of Inachus were Phoroneus and Egialeus;
both of whom however were sometimes represented as autochthonous or indigenous
men, the one in the territory of Argos, the other in that of Sicyon. Egialeus gave his name to the north-western region of the
Peloponnesus, on the southern coast of the Corinthian Gulf. The name of Phoreneus was of great celebrity in the Argeian mythical genealogies, and furnished both the title and the subject of the
ancient poem called Phoronis, in which he is styled
“the father of mortal men”. He is said to have imparted to mankind, who had
before him lived altogether isolated, the first notion and habits of social
existence, and even the first knowledge of fire: his dominion extended over the
whole Peloponnesus. His tomb at Argos, and seemingly also the place, called the Phoronic city, in which he formed the first settlement
of mankind, were still shown in the days of Pausanias. The offspring of Phoroneus, by the nymph Teledike,
were Apis and Niobe. Apis, a harsh ruler, was put to death by Thelxion and Telchin, having
given to Peloponnesus the name of Apia: he was succeeded by Argos, the son of
his sister Niobe by the god Zeus. From this sovereign
Peloponnesus was denominated Argos. By his wife Evadne,
daughter of Strymon, he had four sons, Ekbasus, Peiras, Epidaurus, and Kriasus. Ekbasus was succeeded by
his son Agenor, and he again by his son Argos Panoptes, a very powerful prince, who is said to have bad
eyes distributed over all his body, and to have liberated Peloponnesus from
several monsters and wild animals which infested it: Akusilaus and Aeschylus make this Argos an earthborn person, while Pherekydes reports him
as son of Arestor. Iasus was the son of Argos Panoptes by Ismene, daughter of Asopus. According to the authors whom Apollodorus and
Pausanias prefer, the celebrated Io was his daughter: but the Hesiodic epic (as
well as Akusilaus) represented her as daughter of Peiras, while Aeschylus and Kastor the chronologist affirmed the primitive king Inachus to have been her father. A favorite theme, as well for the ancient genealogical
poets as for the Attic tragedians, were the adventures of Io; of whom, while
priestess of Hera, at the ancient and renowned Heraeon between Mycenae and Tiryns, Zeus became amorous. When Hera discovered the
intrigue and taxed him with it, he denied the charge, and metamorphosed Io into
a white cow. Here, requiring that the cow should be surrendered to her, placed
her under the keeping of Argos Panoptes; but this
guardian was slain by Hermes, at the command of Zeus; and Hera then drove the
cow Io away from her native land by means of the incessant stinging of a gadfly,
which compelled her to wander without repose or sustenance over an immeasurable
extent of foreign regions. The wandering Io gave her name to the Ionian Gulf,
traversed Epirus and Illyria, passed the chain of Mount Haemus and the lofty summits of Caucasus, and swam across the Thracian or Cimmerian
Bosporus (which also from her derived its appellation) into Asia. She then went
through Scythia, Cimmeria, and many Asiatic regions,
until she arrived in Egypt, where Zeus at length bestowed upon her rest,
restored her to her original form, and enabled her to give birth to his black
son Epaphos.
Romance of Io historicized by Egyptians and Phoenicians
Such is a general sketch of the
adventures which the ancient poets, epic, lyric, and tragic, and the
logographers after them, connect with the name of the Argeian Io—one of the numerous tales which the fancy of the Greeks deduced from the
amorous dispositions of Zeus and the jealousy of Hera. That the scene should be
laid in the Argeian territory appears natural, when
we recollect that both Argos and Mycenae were under the special guardianship of
Here, and that the Heraeon near Mycenae was one of
the oldest and most celebrated temples in which she was worshipped. It is
useful to compare this amusing fiction with the representation reported to us
by Herodotus, and derived by him as well from Phoenician as from Persian
antiquarians, of the circumstances which occasioned the transit of Io from
Argos to Egypt—an event recognized by all of them as historical matter of fact.
According to the Persians, a Phoenician vessel had arrived at the port near
Argos, freighted with goods intended for sale to the inhabitants of the
country. After the vessel had remained a few days, and disposed of most of her
cargo, several Argeian women, and among them Io the
king’s daughter, coming on board to purchase, were seized and carried off by
the crew, who sold Io in Egypt. The Phoenician antiquarians, however, while
they admitted the circumstance that Io had left her own country in one of their
vessels, gave a different color to the whole by affirming that she emigrated
voluntarily, having been engaged in an amour with the captain of the vessel,
and fearing that her parents might come to the knowledge of her pregnancy. Both
Persians and Phoenicians described the abduction of Io as the first of a series
of similar acts between Greeks and Asiatics,
committed each in revenge for the preceding. First came the rape of Europe from
Phoenicia by Grecian adventurers—perhaps, as Herodotus supposed, by Cretans:
next, the abduction of Medeia from Colchis by Jason,
which occasioned the retaliatory act of Paris, when he stole away Helena from Menelaos. Up to this point the seizures of women by Greeks
from Asiatics, and by Asiatics from Greeks, had been equivalent both in number and in wrong. But the Greeks
now thought fit to equip a vast conjoint expedition to recover Helen, in the
course of which they took and sacked Troy. The invasions of Greece by Darius
and Xerxes were intended, according to the Persian antiquarians, as a
long-delayed retribution for the injury inflicted on the Asiatics by Agamemnon and his followers.
Danaos and his fifty daughters
The account thus given of the
adventures of Io, when contrasted with the genuine legend, is interesting, as
it tends to illustrate the phenomenon which early Grecian history is constantly
presenting to us—the way in which the epical furniture of an unknown past is
recast and newly colored so as to meet those changes which take place in the
retrospective feelings of the present. The religious and poetical character of
the whole legend disappears: nothing remains except the names of persons and
places, and the voyage from Argos to Egypt: we have in exchange a sober,
quasi-historical narrative, the value of which consists in its bearing on the
grand contemporary conflicts between Persia and Greece, which filled the
imagination of Herodotus and his readers.
To proceed with the genealogy of the
kings of Argos, Iasus was succeeded by Krotopus, son
of his brother Agenor; Krotopus by Sthenelas, and he again by Gelanor.
In the reign of the latter, Danaos came with his
fifty daughters from Egypt to Argos; and here we find another of those romantic
adventures which so agreeably decorate the barrenness of the mythical
genealogies. Danaos and Egyptos were two brothers descending from Epaphos, son of Io: Egyptos had fifty sons, who were eager to marry the
fifty daughters of Danaos, in spite of the strongest
repugnance of the latter. To escape such a necessity, Danaos placed his fifty daughters on board of a penteconter (or vessel with fifty oars) and sought refuge at Argos; touching in his voyage
at the island of Rhodes, where he erected a statue of Athena at Lindos, which was long exhibited as a memorial of his
passage. Egyptos and his sons followed them to Argos,
and still pressed their suit, to which Danaos found
himself compelled to assent; but on the wedding night he furnished each of his
daughters with a dagger, and enjoined them to murder their husbands during the
hour of deep. His orders were obeyed by all, with the single exception of Hypermnestra, who preserved her husband Lynkeus,
incurring displeasure and punishment from her father. He afterwards, however,
pardoned her; and when, by the voluntary abdication of Gelamor,
he became king of Argos, Lynkeus was recognized as
his son-in-law, and ultimately succeeded him. The remaining daughters, having
been purified by Athena and Hermes, were given in marriage to the victors in a gymnic contest publicly proclaimed. From Danaos was derived the name of Danai,
applied to the inhabitants of the Argeian territory,
and to the Homeric Greeks generally.
Akrisios and Proetus
From the legend of the Danaides we pass to two barren names of kings, Lynkeus and his son Abas. The two
sons of Abas were Akrisios and Proetos, who, after much dissension, divided
between them the Argeian territory; Akrisios ruling at Argos, and Proetos at Tiryns. The families of both formed the theme of romantic stories. To pass
over for the present the legend of Bellerophon, and
the unrequited passion which the wife of Proetos conceived for him, we are told that the daughters of Proetos,
beautiful, and solicited in marriage by suitors from all Greece, were smitten
with leprosy and driven mad, wandering in unseemly guise throughout
Peloponnesus. The visitation had overtaken them, according to Hesiod, because
they refused to take part in the Bacchic rites;
according to Pherekydes and the Argeian Akusilaus, because they had treated scornfully the wooden
statue and simple equipments of Hera: the religious
character of the old legend here displays itself in a remarkable manner. Unable
to cure his daughters, Proetos invoked the aid of the
renowned Pylian prophet and leech, Melampus son of Amythaon, who undertook to remove the malady on condition
of being rewarded with the third part of the kingdom. Proetos indignantly refused these conditions : but the state of his daughters becoming
aggravated and intolerable, he was compelled again to apply to Melampus; who,
on the second request, raised his demands still higher, and required another
third of the kingdom for his brother Bias. These terms being acceded to, he
performed his part of the covenant. He appeased the wrath of Hera by prayer and
sacrifice; or, according to another account, he approached the deranged women
at the head of a troop of young men, with shouting and ecstatic dance—the
ceremonies appropriate to the Bacchic worship of Dionysos,—and in this manner effected their cure. Melampus,
a name celebrated in many different Grecian myths, is the legendary founder and
progenitor of a great and long-continued family of prophets. He and his brother
Bias became kings of separate portions of the Argeian territory: he is recognized as ruler there even in the Odyssey, and the prophet Theoklymenos, his grandson, is protected and carried
to Ithaca by Telemachus. Herodotus also alludes to the cure of the women, and
to the double kingdom of Melampus and Bias in the Argeian land: recognizing Melampus as the first person who introduced to the knowledge
of the Greeks the name and worship of Dionysos, with
its appropriate sacrifices and phallic processions. Here again he historicizes
various features of the old legend in a manner not unworthy of notice.
Perseus and the Gorgons
But Danae,
the daughter of Akrisios, with her son Perseus,
acquired still greater celebrity than her cousins the Proetides.
An oracle had apprised Akrisios that his daughter
would give birth to a son by whose hand he would himself be slain. To guard
against this danger, he imprisoned Danae in a chamber
of brass underground. But the god Zeus had become amorous of her, and found
means to descend through the roof in the form of a shower of gold: the
consequence of his visits was the birth of Perseus. When Akrisios discovered that his daughter had given existence to a son, he enclosed both the
mother and the child in a coffer, which he cast into the sea. The coffer was
carried to the isle of Seriphos, where Diktys, brother of the king Polydektes,
fished it up, and rescued both Danae and Perseus. The
exploits of Perseus, when he grew up, against the three Phorkydes or daughters of Phorkys, and the three Gorgons, are
among the most marvelous and imaginative in all Grecian legend: they bear a stamp
almost Oriental. I shall not here repeat the details of those unparalleled
hazards which the special favor of Athene enabled him to overcome, and which
ended in his bringing back from Libya the terrific head of the Gorgon Medusa,
endued with the property of turning everyone who looked upon it into stone. In
his return he rescued Andromeda, daughter of Cepheus,
who had been exposed to be devoured by a sea-monster, and brought her back as
his wife. Akrisios trembled to see him after this
victorious expedition, and retired into Thessaly to avoid him; but Perseus
followed him thither, and having succeeded in calming his apprehensions, became
competitor in a gymnic contest where his grandfather
was among the spectators. By an incautious swing of his quoit, he
unintentionally struck Akrisios, and caused his
death: the predictions of the oracle were thus at last fulfilled. Stung with
remorse at the catastrophe, and unwilling to return to Argos, which had been
the principality of Akrisios, Perseus made an exchange
with Megapenthes, son of Proetos king of Tiryns. Megapenthes became king of Argos, and
Perseus of Tiryns: moreover the latter founded, within ten miles of Argos, the
far-famed city of Mycenae. The massive walls of this city, like those of
Tiryns, of which a large portion yet remains, were built for him by the Lycian Cyclopes.
The Perseids
We here reach the commencement of
the Perseid dynasty of Mycenae. It should be noticed,
however, that there were among the ancient legends contradictory accounts of the
foundation of this city. Both the Odyssey and the great Eoiai enumerated, among the heroines, Mykene, the Eponyma of the city; the former poem classifying her with
Tyre and Alkmene, the latter describing her as the
daughter of Inachus and wife of Arestor.
And Akusilaus mentioned an Eponymous Mykeneus, the son of Sparton and
grand-son of Phoreneus.
The prophetic family of Melampus
maintained itself in one of the three parts of the divided Argeian kingdom for five generations, down to Amphiaraos and
his sons Alkmaeon and Amphilochos.
The dynasty of his brother Bias, and that of Megapenthes,
son of Proetos, continued each for four generations:
a list of barren names fills up the interval. The Perseids of Mykenae boasted a descent long and glorious,
heroic as well as historical, continuing down to the last kings of Sparta. The
issue of Perseus was numerous: his son Alkaeos was
father of Alkmene; a third, Sthenelos,
father of Eurysthenes.
After the death of Perseus, Alkaeos and Amphitryon dwelt at
Tiryns. The latter became engaged in a quarrel with Elektryon respecting cattle, and in a fit of passion killed him; moreover the piratical Taphians from the west coast of Acarnania invaded the
country, and slew the sons of Alektryon, so that Alkmene alone was left of that family. She was engaged to
wed Amphitryon; but she bound him by oath not to
consummate the marriage until he had avenged upon the Teleboae the death of her brothers. Amphitryon, compelled to
flee the country as the murderer of his uncle, took refuge in Thebes, whither Alkmene accompanied him: Sthenelos was left in possession of Tiryns. The Cadmeians of
Thebes, together with the Lokrians and Phokians, supplied Amphitryon with troops, which he conducted against the Teleboae and the Taphians: yet he could not have subdued them
without the aid of Komaetho, daughter of the Taphian king Pterelaus, who
conceived a passion for him, and cut off from her father’s head the golden lock
to which Poseidon had attached the gift of immortality. Having conquered and expelled
his enemies, Amphitryon returned to Thebes, impatient
to consummate his marriage: but Zeus on the wedding-night assumed his form and
visited Alkmene before him: he had determined to
produce from her a son superior to all his prior offspring—“a specimen of
invincible force both to gods and men”. At the proper time Alkmene was delivered of twin sons: Heracles, the offspring of Zeus, and the inferior
and unhonoured Iphikles,
offspring of Amphitryon.
Birth of Herakles
When Alkmene was on the point of being delivered at Thebes, Zeus publicly boasted among the
assembled gods, at the instigation of the mischief-making Ate, that there was
on that day about to be born on earth, from his breed, a son who should rule
over all his neighbors. Hera treated this as an empty boast, calling upon him
to bind himself by an irremissible oath that the prediction should be realized.
Zeus incautiously pledged his solemn word; upon which Hera darted swiftly down
from Olympus to the Achaic Argos, where the wife of Sthenelos (son of Perseus, and therefore grandson of Zeus)
was already seven months gone with child. By the aid of the Eileithyiae,
the special goddesses of parturition, she caused Eurystheus,
the son of Sthenelos, to be born before his time on
that very day, while she retarded the delivery of Alkmene.
Then returning to Olympus, she announced the fact to Zeus: “The good man Eurystheus, son of the Perseid Sthenelos, is this day born of thy loins: the scepter of
the Argeians worthily belongs to him”. Zeus was
thunderstruck at the consummation which he had improvidently bound himself to
accomplish. He seized Ate his evil counselor by the hair, and hurled her for ever away from Olympus: but he had no power to avert
the ascendency of Eurystheus and the servitude of Herakles. “Many a pang did he suffer when he saw his
favorite son going through his degrading toil in the tasks imposed upon him by Eurystheus”.
The legend, of unquestionable
antiquity, here transcribed from the Iliad, is one of the most pregnant and
characteristic in the Grecian mythology. It explains, according to the
religious ideas familiar to the old epic poets, both the distinguishing
attributes and the endless toils and endurances of Heracles—the most renowned
and most ubiquitous of all the semi-divine personages worshipped by the
Hellenes—a being of irresistible force, and especially beloved by Zeus, yet
condemned constantly to labor for others and to obey the commands of a
worthless and cowardly persecutor. His recompense is reserved to the close of his
career, when his afflicting trials are brought to a close: he is then admitted
to the god-head and receives in marriage Hebe. The twelve labors, as they are
called, too notorious to be here detailed, form a very small fraction of the
exploits of this mighty being, which filled the Herakleian epics of the ancient poets. He is found not only in most parts of Hellas, but
throughout all the regions then known to the Greeks, from Gades to the river Thermodon in the Euxine and to Scythia,
overcoming all difficulties and vanquishing all opponents. Distinguished
families are everywhere to be traced who bear his patronymic, and glory in the
belief that they are his descendants. Among Achaeans, Cadmeians,
and Dorians, Heracles is venerated: the latter especially treat him as their
principal hero—the Patron Hero-God of the race: the Herakleids form among all Dorians a privileged gens, in which at Sparta the special
lineage of the two kings was included.
His character lends itself to myths
countless in number, as well as disparate in their character. The irresistible
force remains constant, but it is sometimes applied with reckless violence
against friends as well as enemies, sometimes devoted to the relief of the
oppressed. The comic writers often brought him out as a coarse and stupid
glutton, while the Keian philosopher Prodikos, without at all distorting the type, extracted
from it the simple, impressive, and imperishable apologue still known as the
choice of Hercules.
After the death and apotheosis of Heracles,
his son Hyllos and his other children were expelled
and persecuted by Eurystheus; the fear of whose
vengeance deterred both the Trachinian king Keyx and the Thebans from harboring them. The Athenians
alone were generous enough to brave the risk of offering them shelter. Eurystheus invaded Attica, but perished in the attempt by
the hand of Hyllos, or by that of Iolaos,
the old companion and nephew of Heracles. The chivalrous courage which the
Athenians had on this occasion displayed on behalf of oppressed innocence was a
favorite theme for subsequent eulogy by Attic poets and orators.
All the sons of Eurystheus lost their lives in the battle along with him, so that the Perseid family was now represented only by the Herakleids,
who collected an army and endeavored to recover the possessions from which they
had been expelled. The united forces of Ionians, Achaeans, and Arcadians, then
inhabiting Peloponnesus, met the invaders at the isthmus, when Hyllos, the eldest of the sons of Heracles, proposed that
the contest should be determined by a single combat between himself and any
champion of the opposing army. It was agreed that if Hyllos were victorious, the Herakleids should be restored to
their possessions—if he were vanquished, that they should forego all claim for
the space of a hundred years, or fifty years, or three generations,—for in the
specification of the time accounts differ. Echemos,
the hero of Tegea, in Arcadia, accepted the challenge, and Hyllos was slain in the encounter; in consequence of which the Herakleids retired, and resided along with the Dorians under the protection of Egimios, son of Dorus. As soon as
the stipulated period of truce had expired, they renewed their attempt upon
Peloponnesus, conjointly with the Dorians, and with complete success: the great
Dorian establishments of Argos, Sparta, and Messenia were the result. The
details of this victorious invasion will be hereafter recounted.
Sicyon, Phlios, Epidauros, and Troezen all
boasted of respected eponyms and a genealogy of dignified length, not exempt
from the usual discrepancies—but all just as much entitled to a place on the
tablet of history as the more renowned Eolids or Herakleids. I omit them here because I wish to impress upon
the reader's mind the salient features and character of the legendary
world,—not to load his memory with a full list of legendary names.
IN the Hesiodic theogony,
as well as in the “Works and Days”, the legend of Prometheus and Epimetheus presents an import religious, ethical, and
social, and in this sense it is carried forward by Aeschylus; but to neither of
the characters is any genealogical function assigned. The Hesiodic Catalogue of
Women brought both of them into the stream of Grecian legendary lineage, representing
Deucalion as the son of Prometheus and Pandora, and seemingly his wife Pyrrha as daughter of Epimetheus.
Deucalion is important in Grecian
mythical narrative under two points of view. First, he is the person specially
saved at the time of the general deluge: next, he is the father of Hellen, the great eponym of the Hellenic race: at least
this was the more current story, though there were other statements which made Hellen the son of Zeus.
The name of Deucalion is originally
connected with the Lokrian towns of Kynos and Opus, and with the race of the Leleges, but he appears finally as settled in Thessaly, and
ruling in the portion of that country called Phthiotis.
According to what seems to have been the old legendary account, it is the
deluge which transferred him from the one to the other; but according to
another statement, framed in more historicizing times, he conducted a body of Kuretes and Leleges into
Thessaly, and expelled the prior Pelasgian occupants.
The enormous iniquity with which earth
was contaminated—as Apollodorus says, by the then existing brazen race, or as
others say, by the fifty monstrous sons of Lykaon—provoked
Zeus to send a general deluge? An unremitting and terrible rain laid the whole
of Greece under water, except the highest mountain tops, whereon a few
stragglers found refuge. Deukalion was saved in a
chest or ark, which he had been forewarned by his father Prometheus to
construct. After floating for nine days on the water, he at length landed on
the summit of Mount Parnassus. Zeus having sent Hermes to him, promising to
grant whatever he asked, he prayed that men and companions might be sent to him
in his solitude: accordingly Zeus directed both him and Pyrrha to cast stones over their heads: those cast by Pyrrha became women, those by Deucalion men. And thus the “stony race of men” (if we
may be allowed to translate an etymology which the Greek language presents
exactly, and which has not been disdained by Hesiod, by Pindar, by Epicharmus,
and by Virgil) came to tenant the soil of Greece. Deucalion on landing from the
ark sacrificed a grateful offering to Zeus Phyxios,
or the god of escape; he also erected altars in Thessaly to the twelve great
gods of Olympus.
The reality of this deluge was
firmly believed throughout the historical ages of Greece; the chronologers, reckoning up by genealogies, assigned the
exact date of it, and placed it at the same time as the conflagration of the
world by the rashness of Phaethon, during the reign of Krotopos,
king of Argos, the seventh from Inachus. The
meteorological work of Aristotle admits and reasons upon this deluge as an
unquestionable fact, though he alters the locality by placing it west of Mount
Pindus, near Dodona and the river Achelous. He at the
same time treats it as a physical phenomenon, the result of periodical cycles
in the atmosphere—thus departing from the religious character of the old
legend, which described it as a judgment inflicted by Zeus upon a wicked race.
Statements founded upon this event were in circulation throughout Greece even
to a very late date. The Megarians affirmed that Megaros, their hero, son of Zeus by a local nymph, had
found safety from the waters on the lofty summit of their mountain Geraneia, which had not been completely submerged. And in the
magnificent temple of the Olympian Zeus at Athens a cavity in the earth was
shown, through which it was affirmed that the waters of the deluge had retired.
Even in the time of Pausanias, the priest poured into this cavity holy
offerings of meal and honey. In this, as in other parts of Greece, the idea of
the Deukalionian deluge was blended with the
religious impressions of the people, and commemorated by their sacred
ceremonies.
The offspring of Deucalion and Pyrrha were two sons, Hellen and Amphiktyon, and a daughter, Protogeneia,
whose son by Zeus was Aethlius: it was however
maintained by many that Helen was the son of Zeus and not of Deucalion. Hellen had by a nymph three sons, Dorus, Xuthus, and Eolus. He gave to those who had been
before called Greeks the name of Hellenes, and partitioned his territory among
his three children. Eolus reigned in Thessaly; Xuthus received Peloponnesus, and had by Kreusa as his sons
Achaeus and Ion; while Dorus occupied the country
lying opposite to the Peloponnesus, on the northern side of the Corinthian
Gulf. These three gave to the inhabitants of their respective countries the
names of Aeolians, Achaeans and Ionians, and Dorians.
Such is the genealogy as we find it
in Apollodorus. In so far as the names and filiation are concerned, many points
in it are given differently, or implicitly contradicted by Euripides and other
writers. Though as literal and personal history it deserves no notice, its
import is both intelligible and comprehensive. It expounds and symbolizes the
first fraternal aggregation of Hellenic men, together with their territorial
distribution and the institutions which they collectively venerated.
There were two great holding-points
in common for every section of Greeks. One was the Amphiktyonic assembly, which met half-yearly, alternately at Delphi and at Thermopylae;
originally and chiefly for common religious purposes, but indirectly and
occasionally embracing political and social objects along with them. The other
was the public festivals or games, of which the Olympic came first in
importance; next the Pythian, Nemean,
and Isthmian—institutions which combined religions solemnities with recreative effusion and hearty sympathies, in a manner so
imposing and so unparalleled. Amphiktyon represents
the first of these institutions, and Aethlius the
second. As the Amphiktyonic assembly was always
especially connected with Thermopylae and Thessaly, Amphiktyon is made the son of the Thessalian Deucalion; but as the Olympic festival was
nowise locally connected with Deucalion, Aethlius is
represented as having Zeus for his father, and as touching Deucalion only
through the maternal line. It will be seen presently that the only matter
predicated respecting Aethlius is, that he settled in
the territory of Elis, and begat Endymion: this
brings him into local contact with the Olympic games, and his function is then
ended.
Having thus got Hellas as an
aggregate with its main cementing forces, we march on to its sub-division into
parts, through Eolus, Dorus, and Xuthus,
the three sons of Hellen, a distribution which is far
from being exhaustive: nevertheless, the genealogists whom Apollodorus follows
recognize no more than three sons.
The genealogy is essentially
post-Homeric; for Homer knows Hellas and the Hellenes only in connection with a
portion of Achaia Phthiotis. But as it is recognized
in the Hesiodic Catalogue—composed probably within the first century after the
commencement of recorded Olympiads, or before 676 BC—the peculiarities of it
elating from so early a period, deserve much attention. We may remark, first,
that it seems to exhibit to us Dorus and Eolus as the
only pure and genuine offspring of Hellen. For their
brother Xuthus is not enrolled as an eponymous; he
neither founds nor names any people; it is only his sons Achaeus and Ion, after
his blood has been mingled with that of the Erechtheid Kreusa, who become eponyms and founders, each of his
own separate people. Next, as to the territorial distribution, Xuthus receives Peloponnesus from his father, and unites
himself with Attica (which the author of this genealogy seems to have conceived
as originally unconnected with Hellen) by his
marriage with the daughter of the indigenous hero Erechtheus. The issue of this
marriage, Achaeus and Ion, present to us the population of Peloponnesus and
Attica conjointly as related among themselves by the tie of brotherhood, but as
one degree more distant both from Dorians and Eolians.
Eolus reigns over the regions about Thessaly, and calls the people in those
parts Aeolians; while Dorus occupies “the country
over against Peloponnesus on the opposite side of the Corinthian Gulf”, and
calls the inhabitants after himself Dorians. It is at once evident that this
designation is in no way applicable to the confined district between Parnassus
and Eta, which alone is known by the
name of Doris, and its inhabitants by that of Dorians, in the historical ages.
In the view of the author of this genealogy, the Dorians are the original
occupants of the large range of territory north of the Corinthian Gulf,
comprising Phocis, and the territory of the Ozolian Lokrians. And this farther harmonizes with the other legend
noticed by Apollodorus, when he states that Etolus, son
of Endymion, having been forced to expatriate from
Peloponnesus, crossed into the Kuretid territory, and
was there hospitably received by Dorus, Laodokus, and Polypcetes, sons of
Apollo and Phthia. He slew his hosts, acquired the
territory, and gave to it the name of Etolia; his son Pleuron married Xanthippe,
daughter of Dorus; while his other son, Kalydon, marries Eolia, daughter
of Amythaon. Here again we have the name of Dorus, or the Dorians, connected with the tract
subsequently termed Etolia. That Dorus should in one place be called the son of Apollo and Phthia,
and in another place the son of Hellen by a nymph,
will surprise no one accustomed to the fluctuating personal nomenclature of
these old legends: moreover the name of Phthia is
easy to reconcile with that of Hellen, as both are
identified with the same portion of Thessaly, even from the days of the Iliad.
This story, that the Dorians were at
one time the occupants, or the chief occupants, of the range of territory
between the river Achelous and the northern shore of
the Corinthian gulf, is at least more suitable to the facts attested by
historical evidence than the legends given in Herodotus, who represents the
Dorians as originally in the Phthiotid; then as
passing under Dorus, the son of Hellen,
into the Histiotid, under the mountains of Ossa and
Olympus; next, as driven by the Kadmeians into the
regions of Pindus; from thence passing into the Dryopid territory, on Mount Eta; lastly, from thence into Peloponnesus. The received
story was, that the great Dorian establishments in Peloponnesus were formed by
invasion from the north, and that the invaders crossed the gulf from Naupaktus,—a statement which, however disputable with
respect to Argos, seems highly probable in regard both to Sparta and Messenia.
That the name of Dorians comprehended far more than the inhabitants of the
insignificant tetrapolis of Doris Proper must be
assumed, if we believe that they conquered Sparta and Messenia: both the
magnitude of the conquest itself and the passage of a large portion of them
from Naupaktus, harmonize with the legend as given by
Apollodorus, in which the Dorians are represented as the principal inhabitants
of the northern shore of the gulf.
The statements which we find in
Herodotus, respecting the early migrations of the Dorians, have been considered
as possessing greater historical value than those of the fabulist Apollodorus.
But both are equally matter of legend, while the brief indications of the
latter seem to be most in harmony with the facts which we afterwards find
attested by history.
It has already been mentioned that
the genealogy which makes Eolus, Xuthus, and Dorus sons of Hellen, is as old
as the Hesiodic Catalogue; probably also that which makes Hellen son of Deucalion. Aethlius also is an Hesiodic
personage; whether Amphiktion be so or not, we have
no proof. They could not have been introduced into the legendary genealogy
until after the Olympic games and the Amphiktyonic council had acquired an established and extensive reverence throughout Greece.
Respecting Dorus the son of Hellen, we find neither legends nor
legendary genealogy; respecting Xuthus, very little
beyond the tale of Kreusa and Ion, which has its
place more naturally among the Attic fables. Achaeus, however, who is here
represented as the son of Xuthus, appears in other
stories with very different parentage and accompaniments. According to the
statement which we find in Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Achaeis, Phthius, and Pelasgus are
sons of Poseidon and Larissa. They migrate from Peloponnesus into Thessaly, and
distribute the Thessalian territory between them, giving their names to its
principal divisions: their descendants in the sixth generation were driven out
of that country by the invasion of Deucalion at the head of the Kuretes and the Leleges. This was
the story of those who wanted to provide an eponymus for the Achaeans in the southern districts of Thessaly: Pausanias accomplishes
the same object by different means, representing Achaeus the son of Xuthus as having gone back to Thessaly and occupied the
portion of it to which his father was entitled. Then, by way of explaining how
it was that there were Achaeans at Sparta and at Argos, he tells us that Archander and Architeles the sons
of Achaeus, came back from Thessaly to Peloponnesus, and married two daughters
of Danaus: they acquired great influence at Argos and
Sparta, and gave to the people the name of Achaeans after their father Achaeus.
Euripides also deviates very
materially from the Hesiodic genealogy in respect to the eponymous persons. In
the drama called Ion, he describes Ion as son of Kreusa by Apollo, but adopted by Xuthus: according to him,
the real sons of Xuthus and Kreusa are Dorus and Achaeus,—eponyms of the Dorians and
Achaeans in the interior of Peloponnesus. And it is a still more capital point
of difference that he omits Hellen altogether—making Xuthus an Achaean by race, the son of Eolus, who is the son
of Zeus. This is the more remarkable, as in the fragments of two other dramas
of Euripides, the Melanippe and the Eolus, we find Hellen mentioned both as father of Eolus and son of Zeus.
To the general public even of the most instructed city of Greece, fluctuations
and discrepancies in these mythical genealogies seem to have been neither
surprising nor offensive.
IF two of the sons of Hellen, Dorus and Xuthus, present to us families comparatively unnoticed in
mythical narrative, the third son, Aeolus, richly makes up for the deficiency.
From him we pass to his seven sons and five daughters, amidst a great abundance
of heroic and poetical incident.
In dealing, however, with these
extensive mythical families, it is necessary to observe, that the legendary
world of Greece, in the manner in which it is presented to us, appears invested
with a degree of symmetry and coherence which did not originally belong to it.
For the old ballads and stories which were sung or recounted at the multiplied
festivals of Greece, each on its own special theme, have been lost: the
religious narratives, which the Exegetes of every temple had present to his
memory, explanatory of the peculiar religious ceremonies and local customs in
his own town or deme, had passed
away. All these primitive elements, originally distinct and unconnected, are
removed out of our sight, and we possess only an aggregate result, formed by
many confluent streams of fable, and connected together by the agency of
subsequent poets and logographers. Even the earliest agents in this work of
connecting and systematizing—the Hesiodic poets—have been hardly at all
preserved. Our information respecting Grecian mythology is derived chiefly from
the prose logographers who followed them, and in whose works, since a
continuous narrative was above all things essential to them, the fabulous
personages are woven into still more comprehensive pedigrees, and the original
isolation of the legends still better disguised. Hekataeus, Pherekydes, Hellanikus, and Akusilaus lived
at a time when the idea of Hellas as one great whole, composed of fraternal
sections, was deeply rooted in the mind of every Greek, and when the hypothesis
of a few great families, branching out widely from one common stem was more
popular and acceptable than that of a distinct indigenous origin in each of the
separate districts. These logographers, indeed, have themselves been lost; but
Apollodorus and the various scholiasts, our great immediate sources of
information respecting Grecian mythology, chiefly borrowed from them: so that the
legendary world of Greece is in fact known to us through them, combined with
the dramatic and Alexandrine poets, their Latin imitators, and the still later
class of scholiasts—except indeed such occasional glimpses as we obtain from
the Iliad and the Odyssey, and the remaining Hesiodic fragments, which exhibit
but too frequently a hopeless diversity when confronted with the narratives of
the logographers.
Though Aeolus (as has been already
stated) is himself called the son of Hellen along
with Dorus and Xuthus, yet
the legends concerning the Aeolids, far from being
dependent upon this genealogy, are not all even coherent with it: moreover the
name of Aeolus in the legend is older than that of Hellen,
inasmuch as it occurs both in the Iliad and Odyssey. Odysseus sees in the
underworld the beautiful Tyre, daughter of Salmoneus,
and wife of Kretheus, son of Aeolus.
Aeolus is represented as having
reigned in Thessaly: his seven sons were Kretheus,
Sisyphus, Athamas, Salmoneus, Deion, Magnes, and Perieres: his five
daughters, Canace, Alcyone, Peisidike, Calyce, and Perimede. The fables of this race seem to be distinguished
by a constant introduction of the god Poseidon, as well as by an unusual
prevalence of haughty and presumptuous attributes among the Aeolid heroes, leading them to affront the gods by pretenses of equality, and
sometimes even by defiance. The worship of Poseidon must probably have been
diffused and pre-eminent among a people with whom those legends originated.
SONS OF AEOLUS.
Salmoneus is not described in the Odyssey as
son of Aeolus, but he is so denominated both in the Hesiodic Catalogue and by
the subsequent logographers. His daughter Tyro became enamored of the river Enipeus, the most beautiful of all streams that traverse
the earth; she frequented the banks assiduously, and there the god Poseidon
found means to indulge his passion for her, assuming the character of the
river-god himself. The fruit of this alliance were the twin brothers, Pelias and Neleus: Tyro
afterwards was given in marriage to her uncle Kretheus,
another son of Aolus, by whom she had Aeson, Pheres, and Amythaon—all names of celebrity in the heroic legends. The
adventures of Tyro formed the subject of an affecting drama of Sophocles, now
lost. Her father had married a second wife, named Sidero,
whose cruel counsels induced him to punish and torture his daughter on account
of her intercourse with Poseidon. She was shorn of her magnificent hair, beaten
and ill-used in various ways, and confined in a loathsome dungeon. Unable to
take care of her two children, she had been compelled to expose them
immediately on their birth in a little boat on the river Enipeus;
they were preserved by the kindness of a herdsman, and when grown up to
manhood, rescued their mother, and revenged her wrongs by putting to death the
iron-hearted Sidero. This pathetic tale respecting
the long imprisonment of Tyro is substituted by Sophocles in place of the
Homeric legend, which represented her to have become the wife of Kretheus, and mother of a numerous offspring.
Her father, the unjust Salmoneus, exhibited in his conduct the most insolent
impiety towards the gods. He assumed the name and title even of Zeus, and
caused to be offered to himself the sacrifices destined for that god: he also
imitated the thunder and lightning, by driving about with brazen caldrons
attached to his chariot, and casting lighted torches towards heaven. Such
wickedness finally drew upon him the wrath of Zeus, who smote him with a
thunderbolt, and effaced from the earth the city which he had founded, with all
its inhabitants. Pelias and Neleus,
“both stout vassals of the great Zeus”, became engaged in dissension respecting
the kingdom of Iolkos in Thessaly. Pelias got possession of it, and dwelt there in plenty and
prosperity; but he had offended the goddess Hera by killing Sidero upon her altar, and the effects of her wrath were manifested in his relations
with his nephew Jason.
Neleus quitted Thessaly, went into
Peloponnesus, and there founded the kingdom of Pylos.
He purchased, by immense marriage presents, the privilege of wedding the
beautiful Chloris, daughter of Amphion,
king of Orchomenos, by whom he had twelve sons and
but one daughters—the fair and captivating Pero, whom
suitors from all the neighborhood courted in marriage. But Neleus,
“the haughtiest of living men”, refused to entertain the pretensions of any of
them: he would grant his daughter only to that man who should bring to him the
oxen of Iphiklos, from Phylake in Thessaly. These precious animals were carefully guarded, as well by herdsmen
as by a dog whom neither man nor animal could approach.
Nevertheless, Bias, the son of Amythaon, nephew of Neleus, being
desperately enamored of Pero, prevailed upon his
brother Melampus to undertake for his sake the perilous
adventure in spite of the prophetic knowledge of the latter, which forewarned
him that though he would ultimately succeed, the prize must be purchased by
severe captivity and suffering. Melampus, in
attempting to steal the oxen, was seized and put in prison; from whence nothing
but his prophetic powers rescued him. Being acquainted with the language of
worms, he heard these animals communicating to each other, in the roof over his
head, that the beams were nearly eaten through and about to fall in. He communicated
this intelligence to his guards, and demanded to be conveyed to another place
of confinement, announcing that the roof would presently fall in and bury them.
The prediction was fulfilled, and Phylakos, father of Iphiklos, full of wonder at this specimen of
prophetic power, immediately caused him to be released. He further consulted
him respecting the condition of his son Iphiklos, who
was childless; and promised him the possession of the oxen on condition of his
suggesting the means whereby offspring might be ensured. A vulture having
communicated to Melampus the requisite information, Podarkes, the son of Iphiklos,
was born shortly afterwards. In this manner Melampus obtained possession of the oxen, and conveyed them to Pylos,
ensuring to his brother Bias the hand of Pero. How
this great legendary character, by miraculously healing the deranged daughters
of Proetos, procured both for himself and for Bias
dominion in Argos, has been recounted in a preceding chapter.
Of the twelve sons of Neleus, one at least, Periklymenos,—besides
the ever memorable Nestor,—was distinguished for his exploits as well as for
his miraculous gifts. Poseidon, the divine father of the race, had bestowed
upon him the privilege of changing his form at pleasure into that of any bird,
beast, reptile, or insects He had occasion for all these resources, and he
employed them for a time with success in defending his family against the
terrible indignation of Herakles, who, provoked by
the refusal of Neleus to perform for him the ceremony
of purification after his murder of Iphitus, attacked
the Neleids at Pylos. Periklymenos by his extraordinary powers prolonged the
resistance, but the hour of his fate was at length brought upon him by the
intervention of Athene, who pointed him out to Heracles while he was perched as
a bee upon the hero’s chariot. He was killed, and Heracles became completely
victorious, overpowering Poseidon, Here, Ares, and Hades, and even wounding the
three latter, who assisted in the defence. Eleven of
the sons of Neleus perished by his hand, while
Nestor, then a youth, was preserved only by his accidental absence at Gerena, away from his father's residence.
The proud house of the Neleids was now reduced to Nester; but Nestor singly
sufficed to sustain its eminence. He appears not only as the defender and
avenger of Pylos against the insolence and rapacity
of his Epeian neighbors at Elis, but also as aiding
the Lapithae in their terrible combat against the
Centaurs, and as companion of Theseus, Peirithous, and
the other great legendary heroes who preceded the Trojan war. In extreme old
age his once marvelous power of handling his weapons has indeed passed away,
but his activity remains unimpaired, and his sagacity as well as his influence
in counsel is greater than ever. He not only assembles the various Grecian
chiefs for the armament against Troy, perambulating the districts of Hellas
along with Odysseus, but takes a vigorous part in the siege itself, and is of
pre-eminent service to Agamemnon. And after the conclusion of the siege, he is
one of the few Grecian princes who returns to his original dominions. He is
found, in a strenuous and honored old age, in the midst of his children and
subjects,—sitting with the scepter of authority on the stone bench before his
house at Pylos,—offering sacrifice to Poseidon, as
his father Neleus had done before him,—and mourning
only over the death of his favorite son Antilochus,
who had fallen along with so many brave companions in arms in the Trojan war.
After Nestor the line of the Neleids numbers undistinguished names,—Borus, Penthilus, and Andropompus,—three
successive generations down to Melanthus, who on the invasion of Peloponnesus
by the Herakleids, quitted Pylos and retired to Athens, where he became king, in a manner which I shall
hereafter recount. His son Kodrus was the last Athenian king; and Neleus, one of the sons of Kodrus, is mentioned down to as
the principal conductor of what is called the Ionic emigration from Athens to
Asia Minor. It is certain that during the historical age, not merely the
princely family of the Kodrids in Miletus, Ephesus,
and other Ionic cities, but some of the greatest families even in Athens
itself, traced their heroic lineage through the Neleids up to Poseidon; and the legends respecting Nestor and Periklymenos would find especial favor amidst Greeks with such feelings and belief. The Kodrids at Ephesus, and probably some other Ionic towns,
long retained the title and honorary precedence of kings, even after they had
lost the substantial power belonging to the office. They stood in the same
relation, embodying both religious worship and supposed ancestry, to the Neleids and Poseidon, as the chiefs of the Aeolic colonies
to Agamemnon and Orestes. The Athenian despot Peisistratus was named after the
son of Nestor in the Odyssey; and we may safely presume that the heroic worship
of the Neleids was as carefully cherished at the
Ionic Miletus as at the Italian Metapontum.
Having pursued the line of Salmoneus and Neleus to the end
of its legendary career, we may now turn back to that of another son of Aeolus, Kretheus, a line hardly less celebrated in respect of
the heroic names which it presents. Alcestis, the most beautiful of the
daughters of Pelias, was promised by her father in
marriage to the man who could bring him a lion and a boar tamed to the yoke and
drawing together. Admetus, son of Pheres,
the eponymous of Pherae in Thessaly, and thus grandson of Kretheus,
was enabled by the aid of Apollo to fulfill this condition, and to win her; for
Apollo happened at that time to be in his service as a slave (condemned to this
penalty by Zeus for having put to death the Cyclopes), in which capacity he
tended the herds and horses with such success, as to equip Eumelus (the son of Admetus) to the Trojan war with the
finest horses in the Grecian army. Though menial duties were imposed upon him,
even to the drudgery of grinding in the mill, he yet carried away with him a
grateful and friendly sentiment towards his mortal master, whom he interfered
to rescue from the wrath of the goddess Artemis, when she was indignant at the
omission of her name in his wedding sacrifices.
Admetus was about to perish by a premature
death, when Apollo, by earnest solicitation to the Fates, obtained for him the
privilege that his life should be prolonged, if he could find any person to die
a voluntary death in his place. His father and his mother both refused to make
this sacrifice for him, but the devoted attachment of his wife Alcestis disposed
her to embrace with cheerfulness the condition of dying to preserve her
husband. She had already perished, when Heracles, the ancient guest and friend
of Admetus, arrived during the first hour of
lamentation; his strength and daring enabled him to rescue the deceased
Alcestis even from the grasp of Thanatos (Death), and
to restore her alive to her disconsolate husband.
PELIAS—JASON AND MEDEA.
The son of Pelias, Akastus, had received and sheltered Peleus when
obliged to fly his country in consequence of the involuntary murder of Eurytion. Kretheis, the wife of Akastus, becoming enamored of Peleus, made to him advances
which he repudiated. Exasperated at his refusal, and determined to procure his
destruction, she persuaded her husband that Peleus had attempted her chastity:
upon which Akastus conducted Peleus out upon a
hunting excursion among the woody regions of Mount Pelion, contrived to steal
from him the sword fabricated and given by Hephestos,
and then left him, alone and unarmed, to perish by the hands of the Centaurs or
by the wild beasts. By the friendly aid of the Centaur Cheiron,
however, Peleus was preserved, and his sword restored to him: returning to the
city, he avenged himself by putting to death both Akastus and his perfidious wife.
But amongst all the legends with
which the name of Pelias is connected, by far the
most memorable is that of Jason and the Argonautic expedition. Jason was son of Aeson, grandson of Kretheus, and thus great-grandson of Eolus. Pelias, having consulted the oracle respecting the security
of his dominion at Iolkos, had received in answer a
warning to beware of the man who should appear before him with only one sandal.
He was celebrating a festival in honor of Poseidon, when it so happened that
Jason appeared before him with one of his feet unsandaled:
he had lost one sandal in wading through the swollen current of the river Anauros. Pelias immediately
understood that this was the enemy against whom the oracle had forewarned him.
As a means of averting the danger, he imposed upon Jason the desperate task of
bringing back to Iolkos the Golden Fleece,—the fleece
of that ram which had carried Phryxos from Achaia to
Colchis, and which Phryxos had dedicated in the
latter country as an offering to the god Ares. The result of this injunction
was the memorable expedition—of the ship Argo and her crew called the
Argonauts, composed of the bravest and noblest youths of Greece—which cannot be
conveniently included among the legends of the Aeolids,
and is reserved for a separate chapter.
The voyage of the Argo was long
protracted, and Pelias, persuaded that neither the
ship nor her crew would ever return, put to death both the father and mother of
Jason, together with their infant son. Aeson, the
father, being permitted to choose the manner of his own death, drank bull’s
blood while performing a sacrifice to the gods. At length, however, Jason did
return, bringing with him not only the golden fleece, but also Medea, daughter
of Aetes, king of Colchis, as his wife,—a woman
distinguished for magical skill and cunning, by whose assistance alone the
Argonauts had succeeded in their project. Though determined to avenge himself
upon Pelias, Jason knew that he could only succeed by
stratagem. He remained with his companions a short distance from Iolkos, while Medea, feigning herself a fugitive from his
ill-usage, entered the town alone, and procured access to the daughters of Pelias. By exhibitions of her magical powers she soon
obtained unqualified ascendancy over their minds. For example, she selected
from the flocks of Pelias a ram in the extremity of
old age, cut him up and boiled him in a caldron with herbs, and brought him out
in the shape of a young and vigorous lamb: the daughters of Pelias were made to believe that their old father could in like manner be restored to
youth. In this persuasion they cut him up with their own hands and cast his
limbs into the caldron, trusting that Medea would produce upon him the same
magical effect. Medea pretended that an invocation to the moon was a necessary
part of the ceremony she went up to the top of the house as if to pronounce it,
and there lighting the fire-signal concerted with the Argonauts, Jason and his
companions burst in and possessed themselves of the town. Satisfied with having
thus revenged himself, Jason yielded the principality of Iolkos to Akastus, son of Pelias,
and retired with Medea to Corinth. Thus did the goddess gratify her ancient
wrath against Pelias: she had constantly watched over
Jason, and had carried the “all-notorious” Argos through its innumerable
perils, in order that Jason might bring home Medea to accomplish the ruin of
his uncle. The misguided daughters of Pelias departed
as voluntary exiles to Arcadia: Akastus his son
celebrated splendid funeral games in honor of his deceased father.
Jason and Medea retired from Iolkos to Corinth where they resided ten years: their
children were—Medeius, whom the Centaur Cheiron educated in the regions of Mount Pélion,—and Mermerus and Pheres, born at Corinth. After they had resided there ten
years in prosperity, Jason set his affections on Glauke,
daughter of Kreon, king of Corinth; and as her father
was willing to give her to him in marriage, he determined to repudiate Medea,
who received orders forthwith to leave Corinth. Stung with this insult and bent
upon revenge, Medea prepared a poisoned robe, and sent it as a marriage present
to Glauke: it was unthinkingly accepted and put on,
and the body of the unfortunate bride was burnt up and consumed. Kreon, her father, who tried to tear from her the burning
garment, shared her fate and perished. The exulting Medea escaped by means of a
chariot with winged serpents furnished to her by her grandfather Helios: she
placed herself under the protection of Aegeus at
Athens, by whom she had a son named Medus. She left
her young children in the sacred enclosure of the Akraean Here, relying on the protection of the altar to ensure their safety; but the
Corinthians were so exasperated against her for the murder of Kreon and Glauke, that they dragged
the children away from the altar and put them to death. The miserable Jason
perished by a fragment of his own ship Argo, which fell upon him while he was
asleep under it, being hauled on shore, according to the habitual practice of
the ancients.
MEDEA AT CORINTH—SISYPHUS
The first establishment at Ephyre, or Corinth, had been founded by Sisyphus, another
of the sons of Aeolus, brother of Salmoneus and Kretheus. The Aeolid Sisyphus was
distinguished as an unexampled master of cunning and deceit. He blocked up the
road along the isthmus, and killed the strangers who came along it by rolling
down upon them great stones from the mountains above. He was more than a match
even for the arch thief Autolykus, the son of Hermes,
who derived from his father the gift of changing the color and shape of stolen
goods, so that they could no longer be recognized: Sisyphus, by marking his
sheep under the foot, detected Autolykus when he
stole them, and obliged him to restore the plunder. His penetration discovered
the amour of Zeus with the nymph Aegina, daughter of the river-god Aesopus.
Zeus had carried her off to the island of Oenone (which subsequently bore
the name of Aegina); upon which Aesopus, eager to recover her, inquired of
Sisyphus whither she was gone; the latter told him what had happened, on
condition that he should provide a spring of water on the summit of the Acro-Corinthus. Zeus, indignant with Sisyphus for this
revelation, inflicted upon him in Hades the punishment of perpetually heaving
up a hill a great and heavy stone, which, so soon as it attained the summit,
rolled back again, in spite of all his efforts, with irresistible force into
the plain.
In the application of the Aeolid genealogy to Corinth, Sisyphus, the son of Aeolus,
appears as the first name: but the old Corinthian poet Eumelus either found or framed an heroic genealogy for his native city, independent
both of Aeolus and Sisyphus. According to this genealogy, Ephyre,
daughter of Oceanus and Tethys, was the primitive tenant of the Corinthian
territory, Aesopus of the Sicyonian: both were
assigned to the god Helios, in adjusting a dispute between him and Poseidon, by Briareus. Helios divided the territory between his
two sons Aetes and Aloeus:
to the former he assigned Corinth, to the latter Sicyon. Aetes,
obeying the admonition of an oracle, emigrated to Colchis, leaving his
territory under the rule of Bunos, the son of Hermes,
with the stipulation that it should be restored whenever either he or any of
his descendants returned. After the death of Bunos,
both Corinth and Sicyon were possessed by Epopeus,
son of Aloeus, a wicked man. His son Marathon left
him in disgust, and retired into Attica, but returned after his death and
succeeded to his territory, which he in turn divided between his two sons, Corinthos and Sicyon, from whom the names of the two
districts were first derived. Korinthos died without issue, and the Corinthians
then invited Medea from Iolkos as the representative
of Aetes: she, with her husband Jason, thus obtained
the sovereignty of Corinth. This legend of Eumelus,
one of the earliest of the genealogical poets, so different from the story
adopted by Neophron or Euripides, was followed
certainly by Simonides, and seemingly by Theopompus.
The incidents in it are imagined and arranged with a view to the supremacy of
Medea; the emigration of Aetes and the conditions
under which he transferred his scepter, being so laid out as to confer upon
Medea an hereditary title to the throne. The Corinthians paid to Medea and to
her children solemn worship, either divine, or heroic, in conjunction with Here Akraea, and this was sufficient to give to Medea a
prominent place in the genealogy composed by a Corinthian poet, accustomed to
blend together gods, heroes, and men in the antiquities of his native city.
According to the legend of Eumelus, Jason became
(through Medea) king of Corinth; but she concealed the children of their
marriage in the temple of Here, trusting that the goddess would render them
immortal. Jason, discovering her proceedings, left her, and retired in disgust
to Iolkos; Medea also, being disappointed in her
scheme, quitted the place, leaving the throne in the hands of Sisyphus, to
whom, according to the story of Theopompus, she had
become attached. Other legends recounted that Zeus had contracted a passion for
Medea, but that she had rejected his suit from fear of the displeasure of Here;
who, as a recompense for such fidelity, rendered her children immortal:
moreover, Medea had erected, by special command of Here, the celebrated temple
of Aphrodite at Corinth.
The tenor of these fables manifests
their connection with the temple of Here, and we may consider the legend of
Medea as having been originally quite independent of that of Sisyphus, but
fitted on to it, in seeming chronological sequence, so as to satisfy the
feelings of those Aeolids of Corinth who passed for
his descendants.
Sisyphus had for his sons Glaukos and Ornytion. From Glaukos sprang Bellerophon, whose
romantic adventures commence with the Iliad, and are further expanded by
subsequent poets: according to some accounts, he was really the son of
Poseidon, the prominent deity of the Aeolid family.
The youth and beauty of Bellerophon rendered him the
object of a strong passion on the part of Anteia,
wife of Proetos, king of Argos. Finding her advances
rejected, she contracted a violent hatred towards him, and endeavored, by false
accusations, to prevail upon her husband to kill him. Proetos refused to commit the deed under his own roof, but dispatched him to his son-in-law,
the king of Lykia in Asia Minor, putting into his
hands a folded tablet full of destructive symbols. Conformably to these
suggestions, the most perilous undertakings were imposed upon Bellerophon. He was directed to attack the monster Chimaera
and to conquer the warlike Solymi as well as the
Amazons: as he returned victorious from these enterprises, an ambuscade was
laid for him by the bravest Lycian warriors, all of
whom he slew. At length the Lycian king recognized
him “as the genuine son of a god”, and gave him his daughter in marriage
together with half of his kingdom. The grand-children of Bellerophon, Glaukos and Sarpedon,—the
latter a son of his daughter Laodameia by
Zeus,—combat as allies of Troy against the host of Agamemnon.
Fourth Aeolid line-Athamas.
We now pass from Sisyphus and the
Corinthian fables to another son of Eolus, Athamas, whose family history is not
less replete with mournful and tragical incidents,
abundantly diversified by the poets. Athamas, we are told, was king of Orchomenos; his wife Nephele was
a goddess, and he had by her two children, Phryxus and Helle. After a certain time he neglected Nephele, and took to himself as new wife Ino, the daughter of Kadmus, by
whom he had two sons, Learchus and Melikertes. Ino, looking upon Phryxus with the hatred of a stepmother, laid a snare for
his life. She persuaded the women to roast the seed-wheat, which, when sown in
this condition, yielded no crop, so that famine overspread the land. Athamas,
sending to Delphi to implore counsel and a remedy, received for answer, through
the machinations of Ino with the oracle, that the
barrenness of the fields could not be alleviated except by offering Phryxus as a sacrifice to Zeus. The distress of the people
compelled him to execute this injunction, and Phryxus was led as a victim to the altar. But the power of his mother Nephele snatched him from destruction, and procured for him
from Hermes a ram with a fleece of gold, upon which he and his sister Helle mounted and were carried across the sea. The ram took
the direction of the Euxine sea and Colchis: when they were crossing the
Hellespont, Helle fell off into the narrow strait,
which took its name from that incident. Upon this, the ram, who was endued with
speech, consoled the terrified Phryxus, and
ultimately carried him safe to Colchis: Aetes, king
of Colchis, son of the god Helios, and brother of Circe, received Phryxus kindly, and gave him his daughter Chalkiope in marriage. Phryxus sacrificed the ram to Zeus Phyxios, suspending the
golden fleece in the sacred grove of Ares.
Athamas—according to some both
Athamas and Ino—were afterwards driven mad by the
anger of the goddess Here; insomuch that the father shot his own son Learchus, and would also have put to death his other son Melikertes, if Ino had not
snatched him away. She fled with the boy across the Megarian territory and Mount Geraneia, to the rock Moluris, overhanging the Saronic Gulf: Athamas pursued her, and in order to escape him she leaped into the sea.
She became a sea-goddess under the title of Leukothea;
while the body of Melikertes was cast ashore on the neighboring
territory of Schoenus, and buried by his uncle
Sisyphus, who was directed by the Nereids to pay to
him heroic honours under the name of Palaemon. The Isthmian games, one of the great periodical
festivals of Greece, were celebrated in honor of the god Poseidon, in
conjunction with Palaemon as a hero. Athamas
abandoned his territory, and became the first settler of a neighboring region
called from him Athamantia, or the Athamantian plain.
The legend of Athamas connects
itself with some sanguinary religious rites and very peculiar family customs,
which prevailed at Alos in Achaia Phthiotis,
down to a time later than the historian Herodotus, and of which some remnant
existed at Orchomenos even in the days of Plutarch.
Athamas was worshipped at Alos as a hero, having both
a chapel and a consecrated grove, attached to the temple of Zeus Laphystios. On the family of which he was the heroic
progenitor, a special curse and disability stood affixed. The eldest of the
race was forbidden to enter the prytaneion or
government-house: if he was found within the doors of the building, the other
citizens laid hold of him on his going out, surrounded him with garlands, and
led him in solemn procession to be sacrificed as a victim at the altar of Zeus Laphystios. The prohibition carried with it an exclusion
from all the public meetings and ceremonies, political as well as religious,
and from the sacred fire of the state: many of the individuals marked out had
therefore been bold enough to transgress it. Some had been seized on quitting
the building and actually sacrificed; others had fled the country for a long
time to avoid a similar fate.
The guides who conducted Xerxes and
his army through southern Thessaly detailed to him this existing practice,
coupled with the local legend, that Athamas, together with Ino,
had sought to compass the death of Phryxus, who
however had escaped to Colchis; that the Achaeans had been enjoined by an oracle
to offer up Athamas himself as an expiatory sacrifice to release the country
from the anger of the gods; but that Kytissoros, son
of Phryxus, coming back from Colchis, had intercepted
the sacrifice of Athamas, whereby the anger of the gods remained still
unappeased, and an undying curse rested upon the family.
That such human sacrifices continued
to a greater or less extent, even down to a period later than Herodotus, among
the family who worshipped Athamas as their heroic ancestor, appears certain: mention
is also made of similar customs in parts of Arcadia, and of Thessaly, in honor
of Peleus and Cheiron. But we may reasonably presume,
that in the period of greater humanity which Herodotus witnessed, actual
sacrifice had become very rare. The curse and the legend still remained, but
were not called into practical working, except during periods of intense
national suffering or apprehension, during which the religious sensibilities
were always greatly aggravated. We cannot at all doubt, that during the alarm
created by the presence of the Persian king with his immense and
ill-disciplined host, the minds of the Thessalians must have been keenly alive
to all that was terrific in their national stories, and all that was expiatory
in their religious solemnities. Moreover, the mind of Xerxes himself was so
awe-struck by the tale, that he reverenced the dwelling-place consecrated to
Athamas. The guides who recounted to him the romantic legend gave it as the
historical and generating cause of the existing rule and practice: a critical
inquirer is forced (as has been remarked before) to reverse the order of
precedence, and to treat the practice as having been the suggesting cause of
its own explanatory legend.
The family history of Athamas and
the worship of Zeus Laphystios are expressly
connected by Herodotus with Alos in Achaea Phthiotis—one of the towns enumerated in the Iliad as under
the command of Achilles. But there was also a mountain called Laphystion, and a temple and worship of Zeus Laphystios between Orchomenos and Koroneia, in the northern portion of the territory
known in the historical ages as Boeotia. Here too the family story of Athamas
is localised, and Athamas is presented to us as king
of the districts of Koreneia, Haliartus and Athamas in Mount Laphystion: he is thus
interwoven with the Orchomenian genealogy. Andreus (we are told), son of the river Peneios,
was the first person who settled in the region: from him it received the name Andreis. Athamas, coming subsequently to Andreus, received from him the territory of Koreneia and Haliartus with Mount Laphystion: he gave in marriage to Andreus Euippe, daughter of his
son Leucon, and the issue of this marriage was Eteokles, said to be the son of the river Kephisos. Koronos and Haliartus, grandsons of the Corinthian Sisyphus, were
adopted by Athamas, as he had lost all his children. But when his grandson Presbem, son of Phryxus, returned
to him from Kolchis, he divided his territory in such
manner that Koronos and Haliartus became the founders of the towns which bore their names. Almon,
the son of Sisyphus, also received from Eteokles a
portion of territory, where he established the village Almones.
ETEOKLES- THE CHARITESIA
With Eteokles began, according to a statement in one of the Hesiodic poems, the worship of
the Charites or Graces, so long and so solemnly
continued at Orchomenos in the periodical festival of
the Charitesia, to which many neighbouring towns and districts seem to have contributed. He also distributed the
inhabitants into two tribes—Eteokleia and Kephisias. He died childless, and was succeeded by Almos, who had only two daughters, Chryse and Chrysogeneia. The son of Chryse by the god Ares was Phlegyas, the father and founder
of the warlike and predatory Phlegyae, who despoiled
everyone within their reach, and assaulted not only the pilgrims on their road
to Delphi, but even the treasures of the temple itself. The offended god
punished them by continued thunder, by earthquakes, and by pestilence, which
extinguished all this impious race, except a scanty remnant who fled into Phocis.
Chrysogeneia, the other daughter of Almos, had for issue, by the god Poseidon, Minyas: the son of Minyas was Orchomenos. From these two was derived the name both of Minyae for the people, and of Orchomenos for the town. During the reign of Orchomenos, Hyettus came to him from Argos, having become an exile in
consequence of the death of Molyros: Orchomenos assigned to him a portion of land, where he
founded the village called Hyettus. Orchomenos, having no issue, was succeeded by Klymenos, son of Presbon, of the
house of Athamas: Klymenos was slain by some Thebans
during the festival of Poseidon at Onchestos; and his
eldest son, Erginus, to avenge his death, attacked
the Thebans with his utmost force;—an attack in which he was so successful,
that the latter were forced to submit, and to pay him an annual tribute.
The Orchomenian power was now at its height: both Minyas and Orchomenos had been princes of surpassing wealth, and the
former had built a spacious and durable edifice which he had filled with gold
and silver. But the success of Erginus against Thebes
was soon terminated and reversed by the hand of the irresistible Heracles, who
rejected with disdain the claim of tribute, and even mutilated the envoys sent
to demand it: he not only and the emancipated Thebes, but broke down and
impoverished Orchomenos.
Erginus in his old age married a young
wife, from which match sprang the illustrious heroes, or gods, Trophonius and Agamedes; though
many (amongst whom is Pausanias himself) believed Trophonius to be the son of Apollo. Trophonius, one of the most
memorable persons in Grecian mythology, was worshipped as a god in various
places, but with especial sanctity as Zeus Trophonius at Lebadeia: in his temple at this town, the
prophetic manifestations outlasted those of Delphi itself. Trophonius and Agamedes, enjoying matchless renown as
architects, built the temple of Delphi, the thalamus of Amphitryon at Thebes, and also the inaccessible vault of Hyrieus at Hyria, in which they are said to have left one
stone removable at pleasure so as to reserve for themselves a secret entrance.
They entered so frequently, and stole so much gold and silver, that Hyrieus, astonished at his losses, at length spread a fine
net, in which Agamedes was inextricably caught: Trophonius cut off his brother's head and carried it away,
so that the body, which alone remained, was insufficient to identify the thief.
Like Amphiaraos, whom he resembles in more than one
respect, Trophonius was swallowed up by the earth
near Lebadeia.
THE ORCHOMENIAN GENEALOGY
From Trophonius and Agamedes the Orchomenian genealogy passes to Askalaphos and Ialmenos, the sons of Ares by Astyoche,
who are named in the Catalogue of the Iliad as leaders of the thirty ships from Orchomenos against Troy. Azeus,
the grandfather of Astyoche in the Iliad, is
introduced as the brother of Erginus by Pausanias,
who does not carry the pedigree lower.
The genealogy here given out of
Pausanias is deserving of the more attention, because it seems to have been
copied from the special history of Orchomenos by the
Corinthian Kallippus, who again borrowed from the
native Orchomenian poet, Chersias the works of the latter had never come into the hands of Pausanias. It
illustrates forcibly the principle upon which these mythical genealogies were
framed, for almost every personage in the series is an Eponymous. Andreus gave his name to the country, Athamas to the Athamantian plain; Minyas, Orchomenos, Koronus, Haliartus, Almos, and Hyettos, are each in like manner connected with some name
of people, tribe, town, or village; while Chryse and Chrysogeneia have their origin in the reputed ancient
wealth of Orchomenos. Abundant discrepancies are
found, however, in respect to this old genealogy, if we look to other accounts.
According to one statement, Orchomenos was the son of
Zeus, by Isione, daughter of Danaus; Minyas was the son of Orchomenos (or rather Poseidon) by Hermippe, daughter of Boetos; the sons of Minyas were Presbon, Orchomenos, Athamas, and Diochthondas. Others represented Minyas as son of Poseidon by Kallirrhoe, an Oceanic nymph,
while Dionysius called him son of Ares, and Aristodemus, son of Aleas; lastly, there were not wanting authors who termed
both Minyas and Orchomenos sons of Eteokles. Nor do we find in any one of these
genealogies the name of Amphion the son of Iasus, who
figures so prominently in the Odyssey as king of Orchomenos,
and whose beautiful daughter Chloris is married to Neleus. Pausanias mentions him, but not as king, which is
the denomination given to him in Homer.
The discrepancies here cited are
hardly necessary in order to prove that these Orchomenian genealogies possess no historical value. Yet some probable inferences appear
deducible from the general tenor of the legends, whether the facts and persons
of which they are composed be real or fictitious. Throughout all the historical
age, Orchomenos is a member of the Boeotian
confederation. But the Boeotians are said to have been immigrants into the
territory which bore their name from Thessaly; and prior to the time of their
immigration, Orchomenos and the surrounding territory
appear as possessed by the Minyae, who are recognized
in that locality both in the Iliad and in the Odyssey, and from whom the constantly
recurring Eponymous, king Minyas, is borrowed by the
genealogists. Poetical legend connects the Orchomenian Minyae, on the one side, with Pylos and Triphylia in Peloponnesus; on the other side,
with Phthiotis and the town of Polkos in Thessaly; also with Corinth, through Sisyphus and his sons. Pherekydes
represented Neleus, king of Pylos,
as having also been king of Orchomenos. In the region
of Triphylia, near to or coincident with Pylos, a Minyeian river is
mentioned by Homer; and we find traces of residents called Minyae even in the historical times, though the account given by Herodotus of the way
in which they came thither is strange and unsatisfactory.
Before the great changes which took
place in the inhabitants of Greece from the immigration of the Thesprotians into Thessaly, of the Boeotians into Boeotia,
and of the Dorians and Aetolians into Peloponnesus, at a date which we have no
means of determining, the Minyae and tribes
fraternally connected with them seem to have occupied a large portion of the
surface of Greece, from Iolkos in Thessaly to Pylos in the Peloponnesus. The wealth of Orchomenos is renowned even in the Iliad; and when we study
its topography in detail, we are furnished with a probable explanation both of
its prosperity and its decay. Orchomenos was situated
on the northern bank of the lake Kopais, which
receives not only the river Kephisos from the valleys
of Phocis, but also other rivers from Parnassus and Helicon. The waters of the
lake find more than one subterranean egress—partly through natural rifts and
cavities in the limestone mountains, partly through a tunnel pierced
artificially more than a mile in length—into the plain on the northeastern
side, from whence they flow into the Euboean sea near Larymna. And it appears that, so long as these
channels were diligently watched and kept clear, a large portion of the lake
was in the condition of alluvial land, pre-eminently rich and fertile. But when
the channels came to be either neglected, or designedly choked up by an enemy,
the water accumulated to such a degree as to occupy the soil of more than one
ancient town, to endanger the position of Kopae, and
to occasion the change of the site of Orchomenos itself from the plain to the declivity of Mount Hyphanteion.
An engineer, Krates, began the clearance of the
obstructed water-courses in the reign of Alexander the Great, and by his
commission—the destroyer of Thebes being anxious to re-establish the extinct
prosperity of Orchomenos. He succeeded so far as
partially to drain and diminish the lake, whereby the site of more than one
ancient city was rendered visible: but the revival of Thebes by Cassander,
after the decease of Alexander, arrested the progress of the undertaking, and
the lake soon regained its former dimensions, to contract which no further
attempt was made.
According to the Theban legend,
Heracles, after his defeat of Erginus, had blocked up
the exit of the waters, and converted the Orchomenian plain into a lake. The spreading of these waters is thus connected with the
humiliation of the Minyae; and there can be little
hesitation in ascribing to these ancient tenants of Orchomenos,
before it became boeotised, the enlargement and
preservation of the protective channels. Nor could such an object have been
accomplished without combined action and acknowledged ascendency on the part of
that city over its neighbors, extending even to the sea at Larynma,
where the river Kephisos discharges itself. Of its
extended influence, as well as of its maritime activity, we find a remarkable
evidence in the ancient and venerated Amphiktyony at Kalauria.
The little island so named, near the
harbor of Troezen, in Peloponnesus, was sacred to
Poseidon, and an asylum of inviolable sanctity. At the temple of Poseidon, in Kalauria, there had existed, from unknown date, a
periodical sacrifice, celebrated by seven cities in common—Hermione, Epidaurus,
Aegina, Athens, Prasiae, Nauplia,
and the Minyeian Orchomenos.
This ancient religious combination dates from the time when Nauplia was independent of Argos, and Prasiae of Sparta:
Argos and Sparta, according to the usual practice in Greece, continued to
fulfill the obligation each on the part of its respective dependent. Six out of
the seven states are at once sea-towns, and near enough to Kalauria to account for their participation in this Amphiktyony.
But the junction of Orchomenos, from its comparative
remoteness, becomes inexplicable, except on the supposition that its territory
reached the sea, and that it enjoyed a considerable maritime traffic—, a fact
which helps to elucidate both its legendary connection with Iolkos,
and its partnership in what is called the Ionic emigration.
The great power of Orchomenos was broken down and the city reduced to a
secondary and half-dependent position by the Boeotians of Thebes; at what time
and under what circumstances, history has not preserved. The story that the
Theban hero, Heracles, rescued his native city from servitude and tribute to Orchomenos, since it comes from a Cadmeian and not from an Orchomenian legend, and since the
details of it were favorite subjects of commemoration in the Theban temples,
affords a presumption that Thebes was really once dependent on Orchomenos. Moreover the savage mutilations inflicted by
the hero on the tribute-seeking envoys, so faithfully portrayed in his surname Rhinokoloustes, infuse into the myth a portion of that
bitter feeling which so long prevailed between Thebes and Orchomenos,
and which led the Theban, as soon as the battle of Leuktra had placed supremacy in their hands, to destroy and depopulate their rival. The
ensuing generation saw the same fate retorted upon Thebes, combined with the
restoration of Orchomenos. The legendary grandeur of
this city continued, long after it had ceased to be distinguished for wealth
and power, imperishably recorded both in the minds of the nobler citizens and
in the compositions of the poets: the emphatic language of Pausanias shows how
much he found concerning it in the old epic.
DAUGHTERS OF AEOLUS.
With several of the daughters of
Aeolus memorable mythical pedigrees and narratives are connected. Alcyone married Keyx, the son of Eosphoros, but both she and her husband displayed in a high
degree the overweening insolence common in the Aeolic race. The wife called her
husband Zeus, while he addressed her as Here, for which presumptuous act Zeus
punished them by changing both into birds.
Canace had by the god Poseidon several
children, amongst whom were Epopeus and Aloeus. Aloeus married Iphimedea, who became enamored of the god Poseidon, and
boasted of her intimacy with him. She had by him two sons, Otos and Ephialtes, the huge and formidable Aloids,—Titanic beings, nine fathoms in height and nine
cubits in breadth, even in their boyhood, before they had attained their full
strength. These Aloids defied and insulted the gods
in Olympus. They paid their court to Here and Artemis; moreover they even
seized and bound Ares, confining him in a brazen chamber for thirteen months.
No one knew where he was, and the intolerable chain would have worn him to
death, had not Eriboea, the jealous stepmother of the Aloids, revealed the place of his detention to
Hermes, who carried him surreptitiously away when at the last extremity. Ares
could obtain no atonement for such an indignity. Otos and Ephialtes even prepared to assault the gods in
heaven, piling up Ossa on Olympus and Pelion on Ossa, in order to reach them.
And this they would have accomplished had they been allowed to grow to their
full maturity; but the arrows of Apollo put a timely end to their short-lived
career.
The genealogy assigned to Kalyke, another daughter of Aeolus, conducts us from
Thessaly to Elis and Aetolia. She married Aethlius (the son of Zeus by Protogeneia, daughter of
Deucalion and sister of Hellen), who conducted a colony
out of Thessaly, and settled in the territory of Elis. He had for his son Endymion, respecting whom the Hesiodic Catalogue and the Eoiai related several wonderful things. Zeus granted him
the privilege of determining the hour of his own death, and even translated him
into heaven, which he forfeited by daring to pay court to Here: his vision in
this criminal attempt was cheated by a cloud, and he was cast out into the
underworld. According to other stories, his great beauty caused the goddess
Selene to become enamored of him, and to visit him by night during his
sleep:—the sleep of Endymion became a proverbial
expression for enviable, undisturbed, and deathless repose. Endymion had for issue (Pausanias gives us three different accounts, and Apollodorus a fourth,
of the name of his wife), Epeios, Etolus, Paeon, and a daughter Eurykyde.
He caused his three sons to run a race on the stadium at Olympia, and Epeios, being victorious, was rewarded by becoming his
successor in the kingdom: it was after him that the people were denominated Epeians.
Epeios had no male issue, and was
succeeded by his nephew Eleios, son of Eurykyde by the god Poseidon: the name of the people was
then changed from Epeians to Eleians. Etolus, the brother of Epeios,
having slain Apis, son of Phoroneus,
was compelled to flee from the country: he crossed the Corinthian gulf, and
settled in the territory then called Buretis, but to
which he gave the name of Aetolia.
The Mollonid Brothers
The son of Eleios,—or,
according to other accounts, of the god Helios, of Poseidon, or of Phorbas,—is Augeas, whom we find
mentioned in the Iliad as king of the Epeians or Eleiaus. Augeas was rich in all
sorts of rural wealth, and possessed herds of cattle so numerous, that the dung
of the animals accumulated in the stable or cattle-enclosures beyond all power
of endurance. Eurystheus, as an insult to Heracles,
imposed upon him the obligation of cleansing this stable: the hero, disdaining
to carry off the dung upon his shoulders, turned the course of the river Alpheios through the building, and thus swept the
encumbrance away. But Augeas, in spite of so signal a
service, refused to Heracles the promised reward, though his son Phyleus protested against such treachery, and when he found
that he could not induce his father to keep faith, retired in sorrow and wrath
to the island of Dulichion. To avenge the deceit
practiced upon him, Heracles invaded Elis; but Augeas had powerful auxiliaries, especially his nephews, the two Molionids (sons of Poseidon by Molione, the wife of Akteir), Eurytos, and Kteatos. These two miraculous brothers, of transcendant force, grew together,—having one body, but two
heads and four arms. Such was their irresistible might, that Heracles was
defeated and repelled from Elis: but presently the Eleians sent the two Mollonid brothers as Theori (sacred envoys) to the
Isthmian games, and Heracles, placing himself in ambush at Kleonae,
surprised and killed them as they passed through. For this murderous act the
Eleians in vain endeavored to obtain redress both at Corinth and at Argos;
which is assigned as the reason for the self-ordained exclusion, prevalent
throughout all the historical age, that no Eleian athlete would ever present himself as a competitor at the Isthmian games. The Molionids being thus removed, Heracles again invaded Elis,
and killed Augeas along with his children,—all except Phyleus, whom he brought over from Dulichion, and put in possession of his father's kingdom.
According to the more gentle narrative which Pausanias adopts, Augeas was not killed, but pardoned at the request of Phyleus. He was worshipped as a hero even down to the time
of that author.
It was on occasion of this conquest
of Elis, according to the old myth which Pindar has ennobled in a magnificent
ode, that Heracles first consecrated the ground of Olympia and established the
Olympic games. Such at least was one of the many fables respecting the origin
of that memorable institution.
It has already been mentioned that Etolus, son of Endymion, quitted
Peloponnesus in consequence of having slain Apis. The
country on the north of the Corinthian gulf, between the rivers Euenus and Achelous, received
from him the name of Aetolia, instead of that of Kuretis:
he acquired possession of it after having slain Doruis, Laodokus, and Polypoetes,
sons of Apollo and Phthia, by whom he had been well
received. He had by his wife Pronoe (the daughter of Phorbas) two sons, Pleuron and Kalyden, and from them the two chief towns in Aetolia were
named. Pleuron married Xanthippe,
daughter of Dorus, and had for his son Agenor, from whom sprang Portheus,
or Porthaon, and Demonike: Euenos and Thestius were children
of the latter by the god Ares.
Portheus had three sons, Agrius, Melas, and Eneus: among the
off spring of Thestius were Althea. and Leda,—names
which bring us to a period of interest in the legendary history. Leda marries Tyndareus and becomes mother of Helena and the Dioskuri; Althea marries Eneus,
and has, among other children, Meleager and Deianeira;
the latter being begotten by the god Dionysus, and the former by Ares. Tydeus also is his son, and the father of Diomedes: warlike
eminence goes hand in hand with tragic calamity among the members of this
memorable family.
We are fortunate enough to find the
legend of Althea and Meleager set forth at considerable length in the Iliad, in
the speech addressed by Phoenix to appease the wrath of Achilles. Eneus, king of Kalydon, in the
vintage sacrifices which he offered to the gods, omitted to include Artemis:
the misguided man either forgot her or cared not for her; and the goddess,
provoked by such an insult, sent against the vineyards of Eneus a wild boar of vast size and strength, who tore up the trees by the root, and
laid prostrate all their fruit. So terrible was this boar, that nothing less
than a numerous body of men could venture to attack him: Meleager, the son of Eneus, however, having got together a considerable number
of companions, partly from the Kuretes of Pleuron, at length blew him. But the anger of Artemis was
not yet appeased. She raised a dispute among the combatants respecting the
possession of the boar's head and hide—the trophies of victory. In this dispute
Meleager slew the brother of his mother Althea, prince of the Kuretes of Pleuron: these Kuretes attacked the Etolians, of Kalydon in order to avenge their chief. So long as
Meleager contended in the field the Etolians had the
superiority. But he presently refused to come forth, indignant at the curses
imprecated upon him by his mother. For Althea, wrung with sorrow for the death
of her brother, flung herself upon the ground in tears, beat the earth
violently with her hands, and implored Hades and Persephone to inflict death
upon Meleager,—a prayer which the unrelenting Erinnyes in Erebus heard but too well. So keenly did the hero resent this behavior of
his mother, that he kept aloof from the war. Accordingly, the Kuretes not only drove the Etolians from the field, but assailed the walls and gates of Kalydon,
and were on the point of overwhelming its dismayed inhabitants. There was no
hope of safety except in the arm of Meleager; but Meleager lay in his chamber
by the side of his beautiful wife Cleopatra, the daughter of Idas, and heeded not the necessity. While the shouts of
expected victory were heard from the assailants at the gates, the ancient men
of Etolia and the priests of the gods earnestly
besought Meleager to come forth, offering him his choice of the fattest land in
the plain of Kalydon. His dearest friends, his father Eneus, his sisters, and even his mother herself,
added their supplications—but he remained inflexible. At length the Kuretes penetrated into the town and began to burn it: at
this last moment, Cleopatra his wife addressed to him her pathetic appeal to
avert from her and from his family the desperate horrors impending over them
all. Meleager could no longer resist: he put on his armor, went forth from his
chamber, and repelled the enemy. But when the danger was over, his countrymen
withheld from him the splendid presents which they had promised, because he had
rejected their prayers, and had come forth only when his own haughty caprice
dictated.
Such is the legend of Meleager in
the Iliad: a verse in the second book mentions simply the death of Meleager,
without farther details, as a reason why Thoas appeared in command of the Aetolians
before Troy. Later poets both enlarged and altered the fable. The Hesiodic Eoiai, as well as the old poem called the Minyas, represented Meleager as having been slain by
Apollo, who aided the Kuretes in the war; and the
incident of the burning brand, though quite at variance with Homer, is at least
as old as the tragic poet Phrynichus, earlier than Eschylus.
The Fates, presenting themselves to Althea shortly after the birth of Meleager,
predicted that the child would die so soon as the brand then burning on the
fire near at hand should be consumed. Althea snatched it from the flames and
extinguished it, preserving it with the utmost care, until she became incensed
against Meleager for the death of her brother. She then cast it into the fire,
and as soon as it was consumed the life of Meleager was brought to a close.
We know from the censure of Pliny,
that Sophocles heightened the pathos of this subject by his account of the
mournful death of Meleager’s sisters, who perished
from excess of grief. They were changed into the birds called Meleagrides, and their never-ceasing tears ran together
into amber. But in the hands of Euripides whether originally through him or
not, we cannot tell—Atalanta became the prominent figure
and motive of the piece, while the party convened to hunt the Kalydonian boar was made to comprise all the distinguished
heroes from every quarter of Greece. In fact, as Heyne justly remarks, this event is one of the four aggregate dramas of Grecian heroic
life, along with the Argonautic expedition, the siege
of Thebes, and the Trojan war.
To accomplish the destruction of the
terrific animal which Artemis in her wrath had sent forth, Meleager assembled
not merely the choice youth among the Kuretes and Aetolians
(as we find in the Iliad), but an illustrious troop, including Castor and Pollux, Idas and Lynkeus, Peleus and Telamon, Theseus and Peirithous, Ankaeus and Kepheus,
Jason, Amphiaraus, Admetus, Eurytion and others. Nestor and Phoenix, who appear as
old men before the walls of Troy, exhibited their early prowess as auxiliaries
to the suffering Kalydonians. Conspicuous amidst them
all stood the virgin Atalanta, daughter of the
Arcadian Schoeneus; beautiful and matchless for
swiftness of foot, but living in the forest as a huntress and unacceptable to
Aphrodite. Several of the heroes were slain by the boar; others escaped, by
various stratagems: at length Atalanta first shot him
in the back, next Amphiaraus in the eye, and, lastly,
Meleager killed him. Enamored of the beauty of Atalanta,
Meleager made over to her the chief spoils of the animal, on the plea that she
had inflicted the first wound. But his uncles, the brothers of Thestius, took them away from her, asserting their rights
as next of kin, if Meleager declined to keep the prize for himself: the latter,
exasperated at this behavior, slew them. Althea, in deep sorrow for her
brothers and wrath against her son, is impelled to produce the fatal brand,
which she had so long treasured up, and consign it the flames. The tragedy
concludes with the voluntary death both of Althea and Cleopatra.
Interesting as the Arcadian
huntress, Atalanta, is in herself, she is an
intrusion, and not a very convenient intrusion, into the Homeric story of the Kalydonian boar-hunt, wherein another female, Cleopatra,
already occupied the foreground. But the more recent version became accredited
throughout Greece, and was sustained by evidence which few persons in those
days felt any inclination to controvert. For Atalanta carried away with her the spoils and head of the boar into Arcadia; and there
for successive centuries hung the identical hide and the gigantic tusks, of
three feet in length, in the temple of Athene Alea at
Tegea. Kallimachus mentions them as being there preserved,
in the third century before the Christian era; but the extraordinary value set
upon them is best proved by the fact that the emperor Augustus took away the
tusks from Tegea, along with the great statue of Athene Alea,
and conveyed them to Rome, to be there preserved among the public curiosities.
Even a century and a half afterwards, when Pausanias visited Greece, the skin
worn out with age was shown to him, while the robbery of the tusks had not been
forgotten. Nor were these relics of the boar the only memento preserved at
Tegea of the heroic enterprise. On the pediment of the temple of Athene Alea, unparalleled in Peloponnesus for beauty and grandeur,
the illustrious statuary Skopas had executed one of
his most finished reliefs, representing the Kalydonian hunt. Atalanta and Meleager were placed in the front
rank of the assailants; while Ankaeus, one of the Tegean heroes, to whom the
tusks of the boar had proved fatal, was represented as sinking under his
death-wound into the arms of his brother Epochos. And
Pausanias observes that the Tegeans, while they had
manifested the same honorable forwardness as other Arcadian communities in the
conquest of Troy, the repulse of Xerxes, and the battle of Dipaea against Sparta—might fairly claim to themselves, through Ankaeus and Atalanta, that they alone amongst all Arcadians had
participated in the glory of the Kalydonian boar-hunt. So entire and unsuspecting is the faith both of the Tegeans and of Pausanias in the past historical reality of
this romantic adventure. Strabo indeed tries to transform the romance into
something which has the outward semblance of history, by remarking that the
quarrel respecting the boar's head and hide cannot have been the real cause of
war between the Kuretes and the Aetolians; the true
ground of dispute (he contends) was probably the possession of a portion of
territory. His remarks on this head are analogous to those of Thucydides and
other critics, when they ascribe the Trojan war, not to the rape of Helen, but
to views of conquest or political apprehensions. But he treats the general fact
of the battle between the Kuretes and the Aetolians,
mentioned in the Iliad, as something unquestionably real and
historical—recapitulating at the same time a variety of discrepancies on the part
of different authors, but not giving any decision of his own respecting their
truth or falsehood.
In the same manner as Atalanta was intruded into the Kalydonian hunt, so also she seems to have been introduced into the memorable funeral
games celebrated after the decease of Pelias at Iolkos, in which she had no place at the time when the
works on the chest of Kypselus were executed. But her
native and genuine locality is Arcadia; where her race-course, near to the town
of Methydrion, was shown even in the days of
Pausanias. This race-course had been the scene of destruction for more than one
unsuccessful suitor. For Atalanta, averse to
marriage, had proclaimed that her hand should only be won by the competitor who
would surpass her in running: all who tried and failed were condemned to die,
and many were the persons to whom her beauty and swiftness, alike unparalleled,
had proved fatal. At length Meilanion, who had vainly
tried to win her affections by assiduous services in her hunting excursions,
ventured to enter the perilous lists. Aware that he could not hope to outrun
her except by stratagem, he had obtained, by the kindness of Aphrodite, three
golden apples from the garden of the Hesperides, which he successively let fall
near to her while engaged in the race. The maiden could not resist the
temptation of picking them up, and was thus overcome: she became the wife of Meilanion, and the mother of the Arcadian Parthenopaeus, one of the seven chiefs who perished in the
siege of Thebes.
DEIANIRA-DEATH OF HERAKLES
We have yet another female in the
family of Eneus, whose name the legend has
immortalized. His daughter Deianeira was sought in
marriage by the river Achelous, who presented himself
in various shapes, first as a serpent and afterwards as a bull. From the
importunity of this hateful suitor she was rescued by the arrival of Heracles,
who encountered Achelous, vanquished him and broke
off one of his horns, which Achelous ransomed by
surrendering to him the horn of Amaltheia, endued
with the miraculous property of supplying the possessor with abundance of any
food and drink which he desired. Herakles, being
rewarded for his prowess by the possession of Deianeira,
made over the horn of Amaltheia as his
marriage-present to Eneus. Compelled to leave the residence
of Eneus, in consequence of having in a fit of anger
struck the youthful attendant Eunomus, and
involuntarily killed him, Heracles retired to Trachin,
crossing the river Euenus at the place where the
Centaur Nessus was accustomed to carry over passengers for hire. Nessus carried
over Deianeira, but when he had arrived on the other
side, began to treat her with rudeness, upon which Heracles slew him with an
arrow tinged by the poison of the Lernaean hydra. The
dying Centaur advised Deianeira to preserve the
poisoned blood which flowed from his wound, telling her that it would operate
as a philtre to regain for her the affections of
Heracles, in case she should ever be threatened by a rival. Some
time afterwards the hero saw and loved the beautiful Iole,
daughter of Eurytos, king of Echali : he stormed the town, killed Eurytos, and made Iole his captive. The misguided Deianeira now had recourse to her supposed philter: she sent as a present to Heracles a
splendid tunic, imbued secretly with the poisoned blood of the Centaur.
Heracles adorned himself with the tunic on the occasion of offering a solemn
sacrifice to Zeus on the promontory of Kennon in
Euboea: but the fatal garment, when once put on, clung to him indissolubly,
burnt his skin and flesh, and occasioned an agony of pain from which he was
only relieved by death. Deianeira slew herself in
despair at this disastrous catastrophe.
We have not yet exhausted the
eventful career of Eneus and his family—ennobled
among the Etolians especially, both by religious
worship and by poetical eulogy—and favorite themes not merely in some of the
Hesiodic poems, but also in other ancient epic productions, the Alkmeonis and the Cyclic Thebais. By another marriage, Eneus had for his son Tydeus,
whose poetical celebrity is attested by the many different accounts given both
of the name and condition of his mother. Tydeus,
having slain his cousins, the sons of Melas, who were
conspiring against Eneus, was forced to become an
exile, and took refuge at Argos with Adrastus, whose
daughter Deipyle he married. The issue of this
marriage was Diomedes, whose brilliant exploits in the siege of Troy were not
less celebrated than those of his father at the siege of Thebes. After the
departure of Tydeus, Eneus was deposed by the sons of Agrios. He fell into
extreme poverty and wretchedness, from which he was only rescued by his
grandson Diomedes, after the conquest of Troy. The sufferings of this ancient
warrior, and the final restoration and revenge by Diomedes, were the subject of
a lost tragedy of Euripides, which even the ridicule of Aristophanes
demonstrates to have been eminently pathetic.
Though the genealogy just given of Eneus is in part Homeric, and seems to have been followed
generally by the mythographers, yet we find another
totally at variance with it in Hekataeus, which he doubtless borrowed from some
of the old poets: the simplicity of the story annexed to it seems to attest its
antiquity. Orestheus, son of Deucalion, first passed
into Aetolia, and acquired the kingdom: he was father of Phytios,
who was father of Eneus. Etolus was son of Eneus.
The original migration of Etolus from Elis to Aetolia—and the subsequent
establishment in Elis of Oxylus, his descendant in
the tenth generation, along with the Dorian invaders of Peloponnesus—were
commemorated by two inscriptions, one in the Agora of Elis, the other in that
of the Aetolian chief town, Thermum, engraved upon
the statues of Etelus and Oxylus respectively.
AMONG the ancient legendary genealogies, there was
none which figured with greater splendor, or which attracted to itself a higher
degree of poetical interest and pathos, than that of the Pelopids:
Tantalus, Pelops, Atreus and Thyestes, Agamemnon and
Menelaus and Egisthus, Helen and Clytemnestra,
Orestes and Elektra and Hermione. Each of these characters is a star of the
first magnitude in the Grecian hemisphere: each name suggests the idea of some
interesting romance or some harrowing tragedy: the curse, which taints the
family from the beginning, inflicts multiplied wounds at every successive
generation. So, at least, the story of the Pelopids presents itself, after it had been successively expanded and decorated by epic,
lyric, and tragic poets. It will be sufficient to touch briefly upon events
with which every reader of Grecian poetry is more or less familiar, and to
offer some remarks upon the way in which they were colored and modified by
different Grecian authors.
Pelops is the eponym or name-giver of the
Peloponnesus: to find an eponym for every conspicuous local name was the
invariable turn of Grecian retrospective fancy. The name Peloponnesus is not to
be found either in the Iliad or the Odyssey, nor any other denomination which
can be attached distinctly and specially to the entire peninsula. But we meet
with the name in one of the most ancient post-Homeric poems of which any
fragments have been preserved—the Cyprian Verses—a poem which many (seemingly
most persons) even of the contemporaries of Herodotus ascribed to the author of
the Iliad, though Herodotus contradicts the opinion. The attributes by which
the Pelopid Agamemnon and his house are marked out
and distinguished from the other heroes of the Iliad, are precisely those which
Grecian imagination would naturally seek in an eponymous superior wealth,
power, splendor and regality. Not only Agamemnon himself, but his brother
Menelaus, is “more of a king” even than Nestor or Diomedes. The gods have not
given to the king of the much-golden Mycenae greater courage, or strength, or
ability, than to various other chiefs; but they have conferred upon him a
marked superiority in riches, power and dignity, and have thus singled him out
as the appropriate leader of the forces. He enjoys this preeminence as
belonging to a privileged family and as inheriting the heaven-descended scepter
of Pelops, the transmission of which is described by
Homer in a very remarkable way. The scepter was made “by Hephaestus, who
presented it to Zeus; Zeus gave it to Hermes, Hermes to the charioteer Pelops; Pelops gave it to Atreus,
the ruler of men; Atreus at his death left it to Thyestes, the rich
cattle-owner; Thyestes in his turn left it to his nephew Agamemnon to carry,
that he might hold dominion over many islands and over all Argos”.
We have here the unrivalled wealth and power of the
“king of men, Agamemnon”, traced up to his descent from Pelops,
and accounted for, in harmony with the recognized epical agencies, by the
present of the special scepter of Zeus through the hands of Hermes; the latter being
the wealth-giving god, whose blessing is most efficacious in furthering the
process of acquisition, whether by theft or by accelerated multiplication of
flocks and herds. The wealth and princely character of the Atreids were proverbial among the ancient epic poets. Paris not only carries away Hellen, but much property along with her: the house of
Menelaus, when Telemachus visits it in the Odyssey, is so resplendent with gold
and silver and rare ornament, as to strike the beholder with astonishment and
admiration. The attributes assigned to Tantalus, the father of Pelops, are in conformity with the general idea of the
family—superhuman abundance and enjoyments, and intimate converse with the
gods, to such a degree that his head is turned, and he commits inexpiable sin.
But though Tantalus himself is mentioned, in one of the most suspicious
passages of the Odyssey (as suffering punishment in the under-world), he is not
announced, nor is anyone else announced, as father of Pelops,
unless we are to construe the lines in the Iliad as implying that the latter
was son of Hermes. In the conception of the author of the Iliad, the Pelopids are, if not of divine origin, at least a mortal
breed specially favored and ennobled by the gods—beginning with Pelops, and localized at Mycenae. No allusion is made to
any connection of Pelops either with Pisa or with
Lydia.
The legend which connected Tantalus and Pelops with Mount Sipylus may
probably have grown out of the Eolic settlements at Magnesia and Kyme. Both the Lydian origin and the Pisatic sovereignty of Pelops are adapted to times later than
the Iliad, when the Olympic games had acquired to themselves the general
reverence of Greece, and had come to serve as the religious and recreative center of the Peloponnesus—and when the Lydian
and Phrygian heroic names, Midas and Gyges, were the
types of wealth and luxury, as well as of chariot driving, in the imagination
of a Greek. The inconsiderable villages of the Pisatid derived their whole importance from the vicinity of Olympia: they are not
deemed worthy of notice in the Catalogue of Homer. Nor could the genealogy
which connected the eponym of the entire peninsula with Pisa have obtained
currency in Greece unless it had been sustained by pre-established veneration
for the locality of Olympia. But if the sovereign of the humble Pisa was to be
recognized as forerunner of the thrice-wealthy princes of Mycenae, it became
necessary to assign some explanatory cause of his riches. Hence the supposition
of his being an immigrant, son of a wealthy Lydian named Tantalus, who was the
offspring of Zeus and Plouto. Lydian wealth and
Lydian chariot-driving rendered Pelops a fit person
to occupy his place in the legend, both as ruler of Pisa and progenitor of the
Mycenaean Atreids. Even with the admission of these
two circumstances there is considerable difficulty, for those who wish to read
the legends as consecutive history, in making the Pelopids pass smoothly and plausibly from Pisa to Mycenae.
I shall briefly recount the legends of this great
heroic family as they came to stand in their full and ultimate growth, after
the localization of Pelops at Pisa had been tacked on
as a preface to Homer's version of the Pelopid genealogy.
Tantalus, residing near Mount Sipylus in Lydia, had two children, Pelops and Niobe. He was a man of immense possessions and preeminent
happiness, above the lot of humanity: the gods communicated with him freely,
received him at their banquets, and accepted of his hospitality in return.
Intoxicated with such prosperity, Tantalus became guilty of gross wickedness.
He stole nectar and ambrosia from the table of the gods, and revealed their
secrets to mankind: he killed and served up to them at a feast his own son Pelops. The gods were horror-struck when they discovered
the meal prepared for them: Zeus restored the mangled youth to life, and as
Demeter, then absorbed in grief for the loss of her daughter Persephone, had
eaten a portion of the shoulder, he supplied an ivory shoulder in place of it.
Tantalus expiated his guilt by exemplary punishment. He was placed in the
under-world, with fruit and water seemingly close to him, yet eluding his touch
as often as he tried to grasp them and leaving his hunger and thirst incessant
and unappeased. Pindar, in a very remarkable passage, finds this old legend
revolting to his feelings: he rejects the tale of the flesh of Pelops having been served up and eaten, as altogether
unworthy of the gods.
Niobe, the daughter of Tantalus, was
married to Amphion, and had a numerous and flourishing
offspring of seven sons and seven daughters. Though accepted as the intimate
friend and companion of Leto, the mother of Apollo
and Artemis, she was presumptuous enough to triumph over that goddess, and to
place herself on a footing of higher dignity, on account of the superior number
of her children. Apollo and Artemis avenged this insult by killing all the sons
and all the daughters: Niobe, thus left a childless
and disconsolate mother, wept herself to death, and was turned into a rock,
which the later Greeks continued always to identify on Mount Sipylus.
Some authors represented Pelops as not being a Lydian, but a king of Paphlagonia; by others it was said that
Tantalus, having become detested from his impieties, had been expelled from
Asia, by Ilus the king of Troy—an incident which served the double purpose of
explaining the transit of Pelops to Greece, and of
imparting to the siege of Troy by Agamemnon the character of retribution for
wrongs done to his ancestor. When Pelops came over to
Greece, he found Enomaus, son of the god Ares and Harpinna, in possession of the principality of Pisa,
immediately bordering on the district of Olympia. Enomaus,
having been apprized by an oracle that death would overtake him if he permitted
his daughter Hippodameia to marry, refused to give
her in marriage except to some suitor who should beat him in a chariot-race
from Olympia to the isthmus of Corinth; the ground here selected for the
legendary victory of Pelops deserves attention,
inasmuch as it is a line drawn from the assumed centre of Peloponnesus to its extremity, and thus comprises the whole territory with
which Pelops is connected as eponym. Any suitor
overmatched in the race was doomed to forfeit his life; and the fleetness of
the Pisan horses, combined with the skill of the
charioteer Myrtilus, had already caused thirteen
unsuccessful competitors to perish by the lance of Enomaus. Pelops entered the lists as a suitor: his prayers
moved the god Poseidon to supply him with a golden chariot and winged horses;
or according to another story, he captivated the affections of Hippodameia herself, who persuaded the charioteer Myrtilus to loosen the wheels of Enomaus before he started, so that the latter was overturned and perished in the race.
Having thus won the hand of Hippodameia, Pelops became Prince of Pisa. He put to death the
charioteer Myrtilus, either from indignation at his
treachery to Enomaus, or from jealousy on the score
of Hippodameia: but Myrtilus was the son of Hermes, and though Pelops erected a
temple in the vain attempt to propitiate that god, he left a curse upon his
race which future calamities were destined painfully to work out.
Pelops bad a numerous issue by Hippodameia: Pittheus, Troezen and Epidaurus, the eponyms of the two Argolic cities so called, are said to have been among them:
Atreus and Thyestes were also his sons, and his daughter Nikippe married Sthenelus of Mycenae, and became the mother
of Eurystheus. We hear nothing of the principality of
Pisa afterwards: the Pisatid villages became absorbed
into the larger aggregate of Elis, after a vain struggle to maintain their
separate right of presidency over the Olympic festival. But the legend ran that Pelops left his name to the whole peninsula:
according to Thucydides, he was enabled to do this because of the great wealth
which he had brought with him from Lydia into a poor territory. The historian
leaves out all the romantic interest of the genuine legends —preserving only
this one circumstance, which, without being better attested than the rest,
carries with it, from its common-place and prosaic character, a pretended
historical plausibility.
Besides his numerous issue by Hippodameia, Pelops had an illegitimate son named Chrysippus, of singular grace and beauty, towards whom he
displayed so much affection as to rouse the jealousy of Hippodameia and her sons. Atreus and Thyestes conspired together to put Chrysippus to death, for which they were banished by Pelops and
retired to Mycenae,—an event which brings us into the track of the Homeric
legend. For Thucydides, having found in the death of Chrysippus a suitable ground for the secession of Atreus from Pelops,
conducts him at once to Mycenae, and shows a train of plausible circumstances
to account for his having mounted the throne. Eurystheus,
king of Mycenae, was the maternal nephew of Atreus: when he engaged in any
foreign expedition, he naturally entrusted the regency to his uncle; the people
of Mycenae thus became accustomed to be governed by him, and he on his part
made efforts to conciliate them, so that when Eurystheus was defeated and slain in Attica, the Mycenaean people, apprehensive of an
invasion from the Herakleids, chose Atreus as at once
the most powerful and most acceptable person for his successor. Such was the
tale which Thucydides derived “from those who had learnt ancient Peloponnesian
matters most clearly from their forefathers”. The introduction of so much sober
and quasi-political history, unfortunately unauthenticated, contrasts
strikingly with the highly poetical legends of Pelops and Atreus, which precede and follow it.
Atreus and Thyestes are known in the Iliad only as
successive possessors of the scepter of Zeus, which Thyestes at his death
bequeaths to Agamemnon. The family dissensions among this fated race commence,
in the Odyssey, with Agamemnon the son of Atreus, and Egisthus the son of Thyestes. But subsequent poets dwelt upon an implacable quarrel
between the two fathers. The cause of the bitterness was differently
represented: some alleged that Thyestes had intrigued with the Cretan Aerope, the wife of his brother; other narratives mentioned
that Thyestes procured for himself surreptitiously the possession of a lamb
with a golden fleece, which had been designedly introduced among the flocks of
Atreus by the anger of Hermes, as a cause of enmity and ruin to the whole
family. Atreus, after a violent burst of indignation, pretended to be
reconciled, and invited Thyestes to a banquet, in which he served up to him the
limbs of his own son, and the father ignorantly partook of the fatal meal. Even
the all-seeing Helios is said to have turned back his chariot to the east in
order that he might escape the shocking spectacle of this Thyestean banquet:
yet the tale of Thyestean revenge—the murder of Atreus perpetrated by Egisthus, the incestuous offspring of Thyestes by his
daughter Pelopia is no less replete with horrors.
Homeric legend is never thus revolting. Agamemnon and
Menelaus are known to us chiefly with their Homeric attributes, which have not
been so darkly overlaid by subsequent poets as those of Atreus and Thyestes.
Agamemnon and Menelaus are affectionate brothers: they marry two sisters, the
daughters of Tyndareus king of Sparta, Clytemnestra
and Helen; for Helen, the real offspring of Zeus, passes as the daughter of Tyndareus. The “king of men” reigns at Mycenae; Menelaus
succeeds Tyndareus at Sparta. Of the rape of Helen,
and the siege of Troy consequent upon it, I shall speak elsewhere: I now touch
only upon the family legends of the Atreids. Menelaus,
on his return from Troy with the recovered Helen, is driven by storms far away
to the distant regions of Phoenicia and Egypt, and is exposed to a thousand
dangers and hardships before he again sets foot in Peloponnesus. But at length
he reaches Sparta, resumes his kingdom, and passes the rest of his days in
uninterrupted happiness and splendor: being moreover husband of the godlike
Helen and son-in-law of Zeus, he is even spared the pangs of death. When the
fullness of his days is past he is transported to the Elysian fields, there to
dwell along with “the golden-haired Rhadamanthus” in
a delicious climate and in undisturbed repose.
Far different is the fate of the king of men,
Agamemnon. During his absence, the unwarlike Egisthus,
son of Thyestes, had seduced his wife Clytemnestra, in spite of the special
warning of the gods, who, watchful over this privileged family, had sent their
messenger Hermes expressly to deter him from the attempt. A venerable bard had
been left by Agamemnon as the companion and monitor of his wife, and so long as
that guardian was at hand, Egisthus pressed his suit
in vain. But be got rid of the bard by sending him to perish in a desert
island, and then won without difficulty the undefended Clytemnestra. Ignorant
of what had passed, Agamemnon returned from Troy victorious and full of hope to
his native country; but he had scarcely landed when Egisthus invited him to a banquet, and there with the aid of the treacherous
Clytemnestra, in the very ball of festivity and congratulation, slaughtered him
and his companions “like oxen tied to the manger”. His concubine Cassandra, the
prophetic daughter of Priam, perished along with him by the hand of
Clytemnestra herself. The boy Orestes, the only male offspring of Agamemnon,
was stolen away by his nurse, and placed in safety at the residence of the Phokian Strophius.
For seven years Egisthus and
Clytemnestra reigned in tranquility at Mycenae on the throne of the murdered
Agamemnon. But in the eighth year the retribution announced by the gods
overtook them: Orestes, grown to manhood, returned and avenged his father by
killing Egisthus, according to Homer; subsequent
poets add, his mother also. He recovered the kingdom of Mycenae, and succeeded
Menelaus in that of Sparta. Hermione, the only daughter of Menelaus and Helen,
was sent into the realm of the Myrmidons in Thessaly, as the bride of
Neoptolemus, son of Achilles, according to the promise made by her father
during the siege of Troy.
Here ends the Homeric legend of the Pelopids, the final act of Orestes being cited as one of
unexampled glory. Later poets made many additions: they dwelt upon his remorse
and hardly earned pardon for the murder of his mother, and upon his devoted
friendship for Pylades; they wove many interesting
tales, too, respecting his sisters Iphigenia and Elektra and his cousin
Hermione,—names which have become naturalized in every climate and incorporated
with every form of poetry.
These poets did not at all scruple to depart from
Homer, and to give other genealogies of their own, with respect to the chief
persons of the Pelopid family. In the Iliad and
Odyssey, Agamemnon is son of Atreus. In Homer he is specially marked as
reigning at Mycenae; but Stesichorus, Simonides and Pindar represented him as
having both resided and perished at Sparta or at Amyklae.
According to the ancient Cyprian Verses, Helen was represented as the daughter
of Zeus and Nemesis: in one of the Hesiodic poems she was introduced as an
Oceanic nymph, daughter of Oceanus and Tethys. The genealogical discrepancies,
even as to the persons of the principal heroes and heroines, are far too
numerous to be cited, nor is it necessary to advert to them, except as they
bear upon the unavailing attempt to convert such legendary parentage into a
basis of historical record or chronological calculation.
The Homeric poems probably represent that form of the
legend, respecting Agamemnon and Orestes, which was current and popular among
the Eolic colonists. Orestes was the great heroic chief of the Eolic
emigration; he, or his sons, or his descendants, are supposed to have conducted
the Achaeans to seek a new home, when they were no longer able to make head
against the invading Dorians: the great families at Tenedos and other Eolic cities even during the historical era, gloried in tracing back
their pedigrees to this illustrious source. The legends connected with the
heroic worship of these mythical ancestors form the basis of the character and
attributes of Agamemnon and his family, as depicted in Homer, in which Mycenae
appears as the first place in Peloponnesus, and Sparta only as the second: the
former the special residence of “the king of men”; the latter that of his
younger and inferior brother, yet still the seat of a member of the princely Pelopids, and moreover the birth-place of the divine Helen.
Sparta, Argos and Mycenae are all three designated in the Iliad by the goddess
Here as her favorite cities; yet the connection of Mycenae with Argos, though
the two towns were only ten miles distant, is far less intimate than the
connection of Mycenae with Sparta. When we reflect upon the very peculiar
manner in which Homer identifies Here with the Grecian host and its leader,
—for she watches over the Greeks with the active solicitude of a mother, and
her antipathy against the Trojans is implacable to a degree which Zeus cannot
comprehend, and when we combine this with the ancient and venerated Heraeon, or temple of Here, near Mycenae, we may partly
explain to ourselves the preeminence conferred upon Mycenae in the Iliad and
Odyssey. The Heraeon was situated between Argos and
Mycenae; in later times its priestesses were named and its affairs administered
by the Argeians: but as it was much nearer to Mycenae
than to Argos, we may with probability conclude that it originally belonged to
the former, and that the increasing power of the latter enabled them to usurp
to themselves a religious privilege which was always an object of envy and
contention among the Grecian communities. The Eolic colonists doubtless took
out with them in their emigration the divine and heroic legends, as well as the
worship and ceremonial rites, of the Heraeon; and in
those legends the most exalted rank would be assigned to the close-adjoining
and administering city.
Mycenae maintained its independence even down to the
Persian invasion. Eighty of its heavy-armed citizens, in the ranks of Leonidas
at Thermopile, and a number not inferior at Plataea, upheld the splendid heroic
celebrity of their city during a season of peril, when the more powerful Argos
disgraced itself by a treacherous neutrality. Very shortly afterwards Mycenae
was enslaved and its inhabitants expelled by the Argeians.
Though this city so long maintained a separate existence, its importance had
latterly sunk to nothing, while that of the Thirian Argos was augmented very much, and that of the Dorian Sparta still more.
The name of Mycenae is imperishably enthroned in the
Iliad and Odyssey; but all the subsequent fluctuations of the legend tend to
exalt the glory of other cities at its expense. The recognition of the Olympic
games as the grand religious festival of Peloponnesus gave vogue to that
genealogy which connected Pelops with Pisa or Elis
and withdrew him from Mycenae. Moreover, in the poems of the great Athenian
tragedians, Mycenae is constantly confounded and treated as one with Argos. If
any one of the citizens of the former, expelled at the time of its final
subjugation by the Argeians, had witnessed at Athens
a drama of Aeschylus, Sophocles, or Euripides, or the recital of an ode of
Pindar, he would have heard with grief and indignation the city of his
oppressors made a partner in the heroic glories of his own. But the great
political ascendency acquired by Sparta contributed still farther to degrade
Mycenae, by disposing subsequent poets to treat the chief of the Grecian
armament against Troy as having been a Spartan. It has been already mentioned
that Stesichorus, Simonides and Pindar adopted this version of the legend: we
know that Zeus Agamemnon, as well as the here Menelaus, was worshipped at the
Dorian Sparta, and the feeling of intimate identity, as well as of patriotic
pride, which had grown up in the minds of the Spartans connected with the name
of Agamemnon, is forcibly evinced by the reply of the Spartan Syagrus to Gelon of Syracuse at
the time of the Persian invasion of Greece. Geron was
solicited to lend his aid in the imminent danger of Greece before the battle of
Salamis: he offered to furnish an immense auxiliary force, on condition that
the supreme command should be allotted to him. “Loudly indeed would the Pelopid Agamemnon cry out (exclaimed Syagrus in rejecting this application), if he were to learn that the Spartans had been
deprived of the headship by Geon and the Syracusans”.
Nearly a century before this event, in obedience to the injunctions of the Delphian oracle, the Spartans had brought back from Tegea
to Sparta the bones of “the Laconian Orestes”, as
Pindar denominates him: the recovery of these bones was announced to them as
the means of reversing a course of ill-fortune, and of procuring victory in
their war against Tegea. The value which they set upon this acquisition, and
the decisive results ascribed to it, exhibit a precise analogy with the
recovery of the bones of Theseus from Skyros by the Athenian Cimon shortly
after the Persian invasion. The remains sought were those of a hero properly
belonging to their own soil, but who had died in a foreign land, and of whose
protection and assistance they were for that reason deprived. And the
superhuman magnitude of the bones, which were contained in a coffin seven
cubits long, is well suited to the legendary grandeur of the son of Agamemnon.
THE earliest names in Laconian genealogy are an indigenous Lelex and a Naiad nymph Kleochareia. From this pair sprung
a son Eurotas, and from him a daughter Sparta, who
became the wife of Lacedaemon, son of Zeus and Taygete,
daughter of Atlas. Amyklas, son of Lacedaemon, had
two sons, Kynortas and Hyacinthus—the
latter a beautiful youth, the favorite of Apollo, by whose hand he was
accidentally killed while playing at quoits: the festival of the Hyacinthia, which the Lacedaemonians generally, and the Amyklaeans with special solemnity, celebrated throughout
the historical ages, was traced back to this legend. Kynortas was succeeded by his son Perieres, who married Gorgophone, daughter of Perseus, and had a numerous issue—Tyndareus, Ikarius, Aphareus, Leukippus, and Hippokoon. Some authors gave the genealogy differently,
making Perieres, son of Eolus, to be the father of Kynortas, and Ebalus son of Kynortas, from whom sprung Tyndareus, Ikarius and Hippokoon.
Both Tyndareus and Ikarius, expelled by their brother Hippokoon, were forced to seek shelter at the residence of Thestius, king of Kalydon, whose
daughter, Leda, Tyndareus espoused. It is numbered
among the exploits of the omnipresent Heracles, that he slew Hippokoon and his sons, and restored Tyndareus to his kingdom, thus creating for the subsequent Herakleidan kings a mythical title to the throne. Tyndareus, as
well as his brothers, are persons of interest in legendary narrative: he is the
father of Castor, of Timandra, married to Echemus, the hero of Tegea, and of Clytemnestra, married to
Agamemnon. Pollux and the ever-memorable Helen are
the offspring of Leda by Zeus. Ikarius is the father
of Penelope, wife of Odysseus: the contrast between her behavior and that of
Clytemnestra and Helen became the more striking in consequence of their being
so nearly related. Aphareus is the father of Idas and Lynkeus, while Leukippus has for his daughters, Phoebe and Ilaeira. According to one of the Hesiodic poems, Castor and Pollux were both sons of Zeus by Leda, while Helen
was neither daughter of Zeus nor of Tyndareus, but of
Oceanus and Tethys.
The brothers Castor and (Polydeukes, or) Pollux are no
less celebrated for their fraternal affection than for their great bodily
accomplishment: Castor, the great charioteer and horse-master; Pollux, the first of pugilists. They are enrolled both
among the hunters of the Kalydonian boar and among
the heroes of the Argonautic expedition, in which Pollux represses the insolence of Amykus,
king of the Bebrykes, on the coast of Asiatic Thrace—the
latter, a gigantic pugilist, from whom no rival has ever escaped, challenges Pollux, but is vanquished and killed in the fight.
The two brothers also undertook an
expedition into Attica, for the purpose of recovering their sister Helen, who
had been carried off by Theseus in her early youth, and deposited by him at Aphidna, while he accompanied Perithous to the underworld, in order to assist his friend in carrying off Persephone.
The force of Castor and Pollux was irresistible, and
when they redemanded their sister, the people of
Attica were anxious to restore her: but no one knew where Theseus had deposited
his prize. The invaders, not believing in the sincerity of this denial,
proceeded to ravage the country, which would have been utterly ruined, had not Dekelus, the eponymous of Dekeleia,
been able to indicate Aphidna as the place of
concealment. The indigenous Titakus betrayed Aphidna to Castor and Pollux, and
Helen was recovered: the brothers in evacuating Attica, carried away into
captivity Ethra, the mother of Theseus. In
after-days, when Castor and Pollux, under the title
of the Dioskuri, had come to be worshipped as
powerful gods, and when the Athenians were greatly ashamed of this act of
Theseus—the revelation made by Dekelus was considered
as entitling him to the lasting gratitude of his country, as well as to the
favorable remembrance of the Lacedaemonians, who maintained the Dekeleians in the constant enjoyment of certain honorary
privileges at Sparta, and even spared that dome in all their invasions of
Attica. Nor is it improbable that the existence of this legend had some weight
in determining the Lacedaemonians to select Dekelia as the place of their occupation during the Peloponnesian war.
The fatal combat between Castor and Polydeukes on the one side, and Idas and Lynkeus on the other, for the possession of the
daughters of Leucippus, was celebrated by more than one ancient poet, and forms
the subject of one of the yet remaining Idylls of Theocritus. Leucippus had
formally betrothed his daughters to Idas and Lynkeus; but the Tyndarids, becoming enamored of them,
outbid their rivals in the value of the customary nuptial gifts, persuaded the
father to violate his promise, and carried off Phoebe and Ilaeira as their brides. Idas and Lynkeus pursued them and remonstrated against the injustice: according to Theocritus,
this was the cause of the combat. But there was another tale, which seems the
older, and which assigns a different cause to the quarrel. The four had jointly
made a predatory incursion into Arcadia, and had driven off some cattle, but did
not agree about the partition of the booty—Idas carried off into Messenia a portion of it which the Tyndarids claimed as their
own. To revenge and reimburse themselves, the Tyndarids invaded Messenia,
placing themselves in ambush in the hollow of an ancient oak. But Lynkeus, endued with preternatural powers of vision,
mounted to the top of Taygetus, from whence, as he
could see over the whole Peloponnesus, he detected them in their chosen place
of concealment. Such was the narrative of the ancient Cyprian Verses. Castor
perished by the hand of Idas, Lynkeus by that of Pollux. Idas,
seizing a stone pillar from the tomb of his father Aphareus,
hurled it at Pollux, knocked him down and stunned
him; but Zeus, interposing at the critical moment for the protection of his
son, killed Idas with a thunderbolt. Zeus would have
conferred upon Pollux the gift of immortality, but
the latter could not endure existence without his brother: he entreated
permission to share the gift with Castor, and both were accordingly permitted
to live, but only on every other day.
The Dioskuri,
or sons of Zeus,—as the two Spartan heroes, Castor and Pollux,
were denominated,—were recognized in the historical days of Greece as gods, and
received divine honors. This is even noticed in a passage of the Odyssey, which
is at any rate a very old interpolation, as well as in one of the Homeric
hymns. What is yet more remarkable is, that they were invoked during storms at
sea, as the special and all-powerful protectors of the endangered mariner,
although their attributes and their celebrity seem to be of a character so
dissimilar. They were worshipped throughout most parts of Greece, but with
preeminent sanctity at Sparta.
Castor and Pollux being removed, the Spartan genealogy passes from Tyndareus to Menelaus, and from him to Orestes.
Originally it appears that Messene
was a name for the western portion of Laconia, bordering on what was called Pylos: it is so represented in the Odyssey, and Ephorus seems to have included it amongst the possessions
of' Orestes and his descendants. Throughout the whole duration of the Messenico-Dorian kingdom, there never was any town called
Messene: the town was first founded by Epaminondas, after the battle of
Leuctra. The heroic genealogy of Messenia starts from the same name as that of
Laconia—from the autochthonous Lelex: his younger
son, Polykaon marries Messene, daughter of the Argeian Triopas, and settles the
country. Pausanias tells us that the posterity of this pair occupied the
country for five generations; but he in vain searched the ancient genealogical
poems to find the names of their descendants. To them succeeded Perieres, son of Eolus; and Aphareus and Leukippus, according to Pausanias, were sons of Perieres.
Aphareus, after the death of his sons,
founded the town of Arene, and made over most part of
his dominions to his kinsman Neleus, with whom we
pass into the Pylian genealogy.
THE Arcadian divine or heroic
pedigree begins with Pelasgus, whom both Hesiod and Asius considered as an indigenous man, though Akusilaus the Argeian represented
him as brother of Argos and son of Zeus by Niobe,
daughter of Phoroneus. Akusilaus wished to establish a community of origin between the Argeians and the Arcadians.
Lykaon, son of Pelasgus and king of Arcadia, had, by different wives, fifty sons, the most savage,
impious and wicked of mankind: Maenalus was the
eldest of them. Zeus, in order that he might himself become a witness of their
misdeeds, presented himself to them in disguise. They killed a child and served
it up to him for a meal; but the god overturned the table and struck dead with
thunder Lykaon and all his fifty sons, with the
single exception of Nyktimus, the youngest, whom he
spared at the earnest intercession of the goddess Gaea (the Earth). The town
near which the table was overturned received the name of Trapezus (Tabletown).
This singular legend (framed on the
same etymological type as that of the ants in Aegina, recounted elsewhere)
seems ancient, and may probably belong to the Hesiodic Catalogue. But Pausanias
tells us a story in many respects different, which was represented to him in
Arcadia as the primitive local account, and which becomes the more interesting,
as he tells us that he himself fully believes it. Both tales indeed go to
illustrate the same point—the ferocity of Lykaon’s character, as well as the cruel rites which he practiced. The latter was the
first who established the worship and solemn games of Zeus Lykaeus:
he offered up a child to Zeus, and made libations with the blood upon the
altar. Immediately after having perpetrated this act, he was changed into a
wolf.
“Of the truth of this narrative
(observes Pausanias) I feel persuaded: it has been repeated by the Arcadians
from old times, and it carries probability along with it. For the men of that
day, from their justice and piety, were guests and companions at table with the
gods, who manifested towards them approbation when they were good, and anger if
they behaved ill, in a palpable manner: indeed at that time there were some,
who having once been men, became gods, and who yet retain their privileges as
such Aristaeus, the Cretan Britomartis,
Heracles son of Alkmena, Amphiaraus the son of Oikles, and Pollux and Castor besides. We may therefore believe that Lykaon became a wild beast, and that Niobe, the daughter of
Tantalus, became a stone. But in my time, wickedness having enormously
increased, so as to overrun the whole earth and all the cities in it, there are
no farther examples of men exalted into gods, except by mere title and from
adulation towards the powerful: moreover the anger of the gods falls tardily
upon the wicked, and is reserved for them after their departure from hence”.
Pausanias then proceeds to censure
those who, by multiplying false miracles in more recent times, tended to rob
the old and genuine miracles of their legitimate credit and esteem. The passage
illustrates forcibly the views which a religious and instructed pagan took of
his past time—how inseparably he blended together in it gods and men, and how
little he either recognized or expected to find in it the naked phenomena and
historical laws of connection which belonged to the world before him. He treats
the past as the province of legend, the present as that of history; and in
doing this he is more skeptical than the persons with whom he conversed, who
believed not only in the ancient, but even in the recent and falsely reported
miracles. It is true that Pausanias does not always proceed consistently with
this position: he often rationalizes the stories of the past, as if he expected
to find historical threads of connection; and sometimes, though more rarely,
accepts the miracles of the present. But in the present instance he draws a
broad line of distinction between present and past, or rather between what is
recent and what is ancient: his criticism is, in the main, analogous to that of Arrian in regard to the Amazons —denying their
existence during times of recorded history, but admitting it during the early
and unrecorded ages.
In the narrative of Pausanias, the
sons of Lykaon, instead of perishing by thunder from
Zeus, become the founders of the various towns in Arcadia. And as that region
was subdivided into a great number of small and independent townships, each
having its own eponym, so the Arcadian heroic genealogy appears broken up and
subdivided. Pallas, Orestheus, Phigalus, Trapezeus, Maenalus, Mantineus, and Tegeates, are all
numbered among the sons of Lykaon, and are all
eponyms of various. Arcadian towns.
The legend respecting Kalliste and Arkas, the eponym of
Arcadia generally, seems to have been originally quite independent of and
distinct from that of Lykaon. Eumelus,
indeed, and some other poets made Kallisto daughter
of Lykaon; but neither Hesiod, nor Asius, nor Pherekydes, acknowledged any relationship
between them. The beautiful Kallisto, companion of
Artemis in the chase, had bound herself by a vow of chastity. Zeus, either by
persuasion or by force, obtained a violation of the vow, to the grievous
displeasure both of Here and Artemis. The former changed Kallisto into a bear, the latter when she was in that shape killed her with an arrow.
Zeus gave to the unfortunate Kallisto a place among
the stars, as the constellation of the Bear: he also preserved the child Arkas, of which she was pregnant by him, and gave it to the Atlantid nymph Maia to bring up.
Arkas, when he became king, obtained from Triptolemus and communicated to his people the first
rudiments of agriculture; he also taught them to make bread, to spin, and to
weave. He had three sons—Azan, Apheidas, and Elatus: the first was the eponym of Azania, the northern
region of Arcadia; the second was one of the heroes of Tegea; the third was
father of Ischys (rival of Apollo for the affections
of Koronis), as well as of Epytus and Kyllen: the name of Epytus among the heroes of Arcadia is as old as the Catalogue in the Iliad.
Aleus, son of Apheidas and king of Tegea, was the founder of the celebrated temple and worship of
Athena Alea in that town. Lycurgus and Kepheus were his sons, Auge his
daughter, who was seduced by Heracles, and secretly bore to him a child: the
father, discovering what had happened, sent Auge to Nauplius to be sold into slavery: Teuthras,
king of Mysia in Asia Minor, purchased her and made
her his wife: her tomb was shown at Pergamum on the river Kaikus even in the time of Pausanias.
From Lykurgus,
the son of Aleus and brother of Auge,
we pass to his son Ankaeus, numbered among the
Argonauts, finally killed in the chase of the Kalydonian boar, and father of Agapenor, who leads the Arcadian
contingent against Troy,—(the adventurers of his niece, the Tegeatic huntress Atalanta, have already been touched
upon),—then to Echemus, son of Aöropus and grandson of the brother of Lycurgus, Kepheus. Echemus is the chief heroic ornament of Tegea. When Hyllus, the son of Herakles,
conducted the Herakleids on their first expedition
against Peloponnesus, Echemus commanded the Tegean troops who assembled along with the other
Peloponnesians at the isthmus of Corinth to repel the invasion: it was agreed
that the dispute should be determined by single combat, and Echemus,
as the champion of Peloponnesus, encountered and killed Hyllus.
Pursuant to the stipulation by which
they had bound themselves, the Herakleids retired,
and abstained for three generations from pressing their claim upon
Peloponnesus. This valorous exploit of their great martial hero was cited and
appealed to by the Tegeates before the battle of
Plataea, as the principal evidence of their claim to the second post in the
combined army, next in point of honor to that of the Lacedaemonians, and
superior to that of the Athenians: the latter replied to them by producing as
counter-evidence the splendid heroic deeds of Athens,—the protection of the Herakleids against Eurystheus,
the victory over the Kadmeians of Thebes, and the
complete defeat of the Amazons in Attica. Nor can there be any doubt that these
legendary glories were both recited by the speakers, and heard by the listeners,
with profound and undoubting faith, as well as with heart-stirring admiration.
One other person there is—Ischys, son of Elatus and
grandson of Arkas—in the fabulous genealogy of
Arcadia whom it would be improper to pass over, inasmuch as his name and adventures
are connected with the genesis of the memorable god or hero Esculapius,
or Asklepius. Koronis,
daughter of Phlegyas, and resident near the lake Boebeis in Thessaly, was beloved by Apollo and became
pregnant by him: unfaithful to the god, she listened to the propositions of Ischys son of Elatus, and
consented to wed him: a raven brought to Apollo the fatal news, which so
incensed him that he changed the color of the bird from white, as it previously
had been, into black. Artemis, to Avenge the wounded dignity of her brother,
put Koronis to death; but Apollo preserved the male
child of which she was about to be delivered, and consigned it to the Centaur Cheiron to be brought up. The child was named Asklepius or Aesculapius, and acquired, partly from the
teaching of the beneficent leech Cheiron, partly from
inborn and superhuman aptitude, a knowledge of the virtues of herbs and a
mastery of medicine and surgery, such as had never before been witnessed. He
not only cured the sick, the wounded, and the dying, but even restored the dead
to life. Kapaneus, Eriphyle,
Hippolytus, Tyndareus and Glaukus were all affirmed by different poets and logographers to have been endued by
him with a new life. But Zeus now found himself under the necessity of taking
precautions lest mankind, thus unexpectedly protected against sickness and
death, should no longer stand in need of the immortal gods: he smote Asclepius
with thunder and killed him. Apollo was so exasperated by this slaughter of his
highly-gifted son, that he killed the Cyclopes who had fabricated the thunder,
and Zeus was about to condemn him to Tartarus for
doing so; but on the intercession of Latona he
relented, and was satisfied with imposing upon him a temporary servitude in the
house of Admetus at Pherae.
Asclepius was worshipped with very
great solemnity at Trikka, at Kos, at Cnidus, and in
many different parts of Greece, but especially at Epidaurus, so that more than
one legend had grown up respecting the details of his birth and adventures: in
particular, his mother was by some called Arsinoe. But a formal application had
been made on this subject (so the Epidaurians told
Pausanias) to the oracle of Delphi, and the god in reply acknowledged that
Asclepius was his son by Koronis. The tale above
recounted seems to have been both the oldest and the most current. It is
adorned by Pindar in a noble ode, wherein however he omits all mention of the
raven as messenger —not specifying who or what the spy was from whom Apollo
learnt the infidelity of Koronis. By many this was
considered as an improvement in respect of poetical effect, but it illustrates
the mode in which the characteristic details and simplicity of the old fables
came to be exchanged for dignified generalities, adapted to the altered taste
of society.
Machaon and Podaleirius,
the two sons of Asclepius, command the contingent from Trikka,
in the north-west region of Thessaly, at the siege of Troy by Agamemnon. They
are the leeches of the Grecian army, highly prized and consulted by all the
wounded chiefs. Their medical renown was further prolonged in the subsequent
poem of Arktinus, the Iliu-Persis,
wherein the one was represented as unrivalled in surgical operations, the other
as sagacious in detecting and appreciating morbid symptoms. It was Podaleirius who first noticed the glaring eyes and
disturbed deportment which preceded the suicide of Ajax.
Galen appears uncertain whether
Asclepius (as well as Dionysus) was originally a god, or whether he was first a
man and then became afterwards a god; but Apollodorus professed to fix the
exact date of his apotheosis. Throughout all the historical ages the
descendants of Asclepius were numerous and widely diffused. The many families
or gentes called Asklepiads, who devoted themselves to the
study and practice of medicine, and who principally dwelt near the temples of
Asclepius, whither sick and suffering men came to obtain relief—all recognized
the god not merely as the object of their common worship, but also as their
actual progenitor. Like Solon, who reckoned Neleus and Poseidon as his ancestors, or the Milesian Hekataeus, who traced his origin
through fifteen successive links to a god—like the privileged gens at Pelion in Thessaly, who
considered the wise Centaur Cheiron as their
progenitor, and who inherited from him their precious secrets respecting the
medicinal herbs of which their neighborhood was full,—Asklepiads,
even of the later times, numbered and specified all the intermediate links
which separated them from their primitive divine parent. One of these
genealogies has been preserved to us, and we may be sure that there were many
such, as the Asklepiads were found in many different
places. Among them were enrolled highly instructed and accomplished men, such
as the great Hippocrates and the historian Ktesias,
who prided themselves on the divine origin of themselves and their gens—so much
did the legendary element pervade even the most philosophical and positive
minds of historical Greece. Nor can there be any doubt that their means of
medical observation must have been largely extended by their vicinity to a
temple so much frequented by the sick, who came in confident hopes of divine
relief, and who, whilst they offered up sacrifice and prayer to Aesculapius,
and slept in his temple in order to be favored with healing suggestions in
their dreams, might, in case the god withheld his supernatural aid, consult his
living descendants. The sick visitors at Kos, or Trikka,
or Epidaurus, were numerous and constant, and the tablets usually hung up to
record the particulars of their maladies, the remedies resorted to, and the
cures operated by the god, formed both an interesting decoration of the sacred
ground and an instructive memorial to the Asklepiads.
The genealogical descent of
Hippocrates and the other Asklepiads from the god
Asclepius is not only analogous to that of Hekataeus and Solon from their
respective ancestral gods, but also to that of the Lacedaemonians kings from
Heracles, upon the basis of which the whole supposed chronology of the
ante-historical times has been built, from Eratosthenes and Apollodorus down to
the chronologers of the present century. I shall
revert to this hereafter.
THE memorable
heroic genealogy of the Eakids establishes a fabulous
connection between Aegina, Salamis, and Pithia, which
we can only recognize as a fact, without being able to trace its origin.
Eakus was the son of Zeus, born of Aegina, daughter of Asopus, whom the god had carried off and brought into the
island to which he gave her name: she was afterwards married to Aktor, and had by him Menoetius,
father of Patroclus. As there were two rivers named Asopus,
one between Phlius and Sicyon, and another between
Thebes and Plataea—so the Aeginetans heroic genealogy
was connected both with that of Thebes and with that of Phlius:
and this belief led to practical consequences in the minds of those who
accepted the legends as genuine history. For when the Thebans, in the 68th
Olympiad, were hard-pressed in war by Athens, they were directed by the Delphian oracle to ask assistance of their next of kin:
recollecting that Thebe and Aegina had been sisters, common daughters of Asopus, they were induced to apply to the Aeginetans as their next of kin, and the Aeginetans gave them aid, first by sending to them their
common heroes, the Eakids, next by actual armed
force. Pindar dwells emphatically on the heroic brotherhood between Thebes, his
native city, and Aegina.
Eakus was alone in Aegina: to relieve him from this
solitude, Zeus changed all the ants in the island into men, and thus provided
him with a numerous population, who, from their origin, were called Mylmidons. By his wife Endeis,
daughter of Cheiron, Eakus had for his sons Peleus and Telamon: by the Nereid Psamathe, he had Phokus. A
monstrous crime had then recently been committed by Pelops,
in killing the Arcadian prince, Stymphalus, under a
simulation of friendship and hospitality: for this the gods had smitten all
Greece with famine and barrenness. The oracles affirmed that nothing could
relieve Greece from this intolerable misery except the prayers of Eakus, the most pious of mankind. Accordingly envoys from
all quarters flocked to Aegina, to prevail upon Eakus to put up prayers for them: on his supplications the gods relented, and the
suffering immediately ceased. The grateful Greeks established in Aegina the
temple and worship of Zeus Panhellenius, one of the
lasting monuments and institutions of the island, on the spot where Eakus had offered up his prayer. The statues of the envoys
who had come to solicit him were yet to be seen in the Eakeium,
or sacred edifice of Eakus, in the time of Pausanias:
and the Athenian Isocrates, in his eulogy of Evagoras,
the despot of Salamis in Cyprus (who traced his descent through Teukrus to Eakus), enlarges upon
this signal miracle, recounted and believed by other Greeks as well as by the Aeginetans, as a proof both of the great qualities and of
the divine favor and patronage displayed in the career of the Eakids. Eakus was also employed
to aid Poseidon and Apollo in building the walls of Troy.
Peleus and Telamom, the sons of Eakus,
contracting a jealousy of their bastard brother, Phokus,
in consequence of his eminent skill in gymnastic contests, conspired to put him
to death. Telamon flung his quoit at him while they were playing together, and
Peleus dispatched him by a blow with his hatchet in the back. They then
concealed the dead body in a wood, but Eakus, having
discovered both the act and the agents, banished the brothers from the island.
For both of them eminent destinies were in store.
While we notice
the indifference to the moral quality of actions implied in the old Hesiodic
legend, when it imputes distinctly and nakedly this proceeding to two of the
most admired persons of the heroic world —it is not less instructive to witness
the change of feeling which had taken place in the age of Pindar. That warm
eulogist of the great Eakid race hangs down his head
with shame, and declines to recount, though he is obliged darkly to glance at
the cause which forced the pious Eakus to banish his
sons from Aegina. It appears that Kallimachus, if we
may judge by a short fragment, manifested the same repugnance to mention it.
Telamon retired
to Salamis, then ruled by Kychreus, the son of
Poseidon and Salamis, who had recently rescued the island from the plague of a
terrible serpent. This animal, expelled from Salamis, retired to Eleusis in
Attica, where it was received and harbored by the goddess Demeter in her sacred
domicile. Kychreus dying childless left his dominion
to Telamon, who, marrying Periboea, daughter of Alkathoos, and grand-daughter of Pelops,
had for his son the celebrated Ajax. Telamon took part both in the chase of the Kalydonian boar and in the Argonautic expedition: he was also the intimate friend and companion of Heracles, whom he
accompanied in his enterprise against the Amazons, and in the attack made with
only six ships upon Laomedon, king of Troy. This last enterprise having proved
completely successful, Telamon was rewarded by Heracles with the possession of
the daughter of Laomedon, Hesione—who bore to him Teukros, the most distinguished archer amidst the host of
Agamemnon, and the founder of Salamis in Cyprus.
Peleus went to Pithia, where he married the daughter of Eurytion, son of Aktor, and
received from him the third part of his dominions. Taking part in the Kalydonian boar-hunt, he unintentionally killed his
father-in-law Eurytion, and was obliged to flee to Iolkos, where he received purification from Akastus, son of Pelias: the
danger to which lie became exposed by the calumnious accusations of the
enamored wife of Akastus has already been touched
upon in a previous section. Peleus also was among the Argonauts; the most
memorable event in his life however was his marriage with the sea-goddess
Thetis. Zeus and Poseidon had both conceived a violent passion for Thetis. But
the former, having been forewarned by Prometheus that Thetis was destined to
give birth to a son more powerful than his father, compelled her, much against
her own will, to marry Peleus; who, instructed by the intimations of the wise Cheiron, was enabled to seize her on the coast called
Sepias in the southern region of Thessaly. She changed her form several times,
but Peleus held her fast until she resumed her original appearance, and she was
then no longer able to resist. All the gods were present, and brought splendid
gifts to these memorable nuptials: Apollo sang with his harp, Poseidon gave to
Peleus the immortal horses Xanthus and Balius, and Cheiron presented a formidable spear, cut from an ash-tree
on Mount Pelion. We shall have reason hereafter to recognize the value of both
these gifts in the exploits of Achilles.
The prominent
part assigned to Thetis in the Iliad is well known, and the post-Homeric poets
of the Legend of Troy introduced her as actively concurring first to promote
the glory, finally to bewail the death of her distinguished son. Peleus, having
survived both his son Achilles and his grandson Neoptolemus, is ultimately
directed to place himself on the very spot where he had originally seized
Thetis, and thither the goddess comes herself to fetch him away, in order that
he may exchange the desertion and decrepitude of age for a life of immortality
along with the Nereids. The spot was indicated to
Xerxes when he marched into Greece by the Ionians who accompanied him, and his
magi offered solemn sacrifices to her as well as to the other Nereids, as the presiding goddesses and mistresses of the
coast.
Neoptolemus or
Pyrrhus, the son of Achilles, too young to engage in the commencement of the
siege of Troy, comes on the stage after the death of his father as the
indispensable and prominent agent in the final capture of the city. He returns
victor from Troy, not to Pithia, but to Epirus,
bringing with him the captive Andromache, widow of Hector, by whom Molossus is born to him. He himself perishes in the full
vigor of life at Delphi by the machinations of Orestes, son of Agamemnon. But
his son Molossus —like Fleance,
the son of Banquo, in Macbeth—becomes the father of
the powerful race of Molossian kings, who played so
conspicuous a part during the declining vigor of the Grecian cities, and to
whom the title and parentage of Eakids was a source
of peculiar pride, identifying them by community of heroic origin with genuine
and undisputed Hellenes.
The glories of
Ajax, the second grandson of Eakus, before Troy, are
surpassed only by those of Achilles. He perishes by his own hand, the victim of
an insupportable feeling of humiliation, because a less worthy claimant is
allowed to carry off from him the arms of the departed Achilles. His son Philaeus receives the citizenship of Athens, and the gens
or deme called Philaidae traced up to him its name
and its origin moreover the distinguished Athenians, Miltiades and Thucydides,
were regarded as members of this heroic progeny.
Teukrus escaped from the perils of the
siege of Troy as well as from those of the voyage homeward, and reached Salamis
in safety. But his father Telamon, indignant at his having returned without
Ajax, refused to receive him, and compelled him to expatriate. He conducted his
followers to Cyprus, where he founded the city of Salamis: his descendant Evagoras was recognized as a Teukrid and as an Eakid even in the time of Isocrates.
Such was the
splendid heroic genealogy of the Eakids,—family
renowned for military excellence. The Eakeion at
Aegina, in which prayer and sacrifice were offered to Eakus,
remained in undiminished dignity down to the time of Pausanias. This genealogy
connects together various eminent gentes in Achaia Phthioitis, in
Aegina, in Salamis, in Cyprus, and amongst the Epirotic Molossians. Whether we are entitled to infer from it
that the island of Aegina was originally peopled by Myrmidones from Achaia Phthiotis, as Muller imagines, I will not
pretend to affirm. These mythical pedigrees seem to unite together special
clans or gentes,
rather than the bulk of any community—just as we know that the Athenians
generally had no part in the Eakid genealogy, though
certain particular Athenian families laid claim to it. The intimate friendship
between Achilles and the Opuntian hero Patroclus—and
the community of name and frequent conjunction between the Locrian Ajax, son of Oileus, and Ajax, son of Telamon connect
the Eakids with Opus and the Opuntian Locrians, in a manner which we have no farther means
of explaining. Pindar too represents Menoetius,
father of Patroclus, as son of Aktor and Aegina, and
therefore maternal brother of Eakus.
THE most ancient name in Attic
archaeology, as far as our means of information reach, is that of Erechtheus,
who is mentioned both in the Catalogue of the Iliad and in a brief allusion of
the Odyssey. Born of the Earth, he is brought up by the goddess Athene, adopted
by her as her ward, and installed in her temple at Athens, where the Athenians
offer to him annual sacrifices. The Athenians are styled in the Iliad, “the
people of Erechtheus”. This is the most ancient testimony concerning
Erechtheus, exhibiting him as a divine or heroic, certainly a superhuman
person, and identifying him with the primitive germination (if I may use a
term, the Grecian equivalent of which would have pleased an Athenian ear) of
Attic man. And he was recognized in this same character, even at the close of
the fourth century before the Christian era, by the Butadae,
one of the most ancient and important Gentes at Athens, who boasted of him as their original
ancestor: the genealogy of the great Athenian orator Lycurgus, a member of this
family, drawn up by his son Abron, and painted on a
public tablet in the Erechtheion, contained as its
first and highest name, Erechtheus, son of Hephaestos and the Earth. In the Erechtheion, Erechtheus was
worshipped conjointly with Athene: he was identified with the god Poseidon, and
bore the denomination of Poseidon Erechtheus: one of the family of the Butadae, chosen among themselves by lot, enjoyed the
privilege and performed the functions of his hereditary priest. Herodotus also
assigns the same earth-born origin to Erechtheus but Pindar, the old poem
called the Danais, Euripides and Apollodorus—all name
Erichthonius, son of Hephaestos and the Earth, as the
being who was thus adopted and made the temple-companion of Athene, while
Apollodorus in another place identifies Erichthonius with Poseidon. The Homeric
scholiast treated Erechtheus and Erichthonius as the same person under two
names: and since, in regard to such mythical persons, there exists no other
test of identity of the subject except perfect similarity of the attributes,
this seems the reasonable conclusion.
We may presume, from the testimony
of Homer, that the first and oldest conception of Athens and its sacred
acropolis places it under the special protection, and represents it as the
settlement and favorite abode of Athene, jointly with Poseidon; the latter
being the inferior, though the chosen companion of the former, and therefore
exchanging his divine appellation for the cognomen of Erechtheus. But the
country called Attica, which, during the historical ages, forms one social and
political aggregate with Athens, was originally distributed into many
independent demes or cantons, and included, besides, various religious clans or
hereditary sects (if the expression may be permitted); that is, a multitude of
persons not necessarily living together in the same locality, but bound
together by an hereditary communion of sacred rites, and claiming privileges,
as well as performing obligations, founded upon the traditional authority of
divine persons for whom they had a common veneration. Even down to the
beginning of the Peloponnesian war, the demots of the
various Attic demes, though long since embodied in the larger political union
of Attica, and having no wish for separation, still retained the recollection
of their original political autonomy. They lived in their own separate
localities, resorted habitually to their own temples, and visited Athens only
occasionally for private or political business, or for the great public
festivals. Each of these aggregates, political as well as religious, had its
own eponymous god or hero, with a genealogy more or less extended, and a train
of mythical incidents more or less copious, attached to his name, according to
the fancy of the local exegetes and poets. The eponymous heroes Marathon, Dekelus, Kollinus, or Phlyus, had each their own title to worship, and their own
position as themes of legendary narrative, independent of Erechtheus, or
Poseidon, or Athena, the patrons of the acropolis common to all of them.
But neither the archaeology of
Attica, nor that of its various component fractions, was much dwelt upon by the
ancient epic poets of Greece. Theseus is noticed both in the Iliad and Odyssey
as having carried off from Crete Ariadne, the daughter of Minos — thus
commencing that connection between the Cretan and Athenian legends which we
afterwards find so largely amplified—and the sons of Theseus take part in the
Trojan war. The chief collectors and narrators of the Attic myths were, the
prose logographers, authors of the many compositions called Atthides,
or works on Attic archaeology. These writers—Hellanikus,
the contemporary of Herodotus, is the earliest composer of an Atthis expressly named, though Pherekydes also touched upon
the Attic fables — these writers, I say, interwove into one chronological
series the legends which either greatly occupied their own fancy, or commanded
the most general reverence among their countrymen. In this way the religious
and political legends of Eleusis, a town originally independent of Athens, but
incorporated with it before the historical age, were worked into one continuous
sequence along with those of the Erechtheids. In this
way, Kekrops, the eponymous hero of the portion of
Attica called Kekropia, came to be placed in the
mythical chronology at a higher point even than the primitive god or hero
Erechtheus.
KEKROPS, PROKNE AND PHILOMELA.
Ogyges is said to have reigned in Attica
1020 years before the first Olympiad, or 1796 years BC. In his time happened
the deluge of Deucalion, which destroyed most of the inhabitants of the
country: after along interval, Kekrops, an indigenous
person, half man and half serpent, is given to us by Apollodorus as the first
king of the country: he bestowed upon the land, which had before been called Akte, the name of Kekropia. In
his day there ensued a dispute between Athene and Poseidon respecting the
possession of the acropolis at Athens, which each of them coveted. First,
Poseidon struck the rock with his trident, and produced the well of salt water
which existed in it, called the Erechtheis: next came
Athene, who planted the sacred olive-tree ever afterwards seen and venerated in
the portion of Erechtheion called the cell of Pandrosus. The twelve gods decided the dispute; and Kekrops having testified before them that Athene had
rendered this inestimable service, they adjudged the spot to her in preference
to Poseidon. Both the ancient olive-tree and the well-produced by Poseidon were
seen on the acropolis, in the temple consecrated jointly to Athene and
Erechtheus, throughout the historical ages. Poseidon, as a mark of his wrath
for the preference given to Athens, inundated the Thriasian plain with water.
During the reign of Kekrops, Attica was laid waste by Carian pirates on the
coast, and by invasions of the Aonian inhabitants
from Boeotia. Kekrops distributed the inhabitants of
Attica into twelve local sections—Kekropia, Tetrapolis, Epakria, Dekeleia, Eleusis, Aphidna, Thorikus, Brauron, Kytherus, Sphettus, Kephisius, Phalerus. Wishing to
ascertain the number of inhabitants, he commanded each man to cast a single
stone into a general heap: the number of stones was counted, and it was found
that there were twenty thousand.
Kekrops married the daughter of Aktaeus, who (according to Pausanias’s version) had been
king of the country before him, and had called it by the name of Aktaea. By her he had three daughters, Aglaurus,
Erse and Pandrosus, and a son, Erysichthon.
Erysichthon died without issue, and Kranaus succeeded him, another autochthonous person and
another eponymous,—for the name Kranai was an old
denomination of the inhabitants of Attica. Kranaus was dethroned by Amphiktyon, by some called an
autochthonous man; by others, a son of Deucalion Amphityon in his turn was expelled by Erichthonius, son of Hephaestus and the Earth,—the
same person apparently as Erechtheus, but inserted by Apollodorus at this point
of the series. Erichthonius, the pupil and favored companion of Athene, placed
in the acropolis the original Palladium or wooden statue of that goddess, said
to have dropped from heaven: he was moreover the first to celebrate the
festival of the Panatherinae. He married the nymph Pasithea, and had for his son and successor Pandion. Erichthonius was the first person who taught the
art of breaking in horses to the yoke, and who drove a chariot and four.
In the time of Pandion,
who succeeded to Erichthonius, Dionysus and Demeter both came into Attica: the
latter was received by Keleos at Eleusis. Pandion married the nymph Zeuxippe,
and had twin sons, Erechtheus and Butes, and two
daughters, Prokne and Philomela. The two latter are
the subjects of a memorable and well-known legend. Pandion having received aid in repelling the Thebans from Tereus,
king of Thrace, gave him his daughter Prokne in
marriage, by whom he had a son, Itys. The beautiful
Philomela, going to visit her sister, inspired the barbarous Thracian with an
irresistible passion: he violated her person, confined her in a distant
pastoral hut, and pretended that she was dead, cutting out her tongue to
prevent her from revealing the truth. After a long interval, Philomela found
means to acquaint her sister of the cruel deed which had been perpetrated; she
wove into a garment words describing her melancholy condition, and dispatched
it by a trusty messenger. Prokne, overwhelmed with
sorrow and anger, took advantage of the free egress enjoyed by women during the
Bacchanalian festival to go and release her sister: the two sisters then
revenged themselves upon Tereus by killing the boy Itys, and serving him up for his father to eat: after the
meal had been finished, the horrid truth was revealed to him. Tereus snatched a hatchet to put Prokne to death: she fled, along with Philomela, and all the three were changed into
birds —Prokne became a swallow, Philomela a
nightingale, and Tereus an hoopoe. This tale, so
popular with the poets, and so illustrative of the general character of Grecian
legend, is not less remarkable in another point of view—that the great
historian Thucydides seems to allude to it as an historical fact, not however
directly mentioning the final metamorphosis.
After the death of Pandion, Erechtheus succeeded to the kingdom, and his
brother, Butes, became priest of Poseidon
Erichthonius, a function which his descendants ever afterwards exercised, the Butadae or Eteobutadae.
Erechtheus seems to appear in three characters in the fabulous history of
Athens—as a god, Poseidon Erechtheus—as a hero, Erechtheus, son of the
Earth—and now, as a king, son of Pandion: so much did
the ideas of divine and human rule become confounded and blended together in
the imagination of the Greeks in reviewing their early times.
THE DAUGHTERS OF ERECHTHEUS.
The daughters of Erechtheus were not
less celebrated in Athenian legend than those of Pandion. Prokris, one of them, is among the heroines seen by
Odysseus in Hades: she became the wife of Kephalus,
son of Deiones, and lived in the Attic dome of Thorikus. Kephalus tried her fidelity
by pretending that he was going away for a long period; but shortly returned,
disguising his person and bringing with him a splendid necklace. He presented
himself to Prokris without being recognized, and
succeeded in triumphing over her chastity. Having accomplished this object, he
revealed to her his true character: she earnestly besought his forgiveness, and
prevailed upon him to grant it. Nevertheless he became shortly afterwards the
unintentional author of her death: for he was fond of hunting, and staid out a
long time on his excursions, so that Prokris suspected him of visiting some rival. She determined to watch him by concealing
herself in a thicket near the place of his midday repose; and when Kephalus implored the presence of Nephele,
(a cloud) to protect him from the sun's rays, she suddenly started from her
hiding-place: Kephalus, thus disturbed, cast his
hunting-spear unknowingly into the thicket and slew his wife. Erechtheus
interred her with great magnificence, and Kephalus was tried for the act before the court of Areopagus,
which condemned him to exile.
Kreusa, another daughter of Erechtheus,
seduced by Apollo, becomes the mother of Ion, whom she exposes immediately
after his birth in the cave north of the acropolis, concealing the fact from
every one. Apollo prevails upon Hermes to convey the new-born child to Delphi,
where he is brought up as a servant of the temple, without knowing his parents. Kreusa marries Xuthus, son
of Eolus, but continuing childless, she goes with Xuthus to the Delphian oracle to inquire for a remedy. The
god presents to them Ion, and desires them to adopt him as their son: their son
Achaeus is afterwards born to them, and Ion and Achaeus become the eponyms of
the Ionians and Achaeans.
Oreithyia, the third daughter of Erechtheus,
was stolen away by the god Boreas while amusing herself on the banks of the Ilissus, and carried to his residence in Thrace. The two
sons of this marriage, Zetes and Kalais,
were born with wings: they took part in the Argonautic expedition, and engaged in the purrsuit of the Harpie: they were slain at Tenos by Heracles. Cleopatra,
the daughter of Boreas and Oreithyia, was married to Phineus, and had two sons, Plexippus and Pandion; but Phineus afterwards espoused a second wife, Idaea, the
daughter of Dardanus, who, detesting the two sons of the former bed, accused
them falsely of attempting her chastity, and persuaded Phineus in his wrath to put out the eyes of both. For this cruel proceeding he was
punished by the Argonauts in the course of their voyage.
On more than one occasion the
Athenians derived, or at least believed themselves to have derived, important
benefits from this marriage of Boreas with the daughter of their primeval hero:
one inestimable service, rendered at a juncture highly critical for Grecian
independence, deserves to be specified. At the time a of the invasion of Greece
by Xerxes, the Grecian fleet was assembled at Chalcis and Artemision in Euboea, awaiting the approach of the Persian force, so overwhelming in its
numbers as well by sea as on land. The Persian fleet had reached the coast of
Magnesia and the south-eastern corner of Thessaly without any material damage,
when the Athenians were instructed by an oracle “to invoke the aid of their
son-in-law”. Understanding the advice to point to Boreas, they supplicated his
aid and that of Oreithyia, most earnestly, as well by
prayer as by sacrifice, and the event corresponded to their wishes. A furious
north-easterly wind immediately arose, and continued for three days to afflict
the Persian fleet as it lay on an unprotected coast: the number of ships driven
ashore, both vessels of war and of provision, was immense, and the injury done
to the armament was never thoroughly repaired. Such was the powerful succor
which the Athenians derived, at a time of their utmost need, from their
son-in-law Boreas; and their gratitude was shown by consecrating to him a new
temple on the banks of the Ilissus.
The three remaining daughters of
Erechtheus—he had six in all—were in Athenian legend yet more venerated than
their sisters, on account of having voluntarily devoted themselves to death for
the safety of their country. Eumolpus of Eleusis was
the son of Poseidon and the eponymous hero of the sacred gens called the Eumolpids, in whom the principal functions,
appertaining to the mysterious rites of Demeter at Eleusis, were vested by
hereditary privilege: he made war upon Erechtheus and the Athenians, with the
aid of a body of Thracian allies; indeed it appears that the legends of Athens,
originally foreign and unfriendly to those of Eleusis, represented him as
having been himself a Thracian born and an immigrant into Attica. Respecting Eumolpus however and his parentage, the discrepancies much
exceed even the measure of license usual in the legendary genealogies, and some
critics, both ancient and modern, have sought to reconcile these contradictions
by the usual stratagem of supposing two or three different persons of the same
name. Even Pausanias, so familiar with this class of unsworn witnesses,
complains of the want of native Eleusinian genealogists, and of the extreme
license of fiction in which other authors had indulged.
ATHENS AND ELEUSIS
In the Homeric Hymn to Demeter, the
most ancient testimony before us,—composed, to all appearance, earlier than the
complete incorporation of Eleusis with Athens,—Eumolpus appears (to repeat briefly what has been stated in a previous chapter) as one
of the native chiefs or princes of Eleusis, along with Triptolemus, Diokles, Polyxeinus and Dolichus; Keleos is the king, or
principal among these chiefs, the son or lineal descendant of the eponymous
Eleusis himself. To these chiefs, and to the three daughters of Keleos, the goddess Demeter comes in her sorrow for the
loss of her daughter Persephone; being hospitably entertained by Keleos she reveals her true character, commands that a
temple shall be built to her at Eleusis, and prescribes to them the rites
according to which they are to worship her. Such seems to have been the ancient
story of the Eleusinians respecting their own
religious antiquities; Keleos, with Metaneira his wife, and the other chiefs here mentioned,
were worshipped at Eleusis, and from thence transferred to Athens as local gods
or heroes. Eleusis became incorporated with Athens, apparently not very long
before the time of Solon; and the Eleusinian worship of Demeter was then
received into the great religious solemnities of the Athenian state, to which
it owes its remarkable subsequent extension and commanding influence. In the Atticized worship of the Eleusinian Demeter, the Eumolpids and the Kerykes were
the principal hereditary functionaries: Eumolpus, the
eponym of this great family, came thus to play the principal part in the
Athenian legendary version of the war between Athens and Eleusis. An oracle had
pronounced that Athens could only be rescued from his attack by the death of
the three daughters of Erechtheus; their generous patriotism consented to the
sacrifice, and their father put them to death. He then went forth confidently
to the battle, totally vanquished the enemy, and killed Eumolpus with his own hand. Erechtheus was worshipped as a god, and his daughters as
goddesses, at Athens. Their names and their exalted devotion were cited along
with those of the warriors of Marathon, in the public assembly of Athens, by
orators who sought to arouse the languid patriot, or to denounce the cowardly
deserter; and the people listened both to one and the other with analogous
feelings of grateful veneration, as well as with equally unsuspecting faith in
the matter of fact.
Though Erechtheus gained the victory
over Eumolpus, yet the story represents Poseidon as
having put an end to the life and reign of Erechtheus, who was (it seems) slain
in the battle. He was succeeded by his son Kekrops II, and the latter again by his son Pandion two names
unmarked by any incidents, and which appear to be mere duplication of the
former Kekrops and Pandion,
placed there by the genealogizers for the purpose of
filling up what seemed to them a chronological chasm.
Apollodorus passes at once from
Erechtheus to his son Kekrops II, then to Pandion II, next to the four sons of the latter, Egeus, Pallas, Mins and Lykus. But the tragedians here insert the story of Xuthus, Kreusa and Ion; the
latter being the son of Creusa by Apollo, but given by the god to Xuthus, and adopted by the latter as his own. Ion becomes
the successor of Erechtheus, and his sons (Teleon, Hoples, Argades and Aigikores) become the eponyms of the four ancient tribes of
Athens, which subsisted until the revolution of Kleisthenes.
Ion himself is the eponym of the Ionic race both in Asia, in Europe, and in the
Aegean islands: Dorus and Achaeus are the sons of Kreusa by Xuthus, so that Ion is
distinguished from both of them by being of divine parentage. According to the
story given by Philochorus, Ion rendered such
essential service in rescuing the Athenians from the attack of the Thracians
under Eumolpus, that he was afterwards made king of
the country, and distributed all the inhabitants into four tribes or castes,
corresponding to different modes of life, — soldiers, husbandmen, goatherds,
and artisans. And it seems that the legend explanatory of the origin of the
festival Boedromia, originally important enough to
furnish a name to one of the Athenian months, was attached to the aid thus
rendered by Io.
THESEUS AND HIS ADVENTURES.
We pass from Ion to persons of far
greater mythical dignity and interest,—Egeus and his
son Theseus.
Pandion had four sons, Egeus,
Nisus, Lykus, and Pallas, between whom he divided his
dominions. Nisus received the territory of Megaris,
which had been under the sway of Pandion, and there
founded the seaport of Nistea. Lykus was made king of the eastern coast, but a dispute afterwards ensued, and he
quitted the country altogether, to establish himself on the southern coast of
Asia Minor among the Termilae, to whom he gave the
name of Lykians. Egeus, as
the eldest of the four, became king of Athens; but Pallas received a portion
both of the southwestern coast and the interior, and he as well as his
children appear as frequent enemies both to Egeus and
to Theseus. Pallas is the eponym of the deme Pallene,
and the stories respecting him and his sons seem to be connected with old and
standing feuds among the different demes of Attica, originally independent
communities. These feuds penetrated into the legend, and explain the story
which we find that Egeus and Theseus were not genuine Erechtheids, the former being denominated a
suppositious child to Pandion.
Egeus has little importance in the
mythical history except as the father of Theseus: it may even be doubted
whether his name is anything more than a mere cognomen of the god Poseidon, who
was (as we are told) the real father of this great Attic Heracles. As I pretend
only to give a very brief outline of the general territory of Grecian legend, I
cannot permit myself to recount in detail the chivalrous career of Theseus, who
is found both in the Kalydonian boar-hunt and in the Argonautic expedition —his personal and victorious
encounters with the robbers Siunis, Procrustes, Periphetes, Sciron and others — his valuable service in ridding his
country of the Krommyonian sow and the Maratonian bull—his conquest of the Minotaur in Crete, and
his escape from the dangers of the labyrinth by the aid of Ariadne, whom he
subsequently carries off and abandons—his many amorous adventures, and his
expeditions both against the Amazons and into the under-world along with Peirithous.
Thucydides delineates the character
of Theseus as a man who combined sagacity with political power, and who
conferred upon his country the inestimable benefit of uniting all the separate
and self-governing demes of Attica into one common political society. From the
well-earned reverence attached to the assertion of Thucydides, it has been
customary to reason upon this assertion as if it were historically authentic,
and to treat the romantic attributes which we find in Plutarch and Diodorus as if they were fiction superinduced upon this basis of fact. Such a view of the case is in my judgment erroneous.
The athletic and amorous knight-errant is the old version of the character—the
profound and long-sighted politician is a subsequent correction, introduced
indeed by men of superior mind, but destitute of historical warranty, and
arising out of their desire to find reasons of their own for concurring in the
veneration which the general public paid more easily and heartily to their
national hero. Theseus, in the Iliad and Odyssey, fights with the Lapithae against the Centaurs : Theseus, in the Hesiodic
poems, is misguided by his passion for the beautiful Egle,
daughter of Panopeus: and the Theseus described in
Plutarch’s biography is in great part a continuation and expansion of these
same or similar attributes, mingled with many local legends, explaining, like
the Fasti of Ovid, or the lost Aitia of Callimachus, the original genesis of prevalent religious and social customs.
Plutarch has doubtless greatly softened down and modified the adventures which
he found in the Attic logographers as well as in the poetical epics called Theseis. For in his preface to the life of Theseus, after
having emphatically declared that he is about to transcend the boundary both of
the known and the knowable, but that the temptation of comparing the founder of
Athens with the founder of Rome is irresistible, he concludes with the
following remarkable words: “I pray that this fabulous matter may be so far
obedient to my endeavors as to receive, when purified by reason, the aspect of
history: in those cases where it haughtily scorns plausibility and will admit
no alliance with what is probable, I shall beg for indulgent hearers, willing
to receive antique narrative in a mild spirit”. We see here that Plutarch sat
down, not to recount the old fables as he found them, but to purify them by
reason and to impart to them the aspect of history. We have to thank him for
having retained, after this purification, so much of what is romantic and
marvelous; but we may be sure that the sources from which he borrowed were more
romantic and marvelous still. It was the tendency of the enlightened men of
Athens, from the days of Solon downwards, to refine and politicize the
character of Thesuas : even Peisistratus expunged
from one of the Hesiodic poems the line which described the violent passion of
the hero for the fair Egle : and the tragic poets
found it more congenial to the feelings of their audience to exhibit him as a
dignified and liberal sovereign, rather than as an adventurous single-handed
fighter. But the logographers and the Alexandrine poets remained more faithful
to the old fables. The story of Hekale, the
hospitable old woman who received and blessed Theseus when he went against the Marathonian bull, and whom he found dead when he came back
to recount the news of his success, was treated by Callimachus : and Virgil
must have had his mind full of the unrefined legends when he numbered this
Attic Heracles among the unhappy sufferers condemned to endless penance in the
under-world.
Two however among the Theseian fables cannot be dismissed without some special
notice,—the war against the Amazons, and the expedition against Crete. The
former strikingly illustrates the facility as well as the tenacity of Grecian
legendary faith; the latter embraces the story of Daedalus and Minos, two of
the most eminent among Grecian ante-historical personages.
LEGEND OF THE AMAZONS.
The Amazons, daughters of Ares and Harmonia, are both early creations and frequent
reproductions of the ancient epic—which was indeed, we may generally remark,
largely occupied both with the exploits and sufferings of women, or heroines,
the wives and daughters of the Grecian heroes—and which recognized in Pallas
Athene the finished type of an irresistible female warrior. A nation of courageous,
hardy and indefatigable women, dwelling apart from men, permitting only a short
temporary intercourse for the purpose of renovating their numbers, and burning
out their right breast with a view of enabling themselves to draw the bow
freely,—this was at once a general type stimulating to the fancy of the poet
and a theme eminently popular with his hearers. Nor was it at all repugnant to
the faith of the latter—who had no recorded facts to guide them, and no other
standard of credibility as to the past except such poetical narratives
themselves — to conceive communities of Amazons as having actually existed in
anterior time. Accordingly we find these warlike females constantly reappearing
in the ancient poems, and universally accepted as past realities. In the Iliad,
when Priam wishes to illustrate emphatically the most numerous host in which he
ever found himself included, he tells us that it was assembled in Phrygia, on
the banks of the Sangarius, for the purpose of
resisting the formidable Amazons. When Bellerophon is
to be employed on a deadly and perilous undertaking, by those who indirectly
wish to procure his death, he is dispatched against the Amazons. In the Ethiopis of Arktinus, describing
the post-Homeric war of Troy, Penthesileia, queen of
the Amazons, appears as the most effective ally of the besieged city, and as
the most formidable enemy of the Greeks, succumbing only to the invincible
might of Achilles. The Argonautic heroes find the
Amazons on the river Thermadon, in their expedition
along the southern coast of the Euxine. To the same spot Heracles goes to
attack them, in the performance of the ninth labor imposed upon him by Eurystheus, for the purpose of procuring the girdle of the
Amazonian queen, Hippolyte; and we are told that they
had not yet recovered from the losses sustained in this severe aggression when
Theseus also assaulted and defeated them, carrying off their queen, Antiope. This injury they avenged by invading Attica,—an
undertaking (as Plutarch justly observes) "neither trifling nor
feminine," especially if according to the statement of Hellanikus,
they crossed the Cimmerian Bosporus on the winter ice, beginning their march
from the Asiatic side of the Pallus Maeotis. They overcame all the resistances and difficulties
of this prodigious march, and penetrated even into Athens itself, where the
final battle, hard-fought and at one time doubtful, by which Theseus crushed
them, was fought—in the very heart of the city.
Attic antiquaries confidently
pointed out the exact position of the two contending armies: the left wing of
the Amazons rested upon the spot occupied by the commemorative monument called
the Amazoneion; the right wing touched the Pnyx, the place in which the public assemblies of the
Athenian democracy were afterwards held. The details and fluctuations of the
combat, as well as the final triumph and consequent truce, were recounted by
these authors with as complete faith and as much circumstantiality as those of
the battle of Plataea by Herodotus. The sepulchral edifice called the Amazoneion, the tomb or pillar of Antiope near the western gate of the city—the spot called the Horkomosion near the temple of Theseus—even the hill of Areiopagus itself, and the sacrifices which it was customary to offer to the Amazons at
the periodical festival of the Theseia—were all so
many religious mementos of this victory; which was moreover a favorite subject
of art both with the sculptor and the painter, at Athens as well as in other
parts of Greece.
No portion of the ante-historical epic
appears to have been more deeply worked into the national mind of Greece than
this invasion and defeat of the Amazons. It was not only a constant theme of
the logographers, but was also familiarly appealed to by the popular orators
along with Marathon and Salamis, among those antique exploits of which their
fellow-citizens might justly be proud. It formed a part of the retrospective
faith of Herodotus, Lysias, Plato and Isocrates, and the exact date of the
event was settled by the chronologists. Nor did the Athenians stand alone in
such a belief. Throughout many other regions of Greece, both European and
Asiatic, traditions and memorials of the Amazons were found. At Megara, at Troezen, in Laconia near Cape Taenarus,
at Chaeronea in Boeotia, and in more than one part of Thessaly, sepulchers or
monuments of the Amazons were preserved. The warlike women (it was said), on
their way to Attica, had not traversed those countries, without leaving some
evidences of their passage.
Amongst the Asiatic Greeks the supposed
traces of the Amazons were yet more numerous. Their proper territory was
asserted to be the town and plain of Themiskyra, near
the Grecian colony of Amisus, on the river Thermodon, a region called after their name by Roman
historians and geographers. But they were believed to have conquered and
occupied in early times a much wider range of territory, extending even to the
coast of Ionia and Eolis. Ephesus, Smyrna, Kyme, Myrina, Paphos and Sinope were affirmed to have been founded and denominated by them. Some
authors placed them in Libya or Ethiopia; and when the Poetic Greeks on the
north-western shore of the Euxine had become acquainted with the hardy and
daring character of the Sarmatian maidens,—who were
obliged to have slain each an enemy in battle as the condition of obtaining a
husband, and who artificially prevented the growth of the right breast during
childhood,—they could imagine no more satisfactory mode of accounting for such
attributes than by deducing the Sarmatians from a
colony of vagrant Amazons, expelled by the Grecian heroes from their territory
on the Thermodon. Pindar ascribed the first
establishment of the memorable temple of Artemis at Ephesus to the Amazons. And
Pausanias explains in part the preeminence which this temple enjoyed over every
other in Greece by the widely diffused renown of its female founders,
respecting whom he observes (with perfect truth, if we admit the historical
character of the old epic), that women possess an unparalleled force of
resolution in resisting adverse events, since the Amazons, after having been
first roughly handled by Heracles and then completely defeated by Theseus,
could yet find courage to play so conspicuous a part in the defense of Troy
against the Grecian besiegers.
It is thus that in what is called
early Grecian history, as the Greeks themselves looked back upon it, the
Amazons were among the most prominent and undisputed personages. Nor will the
circumstance appear wonderful if we reflect, that the belief in them was first
established at a time when the Grecian mind was fed with nothing else but
religious legend and epic poetry, and that the incidents of the supposed past,
as received from these sources, were addressed to their faith and feelings,
without being required to adapt themselves to any canons of credibility drawn
from present experience. But the time came when the historians of Alexander the
Great audaciously abused this ancient credence. Amongst other tales calculated
to exalt the dignity of that monarch, they affirmed that after his conquest and
subjugation of the Persian empire, he had been visited in Hyrcania by Thalestris, queen of the Amazons, who admiring his warlike
prowess, was anxious to be enabled to return into her own country in a
condition to produce offspring of a breed so invincible. But the Greeks had now
been accustomed for a century and a half to historical and philosophical
criticism —and that uninquiring faith, which was
readily accorded to the wonders of the past, could no longer be invoked for
them when tendered as present reality. For the fable of the Amazons was here
reproduced in its naked simplicity, without being rationalized or painted over
with historical colors.
Some literary men indeed, among whom
were Demetrius of Skepsis, and the Mitylenaean Theophanes, the
companion of Pompey in his expeditions, still continued their belief both in
Amazons present and Amazons past; and when it becomes notorious that at least
there were none such on the banks of the Thermodon,
these authors supposed them to have migrated from their original locality, and
to have settled in the unvisited regions north of Mount Caucasus. Strabo, on
the contrary, feeling that the grounds of disbelief applied with equal force to
the ancient stories and to the modern, rejected both the one and the other. But
he remarks at the same time, not without some surprise, that it was usual with
most persons to adopt a middle course,—to retain the Amazons as historical
phenomena of the remote past, but to disallow them as realities of the present,
and to maintain that the breed had died out. The accomplished intellect of
Julius Cesar did not scruple to acknowledge them as having once conquered and
held in dominion a large portion of Asia; and the compromise between early,
traditional, and religious faith on the one hand, and established habits of
critical research on the other, adopted by the historian Arrian,
deserves to be transcribed in his own words, as illustrating strikingly the
powerful sway of the old legends even over the most positive-minded
Greeks:—“Neither Aristobulus nor Ptolemy (he observes), nor any other competent
witness, has recounted this visit of the Amazons and their queen to Alexander:
nor does it seem to me that the race of the Amazons was preserved down to that
time, nor have they been noticed either by any one before Alexander, or by
Xenophon, though he mentions both the Phasians and
the Kolchians, and the other barbarous nations which
the Greeks saw both before and after their arrival at Trapezus,
in which marches they must have met with the Amazons, if the latter had been
still in existence. Yet it is incredible to me that this race of women,
celebrated as they have been by authors so many and so commanding, should
never have existed at all. The story tells of Heracles, that he set out
from Greece and brought back with him the girdle of their queen Hippolyte; also of Theseus and the Athenians, that they
were the first who defeated in battle and repelled these women in their
invasion of Europe; and the combat of the Athenians with the Amazons has been
painted by Mikon, not less than that between the
Athenians and the Persians. Moreover Herodotus has spoken in many places of
these women, and those Athenian orators who have pronounced panegyrics on the
citizens slain in battle, have dwelt upon the victory over the Amazons as among
the most memorable of Athenian exploits. If the satrap of Media sent any
equestrian women at all to Alexander, I think that they must have come from
some of the neighboring tribes, practiced in riding and equipped in the costume
generally called Amazonian”.
There cannot be a more striking
evidence of the indelible force with which these ancient legends were worked
into the national faith and feelings of the Greeks, than these remarks of a
judicious historian upon the fable of the Amazons. Probably if any plausible
mode of rationalizing it, and of transforming it into a quasi-political event,
had been offered to Arrian, he would have been better
pleased to adopt such a middle term, and would have rested comfortably in the
supposition that he believed the legend in its true meaning, while his less
inquiring countrymen were imposed upon by the exaggerations of poets. But as
the story was presented to him plain end unvarnished, either for acceptance or
rejection, his feelings as a patriot and a religious man prevented him from
applying to the past such tests of credibility as his untrammeled reason
acknowledged to be paramount in regard to the present. When we see moreover how
much his belief was strengthened, and all tendency to skepticism shut out by
the familiarity of his eye and memory with sculptured or painted Amazons—we may
calculate the irresistible force of this sensible demonstration on the
convictions of the unlettered public, at once more deeply retentive of passive
impressions, and unaccustomed to the countervailing habit of rational
investigation into evidence. Had the march of an army of warlike women, from
the Thermodon or the Tanais into the heart of Attica, been recounted to Arrian as
an incident belonging to the time of Alexander the Great, he would have
rejected it no less emphatically than Strabo; but cast back as it was into an
undefined past, it took rank among the hallowed traditions of divine or heroic
antiquity, — gratifying to extol by rhetoric, but repulsive to scrutinize in
argument.
To understand the adventures of
Theseus in Crete, it will be necessary to touch briefly upon Mines and the
Cretan heroics genealogy.
Minos and Rhadamanthus,
according to Homer, are sons of Zeus, by Europe, daughter of the
widely-celebrated Phoenix, born in Crete. Minos is the father of Deucalion,
whose son Idomeneus, in conjunction with of Zeus,
conducts the Cretan troops to the host of Agamemnon before Troy. Minos is ruler
of Knossos, and familiar companion of the great Zeus. He is spoken of as
holding guardianship in Crete not necessarily meaning the whole of the island :
he is farther decorated with a golden scepter, and constituted judge over the
dead in the under-world to settle their disputes, in which function Odysseus
finds him —this however by a passage of comparatively late interpolation into
the Odyssey. He also had a daughter named Ariadne, for whom the artist Daedalus
fabricated in the town of Knossos the representation of a complicated dance,
and who was ultimately carried off by Theseus: she died in the island of Dia, deserted by Theseus and betrayed by Dionysos to the fatal wrath of Artemis. Rhadamanthus seems to approach to Minos both in judicial functions and posthumous dignity.
He is conveyed expressly to Euboea, by the semi-divine sea-carriers the
Phaeacians, to inspect the gigantic corpse of the earth-born Tityus the longest voyage they ever undertook. He is
moreover after death promoted to an abode of undisturbed bliss in the Elysian
plain at the extremity of the earth.
According to poets later than Homer,
Europe is brought over by Zeus from Phoenicia to Crete, where she bears to him
three sons, Mines, Rhadamanthus and Sarpedon. The latter leaves Crete and settles in Lycia, the
population of which, as well as that of many other portions of Asia Minor, is
connected by various mythical genealogies with Crete, though the Sarpedon of the Iliad has no connection with Crete, and is
not the son of Europe. Sarpedon having become king of
Lycia, was favored by his father, Zeus, with permission to live for three
generations. At the same time the youthful Miletus, a favorite of Sarpedon, quitted Crete, and established the city which bore
his name on the coast of Asia Minor. Rhadamanthus became sovereign of and lawgiver among the islands in the Aegean: he
subsequently went to Boeotia, where he married the widowed Alcmene, mother of
Heracles.
Europe finds in Crete a king Asterius, who marries her and adopts her children by Zeus:
this Asterius is the son of Kres,
the eponym of the island, or (according to another genealogy by which it was
attempted to be made out that Mines was of Arian race) he was a son of the
daughter of Kres by Tektamus,
the son of Dorus, who had migrated into the island
from Greece.
Minos married Pasiphae, daughter of
the god Helios and Perseis, by whom he had Katreus, Deucalion, Glaukus, Androgeos,—names marked in the legendary narrative,—
together with several daughters, among whom were Ariadne and Phaedra. He
offended Poseidon by neglecting to fulfill a solemnly-made vow, and the
displeased god afflicted his wife Pasiphae with a monstrous passion for a bull.
The great artist Daedalus, son of Eupalamus, a
fugitive from Athens, became the confidant of this amour, from which sprang the
Minotaur, a creature half man and half bull. This Minotaur was imprisoned by
Minos in the labyrinth, an inextricable enclosure constructed by Dedalus for that express purpose, by order of Minos.
Minos acquired great nautical power,
and expelled the Carian inhabitants from many of the islands of the Aegean,
which he placed under the government of his sons on the footing of tributaries.
He undertook several expeditions against various places on the coast—one
against Nisus, the son of Pandion, king of Megara,
who had amongst the hair of his head one peculiar lock of a purple color: an
oracle had pronounced that his life and reign would never be in danger so long
as he preserved this precious lock. The city would have remained inexpugnable,
if Scylla, the daughter of Nisus, had not conceived a violent passion for
Minos. While her father was asleep, she cut off the lock on which his safety
hung, so that the Cretan king soon became victorious. Instead of performing his
promise to carry Scylla away with him to Crete, he cast her from the stern of
his vessel into the sea: both Scylla and Nisus were changed into birds.
Androgeos, son of Minos having displayed such
rare qualities as to vanquish all his competitors at the Panathenaic festival
in Athens, was sent by Egeus the Athenian king to
contend against the bull of Marathon,—an enterprise in which he perished, and
Minos made war upon Athens to avenge his death. He was for a long time unable
to take the city: at length he prayed to his father Zeus to aid him in
obtaining redress from the Athenians, and Zeus sent upon them pestilence and
famine. In vain did they endeavor to avert these calamities by offering up as
propitiatory sacrifices the four daughters of Hyacinthus.
Their sufferings still continued, and the oracle directed them to submit to any
terms which Minos might exact. He required that they should send to Crete a
tribute of seven youths and seven maidens, periodically, to be devoured by the
Minotaur,—offered to him in a labyrinth constructed by Dadalus,
including countless different passages, out of which no person could escape.
Every ninth year this offering was
to be dispatched. The more common story was, that the youths and maidens thus destined
to destruction were selected by lot—but the logographer Hellanikus said that Minos came to Athens and chose them himself. The third period for
dispatching the victims had arrived, and Athens was plunged in the deepest
affliction, when Theseus determined to devote himself as one of them, and
either to terminate the sanguinary tribute or to perish. He prayed to Poseidon
for help, and the Delphian god assured him that
Aphrodite would sustain and extricate him. On arriving at Knossos he was
fortunate enough to captivate the affections of Ariadne, the daughter of Minos,
who supplied him with a sword and a duo of thread. With the former he contrived
to kill the Minotaur, the latter served to guide his footsteps in escaping from
the labyrinth. Having accomplished this triumph, he left Crete with his ship
and companions unhurt, carrying off Ariadne, whom however he soon abandoned on
the island of Naxos. On his way borne to Athens, he stopped at Delos, where he
offered a grateful sacrifice to Apollo for his escape, and danced along with
the young men and maidens whom he had rescued from the Minotaur, a dance called
the Geranus, imitated from the twists and
convolutions of the Cretan labyrinth. It had been concerted with his father Egeus, that if he succeeded in his
enterprise against the Minotaur, he should on his return hoist white sails in
his ship in place of the black canvas which she habitually carried when
employed on this mournful embassy. But Theseus forgot to make the change of
sails; so that Egeus, seeing the ship return with her
equipment of mourning unaltered, was impressed with the sorrowful conviction
that his son had perished, and cast himself into the sea. The ship which made
this voyage was preserved by the Athenians with careful solicitude, being
constantly repaired with new timbers, down to the time of the Phalerian Demetrius: every year she was sent from Athens to
Delos with a solemn sacrifice and specially-nominated envoys. The priest of
Apollo decked her stern with garlands before she quitted the port, and during
the time which elapsed until her return, the city was understood to abstain
from all acts carrying with them public impurity, so that it was unlawful to
put to death any person even under formal sentence by the dikastery.
This accidental circumstance becomes especially memorable, from its having
postponed for thirty days the death of the lamented Socrates.
The legend respecting Theseus, and
his heroic rescue of the seven noble youths and maidens from the jaws of the
Minotaur, was thus both commemorated and certified to the Athenian public, by
the annual holy ceremony and by the unquestioned identity of the vessel
employed in it. There were indeed many varieties in the mode of narrating the
incident; and some of the Attic logographers tried to rationalize the fable by
transforming the Minotaur into a general or a powerful athlete, named Taurus,
whom Theseus vanquished in Crete. But this altered version never overbore the
old fanciful character of the tale as maintained by the poets. A great number
of other religious ceremonies and customs, as well as several chapels or sacred
enclosures in honor of different heroes, were connected with different acts and
special ordinances of Theseus. To every Athenian who took part in the festivals
of the Oschophoria, the Pyanepsia,
or the Kybernesia, the name of this great hero was
familiar, and the motives for offering to him solemn worship at his own special
festival of the Theseia, became evident and
impressive.
The same Athenian legends which
ennobled and decorated the character of Theseus, painted in repulsive colors
the attributes of Minos; and the traits of the old Homeric comrade of Zeus were
buried under those of the conqueror and oppressor of Athens. His history like
that of the other legendary personages of Greece, consists almost entirely of a
string of family romances and tragedies. His son Katreus,
father of Aerope, wife of Atreus, was apprized by an
oracle that he would perish by the hand of one of his own children: he
accordingly sent them out of the island, and Althemenes,
his son, established himself in Rhodes. Katreus having become old, and fancying that he had outlived the warning of the oracle,
went over to Rhodes to see Althemenes. In an
accidental dispute which arose between his attendants and the islanders, Althemenes inadvertently took part and slew his father
without knowing him. Glaukus, the youngest son of
Minos, pursuing a mouse, fell into a reservoir of honey and was drowned. No one
knew what had become of him, and his father was inconsolable; at length the Argeian Polyeidus, a prophet
wonderfully endowed by the gods, both discovered the boy and restored him to
life, to the exceeding joy of Minos.
The latter at last found his death
in an eager attempt to overtake and punish Thedalus.
This great artist, the eponymous hero of the Attic gens or deme called the Dedalids, and the descendant of Erechtheus through Metion, had been tried at the tribunal of Areiopagus and banished for killing his nephew Talos, whose rapidly improving skill excited his envy. He
took refuge in Crete, where he acquired the confidence of Minos, and was
employed (as has been already mentioned) in constructing the labyrinth;
subsequently however he fell under the displeasure of Minos, and was confined
as a close prisoner in the inextricable windings of his own edifice. His
unrivalled skill and resource however did not forsake him. He manufactured
wings both for himself and for his son Ikarus, with
which they flew over the sea: the father arrived safely in Sicily at Kamikus, the residence of the Sikulian king Kokalus, but the son, disdaining paternal
example and admonition, flew so high that his wings were melted by the sun and
he fell into the sea, which from him was called the Ikarian sea.
Dedalus remained for some time in Sicily,
leaving in various parts of the island many prodigious evidences of mechanical
and architectural skill. At length Minos bent upon regaining possession of his
person, undertook an expedition against Kokalus with
a numerous fleet and army. Kokalus affecting
readiness to deliver up the fugitive, and receiving Minos with apparent
friendship, ordered a bath to be prepared for him by his three daughters, who,
eager to protect Dedalus at any price, drowned the
Cretan king in the bath with hot water. Many of the Cretans who had accompanied
him remained in Sicily and founded the town of Minoa, which they denominated
after him. But not long afterwards Zeus roused all the inhabitants of Crete
(except the towns of Polichna and Presus)
to undertake with one accord an expedition against Kamikus for the purpose of avenging the death of Minos. They besieged Kamikus in vain for five years, until at last famine compelled them to return. On their way along
the coast of Italy, in the Gulf of Tarentum, a terrible storm destroyed their
fleet and obliged them to settle permanently in the country: they founded Hyria with other cities, and became Messapian Iapygians. Other settlers, for the most part Greeks,
immigrated into Crete to the spots which this movement had left vacant, and in
the second generation after Minos occurred the Trojan war. The departed Minos
was exceedingly offended with the Cretans for cooperating in avenging the
injury to Menelaus, since the Greeks generally had lent no aid to the Cretans in
their expedition against the town of Kamikus. He sent
upon Crete, after the return of Idomeneus from Troy,
such terrible visitations of famine and pestilence, that the population again
died out or expatriated, and was again renovated by fresh immigrations. The
intolerable suffering thus brought upon the Cretans by the anger of Minos, for
having cooperated in the general Grecian aid to Menelaus, was urged by them to
the Greeks as the reason why they could take no part in resisting the invasion
of Xerxes; and it is even pretended that they were advised and encouraged to
adopt this ground of excuse by the Delphian oracle.
Such is the Minos of the poets and
logographers, with his legendary and romantic attributes: the familiar comrade
of the great Zeus,—the judge among the dead in Hades,—the husband of Pasiphae,
daughter of the god Helios,—the father of the goddess Ariadne, as well as of Androgeos, who perishes and is worshipped at Athens, and of
the boy Glaukus, who is miraculously restored to life
by a prophet,—the person beloved by Scylla, and the amorous pursuer of the
nymph or goddess Britomartis,—the proprietor of the
Labyrinth and of the Minotaur, and the exacter of a periodical tribute of
youths and maidens from Athens as food for this monster,—lastly, the follower
of the fugitive artist Dedalus to Kamikus,
and the victim of the three ill-disposed daughters of Kokalus in a bath. With this strongly-marked portrait, the Minos of Thucydides and
Aristotle has scarcely anything in common except the name. He is the first to
acquire Thalassocracy, or command of the Aegean sea:
he expels the Carian inhabitants from the Cyclades islands, and sends thither
fresh colonists under his own sons; he puts down piracy, in order that he may
receive his tribute regularly; lastly, he attempts to conquer Sicily, but fails
in the enterprise and perishes. Here we have conjectures, derived from the
analogy of the Athenian maritime empire in the historical times, substituted in
place of the fabulous incidents, and attached to the name of Minos.
In the fable, a tribute of seven
youths and seven maidens is paid to him periodically by the Athenians; in the
historicized narrative this character of a tribute-collector is preserved, but
the tribute is money collected from dependent islands; and Aristotle points out
to us how conveniently Crete is situated to exercise empire over the Aegean.
The expedition against Kamikus, instead of being
directed to the recovery of the fugitive Dedalus, is
an attempt on the part of the great thalassocrat to
conquer Sicily. Herodotus gives us generally the same view of the character of
Minos as a great maritime king, but his notice of the expedition against Kamicus includes the mention of Dedalus as the intended object of it. Ephorus, while he
described Minos as a commanding and comprehensive lawgiver imposing his
commands under the sanction of Zeus, represented him as the imitator of an
earlier lawgiver named Rhadamanthus, and also as an
immigrant into Crete from the Eolic-Mount Ida, along with the priests or sacred
companions of Zeus called the Ideai Dactyli. Aristotle too points him out as the author of the Syssitia, or public meals common in Crete as well as at
Sparta,—other divergences in a new direction from the spirit of the old fables.
The contradictory attributes
ascribed to Minos, together with the perplexities experienced by those who
wished to introduce a regular chronological arrangement into these legendary
events, has led both in ancient and in modern times to the supposition of two
kings named Minos, one the grandson of the other,—Minos I, the son of Zeus,
lawgiver and judge,—Minos II, the thalassocrat,—a
gratuitous conjecture, which, without solving the problem required, only adds
one to the numerous artifices employed for imparting the semblance of history
to the disparate matter of legend. The Cretans were at all times, from Homer
downward, expert and practiced seamen. But that they were ever united under one
government, or ever exercised maritime dominion in the Aegean is a fact which
we are neither able to affirm nor to deny. The Odyssey, in so far as it
justifies any inference at all, points against such a supposition, since it
recognizes a great diversity both of inhabitants and of languages in the
island, and designates Minos as king specially of Knossos: it refutes still
more positively the idea that Minos put down piracy, which the Homeric Cretans
as well as others continue to practice without scruple.
Herodotus, though he in some places
speaks of Minos as a person historically cognizable, yet in one passage severs
him pointedly from the generation of man. The Samian despot “Polycrates (he tells us) was the first person
who aspired to nautical dominion, excepting Mineos of
Knossos, and others before him (if any such there ever were) who may have ruled
the sea; but Polycrates is the first of that which is
called the generation of man who aspired with much chance of success to govern
Ionia and the islands of the Aegean”. Here we find it manifestly intimated that
Minos did not belong to the generation of man, and the tale given by the
historian respecting the tremendous calamities which the wrath of the departed Mineos inflicted on Crete confirms the impression. The king
of Knossos is a god or a hero, but not a man; he belongs to legend, not to
history. He is the son as well as the familiar companion of Zeus; he marries
the daughter of Helios, and Ariadne is numbered among his offspring. To this
superhuman person are ascribed the oldest and most revered institutions of the
island, religious and political, together with a period of supposed
ante-historical dominion. That there is much of Cretan religious ideas and
practice embodied in the fables concerning Minos can hardly be doubted: nor is
it improbable that the tale of the youths and maidens sent from Athens may be
based in some expiatory offerings ordered to a Cretan divinity. The orgiastic
worship of Zeus, solemnized by the armed priests with impassioned motions and
violent excitement, was of ancient date in that island, as well as the connection
with the worship of Apollo both at Delphi and at Delos. To analyze the fables
and to elicit from them any trustworthy particular facts, appears to me a
fruitless attempt. The religious recollections, the romantic invention, and the
items of matter of fact, if any such there be, must forever remain indissolubly
amalgamated as the poet originally blended them, for the amusement or
edification of his auditors. Hoeck, in his
instructive and learned collection of facts respecting ancient Crete, construes
the mythical genealogy of Minos to denote a combination of the orgiastic
worship of Zeus, indigenous among the Eteokretes,
with the worship of the moon imported from Phoenicia, and signified by the
names Europe, Pasiphae, and Ariadne. This is specious as a conjecture, but I do
not venture to speak of it in terms of greater confidence.
From the connection of religious
worship and legendary tales between Crete and various parts of Asia Minor,—the
Troad, the coast of Miletus and Lycia, especially between Mount Ida in Crete
and Mount Ida in Elis—it seems reasonable to infer an ethnographical kindred or
relationship between the inhabitants anterior to the period of Hellenic
occupation. The tales of Cretan settlement at Minoa and Engyon on the south-western coast of Sicily, and in Iapygia on the Gulf of Tarentum, conduct us to a similar presumption, though the want of evidence forbids our tracing it farther. In the
time of Herodotus, the Eteokretes, or aboriginal
inhabitants of the island, were confined to Polichna and Presus; but in earlier times, prior to the
encroachments of the Hellenes, they had occupied the larger portion, if not the
whole of the island. Mines was originally their hero, subsequently adopted by
the immigrant Hellenes,—at least Herodotus considers him as barbarian, not
Hellenic.
THE ship Argo was the theme of many
songs during the oldest periods of the Grecian epic, even earlier than the
Odyssey. The king Aetes, from whom she is departing,
the hero Jason, who commands her, and the goddess Here, who watches over him,
enabling the Argo to traverse distances and to escape dangers which no ship had
ever before encountered, are all circumstances briefly glanced at by Odysseus
in his narrative to Alkinous. Moreover, Euneus, the son of Jason and Hypsipyle.
governs Lemnos during the siege of Troy by Agamemnon,
and carries on a friendly traffic with the Grecian camp, purchasing from them
their Trojan prisoners.
The legend of Halus in Achaia Phthiotis, respecting the religious
solemnities connected with the family of Athamas and Phryxus (related in a previous chapter), is also interwoven
with the voyage of the Argonauts; and both the legend and the solemnities seem
evidently of great antiquity. We know further, that the adventures of the Argo
were narrated not only by Hesiod and in the Hesiodic poems, but also by Eumelus and the author of the Naupactian verses — by the latter seemingly at considerable length. But these poems are
unfortunately lost, nor have we any means of determining what the original
story was; for the narrative, as we have it, borrowed from later sources, is
enlarged by local tales from the subsequent Greek colonies—Kyzikus,
Herakleia, Sinope, and others.
Jason, commanded by Pelias to depart in quest of the golden fleece belonging to
the speaking ram which had carried away Phryxus and Helle, was encouraged by the oracle to invite the noblest
youth of Greece to his aid, and fifty of the most distinguished amongst them
obeyed the call. Heracles, Theseus, Telamon and Peleus, Castor and Pollux, Idas and Lynkeus—Zete and Kalias, the winged sons of Boreas— Meleager, Amphiaraus, Kepheus,
Laertes, Autolykus, Menoetius, Aktor, Erginus, Euphemus, Ankaeus, Poeas, Periklymenus, Augeas, Eurytus, Admetus, Akastus, Kaeneus, Euryalus, Pencleos and Leitus, Askalaphus and Ialmenus, were among them. Argus the son of Phryxus, directed by the promptings of Athene, built the
ship, inserting in the prow a piece of timber from the celebrated oak of
Dodona, which was endued with the faculty of speech: Tiphys was the steersman, Idmon (the son of Apollo) and Mopsus accompanied them as prophets, while Orpheus came to
amuse their weariness and reconcile their quarrels with his harp.
First they touched at the island of Lemnos, in which at that time there were no men; for the
women, infuriated by jealousy and ill-treatment, had put to death their
fathers, husbands and brothers. The Argonauts, after some difficulty, were
received with friendship, and even admitted into the greatest intimacy. They
staid some months, and the subsequent population of the island was the fruit of
their visit. Hypsipyle, the queen of the island, bore
to Jason two sons.
They then proceeded onward along the
coast of Thrace, up the Hellespont, to the southern coast of the Propontis, inhabited by the Doliones and their king Kyzikus. Here they were kindly
entertained, but after their departure were driven back to the same spot by a
storm; and as they landed in the dark, the inhabitants did not know them. A
battle took place, in which the chief, Kyzikus, was
killed by Jason; whereby much grief was occasioned as soon as the real facts
became known. After Kyzikus had been interred with
every demonstration of mourning and solemnity, the Argonauts proceeded along
the coast of Ilysia. In this part of the voyage they
left Heracles behind. For Hylas, his favorite
youthful companion, had been stolen away by the nymphs of a fountain, and
Heracles, wandering about in search of him, neglected to return. At last he
sorrowfully retired, exacting hostages from the inhabitants of the neighboring
town of Kius that they would persist in the search.
They next stopped in the country of
the Bebrykians, where the boxing contest took place
between the king Amykus and the Argonaut Pollux: they then proceeded onward to Bithynia, the
residence of the blind prophet Phineus. His blindness
had been inflicted by Poseidon as a punishment for having communicated to Phryxus the way to Colchis. The choice had been allowed to
him between death and blindness, and he had preferred the latter. He was also
tormented by the harpies, winged monsters who came down from the clouds
whenever his table was set, snatched the food from his lips and imparted to it
a foul and unapproachable odor. In the midst of this misery, he hailed the
Argonauts as his deliverers—his prophetic powers having enabled him to foresee
their coming. The meal being prepared for him, the harpies approached as usual,
but Zetes and Kalias, the
winged sons of Boreas, drove them away and pursued them. They put forth all
their speed, and prayed to Zeus to be enabled to overtake the monsters; when
Hermes appeared and directed them to desist, the harpies being forbidden
further to molest Phineus, and retiring again to
their native cavern in Crete.
Phineus, grateful for the relief afforded
to him by the Argonauts, forewarned them of the dangers of their voyage and of
the precautions necessary for their safety; and through his suggestions they
were enabled to pass through the terrific rocks called Symplegades.
These were two rocks which alternately opened and shut, with a swift and
violent collision, so that it was difficult even for a bird to fly through
during the short interval. When the Argo arrived at the dangerous spot, Euphemus let loose a dove which flew through and just
escaped with the loss of a few feathers of her tail. This was a signal to the
Argonauts, according to the prediction of Phineus,
that they might attempt the passage with confidence. Accordingly they rowed
with all their might, and passed safely through: the closing rocks, held for a
moment asunder by the powerful arms of Athene, just crushed the ornaments at
the stern of their vessel. It had been decreed by the gods, that so soon as any
ship once got through, the passage should forever afterwards be safe and easy
to all. The rocks became fixed in their separate places, and never again
closed.
After again halting on the coast of
the Maryandinians, where their steersman Tiphys died, as well as in the country of the Amazons, and
after picking up the sons of Phryxus, who had been
cast away by Poseidon in their attempt to return from Colchis to Greece, they
arrived in safety at the river Phasis and the
residence of Aetes. In passing by Mount Caucasus,
they saw the eagle which gnawed the liver of Prometheus nailed to the rock, and
heard the groans of the sufferer himself. The sons of Phryxus were cordially welcomed by their mother Chalciope.
Application was made to Aetes, that he would grant to
the Argonauts, heroes of divine parentage and sent forth by the mandate of the
gods, possession of the golden fleece: their aid in return was proffered to him
against any or all of his enemies. But the king was wroth,
and peremptorily refused, except upon conditions which seemed impracticable.
Hephaestus had given him two ferocious and untamable bulls, with brazen feet,
which breathed fire from their nostrils: Jason was invited, as a proof both of
his illustrious descent and of the sanction of the gods to his voyage, to
harness these animals to the yoke, so as to plough a large field and sow it
with dragon’s teeth. Perilous as the condition was, each one of the heroes
volunteered to make the attempt. Idmon especially
encouraged Jason to undertake it and the goddesses Here and Aphrodite made
straight the way for him. Medea, the daughter of Aetes and Eidyia, having seen the youthful hero in his
interview with her father, had conceived towards him a passion which disposed
her to employ every means for his salvation and success. She had received from Hekate preeminent magical powers, and she prepared for
Jason the powerful Prometheian unguent, extracted
from an herb which had grown where the blood of Prometheus dropped. The body of
Jason having been thus pre-medicated, became invulnerable either by fire or by
warlike weapons. He undertook the enterprise, yoked the bulls without suffering
injury, and ploughed the field: when he had sown the dragon’s teeth, armed men
sprung out of the furrows. But he had been forewarned by Medea to cast a vast
rock into the midst of them, upon which they began to fight with each other, so
that he was easily enabled to subdue them all.
The task prescribed had thus been
triumphantly performed. Yet Aetes not only refused to
hand over the golden fleece, but even took measures for secretly destroying the
Argonauts and burning their vessel. He designed to murder them during the night
after a festal banquet; but Aphrodite, watchful for the safety of Jason,
inspired the Kolchian king at the critical moment
with an irresistible inclination for his nuptial bed. While he slept, the wise Idmon counseled the Argonauts to make their escape, and
Medea agreed to accompany them. She lulled to sleep by a magic potion the
dragon who guarded the golden fleece, placed that much-desired prize on board
the vessel, and accompanied Jason with his companions in their flight, carrying
along with her the young Apsyrtus, her brother.
Aetes, profoundly exasperated at the
flight of the Argonauts with his daughter, assembled his forces forthwith, and
put to sea in pursuit of them. So energetic were his efforts that he shortly
overtook the retreating vessel, when the Argonauts again owed their safety to
the stratagem of Medea. She killed her brother Apsyrtus,
cut his body in pieces and strewed the limbs round about in the sea. Aetes on reaching the spot found these sorrowful traces of
his murdered son; but while he tarried to collect the scattered fragments, and
bestow upon the body an honorable interment, the Argonauts escaped. The spot on
which the unfortunate Apsyrtus was cut up received
the name of Tomi. This fratricide of Medea, however,
so deeply provoked the indignation of Zeus, that he condemned the Argo and her
crew to a trying voyage, full of hardship and privation, before she was
permitted to reach home. The returning heroes traversed an immeasurable length
both of sea and of river: first up the river Phasis into the ocean which flows round the earth—then following the course of that
circumfluous stream until its junction with the Nile, they came down the Nile
into Egypt, from whence they carried the Argo on their shoulders by a fatiguing
land-journey to the lake Tritonis in Libya. Here they
were rescued from the extremity of want and exhaustion by the kindness of the
local god Triton, who treated them hospitably, and even presented to Euphemus a clod of earth, as a symbolical promise that his
descendants should one day found a city on the Libyan shore. The promise was
amply redeemed by the flourishing and powerful city of Cyrene, whose princes
the Battiads boasted themselves as lineal descendants
of Euphemus.
Refreshed by the hospitality of
Triton, the Argonauts found themselves again on the waters of the Mediterranean
in their way homeward. But before they arrived at Iolkos they visited Circe, at the island of Aeaea, where
Medea was purified for the murder of Apsyrtus: they
also stopped at Corcyra, then called Drepane, where Alkinous received and protected them. The cave in that
island where the marriage of Medea with Jason was consummated, was still shown
in the time of the historian Timaeus, as well as the altars to Apollo which she
had erected, and the rites and sacrifices which she had first instituted. After
leaving Korkyra, the Argo was overtaken by a perilous
storm near the island of Thera. The heroes were saved
from imminent peril by the supernatural aid of Apollo, who, shooting from his
golden bow an arrow which pierced the waves like a
track of light, caused a new island suddenly to spring up in their track and
present to them a port of refuge. The island was called Anaphé;
and the grateful Argonauts established upon it an altar and sacrifices in honor
of Apollo Aegletés, which were ever afterwards
continued, and traced back by the inhabitants to this originating adventure.
On approaching the coast of Crete,
the Argonauts were prevented from landing by Talos; a
man of brass, fabricated by Hephaestus, and presented by him to Minos for the
protection of the island. This vigilant sentinel hurled against the approaching
vessel fragments of rock, and menaced the heroes with destruction. But Medea
deceived him by a stratagem and killed him; detecting and assailing the one
vulnerable point in his body. The Argonauts were thus enabled to land and
refresh themselves. They next proceeded onward to Aegina, where however they
again experienced resistance before they could obtain water—then along the
coast of Euboea and Locris back to Iolkos in the gulf of Pagasae,
the place from whence they hail started. The proceedings of Pelias during their absence, and the signal revenge taken upon him by Medea after
their return, have already been narrated in a preceding section. The ship Argo
herself; in which the chosen heroes of Greece had performed so long a voyage
and braved so many dangers, was consecrated by Jason to Poseidon at the isthmus
of Corinth. According to another account, she was translated to the stars by
Athene, and became a constellation.
Traces of the presence of the
Argonauts were found not only in the regions which lay between Iolkos and Colchis, but also in the western portion of the
Grecian world— distributed more or less over all the spots visited by Grecian
mariners or settled by Grecian colonists, and scarcely less numerous than the
wanderings of the dispersed Greeks and Trojans after the capture of Troy. The
number of Jasonia, or temples for the heroic worship
of Jason, was very great, from Abdera in Thrace,
eastward along the coast of the Euxine, to Armenia and Media. The Argonauts had
left their anchoring stone on the coast of Bebrykia,
near Kyzikus, and there it was preserved during the
historical ages in the temple of the Jasonian Athene.
They had founded the great temple of the Idaen mother
on the mountain Dindymon, near Kyzikus,
and the Hieron of Zeus Urios on the Asiatic point at the mouth of the Euxine, near which was also the harbor
of Phryxus. Idmon, the
prophet of the expedition, who was believed to have died of a wound by a wild
boar on the Maryandynian coast, was worshipped by the
inhabitants of the Pontic Herakleia with great
solemnity, as their Heros Poliuchus,
and that too by the special direction of the Delphian god. Autolykus, another companion of Jason, was
worshipped as Oekist by the inhabitants of Sinope.
Moreover, the historians of Herakleia pointed out a temple of Hekate in the neighboring country of Paphlagonia, first
erected by Medea; and the important town Pantikapaeon,
on the European side of the Cimmerian Bosporus, ascribed its first settlement
to a son of Aetes. When the returning ten thousand
Greeks sailed along the coast, called the Jasonian shore, from Sinope to Herakleia, they were told that the grandson of Aetes was reigning king of the territory at the mouth of
the Phasis, and the anchoring-places where the Argo
had stopped were specially pointed out to them. In the lofty regions of the Moschi, near Colchis, stood the temple of Leukothea, founded by Phryxus,
which remained both rich and respected down to the times of the kings of
Pontus, and where it was an inviolable rule not to offer up a ram. The town of Dioskurias, north of the river Phasis,
was believed to have been hallowed by the presence of Castor and Pollux in the Argo, and to have received from them its
appellation. Even the interior of Media and Armenia was full of memorials of
Jason and Medea and their son Medus, or of Armenus the son of Jason, from whom the Greeks deduced not
only the name and foundation of the Medes and Armenians, but also the great
operation of cutting a channel through the mountains for the efflux of the
river Araxes, which they compared to that of the Peneius in Thessaly. And the Roman general Pompey, after having completed the conquest
and expulsion of Mithridates, made long marches through Colchis into the
regions of Caucasus, for the express purpose of contemplating the spots which
had been ennobled by the exploits of the Argonauts, the Dioskuri and Heracles.
In the west, memorials either of the
Argonauts or of the pursuing Kolchians were pointed
out in Corcyra, in Crete, in Epirus near the Akrokeraunian mountains, in the islands called Apsyrtides near the
Illyrian coast, at the bay of Caieta as well as at Poseidonia on the southern coast of Italy, in the island of Aethalia or Elba, and in Libya.
Such is a brief outline of the Argonautic expedition, one of the most celebrated and
widely-diffused among the ancient tales of Greece. Since so many able men have
treated it as an undisputed reality, and even made it the pivot of systematic
chronological calculations, I may here repeat the opinion long ago expressed by Heyne, and even indicated by Burmann,
that the process of dissecting the story, in search of a basis of fact, is one
altogether fruitless. Not only are we unable to assign the date or identify the
crew, or decipher the log-book, of the Argo, but we have no means of settling
even the preliminary question, whether the voyage be matter of fact badly
reported, or legend from the beginning. The widely-distant spots in which the
monuments of the voyage were shown, no less than the incidents of the voyage
itself, suggests no other parentage than epical fancy. The supernatural and the
romantic not only constitute an inseparable portion of the narrative, but even
embrace all the prominent and characteristic features; if they do not comprise
the whole, and if there be intermingled along with them any sprinkling of
historical or geographical fact, — a question to us indeterminable, — there is
at least no solvent by which it can be disengaged, and no test by which it can
be recognized. Wherever the Grecian mariner sailed, he carried his religious
and patriotic myths along with him. His fancy and his faith were alike full of
the long wanderings of Jason, Odysseus, Perseus, Heracles, Dionysus, Triptolemus or Io; it was pleasing to him in success, and
consoling to him in difficulty, to believe that their journeys had brought them
over the ground which he was himself traversing. There was no tale amidst the
wide range of the Grecian epic more calculated to be popular with the seaman,
than the history of the primeval ship Argo and her distinguished crew,
comprising heroes from all parts of Greece, and especially the Tyndarids Castor
and Pollux, the heavenly protector: invoked during
storm and peril. He localized the legend anew wherever he went, often with some
fresh circumstances suggested either by his own adventures or by the scene
before him. He took a sort of religious possession of the spot, connecting it
by a bond of faith with his native land, and erecting in it a temple or an
altar with appropriate commemorative solemnities. The Jasonium thus established, and indeed every visible object called after the name of the
hero, not only served to keep alive the legend of the Argo in the minds of
future corners or inhabitants, but was accepted as an obvious and satisfactory
proof that this marvelous vessel had actually touched there in her voyage.
The epic poets, building both on the
general love of fabulous incident and on the easy faith of the people, dealt
with distant and unknown space in the same manner as with past and unrecorded
time. They created a mythical geography for the former, and a mythical history
for the latter. But there was this material difference between the two: that
while the unrecorded time was beyond the reach of verification, the unknown
space gradually became trodden and examined. In proportion as authentic local
knowledge was enlarged, it became necessary to modify the geography, or shift
the scene of action, of the old myths; and this perplexing problem was
undertaken by some of the ablest historians and geographers of antiquity,—for
it was painful to them to abandon any portion of the old epic, as if it were
destitute of an ascertainable basis of truth.
Many of these fabulous localities
are to be found in Homer and Hesiod, and the other Greek poets and
logographers,—Erytheia, the garden of the Hesperides, the garden of Phoebus, to which Boreas
transported the Attic maiden Orithyia, the delicious
country of the Hyperboreans, the Elysian plain, the
fleeting island of Aeolus, Thrinakia, the country of
the Ethiopians, the Laestrygones, the Cyclopes, the Lotophagi, the Sirens, the Cimmerians and the Gorgons, etc.
These are places which (to use the expression of Pindar respecting the Hyperboreans) you cannot approach either by sea or by land:
the wings of the poet alone can carry you thither. They were not introduced
into the Greek mind by incorrect geographical reports, but, on the contrary,
had their origin in the legend, and passed from thence into the realities of
geography, which they contributed much to pervert and confuse. For the
navigator or emigrant, starting with an unsuspicious faith in their real
existence, looked out for them in his distant voyages, and constantly fancied
that he had seen or heard of them, so as to be able to identify their exact
situation. The most contradictory accounts indeed, as might be expected, were
often given respecting the latitude and longitude of such fanciful spots, but
this did not put an end to the general belief in their real existence.
In the present advanced state of
geographical knowledge, the story of that man who after reading Gulliver's
Travels went to look in his map for Lilliput, appears an absurdity. But those
who fixed the exact locality of the floating island of Aeolus or the rocks of
the Sirens did much the same; and, with their ignorance of geography and
imperfect appreciation of historical evidence, the error was hardly to be
avoided. The ancient belief which fixed the Sirens on the islands of Sirenusae off the coast of Naples —the Cyclopes, Erytheia, and the Laestrygones in
Sicily—the Lotophagi on the island of Meninx near the
Lesser Syrtis—the Phaeakians at Korkyra,—and the goddess Circe at the promontory
of Circeium—took its rise at a time when these
regions were first Hellenized and comparatively little visited. Once embodied
in the local legends, and attested by visible monuments and ceremonies, it
continued for a long time unassailed; and Thucydides
seems to adopt it, in reference to Corcyra and Sicily before the Hellenic
colonization, as matter of fact generally unquestionable, though little
avouched as to details. But when geographical knowledge became extended, and
the criticism upon the ancient epic was more or less systematized by the
literary men of Alexandria and Pergamus, it appeared
to many of them impossible that Odysseus could have seen so many wonders, or
undergone such monstrous dangers, within limits so narrow, and in the familiar
track between the Nile and the Tiber. The scene of his weather-driven course
was then shifted further westward. Many convincing evidences were discovered,
especially by Asklepiades of Myrlea,
of his having visited various places in Iberia: several critics imagined that
he had wandered about in the Atlantic Ocean outside of the Strait of Gibraltar,
and they recognized a section of Lotophagi on the
coast of Mauritania, over and above those who dwelt on the island of Meninx. On
the other hand, Eratosthenes and Apollodorus treated the places visited by
Odysseus as altogether unreal, for which skepticism they incurred much
reproach.
The fabulous island of Erytheia,—the residence of the three headed Geryon with his magnificent herd of oxen, under the custody
of the two-headed dog Orthrus, and described by
Hesiod, like the garden of the Hesperides, as
extraterrestrial, on the farther side of the circuinfluous ocean;—this island was supposed by the interpreters of Stesichorus the poet to
be named by him off the south-western region of Spain called Tartessus, and in the immediate vicinity of Gades. But the historian Hekataeus, in his anxiety to historicize
the old fable, took upon himself to remove Erytheia from Spain nearer home to Epirus. He thought it incredible that Herakles should have traversed Europe from east to west,
for the purpose of bringing the cattle of Geryon to Eurystheus at Mycenae, and he pronounced Geryon to have been a king of Epirus, near the Gulf of Ambrakia. The oxen reared in that neighborhood were
proverbially magnificent, and to get them even from thence and bring them to
Mycenae (he contended) was no inconsiderable task. Arrian,
who cites this passage from Hekataeus, concurs in the same view,— an
illustration of the license with which ancient authors fitted on their fabulous
geographical names to the real earth, and brought down the ethereal matter of
legend to the lower atmosphere of history.
Both the track and the terminus of
the Argonautic voyage appear in the most ancient epic
as little within the conditions of reality, as the speaking timbers or the
semi-divine crew of the vessel. In the Odyssey, Aetes and Circe (Hesiod names Medea also) are brother and sister, offspring of
Helios. Aeaean island, adjoining the circumfluous
ocean, “where the house and dancing-ground of Eos are situated, and where
Helios rises”, is both the residence of Circe and of Aetes,
inasmuch as Odysseus, in returning from the former, follows the same course as
the Argo had previously taken in returning from the latter. Even in the
conception of Mimnermus, about 600 BC, Aea still retained its fabulous attributes in conjunction
with the ocean and Helios, without having been yet identified with any known
portion of the solid earth; and it was justly remarked by Demetrius of Skepsis in antiquity (though Strabo cries to refute him),
that neither Homer nor Mimnermus designates Colchis
either as the residence of Aetes, or as the terminus
of the Argonautic voyage. Hesiod carried the
returning Argonauts through the river Phasis into the
ocean. But some of the poems ascribed to Eumelus were
the first which mentioned Aetes and Colchis, and
interwove both of them into the Corinthian mythical genealogy. These poems seem
to have been composed subsequent to the foundation of Sinope, and to the
commencement of Grecian settlement on the Borysthenes,
between the years 600 and 500 BC. The Greek mariners who explored and colonized
the southern coast of the Euxine, found at the extremity of their voyage the
river Phasis and its barbarous inhabitants: it was
the easternmost point which Grecian navigation (previous to the time of
Alexander the Great) ever attained, and it was within sight of the impassable
barrier of Caucasus. They believed, not unnaturally, that they had here found
“the house of Eos (the morning) and the rising place of the sun”, and that the
river Phasis, if they could follow it to its unknown
beginning, would conduct them to the circumfluous ocean. They gave to the spot
the name of Aea, and the Fabulous and real title
gradually became associated together into one compound appellation,—the Colchian Aea, or Aea of Colchis. While Colchis was thus entered on the map
as a fit representative for the Homeric “house of the morning”, the narrow
strait of the Thracian Bosporus attracted to itself the poetical fancy of the Symplegades, or colliding rocks, through which the
heaven-protected Argo had been the first to pass. The powerful Greek cities of Kyzikus, Herakleia and Sinope, each fertile in local
legends, still farther contributed to give this direction to the voyage; so
that in the time of Hekataeus it had become the established belief that the
Argo had started from Iolkos and gone to Colchis.
Aetes thus received his home from the
legendary faith and fancy of the eastern Greek navigators: his sister Circe,
originally his fellow-resident, was localized by the western. The Hesiodic and
other poems, giving expression to the imaginative impulses of the inhabitants
of Cumae and other early Grecian settlers in Italy and Sicily, had referred the
wanderings of Odysseus to the western or Tyrrhenian sea, and had planted the
Cyclopes, the Laestrygones, the floating island of
Aeolus, the Lotophagi, the Phaeacians, etc., about
the coast of Sicily, Italy, Libya, and Corcyra. In this way the Aeaean island,— the residence of Circe, and the extreme
point of the wanderings of Odysseus, from whence he passes only to the ocean
and into Hades — came to be placed in the far west, while the Aea of Aetes was in the far
east,— not unlike our East and West Indies. The Homeric brother and sister were
separated and sent to opposite extremities of the Grecian terrestrial horizon.
The track from Iolkos to Colchis, however, though plausible as far as it went, did not realize all
the conditions of the genuine fabulous voyage: it did not explain the evidences
of the visit of these maritime heroes which were to be found in Libya, in Crete,
in Anaphe, in Corcyra, in the Adriatic Gulf, in Italy
and in Aethalia. It became necessary to devise
another route for them in their return, and the Hesiodic narrative was (as I
have before observed), that they came back by the circumfluous ocean; first
going up the river Phasis into the circumfluous
ocean; following that deep and gentle stream until they entered the Nile, and
came down its course to the coast of Libya. This seems also to have been the
belief of Hekataeus. But presently several Greeks (and Herodotus among them)
began to discard the Idea of a circumfluous ocean-stream, which had pervaded
their old geographical and astronomical fables, and which explained the
supposed easy communication between one extremity of the earth and another.
Another idea was then started for the returning voyage of the Argonauts. It was
supposed that the river Ister, or Danube, flowing
from the Rhipaean mountains in the north-west of
Europe, divided itself into two branches, one of which fell into the Euxine
Sea, and the other into the Adriatic.
The Argonauts, fleeing from the
pursuit of Aetes, had been obliged to abandon their
regular course homeward, and had gone from the Euxine Sea up the Ister; then passing down the other branch of that river,
they had entered into the Adriatic, the Kolchian pursuers following them. Such is the story given by Apollanius Rhodius from Timagetus, and
accepted even by so able a geographer as Eratosthenes—who preceded him by one
generation, and who, though skeptical in regard to the localities visited by
Odysseus, seems to have been a firm believer in the reality of the Argonautic voyage. Other historians again, among whom was
Timaeus, though they considered the ocean as an outer sea, and no longer
admitted the existence of the old Homeric ocean-stream, yet imagined a story
for the return-voyage of the Argonauts somewhat resembling the old tale of
Hesiod and Hekataeus. They alleged that the Argo, after entering into the Palus Maeotis, had followed the
upward course of the river Tanais; that she had then
been carried overland and launched in a river which had its mouth in the ocean
or great outer sea. When in the ocean, she had coasted along the north and west
of Europe until she reached Gades and the Strait of
Gibraltar, where she entered into the Mediterranean, and there visited the many
places specified in the fable. Of this long voyage, in the outer sea to the
north and west of Europe, many traces were affirmed to exist along the coast of
the ocean. There was again a third version, according to which the Argonauts
came back as they went, through the Thracian Bosporus and the Hellespont. In
this way geographical plausibility was indeed maintained, but a large portion
of the fabulous matter was thrown overboard.
Such were the various attempts made to reconcile the Argonautic legend with enlarged geographical knowledge and improved historical criticism. The problem remained unsolved, but the faith in the legend did not the less continue. It was a faith originally generated at a time when the unassisted narrative of the inspired poet sufficed for the conviction of his hearers; it consecrated one among the capital exploits of that heroic and superhuman race, whom the Greek was accustomed at once to look back upon as his ancestors and to worship conjointly with his gods: it lay too deep in his mind either to require historical evidence for its support, or to be overthrown by geographical difficulties as they were then appreciated. Supposed traces of the past event, either preserved in the names of places, or embodied in standing religious customs with their explanatory comments, served as sufficient authentication in the eyes of the curious inquirer. And even men trained in a more severe school of criticism contented themselves with eliminating the palpable contradictions and softening down the supernatural and romantic events, so as to produce an Argonautic expedition of their own invention as the true and accredited history. Strabo, though he can neither overlook nor explain the geographical impossibilities of the narrative, supposes himself to have discovered the basis of actual fact, which the original poets had embellished or exaggerated. The golden fleece was typical of the great wealth of Colchis, arising from gold-dust washed down by the rivers; and the voyage of Jason was in reality an expedition at the head of a considerable army, with which he plundered this wealthy country and made extensive conquests in the interior. Strabo has nowhere laid down what he supposes to have been the exact measure and direction of Jason’s march, but he must have regarded it as very long, since he classes Jason with Dionysus and Heracles, and emphatically characterizes all the three as having traversed wider spaces of ground than any moderns could equal. Such was the compromise which a mind like that of Strabo made with the ancient legends. He shaped or cut them down to the level of his own credence, and in this waste of historical criticism, without any positive evidence, he took to himself the credit of greater penetration than the literal believers, while he escaped the necessity of breaking formally with the bygone heroic world
THE Boeotians generally, throughout the
historical age, though well-endowed with bodily strength and courage, are
represented as proverbially deficient in intelligence, taste and fancy. But the
legendary population of Thebes, the Kadmeians, are
rich in mythical antiquities, divine as well as heroic. Both Dionysus and
Heracles recognize Thebes as their natal city. Moreover, the two sieges of
Thebes by Adrastus, even taken apart from Cadmus, Antiope, Amphion and Zethus, etc., are the most prominent and most characteristic
exploits, next to the siege of Troy, of that preexisting race of heroes who
lived in the imagination of the historical Hellenes.
It is not Cadmus, but the brothers Amphion and Zethus, who are given
to us in the Odyssey as the first founders of Thebes and the first builders of
its celebrated walls. They are the sons of Zeus by Antiope,
daughter of Asopus. The scholiasts who desire to
reconcile this tale with the more current account of the foundation of Thebes
by Cadmus, tell us that after the death of Amphion and Zethus, Eurymachus, the
warlike king of the Phlegyae, invaded and ruined the
newly-settled town, so that Cadmus on arriving was obliged to refound it. But Apollodorus, and seemingly the older
logographers before him, placed Cadmus at the top, and inserted the two
brothers at a lower point in the series. According to them, Belus and Agenor were the sons of Epaphus,
(son of the Argeian Io), by Libya. Agenor went to Phoenicia and there became king: he bad for
his offspring Cadmus, Phoenix, Kilix, and a daughter
Europa; though in the Iliad Europa is called daughter of Phoenix. Zeus fell in
love with Europa, and assuming the shape of a bull, carried her across the sea
upon his back from Egypt to Crete, where she bore to him Minos, Rhadamanthus and Sarpedon. Two
out of the three sons sent out by Agenos in search of
their lost sister, wearied out by a long-protracted as well as fruitless
voyage, abandoned the idea of returning home: Kilix settled in Cilicia, and Cadmus in Thrace. Thasus, the
brother or nephew of Cadmus, who had accompanied them in the voyage, settled
and gave name to the island of Phasus.
Both Herodotus and Euripides represent Cadmus as
an emigrant from Phoenicia, conducting a body of followers in quest of Europa.
The account of Apollodorus describes him as having come originally from Libya
or Egypt to Phoenicia: we may presume that this was also the statement of the
earlier logographers Pherekydes and Hellanikus.
Conon, who historicizes and politicizes the whole legend, seems to have found
two different accounts; one connecting Cadmus with Egypt, another bringing him
from Phoenicia. He tries to melt down the two into one, by representing that
the Phoenicians, who sent out Cadmus, had acquired great power in Egypt—that
the seat of their kingdom was the Egyptian Thebes — that Cadmus was dispatched,
under pretense indeed of finding his lost sister, but really on a project of
conquest—and that the name Thebes, which he gave to his new establishment in
Boeotia, was borrowed from Thebes in Egypt, his ancestorial seats
Cadmus went from Thrace to Delphi to procure
information respecting his sister Europa, but the god directed him to take no
further trouble about her; he was to follow the guidance of a cow, and to found
a city on the spot where the animal should lie down. The condition was realized
on the site of Thebes. The neighboring fountain Areia was guarded by a fierce dragon, the offspring of Ares, who destroyed all the
persons sent to fetch water. Cadmus killed the dragon, and at the suggestion of
Athena sowed his teeth in the earth, there sprang up at once the armed men
called the Sparti, among whom he flung stones, and
they immediately began to assault each other until all were slain except five.
Ares, indignant at this slaughter, was about to kill Cadmus; but Zeus appeased
him, condemning Cadmus to an expiatory servitude of eight years, after which he
married Harmonia, the daughter of Ares and
Aphrodite—presenting to her the splendid necklace fabricated by the hand of
Hephaestus, which had been given by Zeus to Europa. All the gods came to the
Cadmeia, the citadel of Thebes, to present congratulations and gifts at these
nuptials, which seem to have been hardly less celebrated in the mythical world
than those of Peleus and Thetis. The issue of the marriage was one son, Polyderus, and four daughters, Autonoe, Ino, Semele and Agave.
From the five who alone survived of the warriors
sprung from the dragon’s teeth, arose five great families or gentes in Thebes;
the oldest and noblest of its inhabitants, coeval with the foundation of the
town. They were called Sparti, and their name seems
to have given rise, not only to the fable of the sowing of the teeth, but also
to other etymological narratives.
All the four daughters of Cadmus are illustrious
in fabulous history. The, wife of Athamas, the son of
Aeolus, has already been included among the legends of the Aeolids. Semele became the mistress of Zeus, and inspired Here
with jealousy. Misguided by the malicious suggestions of that goddess, she
solicited Zeus to visit her with all the solemnity and terrors which surrounded
him when he approached Here herself. The god unwillingly consented, and came in
his chariot in the midst of thunder and lightning, under which awful
accompaniments the mortal frame of Semele perished.
Zeus, taking from her the child of which she was pregnant, sewed it into his
own thigh: after the proper interval the child was brought out and born, and
became the great god Dionysus or Bacchus. Hermes took him to Ino and Athamas to receive their
protection. Afterwards, however, Zeus having transformed him into a kid to
conceal him from the persecution of Here, the nymphs of the mountain Nysa became his nurses.
Autonoe, the third daughter of Cadmus, married the
pastoral hero or god Aristaeus, and was mother of Aktaeon, a devoted hunter and a favorite companion of the
goddess Artemis. She however became displeased with him—either because he
looked into a fountain while she was bathing and saw her naked—or according to
the legend set forth by the poet Stesichorus, because he loved and courted Semele—or according to Euripides, because he presumptuously
vaunted himself as her superior in the chase. She transformed him into a stag,
so that his own dogs set upon and devoured him. The rock upon which Aktaeon used to sleep when fatigued with the chase, and the
spring whose transparent waters had too clearly revealed the form of the
goddess, were shown to Pausanias near Plataea, on the road to Megara.
PENTHEUS
Agave, the remaining daughter of Cadmus, married Echion, one of the Sparti.
The issue of these nuptials was Pentheus, who, when
Cadmus became old succeeded him as king of Thebes. In his reign Dionysus
appeared as a god, the author or discoverer of the vine with all its blessings.
He had wandered over Asia, India and Thrace, at the head of an excited troop of
female enthusiasts—communicating and inculcating everywhere the Bacchic ceremonies, and rousing in the minds of women that
impassioned religious emotion which led them to ramble in solitary mountains at
particular seasons, there to give vent to violent fanatical excitement, apart
from the men, clothed in fawn skins and armed with the thyrsus. The obtrusion
of a male spectator upon these solemnities was esteemed sacrilegious. Though
the rites had been rapidly disseminated and fervently welcomed in many parts of
Thrace, yet there were some places in which they had been obstinately resisted
and their votaries treated with rudeness; especially by Lycurgus, king of the Edonian Thracians, upon whom a sharp and exemplary
punishment was inflicted by Dionysus.
Thebes was the first city of Greece to which
Dionysus came, at the head of his Asiatic troop of females, to obtain divine
honors and to establish his peculiar rites in his native city. The venerable
Cadmus, together with his daughters and the prophet Teiresias,
at once acknowledged the divinity of the new god, and began to offer their
worship and praise to him along with the solemnities which he enjoined. But Pentheus vehemently opposed the new ceremonies, reproving
and maltreating the god who introduced them: nor was his unbelief at all
softened by the miracles which Dionysus wrought for his own protection and for
that of his followers. His mother Agave, with her sisters and a large body of
other women from Thebes, had gone out from Thebes to Mount Cithaeron to
celebrate their solemnities under the influence of the Bacchic frenzy. Thither Pentheus followed to watch them, and
there the punishment due to his impiety overtook him. The avenging touch of the
god having robbed him of his senses, he climbed a tall pine for the purpose of
overlooking the feminine multitude, who detected him in this position, pulled
down the tree, and tore him in pieces. Agave, mad and bereft of consciousness,
made herself the foremost in this assault, and carried back in triumph to
Thebes the head of her slaughtered son. The aged Cadmus, with his wife Harmonia, retired among the Illyrians, and at the end of
their lives were changed into serpents, Zeus permitting them to be transferred
to the Elysian fields.
LABDAKUS. —LAIUS. —ANTIOPE.
Polydorus and Labdakus successively became kings of Thebes: the latter at his death left an infant
son, Laius, who was deprived of his throne by Lykus.
And here we approach the legend of Antiope, Zethus and Amphion, whom the
fabulists insert at this point of the Theban series. Antiope is here the daughter of Nykteus, the brother of Lykus. She is deflowered by Zeus, and then, while pregnant,
flies to Epopeus king of Sicyon: Nykteus dying entreats his brother to avenge the injury, and Lykus accordingly invades Sicyon, defeats and kills Epopeus,
and brings back Antiope prisoner to Thebes. In her
way thither, in a cave near Eleutherae, which was shown
to Pausanias, she is delivered of the twin sons of Zeus—Amphion and Zethus—who, exposed to perish, are taken up and
nourished by a shepherd, and pass their youth amidst herdsmen, ignorant of
their lofty descent.
Antiope is conveyed to Thebes, where, after undergoing
a long persecution from Lykus and his cruel wife Dirke, she at length escapes, and takes refuge in the
pastoral dwelling of her sons, now grown to manhood. Dirke pursues and requires her to be delivered up; but the sons recognize and protect
their mother, taking an ample revenge upon her persecutors. Lykus is slain, and Dirke is dragged to death, tied to the
horns of a bull.
Amphion and Zethus, having
banished Laius, become kings of Thebes. The former, taught by Hermes, and
possessing exquisite skill on the lyre, employs it in fortifying the city, the
stones of the walls arranging themselves spontaneously in obedience to the rhythm
of his song.
Zethus marries Aedon, who,
in the dark and under a fatal mistake, kills her son Itylus:
she is transformed into a nightingale, while Zethus dies of grief. Amphion becomes the husband of Niobe, daughter of Tantalus, and the father of a numerous
offspring, the complete extinction of which by the bands of Apollo and Artemis
has already been recounted in these pages.
Here ends the legend of the beautiful Antiope and her twin sons—the rude and unpolished, but
energetic, Zethus and the refined and amiable, but
dreamy, Amphion. For so Euripides, in the drama of Antiope unfortunately lost, presented the two brothers, in
affectionate union as well as in striking contrast. It is evident that the
whole story stood originally quite apart from the Cadmeian family, and so the rudiments of it yet stand in the Odyssey; but the
logographers, by their ordinary connecting artifices, have opened a vacant
place for it in the descending series of Theban myths. And they have here
proceeded in a manner not usual with them. For whereas they are generally fond
of multiplying entities, and supposing different historical personages of the
same name, in order to introduce an apparent smoothness in the chronology—they
have here blended into one person Amphion the son of Antiope and Amphion the father of Chleris, who seem clearly distinguished from each
other in the Odyssey. They have further assigned to the same person all the
circumstances of the legend of Niobe, which seems to
have been originally framed quite apart from the sons of Antiope.
EDIPUS.
Amphion and Zethus being
removed, Laius became king of Thebes. With him commences the ever-celebrated
series of adventures of Oedipus and his family. Laius forewarned by the oracle
that any son whom he might beget would kill him, caused Oedipus as soon as he
was born to be exposed on Mount Cithaeron. Here the herdsmen of Polybus king of Corinth accidentally found him and conveyed
him to their master, who brought him up as his own child. In spite of the
kindest treatment, however, Oedipus when he grew up found himself exposed to
taunts on the score of his unknown parentage, and went to Delphi to inquire of
the god the name of his real father. He received for answer an admonition not
to go back to his country; if he did so, it was his destiny to kill his father
and become the husband of his mother. Knowing no other country but Corinth, he
accordingly determined to keep away from that city, and quitted Delphi by the
road towards Boeotia and Phocis. At the exact spot where the roads leading to
these two countries forked, he met Laius in a chariot drawn by mules, when the
insolence of one of the attendants brought on an angry quarrel, in which Oedipus
killed Laius, not knowing him to be his father.
On the death of Laius, Kreon,
the brother of Yokasta, succeeded to the kingdom of
Thebes. At this time the country was under the displeasure of the gods, and was
vexed by a terrible monster, with the face of a woman, the wings of a bird, and
the tail of a lion, called the Sphinx—sent by the wrath of Here, and occupying
the neighboring mountain of Phikium. The Sphinx had
learned from the Muses a riddle, which she proposed to the Thebans to resolve:
on every occasion of failure she took away one of the citizens and ate him up.
Still no person could solve the riddle; and so great was the suffering
occasioned, that Kreon was obliged to offer both the
crown and the nuptials of his sister Yokasta to
anyone who could achieve the salvation of the city. At this juncture Oedipus
arrived and solved the riddle: upon which the Sphinx immediately threw herself
from the acropolis and disappeared. As a recompense for this service, Oedipus
was made king of Thebes, and married Yokasta, not
aware that she was his mother.
These main tragic circumstances—that Oedipus had
ignorantly killed his father and married his mother—belong to the oldest form
of the legend as it stands in the Odyssey. The gods (it is added in that poem)
quickly made the facts known to mankind. Epikasta (so Yokasta is here called) in an agony of sorrow hanged
herself: Oedipus remained king of the Cadmeians, but
underwent many and great miseries, such as the Erinnyes,
who avenge an injured mother, inflict. A passage in the Iliad implies that he
died at Thebes, since it mentions the funeral games which were celebrated there
in honor of him. His misfortunes were recounted by Nestor, in the old Cyprian
verses, among the stories of aforetime. A fatal curse hung both upon himself
and upon his children, Eteokles, Polynikes,
Antigone and Ismene. According to that narrative
which the Attic tragedians have rendered universally current, they were his
children by Yokasta, the disclosure of her true
relationship to him having been very long deferred. But the ancient epic called Oedipodia, treading more closely in the footsteps of
Homer, represented him as having after her death married a second wife, Euryganeia, by whom the four children were born to him: and
the painter Onatas adopted this story in preference
to that of Sophocles.
The disputes of Eteokles and Polynikes for the throne of their father gave
occasion not only to a series of tragic family incidents, but also to one of
the great quasi-historical events of legendary Greece—the two sieges of Thebes
by Adrastus, king of Argos. The two ancient epic poems
called the Thebais and the Epigoni (if indeed both were not parts of one very
comprehensive poem) detailed these events at great length, and as it appears,
with distinguished poetical merit; for Pausanias pronounces the Cyclic Thebais
(so it was called by the subsequent critics to distinguish it from the more
modern Thebais of Antimachus) inferior only to the Iliad and Odyssey; and the
ancient elegiac poet Kallinus treated it as an
Homeric composition. Of this once-valued poem we unfortunately possess nothing
but a few scanty fragments. The leading points of the legend are briefly
glanced at in the Iliad; but our knowledge of the details is chiefly derived
from the Attic tragedians, who transformed the narratives of their predecessors
at pleasure, and whose popularity constantly eclipsed and obliterated the
ancient version. Antimachus of Kolophon, contemporary
with Euripides, in his long epic, probably took no less liberties with the old
narrative. His Thebaid never became generally
popular, but it exhibited marks of study and elaboration which recommended it
to the esteem of the Alexandrine critics, and probably contributed to discredit
in their eyes the old cyclic poem.
The logographers, who gave a continuous history
of this siege of Thebes, had at least three preexisting epic poems—the Thebais,
the Oedipodia, and the Alkmaeonis,—
from which they could borrow. The subject was also handled in some of the
Hesiodic poems, but we do not know to what extent. The Thebais was composed
more in honor of Argos than of Thebes, as the first line of it, one of the few
fragments still preserved, betokens.
SIEGES OF THEBES.
The legend, about to recount fraternal
dissension of the most implacable kind, comprehending in its results not only
the immediate relations of the infuriated brothers, but many chosen companions
of the heroic race along with them, takes its start from the paternal curse of
Oedipus, which overhangs and determines all the gloomy sequel.
Oedipus, though king of Thebes and father of
four children by Euryganeia (according to the Oedipodia), has become the devoted victim of the Erinnyes, in consequence of the self-inflicted death of his
mother, which he has unconsciously caused, as well as of his unintentional
parricide. Though he had long forsworn the use of all the ornaments and
luxuries which his father had inherited from his kingly progenitors, yet when
through age he had come to be dependent upon his two sons. Polynikes one day broke through this interdict, and set before him the silver table and the
splendid wine-cup of Cadmus, which Laius had always been accustomed to employ.
The old king had no sooner seen these precious appendages of the regal life of
his father, than his mind was overrun by a calamitous frenzy, and he imprecated
terrible curses on his sons, predicting that there would be bitter and endless
warfare between them. The goddess Erinnys heard and
heeded him; and he repeated the curse again on another occasion, when his sons,
who had always been accustomed to send to him the shoulder of the victims
sacrificed on the altar, caused the buttock to be served to him in place of it.
He resented this as an insult, and prayed the gods that they might perish each
by the hand of the other. Throughout the tragedians as well as in the old epic,
the paternal curse, springing immediately from the misguided Oedipus himself,
but remotely from the parricide and incest with which he has tainted his breed,
is seen to domineer over the course of events—the Erinnys who executes that curse being the irresistible, though concealed, agent.
Aeschylus not only preserves the fatal efficiency of the paternal curse, but
even briefly glances at the causes assigned for it in the Thebais, without superadding any new motives. In the judgment of Sophocles,
or of his audience, the conception of a father cursing his sons upon such
apparently trifling grounds was odious; and that great poet introduced many
aggravating circumstances, describing the old blind father as having been
barbarously turned out of doors by his sons to wander abroad in exile and
poverty. Though by this change he rendered his poem more coherent and
self-justifying, yet he departed, from the spirit of the old legend, according
to which Oedipus has contracted by his unconscious misdeeds an incurable taint
destined to pass onward to his progeny. His mind is alienated, and he curses
them, not because he has suffered seriously by their guilt, but because he is
made the blind instrument of an avenging Erinnys for
the ruin of the house of Laius.
After the death of Oedipus and the celebration
of his funeral games, at which amongst others, Argeia,
daughter of Adrastus (afterwards the wife of Polynikes), was present, his two sons soon quarreled
respecting the succession. The circumstances are differently related; but it
appears that, according to the original narrative, the wrong and injustice was
on the part of Polynikes, who, however, was obliged
to leave Thebes and to seek shelter with Adrastus,
king of Argos. Here he met Tydeus, a fugitive, at the
same time, from Aetolia: it was dark when they arrived, and a broil ensued
between the two exiles, but Adrastus came out and
parted them. He had been enjoined by an oracle to give his two daughters in
marriage to a lion and a boar, and he thought this occasion had now arrived,
inasmuch as one of the combatants carried on his shield a lion, the other a
boar. He accordingly gave Deipyle in marriage to Tydeus, and Argeia to Polynikes: moreover, he resolved to restore by armed
resistance both his sons-in-law to their respective countries.
POLYNIKES AND ADRASTUS. AMPHIARAUS.
On proposing the expedition to the Argeian chiefs around him he found most of them willing
auxiliaries; but Amphiaraus—formerly his bitter
opponent, but now reconciled to him, and husband of his sister Eriphyle—strongly opposed him. He denounced the enterprise
as unjust and contrary to the will of the gods. Again, being of a prophetic
stock, descended from Melampus, he foretold the
certain death both of himself and of the principal leaders, should they involve
themselves as accomplices in the mad violence of Tydeus or the criminal ambition of Polynikes. Amphiaraus, already distinguished both in the Kalychinian boar-hunt and in the funeral games of Pelias, was in the Theban war the most conspicuous of all
the heroes, and absolutely indispensable to its success. But his reluctance to
engage in it was invincible, nor was it possible to prevail upon him except
through the influence of his wife Eriphyle. Polynikes, having brought with him from Thebes the splendid
robe and necklace given by the gods to Harmonia on
her marriage with Cadmus, offered it as a bribe to Eriphyle,
on condition that she would influence the determination of Amphiaraus.
The sordid wife, seduced by so matchless a present, betrayed the lurking-place
of her husband, and involved him in the fatal expedition. Amphiaraus,
reluctantly dragged forth, and foreknowing the disastrous issue of the
expedition both to himself and to his associates, addressed his last
injunctions, at the moment of mounting his chariot, to his sons Alkmaeon and Amphilochus,
commanding Alkmaeon to avenge his approaching death
by killing the venal Eriphyle, and by undertaking a
second expedition against Thebes.
The Attic dramatists describe this expedition as
having been conducted by seven chiefs, one to each of the seven celebrated
gates of Thebes. But the Cyclic Thebais gave to it a much more comprehensive
character, mentioning auxiliaries from Arcadia, Messene, and various parts of
Peloponnesus; and the application of Tydeus and Polynikes at Mycenae in the course of their circuit made to
collect allies, is mentioned in the Iliad. They were well received at Mycenae;
but the warning signals given by the gods were so terrible that no Mycenaean
could venture to accompany them. The seven principal chiefs however were Adrastus, Amphiaraus, Kapaneus, Hippomedon, Parthenopaeus, Tydeus and Polynikes.
When the army had advanced as far as the river Asifipus, a halt was made for sacrifice and banquet; while Tydeus was sent to Thebes as envoy to demand the
restoration of Polynikes to his rights. His demand
was refused; but finding the chief Cadmeians assembled at the banquet in the house of Eteoklus, he
challenged them all to contend with him in boxing or wrestling. So efficacious
was the aid of the goddess Athene that he overcame them all; and the Cadmeians were so indignant at their defeat, that they
placed an ambuscade of fifty men to intercept him in his way back to the army.
All of them perished by the band of this warrior, small in stature and of few
words, but desperate and irresistible in the fight. One alone was spared in
consequence of special signals from the gods.
The Cadmeians,
assisted by their allies the Phocaeans and the Phlegyae,
marched out to resist the invaders, and fought a battle near the Ismenian hill, in which they were defeated and forced to
retire within the walls. The prophet Teiresias acquainted them that if Menoekeus, son of Kreon, would offer himself as a victim to Ares, victory
would be assured to Thebes. The generous youth, as soon as he learnt that his
life was to be the price of safety to his country, went and slew himself before
the gates. The heroes along with Adrastus now
commenced a vigorous attack upon the town, each of the seven selecting one of
the gates to assault. The contest was long and strenuously maintained but the
devotion of Menoekeus had procured for the Thebans
the protection of the gods. Parthenopaeus was killed
with a stone by Periklymenus; and when the furious Kapaneus, having planted a scaling-ladder, had mounted the
walls, he was smitten by a thunderbolt from Zeus and cast down dead upon the
earth. This event struck terror into the Argeians,
and Adrastus called back his troops from the attack.
The Thebans now sallied forth to pursue them, when Eteokles,
arresting the battle, proposed to decide the controversy by single combat with
his brother. The challenge, eagerly accepted by Polynikes,
was agreed to by Adrastus: a single combat ensued
between the two brothers, in which both were exasperated to fury and both
ultimately slain by each other's hand. This equal termination left the result
of the general contest still undetermined, and the bulk of the two armies
renewed the fight. In the sanguinary struggle which ensued the sons of Astakus on the Theban side displayed the most conspicuous
and successful valor. One of them, Melanippus,
mortally wounded Tydeus — while two others, Leades and Amphidikus, killed Eteoklus and Hippomedon. Amphiaraus avenged Tydeus by
killing Melanippus; but unable to arrest the rout of
the army, he fled with the rest, closely pursued by Periklymenus.
The latter was about to pierce him with his spear, when the beneficence of Zeus
rescued him from this disgrace—miraculously opening the earth under him, so
that Amphiaraus with his chariot and horses was
received unscathed into her bosom. The exact spot where this memorable incident
happened was indicated by a sepulchral building, and shown by the Thebans down
to the days of Pausanias—its sanctity being attested by the fact, that no
animal would consent to touch the herbage which grew within the sacred inclosure. Amphiaraus, rendered
immortal by Zeus, was worshipped as a god at Argos, at Thebes and at Orepus —and for many centuries gave answers at his oracle
to the questions of the pious applicant.
Adrastus, thus deprived of the prophet and warrior whom
he regarded as “the eye of his army”, and having seen the other chiefs killed
in the disastrous fight, was forced to take flight singly, and was preserved by
the matchless swiftness of his horse Areion, the
offspring of Poseidon. He reached Argos on his return, bringing with him
nothing except “his garments of woe and his black-manned steed”.
ANTIGONE
Kreon, father of the heroic youth Menoekeus,
succeeding to the administration of Thebes after the death of the two hostile
brothers and the repulse of Adrastus, caused Eteokles to be buried with distinguished honor, but cast
out ignominiously the body of Polynikes as a traitor
to his country, forbidding everyone on pain of death to consign it to the tomb.
He likewise refused permission to Adrastus to inter
the bodies of his fallen comrades. This proceeding, so offensive to Grecian
feeling, gave rise to two further tales; one of them at least of the highest
pathos and interest. Antigone, the sister of Polynikes,
heard with indignation the revolting edict consigning her brother’s body to the
dogs and vultures, and depriving it of those rites which were considered
essential to the repose of the dead. Unmoved by the dissuading counsel of an
affectionate but timid sister, and unable to procure assistance, she determined
to brave the hazard and to bury the body with her own hands. She was detected
in the act; and Kreon, though forewarned by Teiresias of the consequences, gave orders that she should
be buried alive, as having deliberately set at naught the solemn edict of the
city. His son Haemon, to whom she was engaged to be
married, in vain interceded for her life. In an agony of despair he slew
himself in the sepulcher to which the living Antigone had been consigned; and
his mother Eurydike, the wife of Kreon,
inconsolable for his death, perished by her own hand. And thus the new light
which seemed to be springing up over the last remaining scion of the devoted
family of Oedipus, is extinguished amidst gloom and horrors—which overshadowed
also the house and dynasty of Kreon.
The other tale stands more apart from the
original legend, and seems to have had its origin in the patriotic pride of the
Athenians. Adrastus, unable to obtain permission from
the Thebans to inter the fallen chieftains, presented himself in suppliant
guise, accompanied by their disconsolate mothers, to Theseus at Eleusis. He
implored the Athenian warrior to extort from the perverse Thebans that last
melancholy privilege which no decent or pious Greeks ever thought of
withholding, and thus to stand forth as the champion of Grecian public morality
in one of its most essential points, not less than of the rights of the
subterranean gods. The Thebans obstinately persisting in their refusal, Theseus
undertook an expedition against their city, vanquished them in the field, and
compelled them by force of arms to permit the sepulture of their fallen enemies.
This chivalrous interposition, celebrated in one of the preserved dramas of
Euripides, formed a subject of glorious recollection to the Athenians
throughout the historical age: their orators dwelt upon it in terms of animated
panegyric; and it seems to have been accepted as a real fact of the past time,
with no less implicit conviction than the battle of Marathon. But the Thebans,
though equally persuaded of the truth of the main story, dissented from the
Athenian version of it, maintaining that they had given up the bodies for
sepulture voluntarily and of their own accord. The tomb of the chieftains was
shown near Eleusis even ill the days of Pausanias.
SECOND EXPEDITION.—THE EPIGONI.
The defeat of the seven chiefs before Thebes was
amply avenged by their sons, again under the guidance of Adrastus: Egialeus son of Adrastus, Thersander son of Polynikes, Alkmaeon and Amphilochus, sons of Amphiaraus, Diomedes son of Tydeus, Sthenelus son of Kapaneus, Promachus son of Parthenopaeus,
and Euryalus son of Mekistheus, joined in this
expedition. Though all these youthful warriors, called the Epigoni, took part
in the expedition, the grand and prominent place appears to have been occupied
by Alkmaeon, son of Amphiaraus.
Assistance was given to them from Corinth and Megara, as well as from Messena and Arcadia; while Zeus manifested his favorable
dispositions by signals not to be mistaken. At the river Glisas the Epigoni were met by the Theban in arms, and a battle took place in which
the latter were completely defeated. Laodamas, son of Eteokles, killed Egialeus,
son of Adrastus; but he and his army were routed and
driven within the walls by the valor and energy of Alkmaeon.
The defeated Cadmeians consulted the prophet Teiresias, who informed them that the gods had declared for
their enemies, and that there was no longer any hope of successful resistance.
By his advice they sent a herald to the assailants offering to surrender the
town, while they themselves convoyed away their wives and children, and fled
under the command of Laodamas to the Illyrians, upon
which the Epigoni entered Thebes, and established Thersander,
son of Polynikes, on the throne.
Adrastus, who in the former expedition had been the
single survivor amongst so many fallen companions, now found himself the only
exception to the general triumph and joy of the conquerors: he had lost his son Egialeus, and the violent sorrow arising from the
event prematurely cut short his life. His soft voice and persuasive eloquence
were proverbial in the ancient epic. He was worshipped as a hero both at Argos
and at Sicyon, but with especial solemnity in the last-mentioned place, where
his Heroum stood in the public agora, and where his
exploits as well as his sufferings were celebrated periodically in lyric
tragedies. Melanippus, son of Astakus,
the brave defender of Thebes, who had slain both Tydeus and Mekistheus, was worshipped with no less solemnity
by the Thebans. The enmity of these two heroes rendered it impossible for both
of them to be worshipped close upon the same spot. Accordingly it came to pass
during the historical period, about the time of the Solonian legislation at Athens, that Kleisthenes, despot of
Sicyon, wishing to banish the hero Adrastus and
abolish the religious solemnities celebrated in honor of the latter by the Sicyonians, first applied to the Delphian oracle for permission to carry this banishment into effect directly and
forcibly. That permission being refused, ho next sent to Thebes an intimation
that he was anxious to introduce their hero Melanippus into Sicyon. The Thebans willingly consented, and he assigned to the new hero a
consecrated spot in the strongest and most commanding portion of the Sicyonian prytaneium. He did this
(says the historian) “knowing that Adrastus would
forthwith go away of his own accord; since Melanippus was of all persons the most odious to him, as having slain both his son-in-law
and his brother”. Kleisthenes moreover diverted the
festivals and sacrifices which had been offered to Adrastus,
to the newly established hero Melanippus; and the
lyric tragedies from the worship of Adrastus to that
of Dionysus. But his dynasty did not long continue after his decease, and the Sicyonians then reestablished their ancient solemnities.
Near the Proetid gate
of Thebes were seen the tombs of two combatants who had hated each other during
life even more than Adrastus and Melanippus the two brothers Eteokles and Polynikes.
Even as heroes and objects of worship, they still continued to manifest their
inextinguishable hostility: those who offered sacrifices to them observed that
the flame and the smoke from the two adjoining altars abhorred all communion,
and flew off in directions exactly opposite. The Theban exegetes assured
Pausanias of this fact. And though he did not himself witness it, yet having
seen with his own eyes a miracle not very dissimilar at Pionis in Mysia, he had no difficulty in crediting their
assertion.
ALKMAEON
Amphiaraus when forced into the first attack of
Thebes—against his own foreknowledge and against the warnings of the gods had
enjoined his sons Alkmaeon and Amphilochus not only to avenge his death upon the Thebans, but also to punish the treachery
of their mother, “Eriphyle, the destroyer of her
husband”. In obedience to this command, and having obtained the sanction of the Delphian oracle, Alkmaeon slew his mother; but the awful Erinnys, the avenger
of matricide, inflicted on him a long and terrible punishment, depriving him of
his reason, and chasing him about from place to place without the possibility
of repose or peace of mind. He craved protection and cure from the god at
Delphi, who required him to dedicate at the temple, as an offering, the
precious necklace of Cadmus, that irresistible bribe which had originally
corrupted Eriphyle. He further intimated to the
unhappy sufferer, that though the whole earth was tainted with his crime, and
had become uninhabitable for him, yet there was a spot of ground which was not
under the eye of the sun at the time when the matricide was committed, and
where therefore Alkmaeon yet might find a tranquil
shelter. The promise was realized at the mouth of the river Achelous,
whose turbid stream was perpetually depositing new earth and forming additional
islands. Upon one of these, near Eniadae, Alkmaeon settled, permanently and in peace: he became the
primitive hero of Acarnania, to which his son Acarnan gave name. The necklace was found among the treasures of Delphi, together with
that which had been given by Aphrodite to Helen, by the Phokian plunderers who stripped the temple in the time of Philip of Macedon. The Phokian women quarreled about these valuable ornaments: and
we are told that the necklace of Eriphyle was
allotted to a woman of gloomy and malignant disposition, who ended by putting
her husband to death; that of Helen to a beautiful but volatile wife, who
abandoned her husband from preference for a young Epirot.
There were several other legends respecting the
distracted Alkmaeon, either appropriated or invented
by the Attic tragedians. He went to Phegeus, king of Psophis in Arcadia, whose daughter Arsinoe he married,
giving as a nuptial present the necklace of Eriphyle.
Being however unable to remain there, in consequence of the unremitting
persecutions of the maternal Erinnys, he sought
shelter at the residence of king Acheous, whose
daughter Kallirhoe he made his wife, and on whose
soil he obtained repose. But Kallirhoe would not be
satisfied without the possession of the necklace of Eriphyle,
and Alkmaeon went back to Psophis to fetch it, where Phegeus and his sons slew him. He
had left twin sons, infants, with Kallirhoe, who
prayed fervently to Zeus that they might be preternaturally invested with
immediate manhood, in order to revenge the murder of their father. Her prayer
was granted, and her sons Amphoterus and Acarnan, having instantaneously sprung up to manhood,
proceeded into Arcadia, slew the murderers of their father, and brought away
the necklace of Eriphyle, which they carried to
Delphi
Euripides deviated still more widely from the
ancient epic, by making Alkmaeon the husband of Manto, daughter of Teiresias, and
the father of Amphilochus. According to the Cyclic
Thebais, Manto was consigned by the victorious
Epigoni as a special offering to the Delphian god;
and Amphilochus was son of Amphiaraus,
not son of Alkmaeon. He was the eponymous hero of the
town called the Amphilochian Argos, in Acarnania, on
the shore of the Gulf of Ambrakia. Thucydides tells
us that he went thither on his return from the Trojan war, being dissatisfied
with the state of affairs which he found at the Peloponnesian Argos. The Acarnanians were remarkable for the numerous prophets which
they supplied to the rest of Greece: their heroes were naturally drawn from the
great prophetic race of the Melampodids.
Thus ends the legend of the two sieges of
Thebes; the greatest event, except the siege of Troy, in the ancient epic; the
greatest enterprise of war, between Greeks and Greeks, during the time of those
who are called the Heroes.
WE now arrive at the capital and culminating
point of the Grecian epic,—the two sieges and capture of Troy, with the
destinies of the dispersed heroes, Trojan as well as Grecian, after the second
and most celebrated capture and destruction of the city. It would require a
large volume to convey any tolerable idea of the vast extent and expansion of
this interesting fable, first handled by so many poets, epic, lyric and tragic,
with their endless additions, transformations and contradictions,—then purged and
recast by historical inquirers, who under color of setting aside the
exaggerations of the poets, introduced a new vein of prosaic invention,—lastly,
moralized and allegorized by philosophers. In the present brief outline of the
general field of Grecian legend, or of that which the Greeks believed to be
their antiquities, the Trojan war can be regarded as only one among a large
number of incidents upon which Hekataeus and Herodotus looked back as
constituting their foretime. Taken as a special legendary event, it is indeed
of wider and larger interest than any other, but it is a mistake to single it
out from the rest as if it rested upon a different and more trustworthy basis.
I must therefore confine myself to an abridged narrative of the current and
leading facts; and amidst the numerous contradictory statements which are to be
found respecting every one of them, I know no better ground of preference than
comparative antiquity, though even the oldest tales which we possess— those
contained in the Iliad—evidently presuppose others of prior date.
The primitive ancestor of the Trojan line of
kings is Dardanus, son of Zeus, founder and eponymous of Dardania: in the
account of later authors, Dardanus was called the son of Zeus by Elektra,
daughter of Atlas, and was further said to have come from Samothrace, or from
Arcadia, or from Italy but of this Homer mentions nothing. The first Dardanian town founded by him was in a lofty position on
the descent of Mount Ida; for he was not yet strong enough to establish himself
on the plain. But his son Erichthonius, by the favor of Zeus, became the
wealthiest of mankind. His flocks and herds having multiplied, he had in his
pastures three thousand mares, the offspring of some of whom, by Boreas,
produced horses of preternatural swiftness. Tros, the son of Erichthonius, and
the eponym of the Trojans, had three sons—Ilus, Assaracus, and the beautiful Ganymedes,
whom Zeus stole away to become his cup-bearer in Olympus, giving to his father
Tros, as the price of the youth, a team of immortal horses.
From Ilus and Assaracus the Trojan and Dardanian lines diverge; the former passing from Ilus to
Laomedon, Priam and Hector; the latter from Assaracus to Capys, Anchises and Aeneas.
Ilus founded in the plain of Troy the holy city of Ilium; Assaracus and his
descendants remained sovereigns of Dardania.
It was under the proud Laomedon, son of Ilus,
that Poseidon and Apollo underwent, by command of Zeus, a temporary servitude;
the former building the walls of the town, the latter tending the flocks and
herds. When their task was completed and the penal period had expired, they
claimed the stipulated reward; but Laomedon angrily repudiated their demand,
and even threatened to cut off their ears, to tie them hand and foot, and to
sell them in some distant island as slaves. He was punished for this treachery
by a sea-monster, whom Poseidon sent to ravage his fields and to destroy his
subjects. Laomedon publicly offered the immortal horses given by Zeus to his
father Tros, as a reward to anyone who would destroy the monster. But an oracle
declared that a virgin of noble blood must be surrendered to him, and the lot
fell upon Hesione, daughter of Laomedon himself.
Heracles arriving at this critical moment, killed the monster by the aid of a
fort built for him by Athena and the Trojans, so as to rescue both the exposed
maiden and the people; but Laomedon, by a second act of perfidy, gave him
mortal horses in place of the matchless animals which had been promised. Thus
defrauded of his due, Heracles equipped six ships, attacked and captured Troy
and killed Laomedon, giving Hesione to his friend and
auxiliary Telamon, to whom she bore the celebrated archer Teukros.
A painful sense of this expedition was preserved among the inhabitants of the
historical town of Ilium, who offered no worship to Heracles.
Among all the sons of Laomedon, Priam was the
only one who had remonstrated against the refusal of the well-earned guerdon of
Heracles; for which the hero recompensed him by placing him on the throne. Many
and distinguished were his sons and daughters, as well by his wife Hecuba,
daughter of Kisseus, as by other women. Among the
sons were Hector, Paris, Daiphobus, Helenus, Troilus, Polites, Polyderus; among the daughters Laodike, Kreusa, Polyxena, and Cassandra.
The birth of Paris was preceded by formidable
presages; for Hecuba dreamt that she was delivered of a firebrand, and Priam,
on consulting the soothsayers, was informed that the son about to be born would
prove fatal to him. Accordingly he directed the child to be exposed on Mount
Ida; but the inauspicious kindness of the gods preserved him, and he grew up
amidst the flocks and herds, active and beautiful, fair of hair and symmetrical
in person, and the special favorite of Aphrodite.
It was to this youth, in his solitary shepherd's
walk on Mount Ida, that the three goddesses Here, Athene, and Aphrodite were
conducted, in order that he might determine the dispute respecting their
comparative beauty, which had arisen at the nuptials of Peleus and Thetis,—a
dispute brought about in pursuance of the arrangement, and in accomplishment of
the deep-laid designs, of Zeus. For Zeus, remarking with pain the immoderate
numbers of the then existing heroic race, pitied the earth for the overwhelming
burden which she was compelled to bear, and determined to lighten it by
exciting a destructive and long-continued war.
Paris awarded the palm of beauty to Aphrodite,
who promised him in recompense the possession of Helena, wife of the Spartan
Menelaus,—the daughter of Zeus and the fairest of living women. At the instance
of Aphrodite, ships were built for him, and be embarked on the enterprise so
fraught with eventual disaster to his native city, in spite of the menacing
prophecies of his brother Helenus, and the always
neglected warnings of Cassandra.
Paris, on arriving at Sparta, was hospitably
entertained by Menelaus as well as by Castor and Pollux,
and was enabled to present the rich gifts which he had brought to Helen.
Menelaus then departed to Crete, leaving Helen to entertain his Trojan guest—a
favorable moment which was employed by Aphrodite to bring about the intrigue
and the elopement. Paris carried away with him both Helen and a large sum of
money belonging to Menelaus— made a prosperous voyage to Troy—and arrived there
safely with his prize on the third day.
Menelaus, informed by Iris in Crete of the
perfidious return made by Paris for his hospitality, hastened home in grief and
indignation to consult with his brother Agamemnon, as well as with the
venerable Nestor, on the means of avenging the outrage. They made known the
event to the Greek chiefs around them: among whom they found universal
sympathy: Nestor, Palamedes and others went round to solicit aid in a
contemplated attack of Troy, under the command of Agamemnon, to whom each chief
promised both obedience and unwearied exertion until Helen should be recovered.
Ten years were spent in equipping the expedition. The goddesses Here and
Athene, incensed at the preference given by Paris to Aphrodite, and animated by
steady attachment to Argos, Sparta and Mycenae, took an active part in the
cause; and the horses of Here were fatigued with her repeated visits to the
different parts of Greece.
By such efforts a force was at length assembled
at Aulis in Boeotia, consisting of 1186 ships and more than 100,000 men,—a
force outnumbering by more than ten to one anything that the Trojans themselves
could oppose, and superior to the defenders of Troy even with all her allies
included. It comprised heroes with their followers from the extreme points of
Greece—from the north-western portions of Thessaly under Mount Olympus, as well
as the western islands of Dulichium and Ithaca, and
the eastern islands of Crete and Rhodes. Agamemnon himself contributed 100
ships manned with the subjects of his kingdom of Mycenae, besides furnishing 60
ships to the Arcadians, who possessed none of their own. Menelaus brought with
him 60 ships, Nestor from Pylus 90, Idomeneus from Crete and Diomedes from Argos 80 each. Forty
ships were manned by the Eleians, under four different chiefs; the like number
under Meges from Dulichium and the Echinades, and under Thoas from Kalydon and the other Aetolian towns. Odysseus from Ithaca,
and Ajax from Salamis, brought 12 ships each. The Abantes from Euboea, under Elephenor, filled 40 vessels; the Boeotians,
under Peneleus and Leitus,
50; the inhabitants of Orchomenus and Aspledon, 30;
the light-armed Locrians, under Ajax son of Oileus, 40; the Phokians as many.
The Athenians, under Menestheus, a chief distinguished
for his skill in marshaling an army, mustered 50 ships; the Myrmidons from Phthia and Hellas, under Achilles, assembled in 50 ships; Protesilaus from Phylake and Pyrasus, and Eurypylus from Ormenium, each came with 40 ships; Machaon and Podaleirius, from Trikka,
with 30; Aumelus, from Pherae and the lake Boebeis, with 11; and Philoktetes from Meliboea with 7: the Lapitha,
under Polypcetes, son of Peirithous, filled 40
vessels; the Enianes and Perrhaebians,
under Guneus, 22; and the Magnetes under Prothous, 40; these last two were from the
northernmost parts of Thessaly, near the mountains Pelion and Olympus. From
Rhodes, under Tlepolemus, son of Heracles, appeared 9
ships; from Syme, under the comely but effeminate Nireus, 3; from Kos, Krapathus and
the neighboring islands, 30, under the orders of Pheidippus and Antiphus, sons of Thessalus and grandsons of Heracles.
ACHILLES.—AJAX.—ODYSSEUS.
Among this band of heroes were included the
distinguished warriors Ajax and Diomedes, and the sagacious Nestor; while
Agamemnon himself, scarcely inferior to either of them in prowess, brought with
him a high reputation for prudence in command. But the most marked and
conspicuous of all were Achilles and Odysseus; the former a beautiful youth
born of a divine mother, swift in the race, of fierce temper and irresistible
might; the latter not less efficient as an ally from his eloquence, his
untiring endurance, his inexhaustible resources under difficulty, and the
mixture of daring courage with deep-laid cunning which never deserted him: the
blood of the arch-deceiver Sisyphus, through an illicit connection with his
mother Antikleia, was said to flow in his veins, and
he was especially patronized and protected by the goddess Athene. Odysseus,
unwilling at first to take part in the expedition, had even simulated insanity;
but Palamedes, sent to Ithaca to invite him, tested the reality of his madness
by placing in the furrow where Odysseus was ploughing,
his infant son Telemachus. Thus detected, Odysseus could not refuse to join the
Achaean host, but the prophet Halitherses predicted
to him that twenty years would elapse before he revisited his native land. To
Achilles the gods had promised the full effulgence of heroic glory before the
walls of Troy; nor could the place be taken without both his cooperation and
that of his son after him. But they had forewarned him that this brilliant
career would be rapidly brought to a close; and that if he desired a long life,
he must remain tranquil and inglorious in his native land. In spite of the
reluctance of his mother Thetis, he preferred few years with bright renown, and
joined the Achaean host. When Nestor and Odysseus came to Phthia to invite him, both he and his intimate friend Patroclus eagerly obeyed the
call.
Agamemnon and his powerful host set sail from
Aulis; but being ignorant of the locality and the direction, they landed by
mistake in Teuthrania, a part of Mysia near the river Kaikus, and began to ravage the
country under the persuasion that it was the neighborhood of Troy. Telephus, the king of the country, opposed and repelled
them, but was ultimately defeated and severely wounded by Achilles. The Greeks
now, discovering their mistake, retired; but their fleet was dispersed by a
storm and driven back to Greece. Achilles attacked and took Skyrus,
and there married Deidamia, the daughter of Lycomedes. Telephus, suffering
from his wounds, was directed by the oracle to come to Greece and present
himself to Achilles to be healed, by applying the scrapings of the spear with
which the wound had been given: thus restored, he became the guide of the
Greeks when they were prepared to renew their expedition.
The armament was again assembled at Aulis, but
the goddess Artemis, displeased with the boastful language of Agamemnon,
prolonged the duration of adverse winds, and the offending chief was compelled
to appease her by the well-known sacrifice of his daughter Iphigenia. They then
proceeded to Tenedos, from whence Odysseus and
Menelaus were dispatched as envoys to Troy, to redemand Helen and the stolen property. In spite of the prudent counsels of Antenor, who
received the two Grecian chiefs with friendly hospitality, the Trojans rejected
the demand, and the attack was resolved upon. It was foredoomed by the gods
that the Greek who first landed should perish: Protesilaus was generous enough to put himself upon this forlorn hope, and accordingly fell
by the hand of Hector.
Meanwhile the Trojans had assembled a large body
of allies from various parts of Asia Minor and Thrace: Dardanians under Aeneas, Lycians under Sarpedon, Mysians, Carians, Maeonians, Alizonians, Phrygians, Thracians, and Paeonians.
But vain was the attempt to oppose the landing of the Greeks: the Trojans were
routed, and even the invulnerable Cycnus, son of Poseidon,
one of the great bulwarks of the defense, was slain by Achilles. Having driven
the Trojans within their walls, Achilles attacked and stormed Lyrnessus, Pedasus, Lesbos and other places in the neighborhood,
twelve towns on the sea-coast and eleven in the interior; he drove off the oxen
of Aeneas and pursued the hero himself, who narrowly escaped with his life: he
surprised and killed the youthful Troilus, son of Priam, and captured several
of the other sons, whom he sold as prisoners into the islands of the Aegean. He
acquired as his captive the fair Briseis, while Chryseis was awarded to
Agamemnon: he was moreover eager to see the divine Helen, the prize and
stimulus of this memorable struggle; and Aphrodite and Thetis contrived to
bring about an interview between them.
At this period of the war the Grecian army was
deprived of Palamedes, one of its ablest chiefs. Odysseus had not forgiven the
artifice by which Palamedes had detected his simulated insanity, nor was be
without jealousy of a rival clever and cunning in a degree equal, if not
superior, to himself; one who had enriched the Greeks with the invention of
letters, of dice for amusement, of night-watches, as well as with other useful
suggestions. According to the old Cyprian epic, Palamedes was drowned while
fishing, by the hands of Odysseus and Diomedes. Neither in the Iliad nor the
Odyssey does the name of Palamedes occur: the lofty position which Odysseus
occupies in both those poems—noticed with some degree of displeasure even by
Pindar, who described Palamedes as the wiser man of the two—is sufficient to
explain the omission. But in the more advanced period of the Greek mind, when
intellectual superiority came to acquire a higher place in the public esteem as
compared with military prowess, the character of Palamedes, combined with his
unhappy fate, rendered him one of the most interesting personages in the Trojan
legend. Aeschylus, Sophocles and Euripides each consecrated to him a special
tragedy; but the mode of his death as described in the old epic was not
suitable to Athenian ideas, and accordingly he was represented as having been
falsely accused of treason by Odysseus, who caused gold to be buried in his
tent, and persuaded Agamemnon and the Grecian chiefs that Palamedes had
received it from the Trojans. He thus forfeited his life, a victim to the
calumny of Odysseus and to the delusion of the leading Greeks. In the last
speech made by the philosopher Socrates to his Athenian judges, he alludes with
solemnity and fellow-feeling to the unjust condemnation of Palamedes, as
analogous to that which he himself was about to suffer, and his companions seem
to have dwelt with satisfaction on the comparison. Palamedes passed for an
instance of the slanderous enmity and misfortune which so often wait upon
superior genius.
In these expeditions the Grecian army consumed
nine years, during which the subdued Trojans dared not give battle without
their walls for fear of Achilles. Ten years was the fixed epical duration of
the siege of Troy, just as five years was the duration of the siege of Kamikus by the Cretan armament which came to avenge the
death of Minos: ten years of preparation, ten years of siege, and ten years of
wandering for Odysseus, were periods suited to the rough chronological dashes
of the ancient epic, and suggesting no doubts nor difficulties with the
original hearers. But it was otherwise when the same events came to be
contemplated by the historicizing Greeks, who could not be satisfied without
either finding or inventing satisfactory bonds of coherence between the
separate events. Thucydides tells us that the Greeks were less numerous than
the poets have represented, and that being moreover very poor, they were unable
to procure adequate and constant provisions: hence they were compelled to
disperse their army, and to employ a part of it in cultivating the
Chersonese,—a part in marauding expeditions over the neighborhood. Could the
whole army have been employed against Troy at once (he says), the siege would
have been much more speedily and easily concluded. If the great historian could
permit himself thus to amend the legend in so many points, we might have
imagined that the simpler course would have been to include the duration of the
siege among the list of poetical exaggerations, and to affirm that the real
siege had lasted only one year instead of ten. But it seems that the ten years’
duration was so capital a feature in the ancient tale, that no critic ventured
to meddle with it.
A period of comparative intermission however was
now at hand for the Trojans. The gods brought about the memorable fit of anger
of Achilles, under the influence of which he refused to put on his armor, and
kept his Myrmidons in camp. According to the Cypria,
this was the behest of Zeus, who had compassion on the Trojans: according to
the Iliad, Apollo was the originating cause, from anxiety to avenge the injury
which his priest Chryses had endured from Agamemnon.
For a considerable time, the combats of the Greeks against Troy were conducted
without their best warrior, and severe indeed was the humiliation which they
underwent in consequence. How the remaining Grecian chiefs vainly strove to
make amends for his absence how Hector and the Trojans defeated and drove them
to their ships—how the actual blaze of the destroying flame, applied by Hector
to the ship of Protesilaus, roused up the anxious and
sympathizing Patroclus, and extorted a reluctant consent from Achilles, to
allow his friend and his followers to go forth and avert the last extremity of
ruin—how Achilles, when Patroclus had been killed by Hector, forgetting his
anger in grief for the death of his friend, reentered the fight, drove the
Trojans within their walls with immense slaughter, and satiated his revenge
both upon the living and the dead Hector—all these events have been chronicled,
together with those divine dispensations on which most of them are made to
depend, in the immortal verse of the Iliad.
Homer breaks off with the burial of Hector,
whose body has just been ransomed by the disconsolate Priam; while the lost
poem of Arktinus, entitled the Ethiopis,
so far as we can judge from the argument still remaining of it, handled only
the subsequent events of the siege. The poem of Quintus Smyrnaeus,
composed about the fourth century of the Christian era, seems in its first
books to coincide with the Ethiopis, in the
subsequent books partly with the Ilias Minor of Lesches.
The Trojans, dismayed by the death of Hector,
were again animated with hope by the appearance of the warlike and beautiful
queen of the Amazons, Penthesileia, daughter of Ares,
hitherto invincible in the field, who came to their assistance from Thrace at
the head of a band of her countrywomen. She again led the besieged without the
walls to encounter the Greeks in the open field; and under her auspices the
latter were at first driven back, until she too was slain by the invincible arm
of Achilles. The victor, on taking off the helmet of his fair enemy as she lay
on the ground, was profoundly affected and captivated by her charms, for which
he was scornfully taunted by Thersites: exasperated by this rash insult, he
killed Thersites on the spot with a blow of his fist. A violent dispute among
the Grecian chiefs was the result, for Diomedes, the kinsman of Thersites,
warmly resented the proceeding; and Achilles was obliged to go to Lesbos, where
he was purified from the act of homicide by Odysseus.
Next arrived Memnon,
son of Tithonus and Eos, the most stately of living
men, with a powerful band of black Ethiopians, to the assistance of Troy.
Sallying forth against the Greeks, he made great havoc among them: the brave
and popular Antilochus perished by his hand, a victim
to filial devotion in defense of Nestor. Achilles at length attacked him, and
for a long time the combat was doubtful between them: the prowess of Achilles
and the supplication of Thetis with Zeus finally prevailed; whilst Eos obtained
for her vanquished son the consoling gift of immortality. His tomb, however,
was shown near the Propontis, within a few miles of
the mouth of the river Esepus, and was visited
annually by the birds called Memnonides, who swept it
and bedewed it with water from the stream. So the traveler Pausanias was told,
even in the second century after the Christian era, by the Hellespontine Greeks.
But the fate of Achilles himself was now at
hand. After routing the Trojans and chasing them into the town, he was slain
near the Skaean gate by an arrow from the quiver of
Paris, directed under the unerring auspices of Apollo. The greatest efforts
were made by the Trojans to possess themselves of the body, which was however
rescued and borne off to the Grecian camp by the valor of Ajax and Odysseus.
Bitter was the grief of Thetis for the loss of her son: she came into the camp
with the Muses and the Nereids to mourn over him; and
when a magnificent funeral-pile had been prepared by the Greeks to burn him
with every mark of honor, she stole away the body and conveyed it to a renewed
and immortal life in the island of Leuke in the
Euxine Sea. According to some accounts he was there blest with the nuptials and
company of Helen.
Thetis celebrated splendid funeral games in
honor of her son, and offered the unrivalled panoply, which Hephaestus had
forged and wrought for him, as a prize to the most distinguished warrior in the
Grecian army. Odysseus and Ajax became rivals for the distinction, when Athena,
together with some Trojan prisoners, who were asked from which of the two their
country had sustained greatest injury, decided in favor of the former. The
gallant Ajax lost his senses with grief and humiliation: in a fit of frenzy he
slew some sheep, mistaking them for the men who had wronged him, and then fell
upon his own sword.
Odysseus now learnt from Helenus son of Priam, whom he had captured in an ambuscade, that Troy could not be
taken unless both Philoktetes, and Neoptolemus, son
of Achilles, could be prevailed upon to join the besiegers. The former, having
been stung in the foot by a serpent, and becoming insupportable to the Greeks
from the stench of his wound, had been left at Lemnus in the commencement of the expedition, and had spent ten years in misery on
that desolate island; but he still possessed the peerless bow and arrows of
Heracles, which were said to be essential to the capture of Troy. Diomedes
fetched Philoktetes from Lemnus to the Grecian camp, where he was healed by the skill of Machaon,
and took an active part against the Trojans—engaging in single combat with
Paris, and killing him with one of the Herakleian arrows. The Trojans were allowed to carry away for burial the body of this
prince, the fatal cause of all their sufferings; but not until it had been
mangled by the hand of Menelaus. Odysseus went to the island of Skyrus to invite Neoptolemus to the army. The untried but
impetuous youth gladly obeyed the call, and received from Odysseus his father’s
armor, while on the other hand, Eurypylus, son of Telephus, came from Mysia as
auxiliary to the Trojans and rendered to them valuable service—turning the tide
of fortune for a time against the Greeks, and killing some of their bravest
chiefs, amongst whom was numbered Peneleos, and the unrivalled leech Maehaon. The exploits of Neoptolemus were numerous, worthy
of the glory of his race and the renown of his father. He encountered and slew Eurypylus, together with numbers of the Mysian warriors: he routed the Trojans and drove them within their walls, from whence
they never again emerged to give battle: nor was he less distinguished for his
good sense and persuasive diction, than for forward energy in the field.
Troy however was still impregnable so long as
the Palladium, a statue given by Zeus himself to Dardanus, remained in the
citadel; and great care had been taken by the Trojans not only to conceal this
valuable present, but to construct other statues so like it as to mislead any
intruding robber. Nevertheless the enterprising Odysseus, having disguised his
person with miserable clothing and self-inflicted injuries, found means to
penetrate into the city and to convey the Palladium by stealth away: Helen alone
recognized him; but she was now anxious to return to Greece, and even assisted
Odysseus in concerting means for the capture of the town.
To accomplish this object, one final stratagem
was resorted to. By the hands of Epeius of Panopeus, and at the suggestion of Athene, a capacious
hollow wooden horse was constructed, capable of containing one hundred men: the
élite of the Grecian heroes, Neoptolemus, Odysseus, Menelaus and others,
concealed themselves in the inside of it, and the entire Grecian army sailed
away to Tenedos, burning their tents and pretending
to have abandoned the siege. The Trojans, overjoyed to find themselves free,
issued from the city and contemplated with astonishment the fabric which their
enemies had left behind: they long doubted what should be done with it; and the
anxious heroes from within heard the surrounding consultations, as well as the
voice of Helen when she pronounced their names and counterfeited the accents of
their wives. Many of the Trojans were anxious to dedicate it to the gods in the
city as a token of gratitude for their deliverance; but the more cautious
spirits inculcated distrust of an enemy’s legacy; and Laocoon,
the priest of Poseidon, manifested his aversion by striking the side of the
horse with his spear. The sound revealed that the horse was hollow, but the
Trojans heeded not this warning of possible fraud; and the unfortunate Laocoon, a victim to his own sagacity and patriotism,
miserably perished before the eyes of his countrymen, together with one of his
sons, —two serpents being sent expressly by the gods out of the sea to destroy
him. By this terrific spectacle, together with the perfidious counsels of Sinon, a traitor whom the Greeks had left behind for the
special purpose of giving false information, the Trojans were induced to make a
breach in their own walls, and to drag the fatal fabric with triumph and
exultation into their city.
CAPTURE OF TROY.
The destruction of Troy, according to the decree
of the gods, was now irrevocably sealed. While the Trojans indulged in a night
of riotous festivity, Sinon kindled the fire-signal
to the Greeks at Tenedos, loosening the bolts of the
wooden horse, from out of which the enclosed heroes descended. The city,
assailed both from within and from without, was thoroughly sacked and
destroyed, with the slaughter or captivity of the larger portion of its heroes
as well as its people. The venerable Priam perished by the hand of Neoptolemus,
having in vain sought shelter at the domestic altar of Zeus Herkeios;
but his son Deiphobus, who since the death of Paris
had become the husband of Helen, defended his house desperately against
Odysseus and Menelaus, and sold his life dearly. After he was slain, his body
was fearfully mutilated by the latter.
Thus was Troy utterly destroyed — the city, the
altars and temples, and the population. Aeneas and Antenor were permitted to
escape, with their families, having been always more favorably regarded by the
Greeks than the remaining Trojans. According to one version of the story, they
had betrayed the city to the Greeks: a panther’s skin had been hung over the
door of Antenor’s house as a signal for the
victorious besiegers to spare it in the general plunder. In the distribution of
the principal captives, Astyanax, the infant son of
Hector, was cast from the top of the wall and killed, by Odysseus or
Neoptolemus: Polyxena, the daughter of Priam, was immolated on the tomb of
Achilles, in compliance with a requisition made by the shade of the deceased
hero to his countrymen; while her sister Cassandra was presented as a prize to
Agamemnon. She had sought sanctuary at the altar of Athene, where Ajax, the son
of Oileus, making a guilty attempt to seize her, had
drawn both upon himself and upon the army the serious wrath of the goddess,
insomuch that the Greeks could hardly be restrained from stoning him to death.
Andromache and Helenus were both given to
Neoptolemus, who, according to the Ilias Minor,
carried away also Aeneas as his captive.
Helen gladly resumed her union with Menelaus:
she accompanied him back to Sparta, and lived with him there many years in
comfort and dignity, passing afterwards to a happy immortality in the Elysian
fields. She was worshipped as a goddess with heir brothers the Dioskuri and her husband, having her temple, statue and
altar at Theraptnae and elsewhere, and various
examples of her miraculous interventions were cited among the Greeks. The lyric
poet Stesichorus had ventured to denounce her, conjointly with her sister
Clytemnestra, in a tone of rude and plain-spoken severity, resembling that of
Euripides and Lycophron afterwards, but strikingly
opposite to the delicacy and respect with which she is always handled by Homer,
who never admits reproaches against her except from her own lips. He was
smitten with blindness, and made sensible of his impiety; but having repented
and composed a special poem formally retracting the calumny, was permitted to
recover his sight. In his poem of recantation (the famous palinode now
unfortunately lost) he pointedly contradicted the Homeric narrative, affirming
that Helen had never been to Troy at all, and that the Trojans had carried
thither nothing but her image. It is, probably, to the excited religious
feelings of Stesichorus that we owe the first idea of this glaring deviation
from the old legend, which could never have been recommended by any
considerations of poetical interest.
Other versions were afterwards started, forming
a sort of compromise between Homer and Stesichorus, admitting that Helen had
never really been at Troy, without altogether denying her elopement. Such is
the story of her having been detained in Egypt during the whole term of the
siege. Paris, on his departure from Sparta, had been driven thither by storms,
and the Egyptian king Proteus, hearing of the grievous wrong which he had
committed towards Menelaus, had sent him away from the country with severe
menaces, detaining Helen until her lawful husband should come to seek her. When
the Greeks reclaimed Helen from Troy, the Trojans assured them solemnly, that
she neither was, nor ever had been, in the town; but the Greeks, treating this
allegation as fraudulent, prosecuted the siege until their ultimate success
confirmed the correctness of the statement, nor did Menelaus recover Helen
until, on his return from Troy, he visited Egypt. Such was the story told by
the Egyptian priests to Herodotus, and it appeared satisfactory to his
historicizing mind. “For if Helen had really been at Troy (he argues) she would
certainly have been given up, even had she been mistress of Priam himself
instead of Paris: the Trojan king, with all his family and all his subjects,
would never knowingly have incurred utter and irretrievable destruction for the
purpose of retaining her: their misfortune was, that while they did not possess,
and therefore could not restore her, they yet found it impossible to convince
the Greeks that such was the fact”. Assuming the historical character of the
war of Troy, the remark of Herodotus admits of no reply; nor can we greatly
wonder that he acquiesced in the tale of Helen's Egyptian detention, as a
substitute for the “incredible insanity” which the genuine legend imputes to
Priam and the Trojans. Pausanias, upon the same ground and by the same mode of
reasoning, pronounces that the Trojan horse must have been in point of fact a
battering-engine, because to admit the literal narrative would be to impute
utter childishness to the defenders of the city. And Mr. Payne Knight rejects
Helen altogether as the real cause of the Trojan war, though she may have been
the pretext of it; for he thinks that neither the Greeks nor the Trojans could
have been so mad and silly as to endure calamities of such magnitude “for one
little woman”. Mr. Knight suggests various political causes as substitutes;
these might deserve consideration, either if any evidence could be produced to
countenance them, or if the subject on which they are brought to bear could be
shown to belong to the domain of history.
RETURN OF THE GRECIAN HEROES.
The return of the Grecian chiefs from Troy
furnished matter to the ancient epic hardly less copious than the siege itself,
and the more susceptible of indefinite diversity, inasmuch as those who had
before acted in concert were now dispersed and isolated. Moreover the stormy
voyages and compulsory wanderings of the heroes exactly fell in with the common
aspirations after an heroic founder, and enabled even the most remote Hellenic
settlers to connect the origin of their town with this prominent event of their
ante-historical and semi-divine world. And an absence of ten years afforded
room for the supposition of many domestic changes in their native abode, and
many family misfortunes and misdeeds during the interval. One of these heroic
“Returns”, that of Odysseus, has been immortalized by the verse if Homer. The
hero, after a series of long-protracted suffering and expatriation, inflicted
on him by the anger of Poseidon, at last reaches his native island, but finds
his wife beset, his youthful son insulted, and his substance plundered, by a
troop of insolent suitors; he is forced to appear as a wretched beggar, and to
endure in his own person their scornful treatment; but finally, by the
interference of Athene coming in aid of his own courage and stratagem, he is
enabled to overwhelm his enemies, to resume his family position, and to recover
his property. The return of several other Grecian chiefs was the subject of an
epic poem by Hagias, which is now lost, but of which a brief abstract or
argument still remains: there were in antiquity various other poems of similar
title and analogous matter.
As usual with the ancient epic, the multiplied
sufferings of this back-voyage are traced to divine wrath, justly provoked by
the sins of the Greeks; who, in the fierce exultation of a victory purchased by
so many hardships, had neither respected nor event spared the altars of the
gods in Troy; and Athene, who had been their most zealous ally during the
siege, was so incensed by their final recklessness, more especially by the
outrage of Ajax, son of Oileus, that she actively
harassed and embittered their return, in spite of every effort to appease her.
The chiefs began to quarrel among themselves; their formal assembly became a
scene of drunkenness; even Agamemnon and Menelaus lost their fraternal harmony,
and each man acted on his own separate resolution. Nevertheless, according to
the Odyssey, Nestor, Diomedes, Neoptolemus, Idomeneus and Philoktetes reached home speedily and safely:
Agamemnon also arrived in Peloponnesus, to perish by the hand of a treacherous
wife; but Menelaus was condemned to long wanderings and to the severest
privations in Egypt, Cyprus and elsewhere, before he could set foot in his
native land. The Lokrian Ajax perished on the Gyraean rock. Though exposed to a terrible storm, he had
already reached this place of safety, when he indulged in the rash boast of
having escaped in defiance of the gods: no sooner did Poseidon hear this
language, than he struck with his trident the rock which Ajax was grasping and
precipitated both into the sea. Kalchas the
soothsayer, together with Leonteus and Polypoetes, proceeded by land from Troy to Kolophon.
UBIQUITY OF THE RETURNING HEROES.
In respect however to these and other Grecian
heroes, tales were told different from those in the Odyssey, assigning to them
a long expatriation and a distant home. Nestor went to Italy, where he founded
Metapontum, Pisa and Herakleia: Philoktetes also went
to Italy, founded Petilia and Krimisa,
and sent settlers to Egesta in Sicily. Neoptolemus,
under the advice of Thetis, marched by land across Thrace, met with Odysseus,
who had come by sea, at Maroneia, and then pursued
his journey to Epirus, where he became king of the Molossians. Idomeneus came to Italy, and founded Uria in the Salentine peninsula.
Diomedes, after wandering far and wide, went along the Italian coast into the
innermost Adriatic gulf, and finally settled in Daunia,
founding the cities of Argyrippa, Beneventum,
Atria and Diomedeia: by the favor of Athene he became
immortal, and was worshipped as a god in many different places. The Lokrian followers of Ajax founded the Epizephyrian Lokri on the southernmost corner of Italy, besides
another settlement in Libya.
I have spoken in another place of the compulsory
exile of Teukros, who, besides founding the city of
Salamis in Cyprus, is said to have established some settlements in the Iberian
peninsula. Menestheus the Athenian did the like, and
also founded both Elaea in Mysia and Skylletium in Italy. The Arcadian chief Agamenor founded Paphus in Cyprus. Epeius,
of Panopeus in Phocis, the constructor of the Trojan
horse with the aid of the goddess Athene, settled at Lagaria near Sybaris on the coast of Italy; and the very tools which he had employed in
that remarkable fabric were shown down to a late date in the temple of Athene
at Metapontum. Temples, altars and towns were also pointed out in Asia Minor,
in Samos and in Crete, the foundation of Agamemnon or of his followers. The
inhabitants of the Grecian town of Scyon, in the
Thracian peninsula called rankle or Pellene,
accounted themselves the offspring of the Pellenians from Achaea, in Peloponnesus, who had served under Agamemnon before Troy, and
who on their return from the siege had been driven on the spot by a storm and
there settled. The Pamphylians, on the southern coast
of Asia Minor, deduced their origin from the wanderings of Amphilochus and Kalchus after the siege of Troy: the inhabitants
of the Amphilochian Argos on the Gulf of Ambrakia revered the same Amphilochus as their founder. The Orchomenians under Ialmenus, on quitting the conquered city, wandered or were
driven to the eastern extremity of the Euxine Sea; and the barbarous Achaeans
under Mount Caucasus were supposed to have derived their first establishment
from this source. Meriones with his Keeton followers
settled at Engyion in Sicily, along with the
preceding Cretans who had remained there after the invasion of Minos. The Elyminians in Sicily also were composed of Trojans and
Greeks separately driven to the spot, who, forgetting their previous
differences, united in the joint settlements of Eryx and Egesta. We hear of Podaleirius both in Italy and on the coast of Caria; of Akamas,
son of Theseus, at Amphipolis in Thrace, at Soli in Cyprus, and at Synnada in Phrygia; of Guneus, Prothous and Eurypylus, in Crete
as well as in Libya. The obscure poem of Lycophron enumerates many of these dispersed and expatriated heroes, whose conquest of
Troy was indeed a Cadmeian victory (according to the
proverbial phrase of the Greeks), wherein the sufferings of the victor were
little inferior to those of the vanquished. It was particularly among the
Italian Greeks, where they were worshipped with very special solemnity, that
their presence as wanderers from Troy was reported and believed.
I pass over the numerous other tales which
circulated among the ancients, illustrating the ubiquity of the Grecian and
Trojan heroes as well as that of the Argonauts,—one of the most striking
features in the Hellenic legendary world. Amongst them all, the most
interesting, individually, is Odysseus, whose romantic adventures in fabulous
places and among fabulous persons have been made familiarly known by Homer. The
goddesses Kalypso and Circe; the semi-divine mariners
of Pheacia, whose ships are endowed with
consciousness and obey without a steersman; the one-eyed Cyclopes, the
gigantic Laestrygones, and the wind-ruler Eolus; the
Sirens who ensnare by their song, as the Lotophagi fascinate by their food—all these pictures formed integral and interesting
portions of the old epic. After the suitors had been buried by their relatives,
he offered sacrifice to the Nymphs, and then went to Elis to inspect his herds
of cattle there pasturing: the Eleian Polyxenus welcomed him hospitably, and made him a present
of a bowl: Odysseus then returned to Ithaca, and fulfilled the rites and
sacrifices prescribed to him by Teiresias in his
visit to the underworld. This obligation discharged, he went to the country of
the Thesprotians, and there married the queen Kallidike: he headed the Thesprotians in a war against the Brygians, the latter being
conducted by Ares himself, who fiercely assailed Odysseus; but the goddess
Athene stood by him, and he was enabled to make head against Ares until Apollo
came and parted them. Odysseus then returned to Ithaca, leaving the Thesprotian kingdom to Polypcetes,
his son by Kallidike.
Homer leaves Odysseus reestablished in his house
and family; but so marked a personage could never be permitted to remain in the
tameness of domestic life: the epic poem called the Telegonia ascribed to him a
subsequent series of adventures. Telegonus, his son by Circe, coming to Ithaca
in search of his father, ravaged the island and killed Odysseus without knowing
who he was. Bitter repentance overtook the son for his undesigned parricide: at his prayer and by the intervention of his mother Circe, both
Penelope and Telemachus were made immortal: Telegonus married Penelope, and
Telemachus married Circe.
We see by this poem that Odysseus was
represented as the mythical ancestor of the Thesprotian kings, just as Neoptolemus was of the Molossian.
WORSHIP OF HECTOR AND ENEAS IN THE TROAD.
It has already been mentioned that Antenor and Aeneas
stand distinguished from the other Trojans by a dissatisfaction with Priam and
a sympathy with the Greeks, which is by Sophocles and others construed as
treacherous collusion,—a suspicion indirectly glanced, though emphatically
repelled, by the Aeneas of Virgil. In the old epic of Arktinus,
next in age to the Iliad and Odyssey, Aeneas abandons Troy and retires to Mount
Ida, in terror at the miraculous death of Laocoon,
before the entry of the Greeks into the town and the last night-battle: yet Lesches, in another of the ancient epic poems, represented
him as having been carried away captive by Neoptolemus. In a remarkable passage
of the Iliad, Poseidon describes the family of Priam as having incurred the
hatred of Zeus, and predicts that Aeneas and his descendants shall reign over
the Trojans: the race of Dardanus, beloved by Zeus more than all his other
sons, would thus be preserved, since Aeneas belonged to it. Accordingly, when Aeneas
is in imminent peril from the hands of Achilles, Poseidon specially interferes
to rescue him, and even the implacable miso-Trojan goddess Here assents to the
proceeding. These passages have been construed by various able critics to refer
to a family of philo-Hellenic or semi-Hellenic Eneads, known even in the time of the early singers of the
Iliad as masters of some territory in or near the Troad, and professing to be
descended from, as well as worshipping, Aeneas. In the town of Skepsis, situated in the mountainous range of Ida, about
thirty miles eastward of Ilium, there existed two noble and priestly families
who professed to be descended, the one from Hector, the other from Eneas. The Skepsian critic
Demetrius (in whose time both these families were still to be found) informs us
that Skamandrius son of Hector, and Ascanius son of Eneas, were the archegets or heroic founders of his native city, which had
been originally situated on one of the highest ranges of Ida, and was
subsequently transferred by them to the less lofty spot on which it stood in
his time. In Arisbe and Gentinus there seem to have been families professing the same descent, since the same archegets were acknowledged. In Ophrynium,
Hector had his consecrated edifice, and in Ilium both he and Aeneas were
worshipped as gods: and it was the remarkable statement of the Lesbian Menekrates, that Eneas, “having
been wronged by Paris and stripped of the sacred privileges which belonged to
him, avenged himself by betraying the city, and then became one of the Greeks”.
One tale thus among many respecting Aeneas, and
that too the most ancient of all, preserved among the natives of the Troad, who
worshipped him as their heroic ancestor, was, that after the capture of Troy he
continued in the country as king of the remaining Trojans, on friendly terms
with the Greeks. But there were other tales respecting him, alike numerous and
irreconcilable: the hand of destiny marked him as a wanderer, and his ubiquity
is not exceeded even by that of Odysseus. We hear of him at Aenus in Thrace, in Pallene, at Eneia in the Thermaic Gulf, in Delus,
at Orchomenus and Mantineia in Arcadia, in the
islands of Kythera and Zakynthus,
in Leukas and Ambrakia, at Buthrotum in Epirus, on the Salentine peninsula and various other places in the southern region of Italy; at Drepana and Segesta in Sicily, at Carthage, at Cape Palinurus, Cumae, Misenum, Caieta, and finally in Latium, where he lays the first
humble foundation of the mighty Rome and her empire. And the reason why his
wanderings were not continued still further was, that the oracles and the
pronounced will of the gods directed him to settle in Latium. In each of these
numerous places his visit was commemorated and certified by local monuments or
special legends, particularly by temples and permanent ceremonies in honor of
his mother Aphrodite, whose worship accompanied him everywhere: there were also
many temples and many different tombs of Aeneas himself. The vast ascendency
acquired by Rome, the ardor with which all the literary Romans espoused the
idea of a Trojan origin, and the fact that the Julian family recognized Aeneas
as their gentile primary ancestor,—all contributed to give to the Roman version
of his legend the preponderance over every other. The various other places in
which monuments of Aeneas were found came thus to be represented as places
where he had halted for a time on his way from Troy to Latium. But though the
legendary pretensions of these places were thus eclipsed in the eyes of those
who constituted the literary public, the local belief was not extinguished:
they claimed the hero as their permanent property, and his tomb was to them a
proof that he had lived and died among them.
Antenor, who shares with Aeneas the favorable
sympathy of the Greeks, is said by Pindar to have gone from Troy along with
Menelaus and Helen into the region of Cyrene in Libya. But according to the
more current narrative, he placed himself at the head of a body of Eneti or Veneti from Paphlagonia,
who had come as allies of Troy, and went by sea into the inner part of the
Adriatic Gulf, where he conquered the neighboring barbarians and founded the
town of Patavium (the modern Padua); the Veneti in this region were said to owe their origin to his
immigration. We learn further from Strabo, that Opsikellas,
one of the companions of Antenor, had continued his wanderings even into
Iberia, and that he had there established a settlement bearing his name.
Thus ended the Trojan war; together with its
sequel, the dispersion of the heroes, victors as well as vanquished. The
account here given of it has been unavoidably brief and imperfect; for in a
work intended to follow consecutively the real history of the Greeks, no
greater space can be allotted even to the most splendid gem of their legendary
period. Indeed, although it would be easy to fill a large volume with the
separate incidents which have been introduced into the “Trojan cycle”, the
misfortune is that they are for the most part so contradictory as to exclude
all possibility of weaving them into one connected narrative. We are compelled
to select one out of the number, generally without any solid ground of
preference, and then to note the variations of the rest. No one who has not
studied the original documents can imagine the extent to which this discrepancy
proceeds; it covers almost every portion and fragment of the tale.
But though much may have been thus omitted of
what the reader might expect to find in an account of the Trojan war, its
genuine character has been studiously preserved, without either exaggeration or
abatement. The real Trojan war is that which was recounted by Homer and the old
epic poets, and continued by all the lyric and tragic composers. For the
latter, though they took great liberties with the particular incidents, and
introduced to some extent a new moral tone, yet worked more or less faithfully
on the Homeric scale: and even Euripides, who departed the most widely from the
feeling of the old legend, never lowered down his matter to the analogy of
contemporary life. They preserved its well-defined object, at once righteous
and romantic, the recovery of the daughter of Zeus and sister of the Dioskuri—its mixed agencies, divine, heroic and human—the
colossal force and deeds of its chief actors—its vast magnitude and long
duration, as well as the toils which the conquerors underwent, and the Nemesis
which followed upon their success. And these were the circumstances which, set
forth in the full blaze of epic and tragic poetry, bestowed upon the legend its
powerful and imperishable influence over the Hellenic mind. The enterprise was
one comprehending all the members of the Hellenic body, of which each
individually might be proud, and in which, nevertheless, those feelings of
jealous and narrow patriotism, so lamentably prevalent in many of the towns,
were as much as possible excluded. It supplied them with a grand and
inexhaustible object of common sympathy, common faith, and common admiration;
and when occasions arose for bringing together a Pan-Hellenic force against the
barbarians, the precedent of the Homeric expedition was one upon which the
elevated minds of Greece could dwell with the certainty of rousing an unanimous
impulse, if not always of counterworking sinister by motives, among their
audience. And the incidents comprised in the Trojan cycle were familiarized,
not only to the public mind but also to the public eye, by innumerable
representations both of the sculptor and the painter,—those which were romantic
and chivalrous being better adapted for this purpose, and therefore more
constantly employed, than any other.
Of such events the genuine Trojan war of the old
epic was for the most part composed. Though literally believed, reverentially
cherished, and numbered among the gigantic phenomena of the past, by the
Grecian public, it is in the eyes of modern inquiry essentially a legend and
nothing more. If we are asked whether it be not a legend embodying portions of
historical matter, and raised upon a basis of truth,—whether there may not
really have occurred at the foot of the hill of Ilium a war purely human and
political, without gods, without heroes, without Helen, without Amazons,
without Ethiopians under the beautiful son of Eos, without the wooden horse,
without the characteristic and expressive features of the old epical war,—like
the mutilated trunk of Deiphobus in the underworld;
if we are asked whether there was not really some such historical Trojan war as
this, our answer must be, that as the possibility of it cannot be denied, so
neither can the reality of it be affirmed. We possess nothing but the ancient
epic itself without any independent evidence: had it been an age of records
indeed, the Homeric epic in its exquisite and unsuspecting simplicity would
probably never have come into existence. Whoever therefore ventures to dissect
Homer, Arktinus and Lesches,
and to pick out certain portions as matters of fact, while he sets aside the
rest as fiction, must do so in full reliance on his own powers of historical
divination, without any means either of proving or verifying his conclusions.
Among many attempts, ancient as well as modern, to identify real objects in
this historical darkness, that of Dio Chrysostom
deserves attention for its extraordinary boldness. In his oration addressed to
the inhabitants of Ilium, and intended to demonstrate that the Trojans were not
only blameless as to the origin of the war, but victorious in its issue—he
overthrows all the leading points of the Homeric narrative, and re-writes
nearly the whole from beginning to end: Paris is the lawful husband of Helen,
Achilles is slain by Hector, and the Greeks retire without taking Troy,
disgraced as well as baffled. Having shown without difficulty that the Iliad,
if it be looked at as a history, is full of gaps, incongruities and
absurdities, he proceeds to compose a more plausible narrative of his own,
which he tenders as so much authentic matter of fact. The most important point,
however, which his Oration brings to view is, the literal and confiding belief
with which the Homeric narrative was regarded, as if it were actual history,
not only by the inhabitants of Ilium, but also by the general Grecian public.
The small town of Ilium, inhabited by Eolic
Greeks and raised into importance only by the legendary reverence attached to
it, stood upon an elevated ridge forming a spur from Mount Ida, rather more
than three miles from the town and promontory of Sigeium,
and about twelve stadia, or less than two miles, from the sea at its nearest
point. From Sigeium and the neighboring town of Achilleium (with its monument and temple of Achilles), to
the town of Rhoeteium on a hill higher up the
Hellespont (with its monument mid chapel of Ajax called the Aianteium),
was a distance of sixty stadia, or seven miles and a half in the straight
course by sea: in the intermediate space was a bay and an adjoining plain,
comprehending the embouchure of the Skamander, and
extending to the base of the ridge on which Ilium stood. This plain was the
celebrated plain of Troy, in which the great Homeric battles were believed to
have taken place: the portion of the bay near to Sigeium went by the name of the Naustathmon of the Achaeans
(i.e. the spot where they dragged their ships ashore), and was accounted to
have been the camp of Agamemnon and his vast army.
Historical Ilium was founded, according to the
questionable statement of Strabo, during the last dynasty of the Lydian kings,
that is, at some period later than 720 BC. Until after the days of Alexander
the Great—indeed until the period of Roman preponderance —it always remained a
place of inconsiderable power and importance, as we learn not only from the
assertion of the geographer, but also from the fact that Achilleium, Sigeium and Rhoeteium were
all independent of it. But inconsiderable as it might be, it was the only place
which ever bore the venerable name immortalized by Homer. Like the Homeric
Ilium, it had its temple of Athene, wherein she was worshipped as the presiding
goddess of the town: the inhabitants affirmed that Agamemnon had not altogether
destroyed the town, but that it had been reoccupied after his departure, and
had never ceased to exist. Their acropolis was called Pergamum, and in it was
shown the house of Priam and the altar of Zeus Herkeius where that unhappy old man had been slain: moreover there were exhibited, in
the temples, panoplies which had been worn by the Homeric heroes, and doubtless
many other relics appreciated by admirers of the Iliad.
These were testimonies which few persons in
those ages were inclined to question, when combined with the identity of name
and general locality; nor does it seem that any one did question them until the
time of Demetrius of Skepsis. Hellanikus expressly described this Ilium as being the Ilium of Homer, for which assertion
Strabo (or probably Demetrius, from whom the narrative seems to be copied)
imputes to him very gratuitously an undue partiality towards the inhabitants of
the town. Herodotus relates, that Xerxes in his march into Greece visited the
place, went up to the Pergamum of Priam, inquired with much interest into the
details of the Homeric siege, made libations to the fallen heroes, and offered
to the Athene of Ilium his magnificent sacrifice of a thousand oxen: he
probably represented and believed himself to be attacking Greece as the avenger
of the Priamid family. The Lacedaemonian admiral Mindarus, while his fleet lay at Abydus,
went personally to Ilium to offer sacrifice to Athene, and saw from that
elevated spot the battle fought between the squadron of Dorieus and the Athenians, on the shore near Rhoeteium.
During the interval between the Peloponnesian war and the Macedonian invasion
of Persia. Ilium was always garrisoned as a strong position; but its domain was
still narrow, and did not extend even to the sea which was so near to it.
Alexander, on crossing the Hellespont, sent his army from Sestus to Abydus, under Parmenio,
and sailed personally from Elaeus in the Chersonese,
after having solemnly sacrificed at the Elaeuntian shrine of Protesilaus, to the harbor of the Achaeans
between Sigeium and Rhoeteium.
He then ascended to Ilium, sacrificed to the Eliean Athene, and consecrated in her temple his own panoply, in exchange for which he
took some of the sacred arms there suspended, which were said to have been
preserved from the time of the Trojan war. These arms were carried before him
when he went to battle by his armor-bearers. It is a fact still more curious,
and illustrative of the strong working of the old legend on an impressible and
eminently religious mind, that he also sacrificed to Priam himself, on the very
altar of Zeus Herkeius from which the old king was
believed to have been torn by Neoptolemus. As that fierce warrior was his
heroic ancestor by the maternal side, he desired to avert from himself the
anger of Priam against the Achilleid race.
Alexander made to the inhabitants of Ilium many
munificent promises, which he probably would have executed, had he not been
prevented by untimely death: for the Trojan war was amongst all the Grecian
legends the most thoroughly Pan-Hellenic, and the young king of Macedon,
besides his own sincere legendary faith, was anxious to merge the local
patriotism of the separate Greek towns in one general Hellenic sentiment under
himself as chief. One of his successors, Antigonus, founded the city of Alexandreia in the Troad, between Sigeium and the more southerly promontory of Lektum;
compressing into it the inhabitants of many of the neighboring Eolic towns in
the region of Ida, — Skepsis, Kebren, Hamaxitus, Kolonae, and Neandria, though the inhabitants of Skepsis were subsequently permitted by Lysimachus to resume their own city and
autonomous government. Ilium however remained without any special mark of favor
until the arrival of the Romans in Asia and their triumph over Antiochus (about
190 BC). Though it retained its walls and its defensible position, Demetrius of Skepsis, who visited it shortly before that event,
described it as being then in a state of neglect and poverty, many of the
houses not even having tiled roofs. In this dilapidated condition, however, it
was still mythically recognized both by Antiochus and by the Roman consul
Livius, who went up thither to sacrifice to the Iliean Athene. The Romans, proud of their origin from Troy and Aeneas, treated Ilium
with signal munificence; not only granting to it immunity from tribute, but
also adding to its domain the neighboring territories of Gergis, Rhoeteium and Sigeium—and
making the Ilieans masters of the whole coasts from
the Peraea (or continental possessions) of Tenedos (southward of Sigeium) to the boundaries of Dardanus,
which had its own title to legendary reverence as the special sovereignty of Eneas. The inhabitants of Sigeium could not peaceably acquiesce in this loss of their autonomy, and their city
was destroyed by the Ilians.
The dignity and power of Ilium being thus
prodigiously enhanced, we cannot doubt that the inhabitants assumed to
themselves exaggerated importance as the recognized parents of all-conquering
Rome. Partly, we may naturally suppose, from the jealousies thus aroused on the
part of their neighbors at Skepsis and Alexandreia Troas—partly from the pronounced tendency of
the age (in which Krates at Pergamum and Aristarchus
at Alexandria divided between them the palm of literary celebrity) towards
criticism and illustration of the old poets—a blow was now aimed at the
mythical legitimacy of Ilium. Demetrius of Skepsis,
one of the most laborious of the Homeric critics, had composed thirty books of
comment upon the Catalogue in the Iliad: Hestiaea, an
authoress of Alexandreia Troas, had written on the
same subject: both of them, well-acquainted with the locality, remarked that
the vast battles described in the Iliad could not be packed into the narrow
space between Ilium and the Naustathmon of the
Greeks; the more so, as that space, too small even as it then stood, had been
considerably enlarged since the date of the Iliad by deposits at the mouth of
the Skamander. They found no difficulty in pointing
out topographical incongruities and impossibilities as to the incidents in the
Iliad, which they professed to remove by the startling theory that the Homeric
Ilium had not occupied the site of the city so called. There was a village,
called the village of the Ilieans, situated rather
less than four miles from the city in the direction of Mount Ida, and further
removed from the sea; here, they affirmed the “holy Troy” had stood.
No positive proof was produced to sustain the
conclusion, for Strabo expressly states that not a vestige of the ancient city
remained at the Village of the Ilieans: but the
fundamental supposition was backed by a second accessory supposition, to
explain how it happened that all such vestiges had disappeared.
Nevertheless Strabo adopts the unsupported
hypothesis of Demetrius as if it were an authenticated fact—distinguishing
pointedly between Old and New Ilium, and even censuring Hellanikus for having maintained the received local faith. But I cannot find that
Demetrius and Hestiaea have been followed in this
respect by any other writer of ancient times excepting Strabo. Ilium still
continued to be talked of and treated by everyone as the genuine Homeric Troy:
the cruel jests of the Roman rebel Fimbria, when he sacked the town and
massacred the inhabitants—the compensation made by Sylla,
and the pronounced favor of Julius Caesar and Augustus,—all prove this
continued recognition of identity. Arrian, though a
native of Nicomedia, holding a high appointment in Asia Minor, and remarkable
for the exactness of his topographical notices, describes the visit of
Alexander to Ilium, without any suspicion that the place with all its relics
was a mere counterfeit: Aristides, Dio Chrysostom,
Pausanias, Appian, and Plutarch hold the same language. But modern writers seem
for the most part to have taken up the supposition from Strabo as implicitly as
he took it from Demetrius. They call Ilium by the disrespectful appellation of New Ilium—while the traveler in the
Troad looks for Old Ilium as if it were the unquestionable spot where Priam had
lived and moved; the name is even formally enrolled on the best maps recently
prepared of the ancient Troad.
CONTINUANCE OF TIIE MYTHICAL FAITH IN ILIUM.
Strabo has here converted into geographical
matter of fact an hypothesis purely gratuitous, with a view of saving the accuracy
of the Homeric topography; though in all probability the locality of the
pretended Old Ilium would have been found open to difficulties not less serious
than those which it was introduced to obviate. It may be true that Demetrius
and he were justified in their negative argument, so as to show that the
battles described in the Iliad could not possibly have taken place if the city
of Priam had stood on the hill inhabited by the Ilieans.
But the legendary faith subsisted before, and continued without abatement
afterwards, notwithstanding such topographical impossibilities. Hellanikus, Herodotus, Mindarus,
the guides of Xerxes, and Alexander, had not been shocked by them: the case of
the latter is the strongest of all, because he had received the best education
of his time under Aristotle—he was a passionate admirer and constant reader of
the Iliad—he was moreover personally familiar with the movements of armies, and
lived at a time when maps, which began with Anaximander, the disciple of
Thales, were at least known to all who sought instruction. Now if,
notwithstanding such advantages, Alexander fully believed in the identity of
Ilium, unconscious of these many and glaring topographical difficulties, much
less would Homer himself, or the Homeric auditors, be likely to pay attention
to them, at a period, five centuries earlier, of comparative rudeness and
ignorance, when prose records as well as geographical maps were totally
unknown. The inspired poet might describe, and his hearers would listen with delight
to the tale, how Hector, pursued by Achilles, ran thrice round the city of
Troy, while the trembling Trojans were all huddled into the city, not one
daring to come out even at this last extremity of their beloved prince—and
while the Grecian army looked on, restraining unwillingly their uplifted spears
at the nod of Achilles, in order that Hector might perish by no other hand than
his; nor were they, while absorbed by this impressive recital, disposed to
measure distances or calculate topographical possibilities with reference to
the site of the real Ilium. The mistake consists in applying to Homer and to
the Homeric siege of Troy, criticisms which would be perfectly just if brought
to bear on the Athenian siege of Syracuse, as described by Thucydides; in the
Peloponnesian war— but which are not more applicable to the epic narrative than
they would be to the exploits of Amadis or Orlando.
There is every reason for presuming that the
Ilium visited by Xerxes and Alexander was really the “holy Ilium” present to
the mind of Homer; and if so, it must have been inhabited, either by Greeks or
by some anterior population, at a period earlier than that which Strabo
assigns. History recognizes neither Troy the city, nor Trojans, as actually
existing; but the extensive region called Trills, or the Tread (more properly Troias), is known both to Herodotus and to Thucydides: it
seems to include the territory westward of an imaginary line drawn from the
northeast corner of the Adramyttian gulf to the Propontis at Parium, since both Antandrus, Kolenae, and the
district immediately round Ilium, are regarded as belonging to the Troad.
Herodotus further notices the Teukrians of Gergis (a township conterminous with Ilium, and lying to
the eastward of the road from Ilium to Abydus),
considering them as the remnant of a larger Teukrian population which once resided in the country, and which had in very early times
undertaken a vast migration from Asia into Europe. To that Teukrian population he thinks that the Homeric Trojans belonged: and by later writers,
especially by Virgil and the other Romans, the names Teukrians and Trojans are employed as equivalents. As the name Trojans is not mentioned
in any contemporary historical monument, so the name Teukrians never once occurs in the old epic. It appears to have been first noticed by the
elegiac poet Kallinus, about 660 BC, who connected it
by an alleged immigration of Teukrians from Crete
into the region round about Ida. Others again denied this, asserting that the
primitive ancestor, Teukrus, had come into the
country from Attica, or that he was of indigenous origin, born from Skamander and the nymph Idaea—all
various manifestations of that eager thirst after an eponymous hero which never
deserted the Greeks. Gergithians occur in more than
one spot in Aeolis, even so far southward as the neighborhood of Kyme: the name has no place in Homer, but he mentions Gorgythion and Kebriones as
illegitimate sons of Priam, thus giving a sort of epical recognition both to Gergis and Kebren. As Herodotus
calls the old epical Trojans by the name Teukrians,
so the Attic Tragedians call them Phrygians; though the Homeric hymn to
Aphrodite represents Phrygians and Trojans as completely distinct, specially
noting the diversity of language; and in the Iliad the Phrygians are simply
numbered among the allies of Troy from the far Ascania,
without indication of any more intimate relationship. Nor do the tales which
connect Dardanus with Samothrace and Arcadia find countenance in the Homeric
poems, wherein Dardanus is the son of Zeus, having no root anywhere except in
Dardania. The mysterious solemnities of Samothrace, afterwards so highly
venerated throughout the Grecian world, date from a period much later than
Homer; and the religious affinities of that island as well as of Crete with the
territories of Phrygia and Eolis, were certain,
according to the established tendency of the Grecian mind, to beget stories of
a common genealogy.
HOMERIC AND HISTORICAL TROAD.
To pass from this legendary world,—an aggregate
of streams distinct and heterogeneous, which do not willingly come into
confluence, and cannot be forced to intermix,—into the clearer vision afforded
by Herodotus, we learn from him that in the year 500 BC the whole coast-region
from Dardanus southward to the promontory of Lektum (including the town of Ilium), and from Lektum eastward to Adramyttium, had been Aeolized,
or was occupied by Eolic Greeks—likewise the inland towns of Skepsist and Kreben. So that if
we draw a line northward from Adramyttium to Kyzikus on the Propontis,
throughout the whole territory westward from that line, to the Hellespont and
the Egean Sea, all the considerable towns would be
Hellenic, with the exception of Gergis and the Teukrian population around it,—all the towns worthy of note
were either Ionic or Eolic. A century earlier, the Teukrian population would have embraced a wider range—perhaps Skepsis and Kreben, the latter of which places was colonized
by Greeks from Kyme: a century afterwards, during the
satrapy of Pharnabazus, it appears that Gergis had become Hellenized as well as the rest. The four
towns, Ilium, Gergis, Kebren and Skepsis, all in lofty and strong positions, were
distinguished each by a solemn worship and temple of Athene, and by the
recognition of that goddess as their special patroness.
The author of the Iliad conceived the whole of
this region as occupied by people not Greek,—Trojans, Dardanians,
Lycians, Lelegians, Pelasgians, and Cilicians. He
recognizes a temple and worship of Athene in Ilium, though the goddess is
bitterly hostile to the Trojans: and Arktinus described the Palladium as the capital protection of the city. But perhaps the
most remarkable feature of identity between the Homeric and the historical Aeolis,
is, the solemn and diffused worship of the Sminthian Apollo. Chryse, Killa and Tenedos, and more than one place called Sminthium,
maintain the surname and invoke the protection of that god during later times,
just as they are emphatically described to do by Homer.
When it is said that the Post-Homeric Greeks
gradually Hellenized this entire region, we are not to understand that the
whole previous population either retired or was destroyed. The Greeks settled
in the leading and considerable towns, which enabled them both to protect one another
and to gratify their predominant tastes. Partly by force—but greatly also by
that superior activity, and power of assimilating foreign ways of thought to
their own, which distinguished them from the beginning—they invested all the
public features and management of the town with an Hellenic air, distributed
all about it their gods, their heroes and their legends, and rendered their
language the medium of public administration, religious songs and addresses to
the gods, and generally for communications wherein any number of persons were
concerned. But two remarks are here to be made: first, in doing this they could
not avoid taking to themselves more or less of that which belonged to the
parties with whom they fraternized, so that the result was not pure Hellenism;
next, that even this was done only in the towns, without being fully extended
to the territorial domain around, or to those smaller townships which stood to
the town in a dependent relation. The and Ionic Greeks borrowed from the Asiatics whom they had Hellenized, musical instruments and
new laws of rhythm and melody, which they knew how to turn to account: they
further adopted more or less of those violent and maddening religion rites,
manifested occasionally in self-inflicted suffering and mutilation, which were
indigenous in Asia Minor in the worship of the Great Mother. The religion of
the Greeks in the region of Ida as well as at Kyzilus was more orgiastic than the native worship of Greece Proper, just as that of
Lampsacus, Priapus and Parium was more licentious. From the Teukrian region of Gergis, and from the Gergithes near Kyme, sprang the original Sibylline prophecies,
and the legendary Sibyll who plays so important a
part in the tale of Aeneas. The myth of the Sibyl, whose prophecies are supposed
to be heard in the hollow blast bursting out from obscure caverns and apertures
in the rocks, was indigenous among the Gergithian Teukrians, and passed from the Kymaeans in Aeolis, along with the other circumstances of the tale of Aeneas, to their
brethren the inhabitants of Cumae in Italy. The date of the Gergithian Sibyl, or rather of the circulation of her supposed prophecies, is placed
during the reign of Croesus, a period when Gergis was
thoroughly Teukrian. Her prophecies, though embodied
in Greek verses, had their root in a Teukrian soil
and feelings; and the promises of future empire which they so liberally make to
the fugitive hero escaping from the flames of Troy into Italy, become
interesting from the remarkable way in which they were realized by Rome.
THE preceding sections have been
intended to exhibit a sketch of that narrative matter, so abundant, so
characteristic and so interesting, out of which early Grecian history and
chronology have been extracted. Raised originally by hands unseen and from data unassignable, it existed first in the shape of
floating talk among the people, from whence a large portion of it passed into
the song of the poets, who multiplied, transformed and adorned it in a thousand
various ways.
These myths or current stories, the
spontaneous and earliest growth of the Grecian mind, constituted at the same
time the entire intellectual stock of the age to which they belonged. They are
the common root of all those different ramifications into which the mental
activity of the Greeks subsequently diverged; containing, as it were, the
preface and germ of the positive history and philosophy, the dogmatic theology
and the professed romance, which we shall hereafter trace each in its separate
development. They furnished aliment to the curiosity, and solution to the vague
doubts and aspirations of the age; they explained the origin of those customs
and standing peculiarities with which men were familiar; they impressed moral
lessons, awakened patriotic sympathies, and exhibited in detail the shadowy,
but anxious presentiments of the vulgar as to the agency of the gods : moreover
they satisfied that craving for adventure and appetite for the marvelous, which
has in modern times become the province of fiction proper.
It is difficult, we may say
impossible, for a man of mature age to carry back his mind to his conceptions
such as they stood when he was a child, growing naturally out of his
imagination and feelings, working upon a scanty stock of materials, and
borrowing from authorities whom he blindly followed but imperfectly
apprehended. A similar difficulty occurs when we attempt to place ourselves in
the historical and quasi-philosophical point of view which the ancient myths
present to us. We can follow perfectly the imagination and feeling which
dictated these tales, and we can admire and sympathize with them as animated,
sublime, and affecting poetry; but we are too much accustomed to matter of fact
and philosophy of a positive kind, to be able to conceive a time when these
beautiful fancies were construed literally and accepted as serious reality.
Nevertheless it is obvious that
Grecian myths cannot be either understood or appreciated except with reference
to the system of conceptions and belief of the ages in which they arose. We
must suppose a public not reading and writing, but seeing, hearing and telling
— destitute of all records, and careless as well as ignorant of positive
history with its indispensable tests, yet at the same time curious and full of
eagerness for new or impressive incidents — strangers even to the rudiments of
positive philosophy and to the idea of invariable sequences of nature either in
the physical or moral world, yet requiring some connecting theory to interpret
and regularize the phenomena before them. Such a theory was supplied by the
spontaneous inspirations of an early fancy, which supposed the habitual agency
of beings intelligent and voluntary like themselves, but superior in extent of
power, and different in peculiarity of attributes. In the geographical ideas of
the Homeric period, the earth was flat and round, with the deep and gentle
ocean-stream flowing around and returning into itself: chronology, or means of
measuring past time, there existed none; but both unobserved regions might be
described, the forgotten past unfolded, and the unknown future
predicted—through particular men specially inspired by the gods, or endowed by
them with that peculiar vision which detected and interpreted passing signs and
omens.
If even the rudiments of scientific
geography and physics, now so universally diffused and so invaluable as a
security against error and delusion, were wanting in this early stage of
society, their place was abundantly supplied by vivacity of imagination and by
personifying sympathy. The unbounded tendency of the Homeric Greeks to multiply
fictitious persons, and to construe the phenomena which interested them into
manifestations of design, is above all things here to be noticed, because the
form of personal narrative, universal in their myths, is one of its many
manifestations. Their polytheism (comprising some elements of an original fetichism, in which particular objects had themselves been
supposed to be endued with life, volition, and design) recognized agencies of
unseen beings identified and confounded with the different localities and
departments of the physical world. Of such beings there were numerous
varieties, and many gradations both in power and attributes; there were
differences of age, sex and local residence, relations both conjugal and filial
between them, and tendencies sympathetic as well as repugnant. The gods formed
a sort of political community of their own, which had its hierarchy, its
distribution of ranks and duties, its contentions for power and occasional
revolutions, its public meetings in the agora of Olympus, and its multitudinous
banquets or festivals. The great Olympic gods were in fact only the most
exalted amongst an aggregate of quasi-human or ultra-human personages,
—daemons, heroes, nymphs, eponymous (or name-giving) genii, identified with
each river, mountain, cape, town, village, or known circumscription of
territory,—besides horses, bulls, and dogs, of immortal breed and peculiar
attributes, and monsters of strange lineaments and combinations, “Gorgons and
Harpies and Chimeras dire”. As there were in every gens or family special gentile deities and foregone ancestors who
watched over its members, forming in each the characteristic symbol and
recognized guarantee of their union, so there seem to have been in each guild
or trade peculiar beings whose vocation it was to cooperate or to impede in various
stages of the business.
We read in the Iliad that Asteropaeus was grandson of the beautiful river Axius, and Achilles, after having slain him, admits the
dignity of this parentage, but boasts that his own descent from Zeus was much
greater, since even the great river Achelous and
Oceanus himself is inferior to Zeus. Skamander fights
with Achilles, calling his brother Simois to his aid.
Tyro, the daughter of Salmoneus, falls in love with Enipeus, the most beautiful of rivers. Achelous appears as a suitor of Deianira.
There cannot be a better
illustration of this feeling than what is told of the New Zealanders at the
present time. The chief Heu-Hen appeals to his
ancestor, the great mountain Tonga Riro: “I am the Heu-Heu, and rule over you all, just as my ancestor Tonga Riro, the mountain of snow, stands above all this land”. Heu-Heu refused permission to anyone to ascend the
mountain, on the ground that it was his tipuna or
ancestor: "he constantly identified himself with the mountain and called
it his sacred ancestor". The mountains in New Zealand are accounted by the
natives masculine and feminine: Tonga Riro, and Taranaki, two male mountains, quarreled about the
affections of a small volcanic female mountain in the neighborhood.
The religious imagination of the Hindoos also (as described by Colonel Sleeman in his excellent work, Rambles and
Recollections of an Indian Official), affords a remarkable parallel to that
of the early Greeks. Colonel Sleeman says, "Any
Englishman can easily conceive a poet in his highest calenture of the brain,
addressing the Ocean as a steed that knows his rider, and patting the crested
billow as his flowing mane. But he must come to India to understand how every
individual of a whole community of many
millions can address a fine river as a living being—a sovereign princess who
hears and understands all they say, and exercises a kind of local
superintendence over their affairs, without a single temple in which her
image is worshipped, or a single priest to profit by the delusion. As in the
case of the Ganges, it is the river
itself to whom they address themselves, and not to any deity residing in it, or
presiding over it—the stream itself is the deity which fills their
imaginations, and receives their homage. Compare also the remarks in the same
work on the sanctity of Mother Nerbudda; also of the
holy personality of the earth. "The land is considered as the MOTHER of
the prince or chief who holds it, the great parent from whom he derives all
that maintains him, his family, and his establishments. If well-treated, she
yields this in abundance to her son; but if he presumes to look upon her with
the eye of desire, she ceases to be fruitful ; or the Deity sends down hail or
blight to destroy all that she yields. The measuring the surface of the fields,
and the frequently inspecting the crops by the chief himself or his immediate
agents, were considered by the people in this light— either it should not be
done at all, or the duty should be delegated to inferior agents, whose close inspection
of the great parent could not be so
displeasing to the Deity".
GEA, URANOS, HELIOS, ETC.
The extensive and multiform
personifications, here faintly sketched, pervaded in every direction the mental
system of the Greeks, and were identified intimately both with their conception
and with their description of phenomena, present as well as past. That which to
us is interesting as the mere creation of an exuberant fancy, was to the Greek
genuine and venerated reality. Both the earth and the solid heaven (Gea and Uranos) were both
conceived and spoken of by him as endowed with appetite, feeling, sex, and most
of the various attributes of humanity. Instead of a sun such as we now see,
subject to astronomical laws, and forming the center of a system the changes of
which we can ascertain and foreknow, he saw the great god Helios, mounting his
chariot in the morning in the east, reaching at midday the height of the solid
heaven, and arriving in the evening at the western horizon, with horses
fatigued and desirous of repose.
Helios, having favorite spots
wherein his beautiful cattle grazed, took pleasure in contemplating them during
the course of his journey, and was sorely displeased if any man slew or injured
them: he had moreover sons and daughters on earth, and as his all-seeing eye
penetrated everywhere, he was sometimes in a situation to reveal secrets even
to the gods themselves—while on other occasions he was constrained to turn
aside in order to avoid contemplating scenes of abomination. To us these now
appear puerile, though pleasing fancies, but to an Homeric Greek they seemed
perfectly natural and plausible. In his view, the description of the sun, as
given in a modern astronomical treatise, would have appeared not merely absurd,
but repulsive and impious. Even in later times, when the positive spirit of
inquiry had made considerable progress, Anaxagoras and other astronomers
incurred the charge of blasphemy for dispersonifying and trying to assign invariable laws to the solar phenomena. Personifying fiction
was in this way blended by the Homeric Greeks with their conception of the
physical phenomena before them, not simply in the way of poetical ornament, but
as a genuine portion of their every-day belief.
It was in this early state of the
Grecian mind, stimulating so forcibly the imagination and the feelings, and
acting through them upon the belief, that the great body of the myths grew up
and obtained circulation. They were, from first to last, personal narratives
and adventures; and the persons who predominated as subjects of them were the
gods, the heroes, the nymphs, etc., whose names were known and reverenced, and
in whom everyone felt interested. To every god and every hero it was consistent
with Grecian ideas to ascribe great diversity of human motive and attribute :
each indeed has his own peculiar type of character, more or less strictly
defined; but in all there was a wide foundation for animated narrative and for
romantic incident. The gods and heroes of the land and the tribe belonged, in the
conception of a Greek, alike to the present and to the past : he worshipped in
their groves and at their festivals; he invoked their protection, and believed
in their superintending guardianship, even in his own day : but their more
special, intimate, and sympathizing agency was cast back into the unrecorded
past. To give suitable utterance to this general sentiment, to furnish body and
movement and detail to these divine and heroic pre-existences, which were
conceived only in shadowy outline, to lighten up the dreams of what the past
must have been, in the minds of those who knew not what it really had been —
such was the spontaneous aim and inspiration of productive genius in the
community, and such were the purposes which the Grecian myths preeminently accomplished.
GOD AND MEN IN COMMUNION.
The love of antiquities, which
Tacitus notices as so prevalent among the Greeks of his day, was one of the
earliest, the most durable, and the most widely diffused of the national
propensities. But the antiquities of every state were divine and heroic,
reproducing the lineaments, but disregarding the measure and limits, of
ordinary humanity. The gods formed the starting-point, beyond which no man
thought of looking, though some gods were more ancient than others : their
progeny, the heroes, many of them sprung from human mothers, constitute an
intermediate link between god and man. The ancient epic usually recognizes the
presence of a multitude of nameless men, but they are introduced chiefly for
the purpose of filling the scene, and of executing the orders, celebrating the
valor, and bringing out the personality, of a few divine or heroic characters.
It was the glory of bards and storytellers to be able to satisfy those
religious and patriotic predispositions of the public, which caused the primary
demand for their tales, and which were of a nature eminently inviting and
expansive. For Grecian religion was many-sided and many colored; it comprised a
great multiplicity of persons, together with much diversity in the types of
character; it divinized every vein and attribute of humanity, the lofty as well
as the mean—the tender as well as the warlike—the self-devoting and adventurous
as well as the laughter-loving and sensual. We shall hereafter reach a time
when philosophers protested against such identification of the gods with the
more vulgar appetites and enjoyments, believing that nothing except the
spiritual attributes of man could properly be transferred to superhuman beings,
and drawing their predicates respecting the gods exclusively from what was
awful, majestic and terror-striking in human affairs. Such restrictions on the
religious fancy were continually on the increase, and the mystic and didactic
stamp which marked the last century of paganism in the days of Julian and Libanius, contrasts forcibly with the concrete and
vivacious forms, full of vigorous impulse and alive to all the capricious gusts
of the human temperament, which people the Homeric Olympus. At present,
however, we have only to consider the early, or Homeric and Hesiodic paganism,
and its operation in the genesis of the mythical narratives. We cannot doubt
that it supplied the most powerful stimulus, and the only one which the times
admitted, to the creative faculty of the people; as well from the sociability,
the gradations, and the mutual action and reaction of its gods and heroes, as
from the amplitude, the variety, and the purely human cast, of its fundamental
types.
STIMULUS TO MYTHOPOEIC FACULTY.
Though we may thus explain the
mythopoeic fertility of the Greeks, I am far from pretending that we can render
any sufficient account of the supreme beauty of their chief epic and artistical productions. There is something in the
first-rate productions of individual genius which lies beyond the compass of
philosophical theory : the special breath of the Muse (to speak the language of
ancient Greece) must be present in order to give them being. Even among her
votaries, many are called, but few are chosen; and the peculiarities of those
few remain as yet her own secret.
We shall not however forget that
Grecian language was also an indispensable requisite to the growth and beauty
of Grecian myths — its richness, its flexibility and capacity of new
combinations, its vocalic abundance and metrical pronunciation: and many even
among its proper names, by their analogy to words really significant, gave
direct occasion to explanatory or illustrative stories. Etymological myths are
found in sensible proportion among the whole number.
To understand properly then the
Grecian myths, we must try to identify ourselves with the state of mind of the
original mythopoeic age; a process not very easy, since it requires us to adopt
a string of poetical fancies not simply as realities, but as the governing
realities of the mental system; yet a process which would only reproduce
something analogous to our own childhood. The age was one destitute both of
recorded history and of positive science, but full of imagination and sentiment
and religious impressibility; from these sources sprung that multitude of
supposed persons around whom all combinations of sensible phenomena were
grouped, and towards whom curiosity, sympathies, and reverence were earnestly
directed. The adventures of such persons were the only aliment suited at once
both to the appetites and to the comprehension of an early Greek; and the myths
which detailed them, while powerfully interesting his emotions, furnished to
him at the same time a quasi-history and quasi-philosophy: they filled up the
vacuum of the unrecorded past, and explained many of the puzzling incognita of
the present. Nor need we wonder that the same plausibility which captivated his
imagination and his feelings was sufficient to engender spontaneous belief; or
rather, that no question as to truth or falsehood of the narrative suggested
itself to his mind. His faith is ready, literal and uninquiring,
apart from all thought of discriminating fact from fiction, or of detecting
hidden and symbolized meaning; it is enough that what he hears be intrinsically
plausible and seductive, and that there be no special cause to provoke doubt.
And if indeed there were, the poet overrules such doubts by the holy and
all-sufficient authority of the Muse, whose omniscience is the warrant for his
recital, as her inspiration is the cause of his success.
The state of mind, and the relation
of speaker to hearers, thus depicted, stand clearly marked in the terms and
tenor of the ancient epic, if we only put a plain meaning upon what we read.
The poet—like the prophet, whom he so much resembles—sings under heavenly
guidance, inspired by the goddess to whom he has prayed for her assisting
impulse : she puts the word into his mouth and the incidents into his mind : he
is a privileged man, chosen as her organ and speaking from her revelations. As
the Muse grants the gift of song to whom she will, so she sometimes in her
anger snatches it away, and the most consummate human genius is then left
silent and helpless. It is true that these expressions, of the Muse inspiring
and the poet singing a tale of past times, have passed from the ancient epic to
compositions produced under very different circumstances, and have now
degenerated into unmeaning forms of speech; but they gained currency originally
in their genuine and literal acceptation. If poets had from the beginning
written or recited, the predicate of singing would never have been ascribed to
them; nor would it have ever become customary to employ the name of the Muse as
a die to be stamped on licensed fiction, unless the practice had begun when her
agency was invoked and hailed in perfect good faith. Belief, the fruit of
deliberate inquiry and a rational scrutiny of evidence, is in such an age
unknown : the simple faith of the time slides in unconsciously, when the imagination
and feeling are exalted; and inspired authority is at once understood, easily
admitted, and implicitly confided in.
ORIGIN OF THE WORD “MYTH”
The word myth (fabula, story), in its original meaning, signified simply a statement or
current narrative, without any connotative implication either of truth or
falsehood. Subsequently the meaning of the word (in Latin and English as well
as in Greek) changed, and came to carry with it the idea of an old personal
narrative, always uncertified, sometimes untrue or avowedly fictitious. And
this change was the result of a silent alteration in the mental state of the
society, — of a transition on the part of the superior minds (and more or less
on the part of all) to a stricter and more elevated canon of credibility, in
consequence of familiarity with recorded history, and its essential tests,
affirmative as well as negative. Among the original hearers of the myths, all
such tests were unknown; they had not yet learned the lesson of critical
disbelief; the myth passed unquestioned from the mere fact of its currency, and
from its harmony with existing sentiments and preconceptions. The very
circumstances which contributed to rob it of literal belief in after-time,
strengthened its hold upon the mind of the Homeric man. He looked for wonders
and unusual combinations in the past; he expected to hear of gods, heroes and
men, moving and operating together upon earth; he pictured to himself the
foretime as a theatre in which the gods interfered directly, obviously and frequently,
for the protection of their favorites and the punishment of their foes. The
rational conception, then only dawning in his mind, of a systematic course of
nature was absorbed by this fervent and lively faith. And if he could have been
supplied with as perfect and philosophical a history of his own real past time,
as we are now enabled to furnish with regard to the last century of England or
France, faithfully recording all the successive events, and accounting for them
by known positive laws, but introducing no special interventions of Zeus and
Apollo — such a history would have appeared to him not merely unholy and
unimpressive, but destitute of all plausibility or title to credence. It would
have provoked in him the same feeling of incredulous aversion as a description
of the sun (to repeat the previous illustration) in a modern book on scientific
astronomy.
To us these myths are interesting
fictions; to the Homeric and Hesiodic audience they were rerum divinarum et humanarum scientia, an aggregate of religious, physical and
historical revelations, rendered more captivating, but not less true and real,
by the bright coloring and fantastic shapes in which they were presented.
Throughout the whole of "myth-bearing Hellas" they formed the staple
of the uninstructed Greek mind, upon which history and philosophy were by so
slow degrees superinduced; and they continued to be
the aliment of ordinary thought and conversation, even after history and
philosophy had partially supplanted the mythical faith among the leading men,
and disturbed it more or less in the ideas of all. The men, the women, and the
children of the remote domes and villages of Greece, to whom Thucydides,
Hippocrates, Aristotle, or Hipparchus were unknown, still continued to dwell
upon the local fables which formed their religious and patriotic antiquity. And
Pausanias, even in his time, heard everywhere divine or heroic legends yet
alive, precisely of the type of the old epic; he found the conceptions of
religious and mythical faith, coexistent with those of positive science, and
contending against them at more or less of odds, according to the temper of the
individual. Now it is the remarkable characteristic of the Homeric age, that no
such coexistence or contention had yet begun. The religious and mythical point
of view covers, for the most part, all the phenomena of nature; while the
conception of invariable sequence exists only in the background, itself
personified under the name of the Moerae, or Fates,
and produced generally as an exception to the omnipotence of Zeus for all
ordinary purposes. Voluntary agents, visible and invisible, impel and govern
everything. Moreover this point of view is universal throughout the community,
adopted with equal fervor, and carried out with equal consistency, by the
loftiest minds and by the lowest. The great man of that day is he who,
penetrated like others with the general faith, and never once imagining any
other system of nature than the agency of these voluntary Beings, can clothe
them in suitable circumstances and details, and exhibit in living body and
action those types which his hearers dimly prefigure. Such men were the authors
of the Iliad and the Odyssey; embodying in themselves the whole measure of
intellectual excellence which their age was capable of feeling: to us, the
first of poets —but to their own public, religious teachers, historians, and
philosophers besides—inasmuch as all that then represented history and
philosophy was derived from those epical effusions and from others homogeneous
with them. Herodotus recognizes Homer and Hesiod as the main authors of Grecian
belief respecting the names and generations, the attributes and agency, the
forms and the worship of the gods.
History, philosophy, etc., properly
so called and conforming to our ideas (of which the subsequent Greeks were the
first creators, never belonged to more than a comparatively small number of
thinking men, though their influence indirectly affected more or less the whole
national mind. But when positive science and criticism, and the idea of an
invariable sequence of events, came to supplant in the more vigorous intellects
the old mythical creed of omnipresent personification, an inevitable scission
was produced between the instructed few and the remaining community. The opposition
between the scientific and the religious point of view was not slow in
manifesting itself: in general language, indeed, both might seem to stand
together, but in every particular case the admission of one involved the
rejection of the other. According to the theory which then became predominant,
the course of nature was held to move invariably on, by powers and attributes
of its own, unless the gods chose to interfere and reverse it; but they had the
power of interfering as often and to as great an extent as they thought fit.
Here the question was at once opened, respecting a great variety of particular
phenomena, whether they were to be regarded as natural or miraculous. No
constant or discernible test could be suggested to discriminate the two : every
man was called upon to settle the doubt for himself, and each settled it
according to the extent of his knowledge, the force of his logic, the state of
his health, his hopes, his fears, and many other considerations affecting his
separate conclusion. In a question thus perpetually arising, and full of
practical consequences, instructed minds, like Pericles, Thucydides, and
Euripides, tended more and more to the scientific point of view, in cases where
the general public were constantly gravitating towards the religious.
The age immediately prior to this
unsettled condition of thought is the really mythopoeic age; in which the
creative faculties of the society know no other employment, and the mass of the
society no other mental demand. The perfect expression of such a period, in its
full peculiarity and grandeur, is to be found in the Iliad and Odyssey, — poems
of which we cannot determine the exact date, but which seem both to have
existed prior to the first Olympiad, 776 BC, our earliest trustworthy mark of
Grecian time. For some time after that event, the mythopoeic tendencies
continued in vigor (Arktinus, Lesches, Eumelus, and seemingly most of the Hesiodic poems,
fall within or shortly after the first century of recorded Olympiads); but from
and after this first century, we may trace the operation of causes which
gradually enfeebled and narrowed them, altering the point of view from which
the myths were looked at. What these causes were, it will be necessary briefly
to intimate.
EXPANSION OF GREEK INTELLECT
The foremost and most general of all
is, the expansive force of Grecian intellect itself, — a quality in which this
remarkable people stand distinguished from all their neighbors and
contemporaries. Most, if not all nations have had myths, but no nation except
the Greeks have imparted to them immortal charm and universal interest; and the
same mental capacities, which raised the great men of the poetic age to this
exalted level, also pushed forward their successors to outgrow the early faith
in which the myths had been generated and accredited.
One great mark, as well as means, of
such intellectual expansion, was the habit of attending to, recording, and
combining, positive and present facts, both domestic and foreign. In the
genuine Grecian epic, the theme was an unknown and aoristic past; but even as
early as the Works and Days of
Hesiod, the present begins to figure: the man who tills the earth appears in
his own solitary nakedness, apart from gods and heroes—bound indeed by serious
obligations to the gods, but contending against many difficulties which are not
to be removed by simple reliance on their help. The poet denounces his age in
the strongest terms as miserable, degraded and profligate, and looks back with
reverential envy to the extinct heroic races who fought at Troy and Thebes. Yet
bad as the present time is, the Muse condescends to look at it along with him,
and to prescribe rules for human life—with the assurance that if a man be
industrious, frugal, provident, just and friendly in his dealings, the gods
will recompense him with affluence and security. Nor does the Muse disdain,
while holding out such promise, to cast herself into the most homely details of
present existence and to give advice thoroughly practical and calculating. Men
whose minds were full of the heroes of Homer, called Hesiod in contempt the
poet of the Helots; and the contrast between the two is certainly a remarkable
proof of the tendency of Greek poetry towards the present and the positive.
Other manifestations of the same
tendency become visible in the age of Archilochus (680-660 BC). In an age when
metrical composition and the living voice are the only means whereby the
productive minds of a community make themselves felt, the invention of a new metre, new forms of song and recitation, at diversified
accompaniments, constitute an epoch. The iambic, elegiac, choric, and lyric
poetry, from Archilochus downwards, all indicate purposes in the poet, and
impressibilities of the hearers, very different from those of the ancient epic.
In all of them the personal feeling of the poet and the specialties of present
time and place, are brought prominently forward, while in the Homeric hexameter
the poet is a mere nameless organ of the historical Muse—the hearers are content
to learn, believe, and feel, the incidents of a foregone world, and the tale is
hardly less suitable to one time and place than to another. The iambic metre (we are told) was first suggested to Archilochus by
the bitterness of his own private antipathies; and the mortal wounds inflicted
by his lampoons, upon the individuals against whom they were directed, still
remain attested, though the verses themselves have perished. It was the metre (according to the well-known judgment of Aristotle)
most nearly approaching to common speech, and well suited both to the coarse
vein of sentiment, and to the smart and emphatic diction of its inventor.
Simonides of Amorgus, the younger contemporary of
Archilochus, employed the same metre, with less
bitterness, but with an anti-heroic tendency not less decided. His remaining
fragments present a mixture of teaching and sarcasm, having a distinct bearing
upon actual life, and carrying out the spirit which partially appears in the
Hesiodic Works and Days. Of Alkaeus and Sappho,
though unfortunately we are compelled to speak of them upon hearsay only, we
know enough to satisfy us that their own personal sentiments and sufferings,
their relations private or public with the contemporary world, constituted the
soul of those short effusions which gave them so much celebrity : and in the
few remains of the elegiac poets preserved to us —Kallinus, Mimnermus, Tyrtaeus — the
impulse of some present motive or circumstance is no less conspicuous. The same
may also be said of Solon, Theognis and Phokylides, who preach, encourage, censure, or complain,
but do not recount—and in whom a profound ethical sensibility, unknown to the
Homeric poems, manifests itself: the form of poetry (to use the words of Solon
himself) is made the substitute for the public speaking of the agora.
Doubtless all these poets made
abundant use of the ancient myths, but it was by turning them to present
account, in the way of illustration, or flattery, or contrast,—a tendency which
we may usually detect even in the compositions of Pindar, in spite of the lofty
and heroic strain which they breathe throughout. That narrative or legendary
poetry still continued to be composed during the seventh and sixth centuries
before the Christian era is not to be questioned; but it exhibited the old
epical character without the old epical genius; both the inspiration of the
composer and the sympathies of the audience had become more deeply enlisted in
the world before them, and disposed to fasten on incidents of their own actual
experience. From Solon and Theognis we pass to the
abandonment of all metrical restrictions and to the introduction of prose
writing,—a fact, the importance of which it is needless to dwell upon—, marking
as well the increased familiarity with written records, as the commencement of
a separate branch of literature for the intellect, apart from the imagination
and emotions wherein the old legends had their exclusive root.
COMMENCEMENT OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE.
Egypt was first unreservedly opened
to the Greeks during the reign of Psammetichus, about
BC 660; gradually it became much frequented by them for military or commercial
purposes, or for simple curiosity, and enlarged the range of their thoughts and
observations, while it also imparted to them that vein of mysticism, which
overgrew the primitive simplicity of the Homeric religion, and of which I have
spoken in a former chapter. They found in it a long-established civilization,
colossal wonders of architecture, and a certain knowledge of astronomy and
geometry, elementary indeed, but in advance of their own. Moreover it was a
portion of their present world, and it contributed to form in them an interest
for noting and describing the actual realities before them. A sensible progress
is made in the Greek mind during the two centuries from 700 to 500 BC, in the
record and arrangement of historical facts: an historical sense arises in the
superior intellects, and some idea of evidence as a discriminating test between
fact and fiction. And this progressive tendency was further stimulated by
increased communication and by more settled and peaceful social relations
between the various members of the Hellenic world, to which may be added
material improvements, purchased at the expense of a period of turbulence and
revolution, in the internal administration of each separate state. The Olympic, Pythian, Nemean, and
Isthmian games became frequented by visitors from the most distant parts of
Greece : the great periodical festival in the island of Delos brought together
the citizens of every Ionic community, with their waves and children, and an
ample display of wealth and ornaments.
Numerous and flourishing colonies
were founded in Sicily, the south of Italy, the coasts of Epirus and of the
Euxine Sea : the Phocaeans explored the whole of the Adriatic, established
Massilia, and penetrated even as far as the south of Iberia, with which they
carried on a lucrative commerce. The geographical ideas of the Greeks were thus
both expanded and rectified : the first preparation of a map, by Anaximander
the disciple of Thales, is an epoch in the history of science. We may note the
ridicule bestowed by Herodotus both upon the supposed people called Hyperboreans and upon the idea of a circumfluous
ocean-stream, as demonstrating the progress of the age in this department of
inquiry. And even earlier than Herodotus, Xanthus had noticed the occurrence of
fossil marine productions in the interior of Asia Minor, which led him to
reflections on the changes of the earth's surface with respect to land and
water.
If then we look down the three
centuries and a half which elapsed between the commencement of the Olympic era
and the age of Herodotus and Thucydides, we shall discern a striking advance in
the Greeks, — ethical, social and intellectual. Positive history and chronology
has not only been created, but in the case of Thucydides, the qualities
necessary to the historiographer, in their application to recent events, have
been developed with a degree of perfection never since surpassed. Men’s minds
have assumed a gentler as well as a juster cast; and
acts come to be criticized with reference to their bearing on the internal
happiness of a well-regulated community, as well as upon the standing harmony
of fraternal states. While Thucydides treats the habitual and licensed piracy,
so coolly alluded to in the Homeric poems, as an obsolete enormity, many of the
acts described in the old heroic and Theogonic legends were found not less repugnant to this improved tone of feeling. The
battles of the gods with the Giants and Titans, — the castration of Uranus by
his son Cronus,— the cruelty, deceit and licentiousness, often supposed both in
the gods and heroes, provoked strong disapprobation. And the language of the
philosopher Xenophanes, who composed both elegiac and iambic poems for the
express purpose of denouncing such tales, is as vehement and unsparing as that
of the Christian writers, who, eight centuries afterwards, attacked the whole
scheme of paganism.
Nor was it alone as an ethical and
social critic that Xenophanes stood distinguished. He was one of a great and
eminent triad — Thales and Pythagoras being the others — who, in the sixth
century before the Christian era, first opened up those veins of speculative
philosophy which occupied afterwards so large a portion of Grecian intellectual
energy. Of the material differences between the three I do not here speak; I
regard them only in reference to the Homeric and Hesiodic philosophy which
preceded them, and from which all three deviated .by a step, perhaps the most
remarkable in all the history of philosophy. In the scheme of ideas common to
Homer and to the Hesiodic Theogony (as has been already stated), we find nature
distributed into a variety of personal agencies, administered according to the
free-will of different Beings more or less analogous to man—each of these
Beings having his own character, attributes and powers, his own sources of pain
and pleasure, and his own especial sympathies or antipathies with human
individuals; each being determined to act or forbear, to grant favor or inflict
injury in his own department of phenomena, according as men, or perhaps other
Beings analogous to himself; might conciliate or offend him. The Gods, properly
so called, (those who bore a proper name and received some public or family
worship,) were the most commanding and capital members amidst this vast network
of agents visible and invisible, spread over the universe. The whole vie of
nature was purely religious and subjective, the spontaneous suggestion of the early
mind. It proceeded from the instinctive tendencies of the feelings and
imagination to transport, to the world without, the familiar type of free-will
and conscious personal action : above all, it took deep hold of the emotions,
from the widely extended sympathy which it so perpetually called forth between
man and nature.
The first attempt to disenthrall the
philosophic intellect from this all-personifying religious faith, and to
constitute a method of interpreting nature distinct from the spontaneous inspirations
of untaught minds, is to be found in Thales, Xenophanes and Pythagoras, in the
sixth century before the Christian era. It is in them that we first find the
idea of Person tacitly set aside or limited, and an impersonal Nature conceived
as the object of study. The divine husband and wife, Oceanus and Tethys,
parents of many gods and of the Oceanic nymphs, together with the avenging
goddess Styx, are translated into the material substance water, or, as we ought
rather to say, the Fluid : and Thales set himself to prove that water was the
primitive element, out of which all the different natural substances had been
formed. He, as well as Xenophanes and Pythagoras, started the problem of
physical philosophy, with its objective character and invariable laws, to be
discoverable by a proper and methodical application of the human intellect. The
Greek word Physic, denoting nature,
and its derivatives physics and physiology, unknown in that large sense
to Homer or Hesiod, as well as the word Cosmos,
to denote the mundane system, first appears with these philosophers. The
elemental analysis of Thales — the one unchangeable cosmic substance, varying
only in appearance, but not in reality, as suggested by Xenophanes,—and the
geometrical and arithmetical combinations of Pythagoras, — all these were
different ways of approaching the explanation of physical phenomena, and each
gave rise to a distinct school or succession of philosophers. But they all
agreed in departing from the primitive method, and in recognizing determinate
properties, invariable sequences, and objective truth, in nature — either
independent of willing or designing agents, or serving to these latter at once
as an indispensable subject-matter and as a limiting condition. Xenophanes
disclaimed openly all knowledge respecting the gods, and pronounced that no man
could have any means of ascertaining when he was right and when he was wrong,
in affirmations respecting them : while Pythagoras represents in part the
scientific tendencies of his age, in part also the spirit of mysticism and of
special fraternities for religious and ascetic observance, which became
diffused throughout Greece in the sixth century before the Christian era. This
was another point which placed him in antipathy with the simple, unconscious
and demonstrative faith of the old poets, as well as with the current legends.
If these distinguished men, when
they ceased to follow the primitive instinct of tracing the phenomena of nature
to personal and designing agents, passed over, not at once to induction and
observation, but to a misemployment of abstract words, substituting
metaphysical eidola in the place of
polytheism, and to an exaggerated application of certain narrow physical
theories— we must remember that nothing else could be expected from the scanty
stock of facts then accessible, and that the most profound study of the human
mind points out such transition as an inevitable law of intellectual progress.
At present, we have to compare them only with that state of the Greek minds
which they partially superseded, and with which they were in decided
opposition. The rudiments of physical science were conceived and developed
among superior men; but the religious feeling of the mass was averse to them;
and the aversion, though gradually mitigated, never wholly died away. Some of
the philosophers were not backward in charging others with irreligion, while
the multitude seems to have felt the same sentiment more or less towards all—or
towards that postulate of constant sequences, with determinate conditions of
occurrence, which scientific study implies, and which they could not reconcile
with their belief in the agency of the gods, to whom they were constantly
praying for special succor and blessings.
SOCRATES. HIPPOCRATES. ANAXAGORAS.
The discrepancy between the
scientific and the religious point of view was dealt with differently by
different philosophers. Thus Socrates openly admitted it, and assigned to each
a distinct and independent province. He distributed phenomena into two classes
: one, wherein the connection of antecedent and consequent was invariable and
ascertainable by human study, and therefore future results accessible to a
well-instructed foresight; the other, and those, too, the most comprehensive
and important, which the gods had reserved for themselves and their own
unconditional agency, wherein there was no invariable or ascertainable
sequence, and where the result could only be foreknown by some omen, prophecy,
or other special inspired communication from themselves. Each of these classes
was essentially distinct, and required to be looked at and dealt with in a
manner radically incompatible with the other. Socrates held it wrong to apply
the scientific interpretation to the latter, or the theological interpretation
to the former. Physics and astronomy, in his opinion, belonged to the divine
class of phenomena, in which human research was insane, fruitless, and impious.
On the other hand, Hippocrates, the
contemporary of Socrates, denied the discrepancy, and merged into one those two
classes of phenomena, the divine and the scientifically determinable,—which the
latter had put asunder. Hippocrates treated all phenomena as at once both
divine and scientifically determinable. In discussing certain peculiar bodily
disorders found among the Scythians, he observes, “The Scythians themselves
ascribe the cause of this to God, and reverence and bow down to such sufferers,
each man fearing that he may suffer the like; and I myself think too that these
affections, as well as all others, are divine : no one among them is either
more divine or more human than another, but all are on the same footing, and
all divine; nevertheless each of them has its own physical conditions, and not
one occurs without such physical conditions”.
A third distinguished philosopher of
the same day, Anaxagoras, allegorizing Zeus and the other personal gods,
proclaimed the doctrine of one common pervading Mind, as having first
established order and system in the mundane aggregate, which had once been in a
state of chaos—and as still manifesting its uninterrupted agency for wise and
good purposes. This general doctrine obtained much admiration from Plato and
Aristotle; but they at the same time remarked with surprise, that Anaxagoras
never made any use at all of his own general doctrine for the explanation of
the phenomena of nature,—that he looked for nothing but physical causes and
connecting laws,—so that in fact the spirit of his particular researches was
not materially different from those of Democritus or Leucippus, whatever might
be the difference in their general theories. His investigations in meteorology
and astronomy, treating the heavenly bodies as subjects for calculation, have
been already noticed as offensive, not only to the general public of Greece,
but even to Socrates himself among them : he was tried at Athens, and seems to
have escaped condemnation only by voluntary exile.
The three eminent men just named,
all essentially different from each other, may be taken as illustrations of the
philosophical mind of Greece during the last half of the fifth century BC.
Scientific pursuits had acquired a powerful hold, and adjusted themselves in
various ways with the prevalent religious feelings of the age. Both Hippocrates
and Anaxagoras modified their ideas of the divine agency so as to suit their
thirst for scientific research. According to the former, the gods were the
really efficient agents in the production of all phenomena,—the mean and
indifferent not less than the terrific or tutelary. Being thus alike connected
with all phenomena, they were specially associated with none—and the proper
task of the inquirer was, to find out those rules and conditions by which (he
assumed) their agency was always determined, and according to which it might be
foretold. And this led naturally to the proceeding which Plato and Aristotle
remark in Anaxagoras,—that the all-governing and Infinite Mind, having been
announced in sublime language at the beginning of his treatise, was afterward
left out of sight, and never applied to the explanation of particular
phenomena, being as much consistent with one modification of nature as with
another.
Now such a view of the divine agency
could never be reconciled with the religious feelings of the ordinary Grecian
believer, even as they stood in the time of Anaxagoras; still less could it
have been reconciled with those of the Homeric man, more than three centuries
earlier. By him Zeus and Athene were conceived as definite Persons, objects of
special reverence, hopes, and fears, and animated with peculiar feelings,
sometimes of favor, sometimes of wrath, towards himself or his family or
country. They were propitiated by his prayers, and prevailed upon to lend him
succor in danger—but offended and disposed to bring evil upon him if he omitted
to render thanks or sacrifice. This sense of individual communion with, and
dependence upon them was the essence of his faith; and with that faith, the
all-pervading Mind proclaimed by Anaxagoras—which had no more concern with one man
or one phenomenon than with another,—could never be brought into harmony. Nor
could the believer, while ho prayed with sincerity for special blessings or
protection from the gods, acquiesce in the doctrine of Hippocrates, that their
agency was governed by constant laws and physical conditions.
That radical discord between the
mental impulses of science and religion, which manifests itself so decisively
during the most cultivated ages of Greece, and which harassed more or less so
many of the philosophers, produced its most afflicting result in the
condemnation of Socrates by the Athenians. According to the remarkable passage
recently cited from Xenophon, it will appear that Socrates agreed with his
countrymen in denouncing physical speculations as impious,—that he recognized
the religious process of discovery as a peculiar branch, coordinate with the
scientific,—and that he laid down a theory, of which the basis was, the
confessed divergence of these two processes from the beginning—thereby seemingly
satisfying the exigencies of religious hopes and fears on the one hand, and
those of reason, in her ardor for ascertaining the invariable laws of
phenomena, on the other. We may remark that the theory of this religious and
extra-scientific process of discovery was at that time sufficiently complete;
for Socrates could point out, that those anomalous phenomena which the gods had
reserved for themselves, and into which science was forbidden to pry, were yet
accessible to the seekings of the pious man, through
oracles, omens, and other exceptional means of communication which divine
benevolence vouchsafed to keep open. Considering thus to how great an extent
Socrates was identified in feeling with the religious public of Athens, and
considering moreover that his performance of open religious duties was
assiduous—we might wonder, as Xenophon does wonder, how it could have happened
that the Athenian dikasts mistook him at the end of
his life for an irreligious man. But we see, by the defense which Xenophon as well
as Plato gives for him, that the Athenian public really considered him, in
spite of his own disclaimer, as homogeneous with Anaxagoras and the other
physical inquirers, because he had applied similar scientific reasonings to moral and social phenomena. They looked upon
him with the same displeasure as he himself felt towards the physical
philosophers, and we cannot but admit that in this respect they were more
unfortunately consistent than he was. It is true that the mode of defense
adopted by Socrates contributed much to the verdict found against him, and that
he was further weighed down by private offence given to powerful individuals
and professions; but all these separate antipathies found their best account in
swelling the cry against him as an over-curious skeptic, and an impious
innovator.
Now the scission thus produced
between the superior minds and the multitude, in consequence of the development
of science and the scientific point of view, is a fact of great moment in the
history of Greek progress, and forms an important contrast between the age of
Homer and Hesiod and that of Thucydides; though in point of fact even the
multitude, during this later age, were partially modified by those very
scientific views which they regarded with disfavor. And we must keep in view
the primitive religious faith, once universal and unobstructed, but
subsequently disturbed by the intrusions of science; we must follow the great
change, as well in respect to enlarged intelligence as to refinement of social
and ethical feeling, among the Greeks, from the Hesiodic times downward, in
order to render some account of the altered manner in which the ancient myths
came to be dealt with. The myth, the spontaneous growth of a creative and
personifying interpretation of nature, had struck root in Grecian associations
at a time when the national faith required no support from what we call
evidence. They were now submitted, not simply to a feeling, imagining, and
believing public, but also to special classes of instructed men, —philosophers,
historians, ethical teachers, and to a public partially modified by their ideas
as well as improved by a wider practical experience. They were not intended for
such an audience; they had ceased to be in complete harmony even with the lower
strata of intellect and sentiment,—much more so with the higher. But they were
the cherished inheritance of a past time; they were interwoven in a thousand
ways with the religious faith, the patriotic respect, and the national worship,
of every Grecian community; the general type of the myth was the ancient,
familiar, and universal form of Grecian thought, which even the most cultivated
men bad imbibed in their childhood from the poets and by which they were to a
certain degree unconsciously enslaved. Taken as a whole the myths and acquired
prescriptive and ineffaceable possession : to attack, call in question, or
repudiate them, was a task painful even to undertake, and far beyond the power
of any one to accomplish.
For these reasons the anti-mythic
vein of criticism was of no effect as a destroying force, but nevertheless its
dissolving decomposing and transforming influence was very considerable. To
accommodate the ancient myths to an improved tone of sentiment and a newly
created canon of credibility, was a function which even the wisest Greeks did
not disdain, and which occupied no small proportion of the whole intellectual
activity of the nation.
The myths were looked at from a
point of view completely foreign to the reverential curiosity and literal
imaginative faith of the Homeric man; they were broken up and recast in order
to force them into new molds such as their authors had never conceived. We may
distinguish four distinct classes of minds, in the literary age now under
examination, as having taken them in hand — the poets, the logographers, the
philosophers, and the historians.
POETS AND LOGOGRAPHERS
With the poets and logographers, the
mythical persons are real predecessors, and the mythical world an antecedent
fact; but it is divine and heroic reality, not human; the present is only
half-brother of the past (to borrow an illustration from Pindar in his allusion
to gods and men), remotely and generically, but not closely and specifically,
analogous to it. As a general habit, the old feelings and the old unconscious
faith, apart from all proof or evidence, still remain in their minds; but
recent feelings have grown up which compel them to omit, to alter, sometimes
even to reject and condemn, particular narratives.
Pindar repudiates some stories and
transforms others, because they are inconsistent with his conceptions of the
gods. Thus he formally protests against the tale that Pelops had been killed and served up at table by his father, for the immortal gods to
eat; he shrinks from the idea of imputing to them so horrid an appetite; he
pronounces the tale to have been originally fabricated by a slanderous
neighbor. Nor can he bring himself to recount the quarrels between different
gods. The amours of Zeus and Apollo are no way displeasing to him; but he
occasionally suppresses some of the simple details of the old myth, as
deficient in dignity : thus, according to the Hesiodic narrative, Apollo was
informed by a raven of the infidelity of the nymph Koronis : but the mention of the raven did not appear to Pindar consistent with the
majesty of the god, and he therefore wraps up the mode of detection in vague
and mysterious language. He feels considerable repugnance to the character of
Odysseus, and intimates more than once that Homer has unduly exalted him, by
force of poetical artifice. With the character of the Eakid Ajax, on the other hand, he has the deepest sympathy, as well as with his
untimely and inglorious death, occasioned by the undeserved preference of a
less worthy rival. He appeals for his authority usually to the Muse, but
sometimes to “ancient sayings of men”, accompanied with a general allusion to
story-tellers and bards,—admitting, however, that these stories present great
discrepancy, and sometimes that they are false. Yet the marvelous and the
supernatural afford no ground whatever for rejecting a story. Pindar makes an
express declaration to this effect in reference to the romantic adventures of
Perseus and the Gorgon's head. He treats even those mythical characters, which
conflict the most palpably with positive experience, as connected by a real
genealogical thread with the world before him. Not merely the heroes of Troy
and Thebes, and the demigod seamen of Jason and the ship Argo, but also the
Centaur Cheiron, the hundred-headed Typhos, the giant Alkyoneus, Antaeus, Bellorophon and Pegasus,
the Chimaera, the Amazons and the Hyperboreans—all
appear painted on the same canvas, and touched with the same colors, as the men
of the recent and recorded past, Phalaris and
Croesus; only they are thrown back to a greater distance in the perspective.
The heroic ancestors of those great Eginetan,
Thessalian, Theban, Argeian, etc. families, whose
present members the poet celebrates for their agonistic victories, sympathize
with the exploits and second the efforts of their descendants : the inestimable
value of a privileged breed and of the stamp of nature is powerfully contrasted
with the impotence of unassisted teaching and practice. The power and skill of
the Argeian Theaeus and his
relatives as wrestlers, are ascribed partly to the fact that their ancestors Pamphaes in aforetime had hospitably entertained the
Tyndarids Castor and Pollux. Perhaps however the
strongest proof of the sincerity of Pindar's mythical faith is afforded when he
notices a guilty incident with shame and repugnance, but with an unwilling
confession of its truth, as in the case of the fratricide committed on Phokus by his brothers Peleus and Telamon.
TRAGIC POETS: AESCHYLUS AND
SOPHOCLES
Aeschylus and Sophocles exhibit the
same spontaneous and uninquiring faith as Pindar in
the legendary antiquities of Greece, taken as a whole; but they allow
themselves greater license as to the details. It was indispensable to the
success of their compositions that they should recast and group anew the
legendary events, preserving the names and general understood relation of those
characters whom they introduced. The demand for novelty of combination
increased with the multiplication of tragic spectacles at Athens : moreover the
feelings of the Athenians, ethical as well as political, had become too
critical to tolerate the literal reproduction of many among the ancient
stories.
Both of them exalted rather than
lowered the dignity of the mythical world, as something divine and heroic rather
than human. The Prometheus of Aeschylus is a far more exalted conception than
his keen-witted namesake in Hesiod, and the more homely details of the ancient
Thebais and Edipodia were in like manner modified by
Sophocles. The religious agencies of the old epic are constantly kept
prominent, and the paternal curse, —the wrath of deceased persons against those
from whom they have sustained wrong,—the judgments of the Erinnys against guilty or foredoomed persons, sometimes inflicted directly, sometimes
brought about through dementation of the sufferer himself
(like the Homeric Atê),—are frequent in their
tragedies.
Aeschylus in two of his remaining
pieces brings forward the gods as the chief personages, and far from sharing
the objection of Pindar to dwell upon dissensions of the gods, he introduces
Prometheus and Zeus in the one, Apollo and the Eumenides in the other, in marked opposition. The dialogue, first superinduced by him upon the primitive Chorus, gradually became the most important portion
of the drama, and is more elaborated in Sophocles than in Aeschylus. Even in
Sophocles, however, it still generally retains its ideal majesty as contrasted
with the rhetorical and forensic tone which afterwards crept in; it grows out
of the piece, and addresses itself to the emotions more than to the reason of
the audience. Nevertheless, the effect of Athenian political discussion and
democratic feeling is visible in both these dramatists. The idea of rights and
legitimate privileges as opposed to usurping force, is applied by Aeschylus
even to the society of the gods : the Eumenides accuse Apollo of having, with the insolence of youthful ambition, "ridden
down" their old prerogatives — while the Titan Prometheus, the champion of
suffering humanity against the unfriendly dispositions of Zeus, ventures to
depict the latter as a recent usurper reigning only by his superior strength,
exalted by one successful revolution, and destined at some future time to be
overthrown by another, — a fate which cannot be averted except through warnings
communicable only by Prometheus himself.
It is commonly understood that
Aeschylus disapproved of the march of democracy at Athens during his later
years, and that the Eumenides is intended as an
indirect manifestation in favor of the senate of Areiopagus.
Without inquiring at present whether such a special purpose can be distinctly
made out, we may plainly see that the poet introduces, into the relations of
the gods with each other, a feeling of political justice, arising out of the
times in which he lived and the debates of which he was a witness. But though
Aeschylus incurred reproaches of impiety from Plato, and seemingly also from
the Athenian public, for particular speeches and incidents in his tragedies,
and though he does not adhere to the received vein of religious tradition with
the same strictness as Sophocles — yet the ascendency and interference of the
gods is never out of sight, and the solemnity with which they are represented,
set off by a bold, figurative, and elliptical style of expression (often but
imperfectly intelligible to modern readers), reaches its maximum in his
tragedies. As he throws round the gods a kind of airy grandeur, so neither do
his men or heroes appear like tenants of the common earth : the mythical world
from which he borrows his characters is peopled only with the immediate seed of
the gods, in close contact with Zeus, in whom the divine blood has not yet had
time to degenerate en his individuals are taken, not from the iron race whom
Hesiod acknowledges with shame as his contemporaries, but from the extinct
heroic race which had fought at Troy and Thebes. It is to them that his
conceptions aspire, and he is even chargeable with frequent straining, beyond
the limits of poetical taste, to realize his picture. If he does not
consistently succeed in it, the reason is because consistency in such a matter
is unattainable, since, after all, the analogies of common humanity, the only
materials which the most creative imagination has to work upon, obtrude themselves
involuntarily, and the lineaments of the man are thus seen even under a dress
which promises superhuman proportions.
Sophocles, the most illustrious
ornament of Grecian tragedy, dwells upon the same heroic characters, and
maintains their grandeur, on the whole, with little abatement, combining with
it a far better dramatic structure, and a wider appeal to human sympathies.
Even in Sophocles, however, we find indications that an altered ethical feeling
and a more predominant sense of artistic perfection are allowed to modify the
harsher religious agencies of the old epic; occasional misplaced effusions of
rhetoric, as well as of didactic prolixity, may also be detected. It is
Aeschylus, not Sophocles, who forms the marked antithesis to Euripides; it is
Aeschylus, not Sophocles, to whom Aristophanes awards the prize of tragedy, as
the poet who assigns most perfectly to the heroes of the past those weighty
words, imposing equipments, simplicity of great deeds
with little talk, and masculine energy superior to the corruptions of
Aphrodite, which beseem the comrades of Agamemnon and Adrastus.
EURIPIDES
How deeply this feeling, of the
heroic character of the mythical world, possessed the Athenian mind, may be
judged by the bitter criticisms made on Euripides, whose compositions were
pervaded, partly by ideas of physical philosophy learnt under Anaxagoras,
partly by the altered tone of education and the wide diffusion of practical
eloquence, forensic as well as political, at Athens. While Aristophanes assails
Euripides as the representative of this "young Athens", with the
utmost keenness of sarcasm, — other critics also concur in designating him as
having vulgarized the mythical heroes, and transformed them into mere
characters of common life, —loquacious, subtle, and savoring of the
market-place. In some of his plays, skeptical expressions and sentiments were
introduced, derived from his philosophical studies, sometimes confounding two
or three distinct gods into one, sometimes translating the personal Zeus into a
substantial Ether with determinate attributes. He put into the mouths of some
of his unprincipled dramatic characters, apologetic speeches which were
denounced as ostentatious sophistry, and as setting out a triumphant case for
the criminal. His thoughts, his words, and the rhythm of his choric songs, were
all accused of being deficient in dignity and elevation. The mean attire and
miserable attitude in which he exhibited Aeneas, Telephus,
Thyestes, Ino, and other heroic characters, were
unmercifully derided, though it seems that their position and circumstances had
always been painfully melancholy; but the effeminate pathos which Euripides
brought so nakedly into the foreground, was accounted unworthy of the majesty
of a legendary hero. And he incurred still greater obloquy on another point, on
which he is allowed even by his enemies to have only reproduced in substance
the preexisting tales, —the illicit and fatal passion depicted in several of
his female characters, such as Phaedra and Sthenoboea.
His opponents admitted that these stories were true, but contended that they
ought to be kept back and not produced upon the stage,—a proof both of the
continued mythical faith and of the more sensitive ethical criticism of his
age. The marriage of the six daughters to the six sons of Eolus is of Homeric
origin, and stands now, though briefly stated, in the Odyssey : but the
incestuous passion of Macareus and Canace, embodied by Euripides in the lost tragedy called Eolus, drew upon him severe censure. Moreover,
he often disconnected the horrors of the old legends with those religious
agencies by which they had been originally forced on, prefacing them by motives
of a more refined character, which carried no sense of awful compulsion : thus
the considerations by which the Euripidean Alkmaeon was reduced to the necessity of killing his mother
appeared to Aristotle ridiculous. After the time of this great poet, his
successors seem to have followed him in breathing into their characters the
spirit of common life, but the names and plot were still borrowed from the
stricken mythical families of Tantalus, Cadmus, etc.: and the heroic exaltation
of all the individual personages introduced, as contrasted with the purely
human character of the Chorus, is still numbered by Aristotle among the
essential points of the theory of tragedy.
PHEREKYDES. HECATAEUS …
The tendency then of Athenian
tragedy—powerfully manifested in Aeschylus, and never wholly lost—was to uphold
an unquestioning faith and a reverential estimate of the general mythical world
and its personages, but to treat the particular narratives rather as matter for
the emotions than as recitals of actual fact. The logographers worked along
with them to the first of these two ends, but not to the second. Their grand
object was, to cast the myths into a continuous readable series, and they were
in consequence compelled to make selection between inconsistent or
contradictory narratives; to reject some narratives as false, and to receive
others as true. But their preference was determined more by their sentiments as
to what was appropriate, than by any pretended historical test. Pherekydes, Akusilaus and Hellanikus did not
seek to banish miraculous or fantastic incidents from the mythical world; they
regarded it as peopled with loftier beings, and expected to find in it
phenomena not paralleled in their own degenerate days. They reproduced the
fables as they found them in the poets, rejecting little except the
discrepancies, and producing ultimately what they believed to be not only a
continuous but an exact and trustworthy history of the past—wherein they carry
indeed their precision to such a length, that Hellanicus gives the year, and even the day of the capture of Troy.
Hecataeus of Miletus (500 BC), anterior to Pherekydes
and Hellanikus, is the earliest writer in whom we can
detect any disposition to disallow the prerogative and specialty of the myths,
and to soften down their characteristic prodigies, some of which however still
find favor in his eyes, as in the case of the speaking ram who carried Phryxus over the Hellespont. He pronounced the Grecian
fables to be “many and ridiculous”; whether from their discrepancies or from
their intrinsic improbabilities we do not know: and we owe to him the first
attempt to force them within the limits of historical credibility; as where he
transforms the three-headed Cerberus, the dog of Hades, into a serpent inhabiting
a cavern on Cape Taenarus—and Geryon of Erytheia into a king of Epirus rich in herds of
oxen. Hecataeus traced the genealogy of himself and
the gens to which he belonged through
a line of fifteen progenitors up to an initial god,— the clearest proof both of
his profound faith in the reality of the mythical world, and of his religious
attachment to it as the point of junction between the human and the divine
personality.
HERODOTUS, THUCYDIDES, ETC.
We have next to consider the
historians, especially Herodotus and Thucydides. Like Hecataeus,
Thucydides belonged to a gens which
traced its descent from Ajax, and through Ajax to Eakus and Zeus. Herodotus modestly implies that he himself had no such privilege to
boast of. Their curiosity respecting the past had no other materials to work
upon except the myths; but these they found already cast by the logographers
into a continuous series, and presented as an aggregate of antecedent history,
chronologically deduced from the times of the gods. In common with the body of
the Greeks, both Herodotus and Thucydides had imbibed that complete and
unsuspecting belief in the general reality of mythical antiquity, which was
interwoven with the religion and the patriotism, and all the public
demonstrations of the Hellenic world. To acquaint themselves with the genuine
details of this foretime, was an inquiry highly interesting to them : but the
increased positive tendencies of their age, as well as their own habits of
personal investigation, had created in them an historical sense in regard to the past as well as to the present.
Having acquired a habit of appreciating the intrinsic tests of historical
credibility and probability, they found the particular narratives of the poets
and logographers, inadmissible as a whole even in the eyes of Hecataeus, still more at variance with their stricter
canons of criticism. And we thus observe in them the constant struggle, as well
as the resulting compromise, between these two opposite tendencies; on one hand
a firm belief in the reality of the mythical world, on the other hand an
inability to accept the details which their only witnesses, the poets and
logographers, told them respecting it.
Each of them however performed the
process in his own way Herodotus is a man of deep and anxious religious
feeling; he often recognizes the special judgments of the gods as determining
historical events : his piety is also partly tinged with that mystical vein
which the last two centuries had gradually infused into the religion of the
Greeks—for he is apprehensive of giving offence to the gods by reciting
publicly what he has heard respecting them; he frequently stops short in his
narrative and intimates that there is a sacred legend, but that he will not
tell it: in other cases, where he feels compelled to speak out, he entreats
forgiveness for doing so from the gods and heroes. Sometimes he will not even
mention the name of a god, though he generally thinks himself authorized to do
so, the names being matter of public notoriety. Such pious reserve, which the
open-hearted Herodotus avowedly proclaims as chaining up his tongue, affords a
striking contrast with the plain-spoken and unsuspecting tone of the ancient
epic, as well as of the popular legends, wherein the gods and their proceedings
were the familiar and interesting subjects of common talk as well as of common
sympathy, without ceasing to inspire both fear and reverence.
Herodotus expressly distinguishes,
in the comparison of Polycrates with Minos, the human
race to which the former belonged, from the divine or heroic race which
comprised the latter. But he has a firm belief in the authentic personality and
parentage of all the names in the myths, divine, heroic and human, as well as
in the trustworthiness of their chronology computed by generations. He counts
back 1600 years from his own day to that of Semele,
mother of Dionysus; 900 years to Heracles, and 800 years to Penelope, the
Trojan war being a little earlier in date. Indeed even the longest of these
periods must have seemed to him comparatively short, seeing that he apparently
accepts the prodigious series of years which the Egyptians professed to draw
from a recorded chronology--17,000 years from their god Heracles, and 15,000
years from their god Osiris or Dionysus, down to their king Amasis (550 BC). So much was his imagination familiarized with these long
chronological computations barren of events, that he treats Homer and Hesiod as
"men of yesterday", though separated from his own age by an interval
which he reckons as four hundred years.
Herodotus had been profoundly
impressed with what he saw and heard in Egypt. The wonderful monuments, the
evident antiquity, and the peculiar civilization of that country, acquired such
preponderance in his mind over his own native legends, that he is disposed to
trace even the oldest religious names or institutions of Greece to Egyptian or
Phoenician original, setting aside in favor of this hypothesis the Grecian
legends of Dionysus and Pan. The oldest Grecian mythical genealogies are thus
made ultimately to lose themselves in Egyptian or Phoenician antiquity, and in
the full extent of these genealogies Herodotus firmly believes. It does not
seem that any doubt had ever crossed his mind as to the real personality of
those who were named or described in the popular myths : all of them have once
had reality, either as men, as heroes, or as gods. The eponyms of cities, demos
and tribes, are all comprehended in this affirmative category; the supposition
of fictitious personages being apparently never entertained. Deucalion, Helen, Dorus,—Ion, with his four sons, the eponyms of the old
Athenian tribes,—the autochthonous Titakus and Dekelus,—Danaus, Lynkeus, Perseus, Amphitryon, Alkmena, and Heracles,—Tathybius,
the heroic progenitor of the privileged heraldic gens at Sparta,—the Tyndarids
and Helena,—Agamemnon, Menelaus, and Orestes,—Nester and his son Peisistratus,—Asopus, Thebe, and Egina,—Inachus and Io, Aetes and Medea,—Melanippus, Adrastus, and Amphiaraus, as well as Jason and the Argo,—all these are
occupants of the real past time, and predecessors of himself and his
contemporaries. In the veins of the Lacedaemonian kings flowed the blood both
of Cadmus and of Danaus, their splendid pedigree
being traceable to both of these great mythical names : Herodotus carries the
lineage up through Heracles first to Perseus and Dame, then through Danae to Akrisius and the
Egyptian Danaus; but he drops the paternal lineage
when he comes to Perseus (inasmuch as Perseus is the son of Zeus by Danae, without any reputed human father, such as Amphitryon was to Heracles), and then follow the higher
members of the series through Danae alone. He also
pursues the same regal genealogy, through the mother of Eurysthenes and Procles, up to Polynikes,
(Edipus, Laius, Labdakus, Polyarus and Kadmus; and he
assigns various ancient inscriptions which he saw in the temple of the Ismenian Apollo at Thebes, to the ages of Laius and Edipus. Moreover, the sieges of Thebes and Troy, —the Argonautic expedition,—the invasion of Attica by the
Amazons,—the protection of the Herakleids, and the
defeat and death of Eurystheus, by the Athenians,—the
death of Mekisteus and Tydeus before Thebes by the hands of Melanippus, and the
touching calamities of Adrastus and Amphiaraus connected with the same enterprise,—the sailing
of Castor and Pollux in the Argo,—the abductions of
Io, Europa, Medea and Helena,—the emigration of Cadmus in quest of Europa, and
his coming to Boeotia, as well as the attack of the Greeks upon Troy to recover
Helen,—all these events seem to him portions of past history, not less
unquestionably certain, though more clouded over by distance and
misrepresentation, than the battles of Salamis and Mycale.
But though Herodotus is thus easy of
faith in regard both to the persons and to the general facts of Grecian myths,
yet when he comes to discuss particular facts taken separately, we find him
applying to them stricter tests of historical credibility, and often disposed
to reject as well the miraculous as the extravagant. Thus even with respect to
Heracles, he censures the levity of the Greeks in ascribing to him absurd and
incredible exploits; he tries their assertion by the philosophical standard of
nature, or of determinate powers and conditions governing the course of events.
“How is it consonant to nature (he asks), that Heracles, being, as he was,
according to the statement of the Greeks, a man, should kill many thousand
persons? I pray that indulgence may be shown to me both by gods and heroes for
saying so much as this”. The religious feelings of Herodotus here told him that
he was trenching upon the utmost limits of admissible skepticism.
Another striking instance of the
disposition of Herodotus to rationalize the miraculous narratives of the
current myths, is to be found in his account of the oracle of Dodona and its
alleged Egyptian origin. Here, if in any case, a miracle was not only in full
keeping, but apparently indispensable to satisfy the exigencies of the
religious sentiment; anything less than a miracle would have appeared tame and
unimpressive to the visitors of so revered a spot, much more to the residents
themselves. Accordingly, Herodotus heard, both from the three priestesses and
from the Dodonaeans generally, that two black doves
had started at the same time from Thebes in Egypt : one of them went to Libya,
where it directed the Libyans to establish the oracle of Zeus Ammon; the other
came to the grove of Dodona, and perched on one of the venerable oaks,
proclaiming with a human voice that an oracle of Zeus must be founded on that
very spot. The injunction of the speaking dove was respectfully obeyed.
Such was the tale related and
believed at Dodona. But Herodotus had also heard, from the priests at Thebes in
Egypt, a different tale, ascribing the origin of all the prophetic
establishments, in Greece as well as in Libya, to two sacerdotal women, who had
been carried away from Thebes by some Phoenician merchants and sold, the one in
Greece, the other in Libya. The Theban priests boldly assured Herodotus that
much pains had been taken to discover what had become of these women so
exported, and that the fact of their having been taken to Greece and Libya had
been accordingly verified.
HERODOTUS AND THE MIRACLE OF DODONA
The historian of Halicarnassus
cannot for a moment think of admitting the miracle which harmonized so well
with the feelings of the priestesses and the Dodonaeans.
“How (he asks) could a dove speak with human voice?” But the narrative of the
priests at Thebes, though its prodigious improbability hardly requires to be
stated, yet involved no positive departure from the laws of nature and possibility,
and therefore Herodotus makes no difficulty in accepting it. The curious
circumstance is, that he turns the native Dodonaean legend into a figurative representation, or rather a misrepresentation, of the
supposed true story told by the Theban priests. According to his
interpretation, the woman who came from Thebes to Dodona was called a dove, and
affirmed to utter sounds like a bird, because she was non-Hellenic and spoke a
foreign tongue : when she learned to speak the language of the country, it was
then said that the dove spoke with a human voice. And the dove was moreover
called black, because of the woman’s Egyptian color.
That Herodotus should thus bluntly
reject a miracle, recounted to him by the prophetic women themselves as the
prime circumstance in the origins of this holy place, is a proof of the hold
which habits of dealing with historical evidence had acquired over his mind;
and the awkwardness of his explanatory mediation between the dove and the
woman, marks not less his anxiety, while discarding the legend, to let it
softly down into a story quasi-historical and not intrinsically incredible.
We may observe another example of
the unconscious tendency of Herodotus to eliminate from the myths the idea of
special aid from the gods, in his remarks upon Melampus.
He designates Melampus “as a clever man, who had
acquired for himself the art of prophecy”; and had procured through Cadmus much
information about the religious rites and customs of Egypt, many of which he
introduced into Greece—especially the name, the sacrifices, and the phallic
processions of Dionysus : he adds, “that Melampus himself did not accurately comprehend or bring out the whole doctrine, but wise
men who came after him made the necessary additions”. Though the name of Melampus is here maintained, the character described is
something in the vein of Pythagoras—totally different from the great seer and
leech of the old epic myths—the founder of the gifted family of the Amythaonids, and the grandfather of Amphiaraus.
But that which is most of all at variance with the genuine legendary spirit, is
the opinion expressed by Herodotus (and delivered with some emphasis as his
own), that Melampus “was a clever man, who had
acquired for himself prophetic powers”. Such a supposition would have appeared
inadmissible to Homer or Hesiod, or indeed to Solon, in the preceding century,
in whose view even inferior arts come from the gods, while Zeus or Apollo
bestows the power of prophesying. The intimation of such an opinion by Herodotus,
himself a thoroughly pious man, marks the sensibly diminished omnipresence of
the gods, and the increasing tendency to look for the explanation of phenomena
among more visible and determinate agencies.
We may make a similar remark on the
dictum of the historian respecting the narrow defile of Tempe, forming the
embouchure of the Peneus and the efflux of all the
waters from the Thessalian basin. The Thessalians alleged that this whole basin
of Thessaly had once been a lake, but that Poseidon had split the chain of
mountains and opened the efflux; upon which primitive belief, thoroughly
conformable to the genius of Homer and Hesiod, Herodotus comments as follows:
“The Thessalian statement is reasonable. For whoever thinks that Poseidon
shakes the earth, and that the rifts of an earthquake are the work of that god,
will, on seeing the defile in question, say that Poseidon has caused it. For
the rift of the mountains is, as appeared to me (when I saw it), the work of an
earthquake”. Herodotus admits the reference to Poseidon, when pointed out to
him, but it stands only in the background : what is present to his mind is the
phenomenon of the earthquake, not as a special act, but as part of a system of
habitual operations.
LEGEND OF TROY IN HERODOTUS.
Herodotus adopts the Egyptian
version of the legend of Troy, founded on that capital variation which seems to
have originated with Stesichorus, and according to
which Helen never left Sparta at all —her eidolon had been taken to Troy in her place. Upon this basis a new story had been
framed, midway between Homer and Stesichorus,
representing Paris to have really carried off Helen from Sparta, but to have
been driven by storms to Egypt, where she remained during the whole siege of
Troy, having been detained by Proteus, the king of the country, until Menelaus
came to reclaim her after his triumph. The Egyptian priests, with their usual
boldness of assertion, professed to have heard the whole story from Menelaus
himself— the Greeks had besieged Troy, in the full persuasion that Helen and
the stolen treasures were within the walls, nor would they ever believe the
repeated denials of the Trojans as to the fact of her presence. In intimating
his preference for the Egyptian narrative, Herodotus betrays at once his perfect
and unsuspecting confidence that he is dealing with genuine matter of history,
and his entire distrust of the epic poets, even including Homer, upon whose
authority that supposed history rested. His reason for rejecting the Homeric
version is that it teems with historical improbabilities. If Helen had been
really in Troy (he says), Priam and the Trojans would
never have been so insane as to retain her to their own utter ruin: but it was
the divine judgment which drove them into the miserable alternative of neither
being able to surrender Helen, nor to satisfy the Greeks of the real fact that
they had never had possession of her—in order that mankind might plainly read,
in the utter destruction of Troy, the great punishments with which the gods
visit great misdeeds. Homer (Herodotus thinks) had heard this story, but
designedly departed from it, because it was not so suitable a subject for epic
poetry.
Enough has been said to show how
wide is the difference between Herodotus and the logographers with their literal
transcript of the ancient legends. Though he agrees with them in admitting the
full series of persons and generations, he tries the circumstances narrated by
a new standard. Scruples have arisen in his mind respecting violations of the
laws of nature : the poets are unworthy of trust, and their narratives must be
brought into conformity with historical and ethical conditions, before they can
be admitted as truth. To accomplish this conformity, Herodotus is willing to
mutilate the old legend in one of its most vital points: he sacrifices the
personal presence of Helena in Troy, which ran through every one of the ancient
epic poems belonging to the Trojan cycle, and is indeed, under the gods, the
great and present moving force throughout.
Thucydides places himself generally
in the same point of view as Herodotus with regard to mythical antiquity, yet
with some considerable differences. Though manifesting no belief in present
miracles or prodigies, he seems to accept without reserve the preexistent reality
of all the persons mentioned in the myths, and of the long series of
generations extending back through so many supposed centuries : in this
category, too, are included the eponymous personages, Hellen, Kekrops, Eumolpus, Pandion, Amphilochus the son of Amphiaraus, and Akarnan. But on
the other hand, we find no trace of that distinction between a human and an
heroic ante-human race, which Herodotus still admitted,—nor any respect for
Egyptian legends. Thucydides, regarding the personages of the myths as men of
the same breed and stature with his own contemporaries, not only tests the acts
imputed to them by the same limits of credibility, but presumes in them the
same political views and feelings as he was accustomed to trace in the
proceedings of Peisistratus or Pericles. He treats the Trojan war as a great
political enterprise, undertaken by all Greece; brought into combination
through the imposing power of Agamemnon, not (according to the legendary
narrative) through the influence of the oath exacted by Tyndareus.
Then he explains how the predecessors of Agamemnon arrived at so vast a
dominion —beginning with Pelops, who came over (as he
says) from Asia with great wealth among the poor Peloponnesians, and by means
of this wealth so aggrandized himself, though a foreigner, as to become the
eponym of the peninsula. Next followed his son Atreus, who acquired after the
death of Eurystheus the dominion of Mycenae, which
had before been possessed by the descendants of Perseus : here the old
legendary tale, which described Atreus as having been banished by his father Pelops in consequence of the murder of his elder brother Chrysippus, is invested with a political bearing, as
explaining the reason why Atreus retired to Mycenae. Another legendary tale—the
defeat and death of Eurystheus by the fugitive Heracleides in Attica, so celebrated in Attic tragedy as
having given occasion to the generous protecting intervention of Athens—is also
introduced as furnishing the cause why Atreus succeeded to the deceased Eurystheus: “for Atreus, the maternal uncle of Eurystheus, had been entrusted by the latter with his
government during the expedition into Attica, and had effectually courted the
people, who were moreover in great fear of being attacked by the Heracleides”. Thus the Pelopids acquired the supremacy in Peloponnesus, and Agamemnon was enabled to get
together his 1200 ships and 100,000 men for the expedition against Troy.
Considering that contingents were furnished from every portion of Greece,
Thucydides regards this as a small number, treating the Homeric catalogue as an
authentic muster-roll, perhaps rather exaggerated than otherwise. He then
proceeds to tell us why the armament was not larger : many more men could have
been furnished, but there was not sufficient money to purchase provisions for
their subsistence; hence they were compelled, after landing and gaining a
victory, to fortify their camp, to divide their army, and to send away one
portion for the purpose of cultivating the Chersonese, and another portion to
sack the adjacent towns. This was the grand reason why the siege lasted so long
as ten years. For if it had been possible to keep the whole army together, and
to act with an undivided force, Troy would have been taken both earlier and at
smaller cost.
Such is the general sketch of the
war of Troy, as given by Thucydides. So different is it from the genuine epical
narrative, that we seem hardly to be reading a description of the same event;
still less should we imagine that the event was known, to him as well as to us,
only through the epic poets themselves. The men, the numbers, and the duration
of the siege, do indeed remain the same; but the east and juncture of events,
the determining forces, and the characteristic features, are altogether heterogeneous.
But, like Herodotus, and still more than Herodotus, Thucydides was under the
pressure of two conflicting impulses—he shared the general faith in the
mythical antiquity, but at the same time he could not believe in any facts
which contradicted the laws of historical credibility or probability. He was
thus under the necessity of torturing the matter of the old myths into
conformity with the subjective exigencies of his own mind: he left out,
altered, recombined, and supplied new connecting principles and supposed
purposes, until the story became such as no one could have any positive reason
for calling in question : though it lost the impressive mixture of religion,
romance, and individual adventure, which constituted its original charm, it
acquired a smoothness and plausibility, and a poetical ensemble, which the
critics were satisfied to accept as historical truth. And historical truth it
would doubtless have been, if any independent evidence could have been found to
sustain it. Had Thucydides been able to produce such new testimony, we should
have been pleased to satisfy ourselves that the war of Troy, as he recounted
it, was the real event; of which the war of Troy, as sung by the epic poets,
was a misreported, exaggerated, and ornamented recital. But in this case the
poets are the only real witnesses, and the narrative of Thucydides is a mere
extract and distillation from their incredibilities.
A few other instances may be
mentioned to illustrate the views of Thucydides respecting various mythical incidents.
1. He treats the residence of the Homeric Phaeakians at Corcyra as an undisputed fact, and employs it partly to explain the
efficiency of the Corcyraean navy in times preceding
the Peloponnesian war. He notices, with equal confidence, the story of Tereus and Prokne, daughter of Pandion, and the murder of the child Itys by Prokne his mother, and Philomela; and he produces
this ancient myth with especial reference to the alliance between the Athenians
and Teres, king of the Odrysian Thracians, during the time of the Peloponnesian war, intimating that the Odrysian Teres was neither of the
same family nor of the same country as Tereus the
husband of Prokne. The conduct of Pandion,
in giving his daughter Prokne in marriage to Tereus, is in his view dictated by political motives and
interests. 3. He mentions the Strait of Messina as the place through which
Odysseus is said to have sailed. 4. The Cyclopes and the Laestrygones (he says) were the most ancient reported inhabitants of Sicily; but he cannot
tell to what race they belonged, nor whence they came. 5. Italy derived its
name from Italus, king of the Sikels.
6. Eryx and Egesto in
Sicily were founded by fugitive Trojans after the capture of Troy; also Skione, in the Thracian peninsula of Pallene,
by Greeks from the Achaean town of Pellene, stopping
thither in their return from the siege of Troy: the Amphilochian Argos in the Gulf of Ambrakia was in like manner
founded by Amphilochus son of Amphiaraus,
in his return from the same enterprise. The remorse and mental derangement of
the matricidal Alkmaeon, son of Amphiarus,
is also mentioned by Thucydides, as well as the settlement of his son Akarnan in the country called after him Akarnania.
Such are the special allusions made
by this illustrious author in the course of his history to mythical events.
From the tenor of his language we may see that he accounted all that could be
known about them to be uncertain and unsatisfactory; but he has it much at
heart to show, that even the greatest were inferior in magnitude and importance
to the Peloponnesian war. In this respect his opinion seems to have been at
variance with that which was popular among his contemporaries.
EPHORUS, THEOPOMPUS, XENOPHON, ETC.
To touch a little upon the later
historians by whom these myths were handled, we find that Anaximenes of Lampsacus composed a consecutive history of events, beginning from the
Theogony down to the battle of Mantineia. But Ephorus professed to omit all the mythical narratives which
are referred to times anterior to the return of the Herakleids,
(such restriction would of course have banished the siege of Troy,) and even
reproved those who introduced myths into historical writing; adding, that
everywhere truth was the object to be aimed at. Yet in practice he seems often
to have departed from his own rule. Theopompus, on
the other hand, openly proclaimed that he could narrate fables in his history
better than Herodotus, or Ktesias, or Hellanicus. The fragments which remain to us, exhibit some
proof that this promise was performed as to quantity; though as to his style of
narration, the judgment of Dionysius is unfavorable. Xenophon ennobled his
favorite amusement of the chase by numerous examples chosen from the heroic
world, tracing their portraits with all the simplicity of an undiminished
faith. Callisthenes, like Ephorus, professed to omit
all myths which referred to a time anterior to the return of the Herakleids; yet we know that he devoted a separate book or
portion of his history to the Trojan war. Philistus introduced
some myths in the earlier portions of his Sicilian history; but Timaeus was
distinguished above all others for the copious and indiscriminate way in which
he collected and repeated such legends. Some of these writers employed their
ingenuity in transforming the mythical circumstances into plausible matter of
history : Ephorus, in particular, converted the
serpent Pythel, slain by Apollo, into a tyrannical
king.
But the author who pushed this
transmutation of legend into history to the greatest length, was the Messenian Euemerus, contemporary
of Cassander of Macedon. He melted down in this way the divine persons and
legends, as well as the heroic — representing both gods and heroes as having
been mere earthborn men, though superior to the ordinary level in respect of
force and capacity, and deified or heroified after
death as a recompense for services or striking exploits. In the course of a
voyage into the Indian sea, undertaken by command of Cassander, Euemerus professed to have discovered a fabulous country
called Panchaia, in which was a temple of the Triphylian Zeus : he there described a golden column, with
an inscription purporting to have been put up by Zeus himself, and detailing
his exploits while on earth. Some eminent men, among whom may be numbered
Polybius, followed the views of Euemerus, and the
Roman poet Ennius translated his Historia Sacra; but on the whole he never acquired favor, and the
unblushing inventions which he put into circulation were of themselves
sufficient to disgrace both the author and his opinions. The doctrine that all
the gods had once existed as mere men offended the religious pagans, and drew
upon Euemerus the imputation of atheism; but, on the
other hand, it came to be warmly espoused by several of the Christian
assailants of paganism, by Minucius Felix, Lactantius, and St. Augustin, who
found the ground ready prepared for them in their efforts to strip Zeus and the
other pagan gods of the attributes of deity. They believed not only in the main
theory, but also in the copious details of Euemerus;
and the same man whom Strabo casts aside as almost a proverb for mendacity, was
extolled by them as an excellent specimen of careful historical inquiry.
But though the pagan world
repudiated that “lowering tone of explanation”, which effaced the superhuman
personality of Zeus and the great gods of Olympus, the mythical persons and
narratives generally came to be surveyed more and more from the point of view
of history, and subjected to such alterations as might make them look more like
plausible matter of fact. Polybius, Strabo, Dioderus,
and Pausanias, cast the myths into historical statements—with more or less of
transformation, as the case may require, assuming always that there is a basis
of truth, which may be discovered by removing poetical exaggerations and
allowing for mistakes. Strabo, in particular, lays down that principle broadly
and unequivocally in his remarks upon Homer. To give pure fiction, without any
foundation of fact, was in his judgment utterly unworthy of so great a genius;
and he comments with considerable acrimony on the geographer Eratosthenes, who
maintains the opposite opinion. Again, Polybius tells us that the Homeric
Eolus, the dispenser of the winds by appointment from Zeus, was in reality a
man eminently skilled in navigation, and exact in predicting the weather; that
the Cyclopes and Laestrygones were wild and savage
real men in Sicily; and that Scylla and Charybdis were a figurative
representation of dangers arising from pirates in the Strait of Messina. Strabo
speaks of the amazing expeditions of Dionysus and Heracles, and of the long
wanderings of Jason, Menelaus, and Odysseus, in the same category with the
extended commercial range of the Phoenician merchant-ships : he explains the report
of Theseus and Poirithous having descended to Hades,
by their dangerous earthly pilgrimages, — and the invocation of the Dioskuri as the protectors of the imperiled mariner, by the
celebrity which they had acquired as real men and navigators.
Diodorus gave at considerable length
versions of the current fables respecting the most illustrious names in the
Grecian mythical world, compiled confusedly out of distinct and incongruous
authors. Sometimes the myth is reproduced in its primitive simplicity, but for
the most part it is partially, and sometimes wholly, historicized. Amidst this
jumble of dissentient authorities we can trace little of a systematic view,
except the general conviction that there was at the bottom of the myths a real
chronological sequence of persons, and real matter of fact, historical or
ultra-historical. Nevertheless, there are some few occasions on which Diodorus brings us back a step nearer to the point of view
of the old logographers. For, in reference to Heracles, he protests against the
scheme of cutting down the myths to the level of present reality, and contends
that a special standard of ultra-historical credibility ought to be
constituted, so as to include the myth in its native dimensions, and do fitting
honor to the grand, beneficent, and superhuman personality of Heracles and
other heroes or demi-gods. To apply to such persons the common measure of
humanity (he says), and to cavil at the glorious picture which grateful man has
drawn of them, is at once ungracious and irrational. All nice criticism into
the truth of the legendary narratives is out of place : we show our reverence
to the god by acquiescing in the incredibilities of
his history, and we must be content with the best guesses which we can make,
amidst the inextricable confusion and numberless discrepancies which they
present. Yet though Diodorus here exhibits a
preponderance of the religious sentiment over the purely historical point of
view, and thus reminds us of a period earlier than Thucydides—he in another place
inserts a series of stories which seem to be derived from Euemerus,
and in which Uranus, Kronus, and Zeus appear reduced
to the character of human kings celebrated for their exploits and benefactions.
Many of the authors, whom Diodorus copies, have so entangled
together Grecian, Asiatic, Egyptian, and Libyan fables, that it becomes
impossible to ascertain how much of this heterogeneous mass can be considered
as at all connected with the genuine Hellenic mind.
Pausanias is far more strictly
Hellenic in his view of the Grecian myths than Diodorus : his sincere piety makes him inclined to faith generally with regard to the
mythical narratives, but subject nevertheless to the frequent necessity of
historicizing or allegorizing them. His belief in the general reality of the
mythical history and chronology is complete, in spite of the many discrepancies
which he finds in it, and which he is unable to reconcile.
Another author who seems to have
conceived clearly, and applied consistently, the semi-historical theory of the
Grecian myths, is Palaephatus, of whose work what
appears to be a short abstract has been preserved. In the short preface of this
treatise concerning Incredible Tales,
he remarks, that some men, from want of instruction, believe all the current
narratives; while others, more searching and cautious, disbelieve them
altogether. Each of these extremes he is anxious to avoid. On the one hand, he
thinks that no narrative could ever have acquired credence unless it had been
founded in truth; on the other, it is impossible for him to accept so much of
the existing narratives as conflicts with the analogies of present natural
phenomena. If such things ever had been, they would still continue to be — but
they never have so occurred; and the extra-analogical features of the stories
are to be ascribed to the license of the poets. Palaephatus wishes to adopt a middle course, neither accepting all nor rejecting all :
accordingly, he had taken great pains to separate the true from the false in
many of the narratives; he had visited the localities wherein they had taken
place, and made careful inquiries from old men and others. The results of his
researches are presented in a new version of fifty legends, among the most
celebrated and the most fabulous, comprising the Centaurs, Pasiphae, Aktaeon, Cadmus and the Sparti,
the Sphinx, Cycnus, Daedalus, the Trojan horse,
Eolus, Scylla, Geryon, Bellorophon,
etc.
It must be confessed that Palaephatus has performed his promise of transforming the “incredibilia” into narratives in themselves plausible and
unobjectionable, and that in doing so he always follows some thread of analogy,
real or verbal. The Centaurs (he tells us) were a body of young men from the
village of Nephele in Thessaly, who first trained and
mounted horses for the purpose of repelling a herd of bulls belonging to Ixion king of the Lapithae, which
had run wild and done great damage : they pursued these wild bulls on
horseback, and pierced them with their spears, thus acquiring both the name of Prickers and the
imputed attribute of joint body with the horse. Aktaeon was an Arcadian, who neglected the cultivation of his land for the pleasures of
hunting, and was thus eaten up by the expense of his hounds. The dragon whom
Cadmus killed at Thebes, was in reality Drako, king
of Thebes; and the dragon's teeth which he was said to have sown, and from
whence sprung a crop of armed men, were in point of fact elephants’ teeth,
which Cadmus as a rich Phoenician had brought over with him : the sons of Drako sold these elephants' teeth and employed the proceeds
to levy troops against Cadmus. Dedalus, instead of
flying across the sea on wings, had escaped from Crete in a swift sailing-boat
under a violent storm : Kottus, Briareus,
and Gyges were not persons with one hundred hands,
but inhabitants of the village of Hekatoncheiria in
Upper Macedonia, who warred with the inhabitants of Mount Olympus against the
Titans : Scylla, whom Odysseus so narrowly escaped, was a fastsailing piratical vessel, as was also Pegasus, the alleged winged horse of Bellorophon.
By such ingenious conjectures, Palaephatus eliminates all the incredible circumstances,
and leaves to us a string of tales perfectly credible and commonplace, which we
should readily believe, provided a very moderate amount of testimony could be
produced in their favor. If his treatment not only disenchants the original
myths, but even effaces their generic and essential character, we ought to
remember that this is not more than what is done by Thucydides in his sketch of
the Trojan war. Palaephatus handles the myths
consistently, according to the semi-historical theory, and his results exhibit
the maximum which that theory can ever present. By aid of conjecture, we get
out of the impossible, and arrive at matters intrinsically plausible, but
totally uncertified; beyond this point we cannot penetrate, without the light
of extrinsic evidence, since there is no intrinsic mark to distinguish truth
from plausible fiction.
MYTHS AS HANDLED BY THE PHILOSOPHERS
It remains that we should notice the
manner in which the ancient myths were received and dealt with by the
philosophers. The earliest expression which we hear, on the part of philosophy,
is the severe censure bestowed upon them on ethical grounds by Xenophanes of Kolophon, and seemingly by some others of his
contemporaries. It was apparently in reply to such charges, which did not admit
of being directly rebutted, that Theagenes of Rhegium (about 520 BC) first started the idea of a double
meaning in the Homeric and Hesiodic narratives,— an interior sense, different
from that which the words in their obvious meaning bore, yet to a certain
extent analogous, and discoverable by sagacious divination. Upon this
principle, he allegorized especially the battle of the gods in the Iliad. In
the succeeding century Anaxagoras and Metrodorus carried out the allegorical explanation more comprehensively and
systematically; the former representing the mythical personages as mere mental
conceptions, invested with name and gender, and illustrative of ethical
precepts, — the latter connecting them with physical principles and phenomena. Metrodorus resolved not only the persons of Zeus, Here, and
Athene, but also those of Agamemnon, Achilles, and Hector, into various
elemental combinations and physical agencies, and treated the adventures
ascribed to them as natural facts concealed under the veil of allegory.
Empedocles, Prodikus, Antisthenes, Parmenides, Heracleides of Pontus, and in a later age, Chrysippus, and the Stoic philosophers generally, followed
more or less the same principle of treating the popular gods as allegorical
personages; while the expositors of Homer (such as Stesimbrotus, Glaukon, and others, even down to the Alexandrine
age), though none of them proceeded to the same extreme length as Metrodorus, employed allegory amongst other media of
explanation for the purpose of solving difficulties, or eluding reproaches
against the poet.
In the days of Plato and Xenophon,
this allegorizing interpretation was one of the received methods of softening
down the obnoxious myths —though Plato himself treated it as an insufficient defense,
seeing that the bulk of youthful hearers could not see through the allegory,
but embraced the story literally as it was set forth. Pausanias tells us, that
when he first began to write his work, he treated many of the Greek legends as
silly and undeserving of serious attention; but as he proceeded, he gradually
arrived at the full conviction, that the ancient sages had designedly spoken in
enigmatical language, and that there was valuable truth wrapped up in their
narratives : it was the duty of a pious man, therefore, to study and interpret,
but not to reject stories current and accredited respecting the gods. And
others,—arguing from the analogy of the religious mysteries, which could not be
divulged without impiety to any except such as had been specially admitted and
initiated,—maintained that it would be a profanation to reveal directly to the
vulgar, the genuine scheme of nature and the divine administration : the
ancient poets and philosophers had taken the only proper course, of talking to
the many in types and parables, and reserving the naked truth for privileged
and qualified intelligences. The allegorical mode of explaining the ancient
fables became more and more popular in the third and fourth centuries after the
Christian era, especially among the new Platonic philosophers; being both
congenial to their Orientalized turn of thought, and useful as a shield against
the attacks of the Christians.
It was from the same strong
necessity, of accommodating the old myths to a new standard both of belief and
of appreciation, that both the historical and the allegorical schemes of
transforming them arose; the literal narrative being decomposed for the purpose
of arriving at a base either of particular matter of fact, or of general
physical or moral truth. Instructed men were commonly disposed to historicize
only the heroic legends, and to allegorize more or less of the divine legends :
the attempt of Euemerus to historicize the latter was
for the most part denounced as irreligious, while that of Metrodorus to allegorize the former met with no success. In allegorizing, moreover, even
the divine legends, it was usual to apply the scheme of allegory only to the
inferior gods, though some of the great Stoic philosophers carried it farther,
and allegorized all the separate personal gods, leaving only an all-pervading
cosmic Mind, essential as a coefficient along with Matter, yet not separable
from Matter. But many pious pagans seem to have perceived that allegory pushed
to this extent was fatal to all living religious faith, inasmuch as it divested
the gods of their character of Persons, sympathizing with mankind and
modifiable in their dispositions according to the conduct and prayers of the
believer: and hence they permitted themselves to employ allegorical
interpretation only to some of the obnoxious legends connected with the
superior gods, leaving the personality of the latter unimpeached.
One novelty, however, introduced
seemingly by the philosopher Empedocles and afterwards expanded by others,
deserves notice, inasmuch as it modified considerably the old religious creed
by drawing a pointed contrast between gods and daemons, — a distinction hardly
at all manifested in Homer, but recognized in the Works and Days of Hesiod.
Empedocles’ widened the gap between the two, and founded upon it important
consequences. The gods were good, immortal, and powerful agents, having
freewill and intelligence, but without appetite, passion, or infirmity : the
daemons were of a mired nature between gods and men, ministers and interpreters
from the former to the latter, but invested also with an agency and
dispositions of their own. They were very long-lived, but not immortal, and
subject to the passions and propensities of men, so that there were among them
beneficent and maleficent demons with every shade of intermediate difference.
CHARACTER OF THE DEMONS
It had been the mistake (according
to these philosophers) of the old myths to ascribe to the gods proceedings
really belonging to the Demons, who were always the immediate communicants with
mortal nature, inspiring prophetic power to the priestesses of the oracles,
sending dreams and omens, and perpetually interfering either for good or for
evil. The wicked and violent demons, having committed many enormities, had thus
sometimes incurred punishment from the gods : besides which, their bad
dispositions had imposed upon men the necessity of appeasing them by religious
ceremonies of a kind acceptable to such beings: hence, the human sacrifices,
the violent, cruel, and obscene exhibitions, the wailings and fastings, the tearing and eating of raw flesh, which it had
become customary to practice on various consecrated occasions, and especially
in the Dionysian solemnities. Moreover, the discreditable actions imputed to
the gods,—the terrific combats, the Typhonic and
Titanic convulsions, the rapes, abductions, flight, servitude, and concealment,—all
these were really the doings and sufferings of bad demons, placed far below the
sovereign agency—equable, undisturbed, and unpolluted—of the immortal gods. The
action of such demons upon mankind was fitful and intermittent : they sometimes
perished or changed their local abode, so that oracles which had once been
inspired became after a time forsaken and disfranchised.
This distinction between gods and
demons appeared to save in a great degree both the truth of the old legends and
the dignity of the gods : it obviated the necessity of pronouncing either that
the gods were unworthy, or the legends untrue. Yet although devised for the
purpose of satisfying a more scrupulous religious sensibility, it was found
inconvenient afterwards, when assailants arose against paganism generally. For
while it abandoned as indefensible a large portion of what had once been
genuine faith, it still retained the same word demons with an entirely altered
signification. The Christian writers in their controversies found ample warrant
among the earlier pagan authors for treating all the gods as demons — and not
less ample warrant among the later pagans for denouncing the demons generally
as evil beings.
Such were the different modes in
which the ancient myths were treated, during the literary life of Greece, by
the four classes above named—poets, logographers, historians, and philosophers.
Literal acceptance, and unconscious, uninquiring faith, such as they had obtained from the
original auditors to whom they were addressed, they now found only among the
multitude—alike retentive of traditional feelings and fearful of criticizing
the proceedings of the gods. But with instructed men they became rather
subjects of respectful and curious analysis—all agreeing that the Word as
tendered to them was inadmissible, yet all equally convinced that it contained
important meaning, though hidden yet not undiscoverable. A very large
proportion of the force of Grecian intellect was engaged in searching after
this unknown base, by guesses, in which sometimes the principle of
semi-historical interpretation was assumed, sometimes that of allegorical,
without any collateral evidence in either case, and without possibility of
verification. Out of the one assumption grew a string of allegorized phenomenal
truths, out of the other a long series of seeming historical events and
chronological persons, —both elicited from the transformed myths and from
nothing else
The utmost which we accomplish by
means of the semi-historical theory, even in its most successful applications,
is, that after leaving out from the mythical narrative all that is miraculous
or high-colored or extravagant, we arrive at a series of credible incidents—incidents
which may, perhaps, have really occurred, and against which no intrinsic
presumption can be raised. This is exactly the character of a well-written
modern novel (as, for example, several among the compositions of Defoe), the
whole story of which is such as may well have occurred in real life: it is
plausible fiction, and nothing beyond. To raise plausible fiction up to the
superior dignity of truth, some positive testimony or positive ground of
inference must be shown; even the highest measure of intrinsic probability is
not alone sufficient. A man who tells us that, on the day of the battle of
Plataea, rain fell on the spot of ground where the city of New York now stands,
will neither deserve nor obtain credit, because he can have had no means of
positive knowledge; though the statement is not in the slightest degree
improbable. On the other hand, statements in themselves very improbable may
well deserve belief, provided they be supported by sufficient positive
evidence; thus the canal dug by order of Xerxes across the promontory of Mount
Athos, and the sailing of the Persian fleet through it, is a fact which I
believe, because it is well-attested—notwithstanding its remarkable
improbability, which so far misled Juvenal as to induce him to single out the
narrative as a glaring example of Grecian mendacity. Again, many critics have
observed that the general tale of the Trojan war (apart from the superhuman
agencies) is not more improbable than that of the Crusades, which everyone
admits to be an historical fact. But (even if we grant this position, which is
only true to a small extent), it is not sufficient to show an analogy between
the two cases in respect to negative presumptions alone; the analogy ought to
be shown to hold between them in respect to positive certificate also. The
Crusades are a curious phenomenon in history, but we accept them, nevertheless,
as an unquestionable fact, because the antecedent improbability is surmounted
by adequate contemporary testimony. When the like testimony, both in amount and
kind, is produced to establish the historical reality of a Trojan war, we shall
not hesitate to deal with the two events on the same footing.
TRUTH UNDISTINGUISHABLE FROM FICTION
In applying the semi-historical
theory to Grecian mythical narrative, it has been often forgotten that a
certain strength of testimony, or positive ground of belief, must first be
tendered, before we can be called upon to discuss the antecedent probability or
improbability of the incidents alleged. The belief of the Greeks themselves,
without the smallest aid of special or contemporary witnesses, has been tacitly
assumed as sufficient to support the case, provided only sufficient deduction
be made from the mythical narratives to remove all antecedent improbabilities.
It has been taken for granted that the faith of the people must have rested
originally upon some particular historical event, involving the identical
persons, things, and places which the original myths exhibit, or at least the
most prominent among them. But when we examine the pyschagogic influences predominant in the society among whom this belief originally grew
up, we shall see that their belief is of little or no evidentiary value, and
that the growth and diffusion of it may be satisfactorily explained without
supposing any special basis of matters of fact. The popular faith, so far as it
counts for anything, testifies in favor of the entire and literal myths, which
are now universally rejected as incredible. We have thus the very minimum of
positive proof, and the maximum of negative presumption : we may diminish the
latter by conjectural omissions and interpolations, but we cannot by any
artifice increase the former: the narrative ceases to be incredible, but it
still remains uncertified,—a mere commonplace possibility. Nor is fiction
always, or essentially, extravagant and incredible. It is often not only
plausible and coherent, but even more like truth (if a paradoxical phrase may
be allowed) than truth itself. Nor can we, in the absence of any extrinsic
test, reckon upon any intrinsic mark to discriminate the one from the other.
In the semi-historical theory
respecting Grecian mythical narrative, the critic unconsciously transports into
the Homeric age those habits of classification and distinction, and that
standard of acceptance or rejection, which he finds current in his own. Amongst
us, the distinction between historical fact and fiction is highly valued as
well as familiarly understood : we have a long history of the past, deduced
from a study of contemporary evidences; and we have a body of fictitious
literature, stamped with its own mark and interesting in its own way. Speaking
generally, no man could now hope to succeed permanently in transferring any
striking incident from the latter category into the former, nor could any man
deliberately attempt it without incurring well-merited obloquy. But this historical sense, now so deeply rooted
in the modern mind that we find a difficulty in conceiving any people to be
without it, is the fruit of records and inquiries, first applied to the
present, and then preserved and studied by subsequent generations; while in a
society which has not yet formed the habit of recording its present, the real
facts of the past can never be known; the difference between attested matter of
fact and plausible fiction—between truth and that which is like truth—can
neither be discerned nor sought for. Yet it is precisely upon the supposition
that this distinction is present to men's habitual thoughts, that the
semi-historical theory of the myths is grounded.
It is perfectly true, as has often
been stated, that the Grecian epic contains what are called traditions
respecting the past — the larger portion of it, indeed, consists of nothing
else. But what are these traditions? They are the matter of those songs and
stories which have acquired hold on the public mind; they are the creations of
the poets and storytellers themselves, each of whom finds some preexisting, and
adds others of his own, new and previously untold, under the impulse and
authority of the Inspiring Muse. Homer doubtless found many songs and stories current
with respect to the siege of Troy; he received and transmitted some of these
traditions, recast and transformed others, and enlarged the whole mass by new
creations of his own. To the subsequent poets, such as Arktinus and Lesches, these Homeric creations formed portions
of preexisting tradition, with which they dealt in the same manner; so that the
whole mass of traditions constituting the tale of Troy became larger and larger
with each successive contributor. To assume a generic difference between the
older and the newer strata of tradition—to treat the former as morsels of
history, and the latter as appendages of fiction — is an hypothesis gratuitous
at the least, not to say inadmissible. For the further we travel back into the
past, the more do we recede from the clear day of positive history, and the
deeper do we plunge into the unsteady twilight and gorgeous clouds of fancy and
feeling. It was one of the agreeable dreams of the Grecian epic, that the man
who travelled far enough northward beyond the Rhipaean mountains, would in time reach the delicious country and genial climate of the
virtuous Hyperboreans—the votaries and favorites of
Apollo, who dwelt in the extreme north beyond the chilling blasts of Boreas.
Now the hope that we may, by carrying our researches up the stream of time,
exhaust the limits of fiction, and land ultimately upon some points of solid
truth, appears to me no less illusory than leis northward journey in quest of
the Hyperborean Elysium.
The general disposition to adopt the
semi-historical theory as to the genesis of Grecian myths, arises in part from
reluctance in critics to impute to the mythopoeic ages extreme credulity or
fraud; together with the usual presumption, that where much is believed some
portion of it must be true. There would be some weight in these grounds of
reasoning, if the ages under discussion had been supplied with records and
accustomed to critical inquiry. But amongst a people unprovided with the former and strangers to the latter, credulity is naturally at its
maximum, as well in the narrator himself as in his hearers: the idea of
deliberate fraud is moreover inapplicable, for if the hearers are disposed to
accept what is related to them as a revelation from the Muse, the oestrus of
composition is quite sufficient to impart a similar persuasion to the poet
whose mind is penetrated with it. The belief of that day can hardly be said to
stand apart by itself as an act of reason. It becomes confounded with vivacious
imagination and earnest emotion; and in every case where these mental
excitabilities are powerfully acted upon, faith ensues unconsciously and as a
matter of course. How active and prominent such tendencies were among the early
Greeks, the extraordinary beauty and originality of their epic poetry may teach
us.
It is, besides, a presumption far
too largely and indiscriminately applied, even in our own advanced age, that
where much is believed, something must necessarily be true — that accredited
fiction is always traceable to some basis of historical truth. The influence of
imagination and feeling is not confined simply to the process of retouching,
transforming, or magnifying narratives originally founded on fact; it will
often create new narratives of its own, without any such preliminary basis.
Where there is any general body of sentiment pervading men living in society,
whether it be religious or political—love, admiration, or antipathy — all
incidents tending to illustrate that sentiment are eagerly welcomed, rapidly
circulated and (as a general rule) easily accredited. If real incidents are not
at hand, impressive fictions will be provided to satisfy the demand. The
perfect harmony of such fictions with the prevalent feeling stands in the place
of certifying testimony, and causes men to hear them not merely with credence,
but even with delight: to call them in question and require proof, is a task
which cannot be undertaken without incurring obloquy. Of such tendencies in the
human mind, abundant evidence is furnished by the innumerable religious legends
which have acquired currency in various parts of the world, and of which no
country was more fertile than Greece —legends which derived their origin, not
from special facts misreported and exaggerated, but from pious feelings
pervading the society, and translated into narrative by forward and imaginative
minds — legends, in which not merely the incidents, but often even the
personages are unreal, yet in which the generating sentiment is conspicuously
discernible, providing its own matter as well as its own form. Other sentiments
also, as well as the religious, provided they be fervent and widely diffused,
will find expression in current narrative, and become portions of the general
public belief — every celebrated and notorious character is the source of a
thousand fictions exemplifying his peculiarities. And if it be true, as I think
present observation may show us, that such creative agencies are even now
visible and effective, when the materials of genuine history are copious and
critically studied—much more are we warranted in concluding that, in ages
destitute of records, strangers to historical testimony, and full of belief in
divine inspiration both as to the future and as to the past, narratives purely
fictitious will acquire ready and uninquiring credence, provided only they be plausible and in harmony with the
preconceptions of the auditors.
The allegorical interpretation of
the myths has been by several learned investigators, especially by Creuzer, connected with the hypothesis of an ancient and
highly instructed body of priests, having their origin either in Egypt or in
the East, and communicating to the rude and barbarous Greeks religious,
physical, and historical knowledge under the veil of symbols. At a time (we are
told) when language was yet in its infancy, visible symbols were the most vivid
means of acting upon the minds of ignorant hearers: the next step was to pass
to symbolical language and expressions—for a plain and literal exposition, even
if understood at all, would at least have been listened to with indifference,
as not corresponding with any mental demand. In such allegorizing way, then,
the early priests set forth their doctrines respecting God, nature, and
humanity — a refined monotheism and a theological philosophy—and to this
purpose the earliest myths were turned. But another class of myths, more
popular and more captivating, grew up under the hands of the poets—myths purely
epical, and descriptive of real or supposed past events. The allegorical myths,
being taken up by the poets, insensibly became confounded in the same category
with the purely narrative myths—the matter symbolized was no longer thought of,
while the symbolizing words came to be construed in their own literal
meaning—and the basis of the early allegory, thus lost among the general
public, was only preserved as a secret among various religious fraternities,
composed of members allied together by initiation in certain mystical
ceremonies, and administered by hereditary families of presiding priests. In
the Orphic and Bacchic sects, in the Eleusinian and Samothracian mysteries, was thus treasured up the secret
doctrine of the old theological and philosophical myths, which had once
constituted the primitive legendary stock of Greece, in the hands of the
original priesthood and in ages anterior to Homer. Persons who had gone through
the preliminary ceremonies of initiation, were permitted at length to hear,
though under strict obligation of secrecy, till ancient religious and cosmogonic doctrine, revealing the destination of man and
the certainty of posthumous rewards and punishments — all disengaged from the
corruptions of poets, as well as from the symbols and allegories under which
they still remained buried in the eyes of the vulgar. The mysteries of Greece
were thus traced up to the earliest ages, and represented as the only faithful
depository channels of that purer theology and physics which had originally
been communicated, though under the unavoidable inconvenience of a symbolical
expression, by an enlightened priesthood coming from abroad to the then rude
barbarians of the country.
THEORIES OF LEARNED MEN
But this theory, though advocated by
several learned men, has been shown to be unsupported and erroneous. It implies
a mistaken view both of the antiquity and the purport of the mysteries, which
cannot be safely carried up even to the age of Hesiod, and which, though
imposing and venerable as religious ceremonies, included no recondite or
esoteric teaching.
The doctrine, supposed to have been
originally symbolized and subsequently overclouded, in the Greek myths, was in
reality first intruded into them by the unconscious fancies of later
interpreters. It was one of the various roads which instructed men took to
escape from the literal admission of the ancient myths, and to arrive at some
new form of belief, more consonant with their ideas of what the attributes and
character of the gods ought to be. It was one of the trays of constituting, by
help of the mysteries, a philosophical religion apart from the general public,
and of connecting that distinction with the earliest periods of Grecian
society. Such a distinction was both avowed and justified among the superior
men of the later pagan world. Varro and Scaevola distributed theology into three distinct departments,—the mythical or fabulous,
the civil, and the physical. The first had its place in the theatre, and was
left without any interference to the poets; the second belonged to the city of
political community as such,—it comprised the regulation of all the public
worship and religious rites, and was consigned altogether to the direction of
the magistrate; the third was the privilege of philosophers, but was reserved
altogether for private discussion in the schools, apart from the general public.
As a member of the city, the philosopher sympathized with the audience in the
theatre, and took a devout share in the established ceremonies, nor was he
justified in trying what he heard in the one or saw in the other by his own
ethical standard. But in the private assemblies of instructed or inquisitive
men, he enjoyed the fullest liberty of canvassing every received tenet, and of
broaching his own theories unreservedly, respecting the existence and nature of
the gods. By these discussions, the activity of the philosophical mind was
maintained and truth elicited; but it was such truth as the body of the people
ought not to hear, lest their faith in their own established religious worship
should be overthrown. In thus distinguishing the civil theology from the
fabulous, Varro was enabled to cast upon the poets all the blame of the
objectionable points in the popular theology, and to avoid the necessity of
pronouncing censure on the magistrates, who (he contended) had made as good a
compromise with the settled prejudices of the public as the case permitted.
The same conflicting sentiments
which led the philosophers to decompose the divine myths into allegory,
impelled the historians to melt down the heroic myths into something like
continuous political history, with a long series of chronology calculated upon
the heroic pedigrees. The one process as well as the other was interpretative
guesswork, proceeding upon unauthorized assumptions, and without any verifying
test or evidence : while it frittered away the characteristic beauty of the
myth into something essentially anti-mythical, it sought to arrive both at
history and philosophy by impracticable roads. That the superior men of
antiquity should have striven hard to save the dignity of legends which constituted
the charm of their literature as well as the substance of the popular religion,
we cannot be at all surprised; but it is gratifying to find Plato discussing
the subject in a more philosophical spirit. The Platonic Socrates, being asked
whether he believed the current Attic fable respecting the abduction of Oreithyia (daughter of Erechtheus)
by Boreas, replies, in substance,—“It would not be strange if I disbelieved it,
as the clever men do; I might then show my cleverness by saying that a gust of
Boreas blew her down from the rocks above while she was at play, and that,
having been killed in this manner, she was reported to have been carried off by
Boreas. Such speculations are amusing enough, but they belong to men ingenious
and busy-minded overmuch, and not greatly to be envied, if it be only for this
reason, that, after having set right one fable, they are under the necessity of
applying the same process to a host of others—Hippo-centaurs, Chimeras,
Gorgons, Pegasus, and numberless other monsters and incredibilities.
A man, who, disbelieving these stories, shall try to find a probable basis for
each of them, will display an ill-placed acuteness and take upon himself an
endless burden, for which I at least have no leisure : accordingly, I forego
such researches, and believe in the current version of the stories”.
These remarks of Plato are valuable,
not simply because they point out the uselessness of digging for a supposed
basis of truth in the myths, but because they at the same time suggest the true
reason for mistrusting all such tentatives. The myths
form a class apart, abundant as well as peculiar : to remove any individual
myth from its own class into that of history or philosophy, by simple
conjecture, and without any collateral evidence, is of no advantage, unless you
can perform a similar process on the remainder. If the process be trustworthy,
it ought to be applied to all; and e converso, if it be not applicable to all, it is not
trustworthy as applied to any one specially; always assuming no special
evidence to be accessible. To detach any individual myth from the class to
which it belongs, is to present it in an erroneous point of view; we have no
choice except to admit them as they stand, by putting ourselves approximately
into the frame of mind of those for whom they were destined and to whom they
appeared worthy of credit.
OPINION OF PLATO
If Plato thus discountenances all
attempts to transform the myths by interpretation into history or philosophy,
indirectly recognizing the generic difference between them—we find
substantially the same view pervading the elaborate precepts in his treatise on
the Republic. He there regards the myths, not as embodying either
matter-of-fact or philosophical principle, but as portions of religious and
patriotic faith, and instruments of ethical tuition. Instead of allowing the
poets to frame them according to the impulses of their own genius, and with a
view to immediate popularity, he directs the legislator to provide types of his
own for the characters of the gods and heroes, and to suppress all such divine
and heroic legends as are not in harmony with these pre-established canons. In
the Platonic system, the myths are not to be matters of history, nor yet of
spontaneous or casual fiction, but of prescribed faith : he supposes that the
people will believe, as a thing of course, what the poets circulate, and he
therefore directs that the latter shall circulate nothing which does not tend
to ennoble and improve the feelings. He conceives the myths as stories composed
to illustrate the general sentiments of the poets and the community, respecting
the character and attributes of the gods and heroes, or respecting the social
relations, and ethical duties as well as motives of mankind : hence the obligation
upon the legislator to prescribe beforehand the types of character which shall
be illustrated, and to restrain the poets from following out any opposing
fancies. “Let us neither believe ourselves (he exclaims), nor permit any one to
circulate, that Theseus son of Poseidon and Peirithous son of Zeus, or any other hero or son of a god, could ever have brought
themselves to commit abductions or other enormities such as are now falsely
ascribed to them. We must compel the poets to say, either that such persons
were not the sons of gods, or that they were not the perpetrators of such
misdeeds”.
Most of the myths which the youth
hear and repeat (according to Plato) are false, but some of them are true: the
great and prominent myths which appear in Homer and Hesiod are no less fictions
than the rest. But fiction constitutes one of the indispensable instruments of
mental training as well as truth; only the legislator must take care that the
fiction so employed shall be beneficent and not mischievous. As the mischievous
fictions (he says) take their rise from wrong preconceptions respecting the
character of the gods and heroes, so the way to correct them is to enforce, by
authorized compositions, the adoption of a more correct standard.
The comments which Plato has
delivered with so much force in his Republic, and the enactments which he
deduce from them, are in the main an expansion of that sentiment of
condemnation, which he shared with so many other philosophers, towards a large
portion of the Homeric and Hesiodic stories. But the manner in which he has set
forth this opinion, unfolds to us more clearly the real character of the
mythical narratives. They are creations of the productive minds in the
community, deduced from the supposed attributes of the gods and heroes : so
Plato views them, and in such character he proposes to amend them. The
legislator would cause to be prepared a better and truer picture of the
foretime, because he would start from truer (that is to say, more creditable)
conceptions of the gods and heroes. For Plato rejects the myths respecting Zeus
and Here, or Theseus and Peirithous, not from any
want of evidence, but because they are unworthy of gods and heroes : he
proposes to call forth new myths, which, though he admits them at the outset to
be fiction, he knows will soon be received as true, and supply more valuable
lessons of conduct.
We may consider, then, that Plato
disapproves of the attempt to identify the old myths either with exaggerated
history or with disguised philosophy. He shares in the current faith, without
any suspicion or criticism, as to Orpheus, Palamedes,
Daedalus, Amphion, Theseus, Achilles, Cheiron, and other mythical personages; but what chiefly
fills his mind is, the inherited sentiment of deep reverence for these superhuman
characters and for the age to which they belonged, — a sentiment sufficiently
strong to render him not only an unbeliever in such legends as conflict with
it, but also a deliberate creator of new legends for the purpose of expanding
and gratifying it. The more we examine this sentiment, both in the mind of
Plato as well as in that of the Greeks generally, the more shall we be
convinced that it formed essentially and inseparably a portion of Hellenic
religious faith. The myth both presupposes, and springs out of, a settled
basis, and a strong expansive force of religious, social, and patriotic
feeling, operating upon a past which is little better than a blank as to
positive knowledge. It resembles history, in so far as its form is narrative;
it resembles philosophy, in so far as it is occasionally illustrative; but in
its essence and substance, in the mental tendencies by which it is created as
well as in those by which it is judged and upheld, it is a popularized
expression of the divine and heroic faith of the people.
Grecian antiquity cannot be at all
understood except in connection with Grecian religion. It begins with gods and
it ends with historical men, the former being recognized not simply as gods,
but as primitive ancestors, and connected with the latter by a long mythical
genealogy, partly heroic and partly human. Now the whole value of such
genealogies arises from their being taken entire; the god or hero at the top is
in point of fact the most important member of the whole for the length and
continuity of the series arises from anxiety on the part of historical men to
join themselves by a thread of descent with the being whom they worshipped in
their gentile sacrifices. Without the ancestral god, the whole pedigree would
have become not only acephalous, but worthless and
uninteresting. The pride of the Heracleides,
Asclepiads, Neleids, Daedalids,
etc. was attached to the primitive eponymous hero and to the god from whom they
sprung, not to the line of names, generally long and barren, through which the
divine or heroic dignity gradually dwindled down into common manhood. Indeed,
the length of the genealogy (as I have before remarked) was an evidence of the
humility of the historical man, which led him to place himself at a respectful
distance from the gods or heroes; for Hecataeus of
Miletus, who ranked himself as the fifteenth descendant of a god, might perhaps
have accounted it an overweening impiety in any living man to claim a god for
his immediate father.
MYTHICAL GENEALOGIES.
The whole chronology of Greece,
anterior to 776 BC, consists of calculations founded upon these mythical
genealogies, especially upon that of the Spartan kings and their descent from
Heracles, — thirty years being commonly taken as the equivalent of a generation,
or about three generations to a century. This process of computation was
altogether illusory, as applying historical and chronological conditions to a
case on which they had no bearing. Though the domain of history was seemingly
enlarged, the religious element was tacitly set aside: when the heroes and gods
were chronologized, they became insensibly
approximated to the limits of humanity, and the process indirectly gave
encouragement to the theory of Euemerus. Personages
originally legendary and poetical were erected into definite landmarks for
measuring the duration of the foretime, thus gaining in respect to historical
distinctness, but not without loss on the score of religious association. Both Euemerus and the subsequent Christian writers, who denied
the original and inherent divinity of the pagan gods, had a great advantage in
carrying their chronological researches strictly and consistently upwards —for
all chronology fails as soon as we suppose a race superior to common humanity.
Moreover, it is to be remarked that
the pedigree of the Spartan kings, which Apollodorus and Eratosthenes selected
as the basis of their estimate of time, is nowise superior in credibility and
trustworthiness to the thousand other gentile and family pedigrees with which Greece
abounded; it is rather indeed to be numbered among the most incredible of all,
seeing that Heracles as a progenitor is placed at the head of perhaps more
pedigrees than any other Grecian god or hero. The descent of the Spartan king
Leonidas from Heracles rests upon no better evidence than that of Aristotle or
Hippocrates from Asclepius,—of Evagoras or Thucydides
from Eakus,—of Socrates from Dadalus,
— of the Spartan heraldic family from Talthybius,—of
the prophetic Iamid family in Elis from Iamus,—of the root-gatherers in Pelion from Cheiron,—and of Hekataeus and his gens from some god in the sixteenth ascending line of the series.
There is little exaggeration in saying, indeed, that no permanent combination
of men in Greece, religious, social, or professional, was without a similar
pedigree; all arising out of the same exigencies of the feelings and
imagination, to personify as well as to sanctify the bond of union among the
members. Every one of these gentes began with a religious and ended with an historical
person. At some point or other in the upward series, entities of history were
exchanged for entities of religion; but where that point is to be found we are
unable to say, nor had the wisest of the ancient Greeks any means of
determining. Thus much, however, we know, that the series taken as a whole,
though dear and precious to the believing Greek, possesses no value as
chronological evidence to the historian.
When Hecataeus visited Thebes in Egypt, he mentioned to the Egyptian priests, doubtless with a
feeling of satisfaction and pride, the imposing pedigree of the gens to which he belonged,—with fifteen
ancestors in ascending line, and a god as the initial progenitor. But he found
himself immeasurably overdone by the priests “who genealogized against him”. They showed to him three hundred and forty-one wooden colossal
statues, representing the succession of chief priests in the temple in
uninterrupted series from father to son, through a space of 11,300 years. Prior
to the commencement of this long period (they said), the gods dwelling along
with men, had exercised sway in Egypt; but they repudiated altogether the idea
of men begotten by gods or of heroes.
Both these counter-genealogies, are,
in respect to trustworthiness and evidence, on the same footing. Each
represents partly the religious faith, partly the retrospective imagination, of
the persons from whom it emanated; in each, the lower members of the series (to
what extent we cannot tell) are real, the upper members fabulous; but in each
also the series derived all its interest and all its imposing effect from being
conceived unbroken and entire. Herodotus is much perplexed by the capital
discrepancy between the Grecian and Egyptian chronologies, and vainly employs
his ingenuity in reconciling them. There is no standard of objective evidence
by which either the one or the other of them can be tried : each has its own
subjective value, in conjunction with the faith and feelings of Egyptians and
Greeks, and each presupposes in the believer certain mental prepossessions
which are not to be found beyond its own local limits. Nor is the greater or
less extent of duration at all important, when we once pass the limits of
evidence and verifiable reality. One century of recorded time, adequately
studded with authentic and orderly events, presents a greater mass and a
greater difficulty of transition to the imagination than a hundred centuries of
barren genealogy. Herodotus, in discussing the age of Homer and Hesiod, treats
an anterior point of 400 years as if it were only yesterday; the reign of Henry
VI is separated from us by an equal interval, and the reader will not require
to be reminded how long that interval now appears.
The mythical age was peopled with a
mingled aggregate of gods, heroes, and men, so confounded together that it was
often impossible to distinguish to which class any individual name belonged. In
regard to the Thracian god Zalmoxis, the Hellespontic Greeks interpreted his character and
attributes according to the scheme of Euemerism. They
affirmed that be had been a man, the slave of the philosopher Pythagoras at
Samos, and that he had by abilities and artifice established a religious
ascendency over the minds of the Thracians, and obtained from them divine
honors. Herodotus cannot bring himself to believe this story, but he frankly
avows his inability to determine whether Zalmoxis was
a god or a man, nor can he extricate himself from a similar embarrassment in
respect to Dionysus and Pan. Amidst the confusion of the Homeric fight, the
goddess Athens confers upon Diomedes the miraculous favor of dispelling the
mist from his eyes, so as to enable him to discriminate gods from men; and
nothing less than a similar miracle could enable a critical reader of the
mythical narratives to draw an ascertained boundary-line between the two. But
the original hearers of the myths felt neither surprise nor displeasure from
this confusion of the divine with the human individual. They looked at the past
with a film of faith over their eyes —neither knowing the value, nor desiring
the attainment, of an unclouded vision. The intimate companionship, and the
occasional mistake of identity between gods and men, were in full harmony with
their reverential restrospect. And we, accordingly,
see the poet Ovid in his Fasti, when he undertakes
the task of unfolding the legendary antiquities of early Rome, reacquiring, by
the inspiration of Juno, the power of seeing gods and men in immediate vicinity
and conjunct action, such as it existed before the development of the critical
and historical sense.
GENERAL RECAPITULATION.
To resume, in brief, what has been
laid down in this and the preceding chapters respecting the Grecian myths :
1. They are a special product of the
imagination and feelings, radically distinct both from history and philosophy :
they cannot be broken down and decomposed into the one, nor allegorized into
the other. There are indeed some particular and even assignable myths, which
raise intrinsic presumption of an allegorizing tendency; and there are
doubtless some others, though not specially assignable, which contain portions
of matter of fact, or names of real persons, embodied in them. But such matter
of fact cannot be verified by any intrinsic mark, nor we are entitled to
presume its existence in any given case unless some collateral evidence can be
produced.
2. We are not warranted in applying
to the mythical world the rules either of historical credibility or
chronological sequence. Its personages are gods, heroes, and men, in constant
juxtaposition and reciprocal sympathy; men, too, of whom we know a large
proportion to be fictitious, and of whom we can never ascertain how many may
have been real. No series of such personages can serve as materials for
chronological calculation.
3. The myths were originally
produced in an age which had no records, no philosophy, no criticism, no canon
of belief, and scarcely any tincture either of astronomy or geography—but
which, on the other hand, was full of religious faith, distinguished for quick
and susceptible imagination, seeing personal agents where we look only for
objects and connecting laws;— an age, moreover, eager for new narrative,
accepting with the unconscious impressibility of children (the question of
truth or falsehood being never formally raised) all which ran in harmony with
its preexisting feelings, and penetrable by inspired prophets and poets in the
same proportion that it was indifferent to positive evidence. To such hearers
did the primitive poet or story-teller address himself: it was the glory of his
productive genius to provide suitable narrative expression for the faith and
emotions which he shared in common with them, and the rich stock of Grecian
myths attests how admirably he performed his task. As the gods and the heroes
formed the conspicuous object of national reverence, so the myths were partly
divine, partly heroic, partly both in one. The adventures of Achilles, Helen,
and Diomedes, of Edipus and Adrastus,
of Meleager and Althea, of Jason and the Argo, were
recounted by the same tongues, and accepted with the same unsuspecting
confidence, as those of Apollo and Artemis, of Ares and Aphrodite, of Poseidon
and Heracles.
4. The time however came, when this
plausibility ceased to be complete. The Grecian mind made an important advance,
socially, ethically, and intellectually. Philosophy and history were
constituted, prose writing and chronological records became familiar; a canon
of belief more or less critical came to be tacitly recognized. Moreover,
superior men profited more largely by the stimulus, and contracted habits of
judging different from the vulgar : the god Elenchus (to use a personification
of Menander) the giver and prover of truth, descended
into their minds. Into the new intellectual medium, thus altered in its
elements, and no longer uniform in its quality, the myths descended by
inheritance; but they were found, to a certain extent, out of harmony even with
the feelings of the people, and altogether dissonant with those of instructed
men. But the most superior Greek was still a Greek, and cherished the common
reverential sentiment towards the foretime of his country. Though he could
neither believe nor respect the myths as they stood, he was under an imperious
mental necessity to transform them into a state worthy of his belief and
respect. Whilst the literal myth still continued to float among the poets and
the people, critical men interpreted, altered, decomposed, and added, until
they found something which satisfied their minds as a supposed real basis. They
manufactured some dogmas of supposed original philosophy, and a long series of
fancied history and chronology, retaining the mythical names and generations
even when they were obliged to discard or recast the mythical events. The
interpreted myth was thus promoted into a reality, while the literal myth was
degraded into a fiction.
SUBSEQUENT AGE OF INTERPRETATION.
The habit of distinguishing the
interpreted from the literal myth has passed from the literary men of antiquity
to those of the modern world, who have for the most part construed the divine
myths as allegorized philosophy, and the heroic myths as exaggerated, adorned,
and over-colored history. The early ages of Greece have thus been peopled with
quasi-historical persons and quasi-historical events, all extracted from the
myths after making certain allowances for poetical ornament. But we must not
treat this extracted product as if it were the original substance; we cannot
properly understand it except by viewing it in connection with the literal
myths out of which it was obtained, in their primitive age and appropriate
medium, before the superior minds had yet outgrown the common faith in an
all-personified Nature, and learned to restrict the divine free-agency by the
supposition of invariable physical laws. It is in this point of view that the
myths are important for anyone who would correctly appreciate the general tone
of Grecian thought and feeling; for they were the universal mental stock of the
Hellenic world—common to men and women, rich and poor, instructed and ignorant;
they were in every one's memory and in every one's mouth,1 while science and
history were confined to comparatively few. We know from Thucydides how
erroneously and carelessly the Athenian public of his day retained the history
of Peisistratus, only one century past; but the adventures of the gods and
heroes, the numberless explanatory legends attached to visible objects and
periodical ceremonies, were the theme of general talk, and any man unacquainted
with them would have found himself partially excluded from the sympathy of his
neighbors. The theatrical representations, exhibited to the entire city
population, and listened to with enthusiastic interest, both presupposed and
perpetuated acquaintance with the great lines of heroic fable: indeed, in later
times even the pantomimic dancers embraced in their representations the whole
field of mythical incident, and their immense success proves at once how
popular and how well known such subjects were. The names and attributes of the
heroes were incessantly alluded to in the way of illustration, to point out a
consoling, admonitory, or repressive moral: the simple mention of any of them
sufficed to call up in every one's mind the principal events of his life, and
the poet or rhapsode could thus calculate on touching chords not less familiar
than susceptible.
A similar effect was produced by the
multiplied religious festivals and processions, as well as by the oracles and
prophecies which circulated in every city. The annual departure of the Theoric ship from Athens to the sacred island of Delos,
kept alive, in the minds of Athenians generally, the legend of Theseus and his
adventurous enterprise in Crete; and in like manner most of the other public
rites and ceremonies were of a commemorative character, deduced from some
mythical person or incident familiarly known to natives, and forming to
strangers a portion of the curiosities of the place. During the period of
Grecian subjection under the Romans, these curiosities, together with their
works of art and their legends, were especially clung to as a set-off against
present degradation. The Theban citizen who found himself restrained from the
liberty enjoyed by all other Greeks, of consulting Amphiaraus as a prophet, though the sanctuary and chapel of the hero stood in his own
city, could not be satisfied without a knowledge of the story which explained
the origin of such prohibition, and which conducted him back to the originally
hostile relations between Amphiaraus and Thebes. Nor
can we suppose among the citizens of Sicyon anything less than a perfect and
reverential conception of the legend of Thebes, when we read the account given
by Herodotus of the conduct of the despot Kleisthenes in regard to Adrastus and Melanippus.
The Troezenian youths and maidens, who universally,
when on the eve of marriage, consecrated an offering of their hair at the
Hellion of Hippolytus, maintained a lively recollection of the legend of that
unhappy recusant whom Aphrodite had so cruelly punished. Abundant relics
preserved in many Grecian cities and temples, served both as mementos and
attestations of other legendary events; and the tombs of the heroes counted
among the most powerful stimulants of mythical reminiscence. The scepter of Pelops and Agamemnon, still preserved in the days of
Pausanias at Chaeroneia in Boeotia, was the work of
the god Hephaestus. While many other alleged productions of the same divine
hand were preserved in different cities of Greece, this is the only one which
Pausanias himself believed to be genuine : it had been carried by Elektra,
daughter of Agamemnon to Phocis, and received divine honors from the citizens
of Chaeronea. The spears of Meriones and Odysseus
were treasured up at Engyium in Sicily, that of
Achilles at Phaselis; the sword of Memmon adorned the temple of Asklepius at Nicomedia; and Pausanias, with unsuspecting confidence, adduces the two
latter as proofs that the arms of the heroes were made of brass. The hide of
the Kalydonian boar was guarded and shown by the Tegeates as a precious possession; the shield of Euphorbus was in like manner suspended in the temple of Branchids near Miletus, as well as in the temple of Here in
Argos. Visible relics of Epeius and Philoktetes were not wanting, while Strabo raises his voice
with indignation against the numerous Palladia which were shown in different
cities, each pretending to be the genuine image from Troy. It would be
impossible to specify the number of chapels, sanctuaries, solemnities,
foundations of one sort or another, said to have been first commenced by heroic
or mythical personages,—by Heracles, Jason, Medea, Alkmaeon,
Diomedes, Odysseus, Danaus, and his daughters, etc.
Perhaps in some of these cases particular critics might raise objections, but
the great bulk of the people entertained a firm and undoubted belief in the
current legend.
If we analyze the intellectual
acquisitions of a common Grecian townsman, from the rude communities of Arcadia
or Phocis even up to the enlightened Athens, we shall find that, over and above
the rules of art or capacities requisite for his daily wants, it consisted
chiefly of the various myths connected with his gens, his city, his religious festivals, and the mysteries in which
he might have chosen to initiate himself, as well as with the works of art and
the more striking natural objects which he might see around him,—the whole set
off and decorated by some knowledge of the epic and dramatic poets. Such was
the intellectual and imaginative reach of an ordinary Greek, considered apart
from the instructed few : it was an aggregate of religion, of social and
patriotic retrospect, and of romantic fancy, blended into one indivisible
faith. And thus the subjective value of the myths, looking at them purely as
elements of Grecian thought and feeling, will appear indisputably great,
however little there may be of objective reality, either historical or
philosophical, discoverable under them.
Nor must we omit the incalculable
importance of the myths as stimulants to the imagination of the Grecian artist
in sculpture, in painting, in carving, and in architecture. From the divine and
heroic legends and personages were borrowed those paintings, statues, and
reliefs, which rendered the temples, porticos, and public buildings, at Athens
and elsewhere, objects of surpassing admiration; and such visible reproduction
contributed again to fix the types of the gods and heroes familiarly and
indelibly on the public mind. The figures delineated on cups and vases, as well
as on the walls of private houses, were chiefly drawn from the same source —
the myths being the great storehouse of artistic scenes and composition.
To enlarge on the characteristic
excellence of Grecian art would here be out of place. I regard it only in so
far as, having originally drawn its materials from the myths, it reacted upon
the mythical faith and imagination—the reaction imparting strength to the
former as well as distinctness to the latter. To one who saw constantly before
him representations of the battles of the Centaurs or the Amazons, of the
exploits performed by Perseus and Bellerophon, of the
incidents composing the Trojan war or the Kalydonian boar-hunt—the process of belief, even in the more fantastic of these
conceptions, became easy in proportion as the conception was familiarized. And
if any person had been slow to believe in the efficacy of the prayers of Eakus, whereby that devout hero once obtained special
relief from Zeus, at a moment when Greece was perishing with long-continued
sterility, his doubts would probably vanish when, on visiting the Eakeium at Egina, there were
exhibited to him the statues of the very envoys who had come on the behalf of
the distressed Greeks to solicit that Eakus would
pray for them. A Grecian temple was not simply a place of worship, but the
actual dwelling-place of a god, who was believed to be introduced by the solemn
dedicatory ceremony, and whom the imagination of the people identified in the
most intimate manner with his statue. The presence or removal of the statue was
conceived as identical with that of the being represented,—and while the statue
was solemnly washed, dressed, and tended with all the respectful solicitude
which would have been bestowed upon a real person, miraculous tales were often
rife respecting the manifestation of real internal feeling in the wood and the
marble. At perilous or critical moments, the statue was affirmed to have
sweated, to have wept, to have closed its eyes, or brandished the spear in its
hands, in token of sympathy or indignation. Such legends, springing up usually
in times of suffering and danger, and finding few men bold enough openly to
contradict them, ran in complete harmony with the general mythical faith, and
tended to strengthen it in all its various ramifications. The renewed activity
of the god or hero both brought to mind and accredited the preexisting myths
connected with his name. When Boreas, during the invasion of Greece by Xerxes,
and in compliance with the fervent prayers of the Athenians, had sent forth a
providential storm, to the irreparable damage of the Persian armada, the
skeptical minority (alluded to by Plato), who doubted the myth of Boreas and Oreithyia, and his close connection thus acquired with Erechtheus, and the Erechtheids generally, must for the time have been reduced to absolute silence.
I HAVE already remarked that the existence of
that popular narrative talk, which the Germans express by the significant word Sage or Volks-Sage, in a greater or less degree of perfection or development, is
a phenomenon common to almost all stages of society and to almost all quarters
of the globe. It is the natural effusion of the unlettered, imaginative, and
believing man, and its maximum of influence belongs to an early state of the
human mind; for the multiplication of recorded facts, the diffusion of positive
science, and the formation of a critical standard of belief, tend to discredit
its dignity and to repress its easy and abundant flow. It supplies to the poet
both materials to recombine and adorn, and a basis as well as a stimulus for
further inventions of his own; and this at a time when the poet is religious
teacher, historian, and philosopher, all in one,—not, as he becomes at a more
advanced period, the mere purveyor of avowed, though interesting, fiction.
Such popular stories, and such historical songs
(meaning by historical, simply that which is accepted as history) are found in
most quarters of the globe, and especially among the Teutonic and Celtic
populations of early Europe. The old Gothic songs were east into a continuous
history by the historian Ablavius; and the poems of
the Germans respecting Tuisto the earth-born god, his
son Mannus, and his descendants the eponyms of the
various German tribes, as they are briefly described by Tacitus, remind us of
Hesiod, or Eumelus, or the Homeric Hymns. Jacob
Grimm, in his learned and valuable Deutsche Mythologic, has exhibited copious evidence of the
great fundamental analogy, along with many special differences, between the
German, Scandinavian, and Grecian mythical world; and the Dissertation of Mr.
Price (prefixed to his edition of Warton’s History of English Poetry) sustains and
illustrates Grimm’s view. The same personifying imagination, the same
ever-present conception of the will, sympathies, and antipathies of the gods as
the producing causes of phenomena, and as distinguished from a course of nature
with its invariable sequence, the same relations between gods, heroes, and men,
with the like difficulty of discriminating the one from the other in many
individual names, a similar wholesale transfer of human attributes to the gods,
with the absence of human limits and liabilities, a like belief in Nymphs,
Giants, and other beings, neither gods nor men, the same coalescence of the
religious with the patriotic feeling and faith, these are positive features
common to the early Greeks with the early Germans: and the negative conditions
of the two are not less analogous, the absence of prose writing, positive
records, and scientific culture. The preliminary basis and encouragements for
the mythopoeia faculty were thus extremely similar.
But though the prolific forces were the same in
kind, the results were very different in degree, and the developing
circumstances were more different still.
First, the abundance, the beauty, and the long
continuance of early Grecian poetry, in the purely poetical age, is a
phenomenon which has no parallel elsewhere.
Secondly, the transition of the Greek mind from
its poetical to its comparatively positive state was self-operated,
accomplished by its own inherent and expansive force—aided indeed, but by no
means either impressed or provoked, from without. From the poetry of Homer, to
the history of Thucydides and the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, was a
prodigious step, but it was the native growth of the Hellenic youth into an
Hellenic man; and what is of still greater moment, it was brought about without
breaking the thread either of religious or patriotic tradition—without any
coercive innovation or violent change in the mental feelings. The legendary
world, though the ethical judgments and rational criticisms of superior men had
outgrown it, still retained its hold upon their feelings as an object of
affectionate and reverential retrospect.
MYTHS AMONG THE EARLY GERMANS.
Far different from this was the development of
the early Germans. We know little about their early poetry, but we shall run no
risk of error in affirming that they had nothing to compare with either Iliad
or Odyssey. Whether, if left to themselves, they would have possessed
sufficient progressive power to make a step similar to that of the Greeks, is a
question which we cannot answer. Their condition, mental as well as political,
was violently changed by a foreign action from without.
The influence of the Roman empire introduced
artificially among them new institutions, new opinions, habits, and luxuries,
and, above all, a new religion; the Romanized Germans becoming themselves
successively the instruments of this revolution with regard to such of their
brethren as still remained heathen. It was a revolution often brought about by
penal and coercive means: the old gods Thor and Woden were formally deposed and renounced, their images were crumbled into dust, and
the sacred oaks of worship and prophecy hewn down. But even where conversion
was the fruit of preaching and persuasion, it did not the less break up all the
associations of a German with respect to that mythical world which he called
his past, and of which the ancient gods constituted both the charm and the
sanctity: he had now only the alternative of treating them either as men or as
daemons.
That mixed religious and patriotic retrospect,
formed by the coalescence of piety with ancestral feeling, which constituted
the appropriate sentiment both of Greeks and of Germans towards their
unrecorded antiquity, was among the latter banished by Christianity: and while
the root of the old myths was thus cankered, the commemorative ceremonies and
customs with which they were connected, either lost their consecrated character
or disappeared altogether. Moreover, new influences of great importance were at
the same time brought to bear. The Latin language, together with some tinge of Latin literature—the habit of writing and of
recording present events—the idea of a systematic law and pacific adjudication
of disputes,—all these formed a part of the general working of Roman
civilization, even after the decline of the Roman empire, upon the Teutonic and
Celtic tribes. A class of specially-educated men was formed, upon a Latin basis
and upon Christian principles, consisting too almost entirely of priests, who
were opposed, as well by motives of rivalry as by religious feeling, to the ancient
bards and storytellers of the community: the “lettered men” were constituted
apart from “the men of story”, and Latin literature contributed along with
religion to sink the myths of untaught heathenism. Charlemagne, indeed, at the
same time that he employed aggressive and violent proceedings to introduce
Christianity among the Saxons, also took special care to commit to writing and
preserve the old heathen songs. But there can be little doubt that this step
was the suggestion of a large and enlightened understanding peculiar to
himself. The disposition general among lettered Christians of that age is more
accurately represented by his son Louis le Debonnaire,
who, having learned these songs as a boy, came to abhor them when he arrived at
mature years, and could never be induced either to repeat or tolerate them.
EARLY GERMAN GENEALOGIES.
According to the old heathen faith, the pedigree
of the Saxon, Anglian, Danish, Norwegian, and Swedish kings,—probably also
those of the German and Scandinavian kings generally,—was traced to Odin, or to
some of his immediate companions or heroic sons. I have already observed that
the value of these genealogies consisted not so much in their length, as in the
reverence attached to the name serving as primitive source. After the worship
attached to Odin had been extinguished, the genealogical line was lengthened up
to Japhet or Noah,—and Odin, no longer accounted
worthy to stand at the top, was degraded into one of the simple human members
of it. And we find this alteration of the original mythical genealogies to have
taken place even among the Scandinavians, although the introduction of
Christianity was in those parts both longer deferred, so as to leave time for a
more ample development of the heathen poetical vein—and seems to have created a
less decided feeling of antipathy (especially in Iceland) towards the extinct
faith. The poems and tales composing the Edda, though
first committed to writing after the period of Christianity, do not present the
ancient gods in a point of view intentionally odious or degrading.
The transposition above alluded to, of the
genealogical root from Odin to Noah, is the more worthy of notice, as it
illustrates the genuine character of these genealogies, and shows that they
sprung, not from any erroneous historical data, but from the turn of the
religious feeling; also that their true value is derived from their being taken
entire, as connecting the existing race of men with a divine original. If we
could imagine that Grecian paganism had been superseded by Christianity in the
year 500 BC, the great and venerated
gentile genealogies of Greece would have undergone the like modification; the Herakleids, Pelopids, Eakids, Asklepiads, &c.,
would have been merged in some larger aggregate branching out from the
archeology of the Old Testament. The old heroic legends connected with these
ancestral names would either have been forgotten, or so transformed as to suit
the new vein of thought; for the altered worship, ceremonies, and customs would
have been altogether at variance with them, and the mythical feeling would have
ceased to dwell upon those to whom prayers were no longer offered. If the oak
of Dodona had been cut down, or the Theoric ship had
ceased to be sent from Athens to Delos, the myths of Theseus and of the two
black doves would have lost their pertinence, and died away. As it was, the
change from Homer to Thucydides and Aristotle took place internally, gradually,
and imperceptibly. Philosophy and history were superinduced in the minds of the superior few, but the feelings of the general public
continued unshaken—the sacred objects remained the same both to the eye and to
the heart—and the worship of the ancient gods was even adorned by new
architects and sculptors who greatly strengthened its imposing effect.
While then in Greece the mythopoeic stream
continued in the same course, only with abated current and influence, in modern
Europe its ancient bed was blocked up, and it was turned into new and divided
channels. The old religion—though as an ascendant faith, unanimously and
publicly manifested, it became extinct—still continued in detached scraps and
fragments, and under various alterations of name and form. The heathen gods and
goddesses, deprived as they were of divinity, did not pass out of the
recollection and fears of their former worshippers, but were sometimes
represented (on principles like those of Euemerus) as
having been eminent and glorious men—sometimes degraded into daemons,
magicians, elfs, fairies, and other supernatural
agents, of an inferior grade and generally mischievous cast. Christian writers,
such as Saxo Grammaticus and Snorro Sturleson, committed to writing the ancient oral
songs of the Scandivian Scalds, and digested the
events contained in them into continuous narrative—performing in this respect a
task similar to that of the Grecian logographers Pherekydes and Hellanikus, in reference to Hesiod and the Cyclic poets.
But while Pherekydes and Hellanikus compiled under
the influence of feelings substantially the same as those of the poets on whom
they bestowed their care, the Christian logographers felt it their duty to
point out the Odin and Thor of the old Scalds as evil daemons, or cunning
enchanters, who had fascinated the minds of men into a false belief in their
divinity. In some cases, the heathen recitals and ideas were modified so as to
suit Christian feeling. But when preserved without such a change, they
exhibited themselves palpably, and were designated by their compilers, as at
variance with the religious belief of the people, and as associated either with
imposture or with evil spirits.
LEGENDS OF THE SAINTS.
A new vein of sentiment had arisen in Europe,
unsuitable indeed to the old myths, yet leaving still in force the demand for
mythical narrative generally. And this demand was satisfied, speaking
generally, by two classes of narratives,—the legends of the Catholic Saints and
the Romances of Chivalry, corresponding to two types of character, both
perfectly accommodated to the feelings of the time,—the saintly ideal and the
chivalrous ideal.
Both these two classes of narrative correspond,
in character as well as in general purpose, to the Grecian myths—being stories
accepted as realities, from their full conformity with the predispositions and
deep-seated faith of an uncritical audience, and prepared beforehand by their
authors, not with any reference to the conditions of historical proof, but for
the purpose of calling forth sympathy, emotion, or reverence. The type of the
saintly character belongs to Christianity, being the history of Jesus Christ as
described in the gospels, and that of the prophets in the Old Testament; whilst
the lives of holy men, who acquired a religious reputation from the fourth to
the fourteenth century of the Christian era, were invested with attributes, and
illustrated with ample details, tending to assimilate them to this revered
model. The numerous miracles, the cure of diseases, the expulsion of demons,
the temptations and sufferings, the teachings and commands, with which the
biography of Catholic saints abounds, grew chiefly out of this pious feeling,
common to the writer and to his readers. Many of the other incidents, recounted
in the same performances, take their rise from misinterpreted allegories, from
ceremonies and customs of which it was pleasing to find a consecrated origin,
or from the disposition to convert the etymology of a name into matter of
history : many have also been suggested by local peculiarities, and by the
desire of stimulating or justifying the devotional emotions of pilgrims who
visited some consecrated chapel or image. The dove was connected, in the faith
of the age, with the Holy Ghost, the serpent with Satan; lions, wolves, stags,
unicorns, etc. were the subjects of other emblematic associations; and such
modes of belief found expression for themselves in many narratives which
brought the saints into conflict or conjoint action with these various animals.
Legends of this kind, so indefinitely multiplied and so preeminently popular
and affecting, in the Middle Ages, are not exaggerations of particular matters
of fact, but emanations in detail of some current faith or feeling, which they
served to satisfy, and by which they were in turn amply sustained and
accredited.
Readers of Pausanias will recognize the great
general analogy between the stories recounted to him at the temples which he
visited, and these legends of the Middle Ages. Though the type of character
which the latter illustrate is indeed materially different, yet the source as
well as the circulation, the generating as well as the sustaining forces, were
in both cases the same. Such legends were the natural growth of a religious
faith earnest, unexamining, and interwoven with the
feelings at a time when the reason does not need to be cheated. The lives of
the Saints bring us even back to the simple and ever-operative theology of the
Homeric age; so constantly is the hand of God exhibited even in the minutest
details, for the succor of a favored individual,—so completely is the scientific
point of view, respecting the phenomena of nature, absorbed into the religious.
During the intellectual vigor of Greece and Rome, a sense of the invariable
course of nature and of the scientific explanation of phenomena had been
created among the superior minds, and through them indirectly among the
remaining community; thus limiting to a certain extent the ground open to be
occupied by a religious legend. With the decline of the pagan literature and
philosophy, before the sixth century of the Christian era, this scientific
conception gradually passed out of sight, and left the mind free to a religious
interpretation of nature not less simple and nay than that which had prevailed
under the Homeric paganism. The great religious movement of the Reformation, and
the gradual formation of critical and philosophical habits in the modern mind,
have caused these legends of the Saints,—once the charm and cherished creed of
a numerous public, to pass altogether out of credit, without even being
regarded, among Protestants at least, as worthy of a formal scrutiny into the
evidence,—a proof of the transitory value of public belief, however sincere and
fervent, as a certificate of historical truth, if it be blended with religious
predispositions.
LEGENDS OF CHIVALRY.
The same mythopoeic vein, and the same
susceptibility and facility of belief, which had created both supply and demand
for the legends of the Saints, also provided the abundant stock of romantic
narrative poetry, in amplification and illustration of the chivalrous ideal.
What the legends of Troy, of Thebes, of the Kalydonian boar, of Edipus, Theseus, etc. were to an early
Greek, the tales of Arthur, of Charlemagne, of the Niebelungen,
were to an Englishman, or Frenchman, or German, of the twelfth or thirteenth
century. They were neither recognized fiction nor authenticated history: they
were history, as it is felt and welcomed by minds unaccustomed to investigate
evidence, and unconscious of the necessity of doing so. That the Chronicle of
Turpin, a mere compilation of poetical legends respecting Charlemagne, was
accepted as genuine history, and even pronounced to be such by papal authority,
is well known; and the authors of the Romances announce themselves, not less
than those of the old Grecian epic, as being about to recount real matter of
fact. It is certain that Charlemagne is a great historical name, and it is
possible, though not certain, that the name of Arthur may be historical also.
But the Charlemagne of history, and the Charlemagne of romance, have little
except the name in common nor could we ever determine, except by independent
evidence (which in this case we happen to possess), whether Charlemagne was a
real or a fictitious person. That illustrious name, as well as the more
problematical Arthur, is taken up by the romancers, not with a view to
celebrate realities previously verified, but for the purpose of setting forth
or amplifying an ideal of their own, in such manner as both to rouse the
feelings and captivate the faith of their hearers.
To inquire which of the personages of the
Carolingian epic were real and which were fictitious,—to examine whether the
expedition ascribed to Charlemagne against Jerusalem had ever taken place or
not,—to separate truth from exaggeration in the exploits of the Knights of the
Round Table,—these were problems which an audience of that day had neither
disposition to undertake nor means to resolve. They accepted the narrative as
they heard it, without suspicion or reserve; the incidents related, as well as
the connecting links between them, were in full harmony with their feelings,
and gratifying as well to their sympathies as to their curiosity: nor was
anything farther wanting to induce them to believe it, though the historical
basis might be ever so slight or even non-existent.
The romances of chivalry represented, to those
who heard them, real deeds of the foretime—“glories of the foregone men”, to
use the Hesiodic expression—at the same time that they embodied and filled up
the details of an heroic ideal, such as that age could conceive and admire—a
fervent piety, combined with strength, bravery, and the love of adventurous
aggression, directed sometimes against infidels, sometimes against enchanters
or monsters, sometimes in defence of the fair sex.
Such characteristics wore naturally popular, in a century of feudal struggles
and universal insecurity, when the grand subjects of common respect and
interest were the Church and the Crusades, and when the latter especially were
embraced with an enthusiasm truly astonishing.
NIEBELUNGEN LIED. EDDA.
The long German poem of the Niebelungen Lied, as well as the Volsunga Saga and a portion of
the songs of the Edda, relate to a common fund of
mythical, superhuman personages, and of fabulous adventure, identified with the
earliest antiquity of the Teutonic and Scandinavian race, and representing
their primitive sentiment towards ancestors of divine origin. Sigurd, Brynhilde, Gudrun, and Atle, are mythical characters celebrated as well by the
Scandinavian Scalds as by the German epic poets, but with many varieties and
separate additions to distinguish the one from the other. The German epic,
later and more elaborated, includes various persons not known to the songs in
the Edda, in particular the prominent name of Dieterich of Bern—presenting, moreover, the principal
characters and circumstances as Christian, while in the Edda there is no trace of anything but heathenism. There is, indeed, in this the old
and heathen version, a remarkable analogy with many points of Grecian mythical
narrative. As in the case of the short life of Achilles, and of the miserable Labdakids of Thebes—so in the family of the Volsungs, though sprung from and protected by the gods—a
curse of destiny hangs upon them and brings on their ruin, in spite of preeminent
personal qualities. The more thoroughly this old Teutonic story has been traced
and compared, in its various transformations and accompaniments, the less can
any well-established connection be made out for it with authentic historical
names or events. We must acquiesce in its personages as distinct in original
conception from common humanity, and as belonging to the subjective mythical
world of the race by whom they were sung.
Such were the compositions which not only
interested the emotions, but also satisfied the undistinguishing historical
curiosity, of the ordinary public in the middle ages. The exploits of many of
these romantic heroes resemble in several points those of the Grecian the
adventures of Perseus, Achilles, Odysseus, Atalanta, Bellerophon, Jason, and the Trojan war, or Argonautic expedition generally, would have fitted in
perfectly to the Carolingian or other epics of the period. That of the middle
ages, like the Grecian, was eminently expansive in its nature: new stories were
successively attached to the names and companions of Charlemagne and Arthur,
just as the legend of Troy was enlarged by Arktinus, Lesches, and Stesichorus,—that of
Thebes, by fresh miseries entailed on the fated head of Edipus,—and
that of the Kalydonian boar, by the addition of Atalanta. Altogether, the state of mind of the hearers
seems in both cases to have been much the same,—eager for emotion and sympathy,
and receiving any narrative attuned to their feelings, not merely with hearty
welcome, but also with unsuspecting belief.
EXPANSIVE CHARACTER OF EPIC LEGEND.
Nevertheless, there were distinctions deserving
of notice, which render the foregoing proposition more absolutely exact with
regard to Greece than with regard to the middle ages. The tales of the epic,
and the myths in their most popular and extended signification, were the only
intellectual nourishment with which the Grecian public was supplied, until the
sixth century before the Christian era: there was no prose writing, no history,
no philosophy. But such was not exactly the case at the time when the epic of
the middle ages appeared. At that time, a portion of society possessed the
Latin language, the habit of writing, and some tinge both of history and philosophy : there were a series of chronicles, scanty,
indeed, and imperfect, but referring to contemporary events and preventing the
real history of the past from passing into oblivion: there were even individual
scholars, in the twelfth century, whose acquaintance with Latin literature was
sufficiently considerable to enlarge their minds and to improve their
judgments. Moreover, the epic of the middle ages, though deeply imbued with
religious ideas, was not directly amalgamated with the religion of the people,
and did not always find favor with the clergy; while the heroes of the Grecian
epic were not only linked in a thousand ways with existing worship, practices,
and sacred localities, but Homer and Hesiod pass with Herodotus for the
constructors of Grecian theology. We thus see that the ancient epic was both
exempt from certain distracting influences by which that of the middle ages was
surrounded, and more closely identified with the veins of thought and feeling
prevalent in the Grecian public. Yet these counteracting influences did not
prevent Pope Calixtus II from declaring the Chronicle
of Turpin to be a genuine history.
If we take the history of our own country
(England) as it was conceived and written from the twelfth to the seventeenth
century by Hardyng, Fabyan,
Grafton, Hollinshed, and others, we shall find that
it was supposed to begin with Brute the Trojan, and was carried down from
thence, for many ages and through a long succession of kings, to the times of
Julius Caesar. A similar belief of descent from Troy, arising seemingly from a
reverential imitation of the Romans and of their Trojan origin, was cherished
in the fancy of other European nations. With regard to the English, the chief
circulator of it was Geoffrey of Monmouth, and it passed with little resistance
or dispute into the national faith—the kings from Brute downward being enrolled
in regular chronological series with their respective dates annexed. In a
dispute which took place during the reign of Edward I (AD 1301) between England and Scotland, the descent of the kings of
England from Brute the Trojan was solemnly embodied in a document put forth to
sustain the rights of the crown of England, as an argument bearing on the case
then in discussion: and it passed without attack from the opposing party,—an
incident which reminds as of the appeal made by Aschines,
in the contention between the Athenians and Philip of Macedon, respecting
Amphipolis, to the primitive dotal rights of Akamas son of Theseus —and also of the defense urged by the
Athenians to sustain their conquest of Sigeium,
against the reclamations of the Mityleneans, wherein
the former alleged that they had as much right to the place as any of the other
Greeks who had formed part of the victorious armament of Agamemnon.
The tenacity with which this early series of
British kings was defended, is no less remarkable than the facility with which
it was admitted. The chroniclers at the beginning of the seventeenth century
warmly protested against the intrusive skepticism which would cashier so many
venerable sovereigns and efface so many noble deeds. They appealed to the
patriotic feelings of their hearers, represented the enormity of thus setting
up a presumptuous criticism against the belief of ages, and insisted on the
danger of the precedent as regarded history generally. How this controversy
stood, at the time and in the view of the illustrious author of Paradise Lost,
I shall give in his own words, at they appear in the second page of his History
of England. After having briefly touched upon the stories of Samothes son of Japhet, Albion
son of Neptune, etc., he proceeds :
“But now of Brutus and his line, with the whole
progeny of kings to the entrance of Julius Caesar, we cannot so easily be
discharged : descents of ancestry long continued, laws and exploits not plainly
seeming to be borrowed or devised, which on the common belief have wrought no
small impression: defended by many,
denied utterly by few. For what though Brutus and the whole Trojan pretense
were yielded up, seeing they, who first devised to bring us some noble
ancestor, were content at first with Brutus the Consul, till better invention,
though not willing to forego the name, taught them to remove it higher into a
more fabulous age, and by the same remove lighting on the Trojan tales, in
affectation to make the Briton of one original with the Roman, pitched there: Yet those old and inborn kings, never any to
have been real persons, or done in their lives at least some part of what so
long had been remembered, cannot be thought without too strict incredulity.
For these, and those causes above mentioned, that which had received
approbation from so many, I have chosen not to omit. Certain or uncertain, be
that upon the credit of those whom I must follow: so far as keeps aloof from impossible or absurd, attested by
ancient writers from books more ancient, I refuse not, as the due and proper
subject of story”.
Yet in spite of the general belief of so many
centuries—in spite of the concurrent persuasion of historians and poets—in
spite of the declaration of Milton, extorted from his feelings rather than from
his reason, that this long line of quasi-historical kings and exploits could
not be all unworthy of belief—in spite of so large a body of authority and
precedent, the historians of the nineteenth century begin the history of
England with Julius Caesar. They do not attempt either to settle the date of
king Bladud’s accession, or to determine what may be
the basis of truth in the affecting narrative of Lear. The standard of
historical credibility, especially with regard to modern events, has Indeed
been greatly and sensibly raised within the last hundred years.
HISTORICAL STANDARD OF CREDIBILITY.
But in regard to ancient Grecian history, the
rules of evidence still continue relaxed. The dictum of Milton, regarding the
ante-Caesarian history of England, still represents pretty exactly the feeling
now prevalent respecting the mythical history of Greece: “Yet those old and
inborn kings (Agamemnon, Achilles, Odysseus, Jason, Adrastus, Amphiaraus, Meleager,
etc.), never any to have been real persons, or done in their lives at least
some part of what so long hath been remembered, cannot be thought without too
strict incredulity”. Amidst much fiction (we are still told), there must be
some truth: but how is such truth to be singled out? Milton does not even
attempt to make the severance: he contents himself with “keeping aloof from the
impossible and the absurd”, and ends in a narrative which has indeed the merit
of being sober-colored, but which he never for a moment thinks of recommending
to his readers as true. So in regard to the legends of Greece,—Troy, Thebes,
the Argonauts, the Boar of Kalydom, Heracles,
Theseus, Oedipus,—the conviction still holds in men's minds, that there must be
something true at the bottom; and many readers of this work may be displeased,
I fear, not to see conjured up before them the Eidolon of an authentic history,
even though the vital spark of evidence be altogether wanting.
I presume to think that our great poet has
proceeded upon mistaken views with respect to the old British fables, not less
in that which he leaves out than in that which he retains. To omit the
miraculous and the fantastic, (it is that which he really means by “the
impossible and the absurd”), is to suck the lifeblood out of these once popular
narratives,—to divest them at once both of their genuine distinguishing mark,
and the charm by which they acted on the feelings of believers. Still less
ought we to consent to break up and disenchant in a similar manner the myth of
ancient Greece,—partly because they possess the mythical beauties and
characteristics in far higher perfection, partly because they sank deeper into
the mind of a Greek, and pervaded both the public and private sentiment of the
country to a much greater degree than the British fables in England.
Two courses, and two only, are open; either to
pass over the myths altogether, which is the way in which modern historians
treat the old British fables, or else to give an account of them as myths; to
recognize and respect their specific nature, and to abstain from confounding
them with ordinary and certifiable history. There are good reasons for pursuing
this second method in reference to the Grecian myths; and when so considered,
they constitute an important chapter in the history of the Grecian mind, and
indeed in that of the human race generally. The historical faith of the Greeks,
as well as that of other people, in reference to early and unrecorded times, is
as much subjective and peculiar to themselves as their religious faith: among
the Greeks, especially, the two are confounded with an intimacy which nothing
less than great violence can disjoin. Gods, heroes, and men—religion and
patriotism—matters divine, heroic, and human—were all woven together by the Greeks
into one indivisible web, in which the threads of truth and reality, whatever
they might originally have been, were neither intended to be nor were actually,
distinguishable. Composed of such materials, and animated by the electric spark
of genius, the mythical antiquities of Greece formed a whole at once
trustworthy and captivating to the faith and feelings of the people; but
neither trustworthy nor captivating, when we sever it from these subjective
conditions, and expose its naked elements to the scrutiny of an objective
criticism. Moreover the separate portions of Grecian mythical foretime ought to
be considered with reference to that aggregate of which they form a part : to
detach the divine from the heroic legends, or some one of the heroic legends
from the remainder, as if there were an essential and generic difference
between them, is to present the whole under an erroneous point of view. The
myths of Troy and Thebes are no more to be handled objectively, with a view to
detect an historical base, than those of Zeus in Crete, of Apollo and Artemis
in Delos, of Hermes, or of Prometheus. To single out the siege of Troy from the
other myths, as if it were entitled to pre-eminence as an ascertained
historical and chronological event, is a proceeding which destroys the true
character and coherence of the mythical world: we only transfer the story (as
has been remarked in the preceding chapter) from a class with which it is
connected by every tie both of common origin and fraternal affinity, to another
with which it has no relationship, except such as violent and gratuitous
criticism may enforce.
By drawing this marked distinction between the
mythical and the historical world, between matter appropriate only for
subjective history, and matter in which objective evidence is attainable, we
shall only carry out to its proper length the just and well-known position long
ago laid down by Varro. That learned man recognized three distinguishable
periods preceding his own age: “First, the time from the beginning of mankind
down to the first deluge; a time wholly unknown. Secondly, the period from the
first deluge down to the first Olympiad, which is called the mythical period,
because many fabulous things are recounted in it. Thirdly, the time from the
first Olympiad down to ourselves, which is called the historical period,
because the things done in it are comprised in true histories”.
Taking the commencement of true or objective
history at the point indicated by Varro, I still consider the mythical and
historical periods to be separated by a wider gap than he would have admitted.
To select any one year as an absolute point of commencement, is of course not
to be understood literally: but in point of fact, this is of every little
importance in reference to the present question, seeing that the great mythical
events the sieges of Thebes and Troy, the Argonautic expedition, the Kalydonian boar-hunt, the return of
the Herakleids, &c. are all placed long anterior
to the first Olympiad, by those who have applied chronological boundaries to
the mythical narratives. The period immediately preceding the first Olympiad is
one exceedingly barren of events; the received chronology recognizes 400 years,
and Herodotus admitted 500 years, from that date back to the Trojan war.
XVII.
CLOSING EVENTS OF LEGENDARY GREECE. PERIOD OF INTERMEDIATE DARKNESS
BEFORE THE DAWN OF HISTORICAL GREECE.
SECTION I.
RETURN OF THE
HERAKLEIDS INTO PELOPONNESUS.
IN one of the
preceding chapters, we have traced the descending series of the two most
distinguished mythical families in Peloponnesus,—the Perseids and the Pelopids: we have followed the former down to
Heracles and his son Hyllus, and the latter down to
Orestes son of Agamemnon, who is left in possession of that ascendancy in the
peninsula which had procured for his father the chief command in the Trojan
war. The Herakleids, or sons of Heracles, on the
other hand, are expelled fugitives, dependent upon foreign aid or protection: Hyllus had perished in single combat with Echemus of Tegea, (connected with the Pelopids by marriage with Timandra sister of Clytemnestra,)
and a solemn compact had been made, as the preliminary condition of this duel,
that no similar attempt at an invasion of the peninsula should be undertaken by
his family for the space of one hundred years. At the end of the stipulated
period the attempt was renewed, and with complete success; but its success was
owing, not so much to the valor of the invaders as to a powerful body of new
allies. The Herakleids reappear as leaders and
companions of the Dorians,— a northerly section of the Greek name, who now
first come into importance,—poor, indeed, in mythical renown, since they are
never noticed in the Iliad, and only once casually mentioned in the Odyssey, as
a fraction among the many-tongued inhabitants of Crete,—but destined to form
one of the grand and predominant elements throughout all the career of
historical Hellas.
The son of Hyllus—Kleodeus—as well as his
grandson Aristomachus, were now dead, and the lineage
of Heracles was represented by the three sons of the latter,—Temenus, Kresphontes, and Aristodemus, and under their conduct the
Dorians penetrated into the peninsula. The mythical account traced back this
intimate union between the Herakleids and the Dorians
to a prior war, in which Heracles himself had rendered inestimable aid to the
Dorian king Egimius, when the latter was hard pressed in a contest with the Lapithae. Heracles defeated the Lapithae,
and slew their king Koronus; in return for which Egimius
assigned to his deliverer one third part of his whole territory, and adopted Hyllus as his son. Heracles desired that the territory thus
made over might be held in reserve until a time should come when his
descendants might stand in need of it; and that time did come, after the death
of Hyllus. Some of the Herakleids then found shelter at Trikorythus in Attica, but the
remainder, turning their steps towards Egimius, solicited from him the
allotment of land which had been promised to their valiant progenitor. Egimius
received them according to his engagement, and assigned to them the stipulated
third portion of his territory and from this moment the Herakleids and Dorians became intimately united together into one social communion.
Pamphylus and Dymas, sons of Egimius, accompanied
Temenus and his two brothers in their invasion of Peloponnesus.
Such is the
mythical incident which professes to explain the origin of those three tribes
into which all the Dorian communities were usually divided,—the Hylleis, the Phamphyli, and the Dymanes,—the first of the three including certain
particular families, such as that of the kings of Sparta, who bore the special
name of Herakleids. Hyllus,
Pamphylus, and Dymas are the eponymous heroes of the
three Dorian tribes.
DORIAN INVASION OF PELOPONNESUS.
Temenus and his
two brothers resolved to attack Peloponnesus, not by a land-march along the
Isthmus, such as that in which Hyllus had been
previously slain, but by sea, across the narrow inlet between the promontories
of Rhium and Antirrhium,
with which the Gulf of Corinth commences. According to one story,
indeed,—which, however, does not seem to have been known to Herodotus,—they are
said to have selected this line of march by the express direction of the Delphian god, who vouchsafed to expound to them an oracle
which had been delivered to Hyllus in the ordinary
equivocal phraseology. Both the Ozolian Lokrians, and the Etolians,
inhabitants of the northern coast of the Gulf of Corinth, were favorable to the
enterprise, and the former granted to them a port for building their ships,
from which memorable circumstance the port ever afterwards bore the name of Naupaktus. Aristodemus was here struck with lightning and
died, leaving twin sons, Eurysthenes and Prokles; but his remaining brothers continued to press the
expedition with alacrity.
At this
juncture, an Acarnanians prophet named Carnus presented himself in the camps under the inspiration
of Apollo, and uttered various predictions: he was, however, so much suspected
of treacherous collusion with the Peloponnesians, that Hippotes,
great-grandson of Heracles through Phylas and
Antiochus, slew him. His death drew upon the army the wrath of Apollo, who
destroyed their vessels and punished them with famine. Temenus, in his distress,
again applying to the Delphian god for succor and
counsel, was made acquainted with the cause of so much suffering, and was
directed to banish Hippotes for ten years, to offer
expiatory sacrifice for the death of Carnus, and to
seek as the guide of the army a man with three eyes. On coming back to Naupaktus, he met the Etolian Oxyltis, son of Andraemon,
returning to his country, after a temporary exile in Elis, incurred for
homicide: Oxylus had lost one eye, but as he was
seated on a horse, the man and the horse together made up the three eyes
required, and he was adopted as the guide prescribed by the oracle. Conducted
by him, they refitted their ships, landed on the opposite coast of Achaia, and
marched to attack Tisamenus, son of Orestes, then the great potentate of the
peninsula. A decisive battle was fought, in which the latter was vanquished and
slain, and in which Pamphylus and Dymas also
perished. This battle made the Dorians so completely masters of the
Peloponnesus, that they proceeded to distribute the territory among themselves.
The fertile land of Elis had been by previous stipulation reserved for Oxylus, as a recompense for his services as conductor: and
it was agreed that the three Herakleids,—Temenus, Kresphontes, and the infant sons of Aristodemus,—should
draw lots for Argos, Sparta, and Messene. Argos fell to Temenus, Sparta to the
sons of Aristodemus, and Messene to Kresphontes; the
latter having secured for himself this prize, the most fertile territory of the
three, by the fraud of putting into the vessel out of which the lots were
drawn, a lump of clay instead of a stone, whereby the lots of his brothers were
drawn out while his own remained inside. Solemn sacrifices were offered by each
upon this partition: but as they proceeded to the ceremony, a miraculous sign
was seen upon the altar of each of the brothers,—a toad corresponding to Argos,
a serpent to Sparta, and a fox to Messene. The prophets, on being consulted,
delivered the import of these mysterious indications: the toad, as an animal
slow and stationary, was an evidence that the possessor of Argos would not
succeed in enterprises beyond the limits of his own city; the serpent denoted
the aggressive and formidable future reserved to Sparta; the fox prognosticated
a career of wile and deceit to the Messenian.
MYTHICAL BEARING OF THE STORY
Such is the
brief account given by Apollodorus of the Return of the Herakleids,
at which point we pass, as if touched by the wand of a magician, from mythical
to historical Greece. The story bears on the face of it the stamp, not of
history, but of legend,— abridged from one or more of the genealogical poets,
and presenting such an account as they thought satisfactory, of the first
formation of the great Dorian establishments in Peloponnesus, as well as of the
semi-Aetolian Elis. Its incidents are so conceived as to have an explanatory
bearing on Dorian institutions,—upon the triple division of tribes,
characteristic of the Dorians,—upon the origin of the great festival of the Karneia at Sparta, alleged to be celebrated in expiation of
the murder of Carnus,—upon the different temper and
character of the Dorian states among themselves,—upon the early alliance of the
Dorians with Elis, which contributed to give ascendency and vogue to the
Olympic games,—upon the reverential dependence of Dorians towards the Delphian oracle,—and, lastly, upon the etymology of the
name Naupaktus. If we possessed the narrative more in
detail, we should probably find many more examples of coloring of the legendary
past suitable to the circumstances of the historical present.
Above all, this
legend makes out in favor of the Dorians and their kings a mythical title to
their Peloponnesian establishments; Argos, Sparta, and Messene are presented as
rightfully belonging, and restored by just retribution, to the children of
Heracles. It was to them that Zeus had especially given the territory of
Sparta; the Dorians came in as their subjects and auxiliaries. Plato gives a
very different version of the legend, but we find that he, too, turns the story
in such a manner as to embody a claim of right on the part of the conquerors.
According to him, the Achaeans, who returned from the capture of Troy, found
among their fellow-citizens at home—the race which had grown up during their absence—an
aversion to readmit them: after a fruitless endeavor to make good their rights,
they were at last expelled, but not without much contest and bloodshed. A
leader named Dorieus, collected all these exiles into
one body, and from him they received the name of Dorians instead of Achaeans;
then marching back, under the conduct of the Herakleids into Peloponnesus, they recovered by force the possessions from which they had
been shut out, and constituted the three Dorian establishments under the
separate Herakleid brothers, at Argos, Sparta, and
Messene. These three fraternal dynasties were founded upon a scheme of intimate
union and sworn alliance one with the other, for the purpose of resisting any
attack which might be made upon them from Asia, either by the remaining Trojans
or by their allies. Such is the story as Plato believed it; materially
different in the incidents related, yet analogous in mythical feeling, and
embodying alike the idea of a rightful reconquest. Moreover, the two accounts
agree in representing both the entire conquest and the triple division of
Dorian Peloponnesus as begun and completed in one and the same enterprise,—so
as to constitute one single event, which Plato would probably have called the
Return of the Achaeans, but which was commonly known as the Return of the Herakleids. Though this is both inadmissible and
inconsistent with other statements which approach close to the historical
times, yet it bears every mark of being the primitive view originally presented
by the genealogical poets: the broad way in which the incidents are grouped
together, was at once easy for the imagination to follow, and impressive to the
feelings.
The existence
of one legendary account must never be understood as excluding the probability
of other accounts, current at the same time, but inconsistent with it: and many
such there were as to the first establishment of the Peloponnesian Dorians. In
the narrative which I have given from Apollodorus, conceived apparently under
the influence of Dorian feelings, Tisamenus is stated to have been slain in the
invasion. But according to another narrative, which seems to have found favor
with the historical Achaeans on the north coast of Peloponnesus, Tisamenus,
though expelled by the invaders from his kingdom of Sparta or Argos, was not
slain: he was allowed to retire under agreement, together with a certain
portion of his subjects, and he directed his steps towards the coast of
Peloponnesus south of the Corinthian Gulf, then occupied by the Ionians. As
there were relations, not only of friendship, but of kindred origin, between
Ionians and Achaeans, (the eponymous heroes Ion and Achaeus pass for brothers,
both sons of Xuthus), Tisamenus solicited from the
Ionians admission for himself and his fellow-fugitives into their territory.
The leading Ionians declining this request, under the apprehension that
Tisamenus might be chosen as sovereign over the whole, the latter accomplished
his object by force. After a vehement struggle, the Ionians were vanquished and
put to flight, and Tisamenus thus acquired possession of Helike,
as well as of the northern coast of the peninsula, westward from Sicyon; which
coast continued to be occupied by the Achaeans, and received its name from
them, throughout all the historical times. The Ionians retired to Attica, many
of them taking part in what is called the Ionic emigration to the coast of Asia
Minor, which followed shortly after. Pausanias, indeed, tells us that
Tisamenus, having gained a decisive victory over the Ionians, fell in the
engagement, and did not himself live to occupy the country of which his troops
remained masters. But this story of the death of Tisamenus seems to arise from
a desire, on the part of Pausanias, to blend together into one narrative two
discrepant legends; at least the historical Achaeans in later times continued
to regard Tisamenus himself as having lived and reigned in their territory, and
as having left a regal dynasty which lasted down to Ogyges,
after whom it was exchanged for a popular government.
The conquest of
Temenus, the eldest of the three Herakleids,
originally comprehended only Argos and its neighborhood; it was from thence
that Troezen, Epidaurus, Egina, Sikyon, and Phlius were
successfully occupied by Dorians, the sons and son-in-law of Temenus—Deiphontes, Phalkes, and Keisus—being the leaders under whom this was accomplished.
At Sparta, the success of the Dorians was furthered by the treason of a man
named Philonomus, who received as recompense the
neighboring town and territory of Amyklae. Messenia
is said to have submitted without resistance to the dominion of the Herakleid Kresphontes, who
established his residence at Stenyklarus: the Pylian Melanthus, then ruler of the country, and
representative of the great mythical lineage of Neleus and Nestor, withdrew with his household gods and with a portion of his subjects
to Attica.
OXYLUS AND THE
ETOLIANS IN ELIS
The only Dorian
establishment in the peninsula not directly connected with the triple partition
is Corinth, which is said to have been Dorized somewhat later and under another leader, though still a Herakleid. Hippotes—descendant of Heracles in the fourth
generation, but not through Hyllus,—had been guilty
(as already mentioned) of the murder of Karnus the
prophet at the camp of Naupaktus, for which he had
been banished and remained in exile for ten years; his son deriving the name of Aletes from the long wanderings endured by the
father. At the head of a body of Dorians, Aletes attacked Corinth: he pitched his camp on the Solygeian eminence near the city, and harassed the inhabitants with constant warfare
until he compelled them to surrender. Even in the time of the Peloponnesian
war, the Corinthians professed to identify the hill on which the camp of these
assailants had been placed. The great mythical dynasty of the Sisyphids was expelled, and Aletes became ruler and Ekist of the Dorian city; many of the inhabitants, however, Eolic or Ionic, departed.
The settlement
of Oxylus and his Etolians in Elis is said by some to have been accomplished with very little opposition;
the leader professing himself to be descended from Etolus,
who had been in a previous age banished from Elis into Etelia,
and the two people, Epeians and Etolians,
acknowledging a kindred origin one with the other. At first, indeed, according
to Ephorus, the Epeians appeared in arms, determined to repel the intruders, but at length it was
agreed on both sides to abide the issue of a single combat. Degmenus,
the champion of the Epeians, confided in the long
shot of his bow and arrow; but the Etolian Pyraichmes came provided with his sling,—a weapon then
unknown and recently invented by the Etolians,—the
range of which was yet longer than that of the bow of his enemy: he thus killed Degmenus, and secured the victory to Oxylus and his followers. According to one statement, the Epeians were expelled; according to another, they
fraternized amicably with the new-comers: whatever may be the truth as to this
matter, it is certain that their name is from this moment lost, and that they
never reappear among the historical elements of Greece: we hear from this time
forward only of Eleians, said to be of Etolian descent.
One most
important privilege was connected with the possession of the Eleian territory by Oxylus,
coupled with his claim on the gratitude of the Dorian kings. The Eleians
acquired the administration of the temple at Olympia, which the Achaeans are
said to have possessed before them; and in consideration of this sacred
function, which subsequently ripened into the celebration of the great Olympic
games, their territory was solemnly pronounced to be inviolable. Such was the
statement of Ephorus: we find, in this case as in so
many others, that the Return of the Herakleids is
made to supply a legendary basis for the historical state of things in
Peloponnesus.
ACHAEAN LEGENDS
ADOPTED DY THE DORIANS
It was the
practice of the great Attic tragedians, with rare exceptions, to select the
subjects of their composition from the heroic or legendary world, and Euripides
had composed three dramas, now lost, on the adventures of Temenus with his
daughter Hyrnetho and his son-in-law Deiphontes,—on the family misfortunes of Kresphontes and Merope,—and on
the successful valor of Archelaus the son of Temenus in Macedonia, where he was
alleged to have first begun the dynasty of the Temenid kings. Of these subjects the first and second were eminently tragical, and the third, relating to Archelaus, appears to
have been undertaken by Euripides in compliment to his contemporary sovereign
and patron, Archelaus king of Macedonia: we are even told that those exploits
which the usual version of the legend ascribed to Temenus, were reported in the
drama of Euripides to have been performed by Archelaus his son. Of all the
heroes, touched upon by the three Attic tragedians, these Dorian Herakleids stand lowest in the descending genealogical
series—one mark amongst others that we are approaching the ground of genuine
history.
Though the name
Achaeans, as denoting a people, is henceforward confined to the
North-Peloponnesian territory specially called Achaia, and to the inhabitants
of Achaea, Phthiotis, north of Mount Eta,—and though
the great Peloponnesian states always seem to have prided themselves on the
title of Dorians—yet we find the kings of Sparta, ever in the historical age
taking pains to appropriate to themselves the mythical glories of the Achaeans,
and to set themselves forth as the representatives of Agamemnon and Orestes.
The Spartan king Kleomenes even went so far as to
disavow formally any Dorian parentage; for when the priestess at Athens refused
to permit him to sacrifice in the temple of Athene, on the plea that it was
peremptorily closed to all Dorians, he replied: "I am no Dorian, but an
Achaean." Not only did the Spartan envoy, before Gelon of Syracuse, connect the indefeasible title of his country to the supreme
command of the Grecian military force, with the ancient name and lofty
prerogatives of Agamemnon—but, in farther pursuance of the same feeling, the
Spartans are said to have carried to Sparta both the bones of Orestes from
Tegea, and those of Tisamenus from Helike, at the
injunction of the Delphian oracle. There is also a
story that Oxylus in Elis was directed by the same
oracle to invite into his country an Achaean, as Ekist conjointly with himself;
and that he called in Agorius, the great-grandson of
Orestes, from Helike, with a small number of Achaeans
who joined him. The Dorians themselves, being singularly poor in native
legends, endeavored, not unnaturally, to decorate themselves with those
legendary ornaments which the Achaeans possessed in abundance.
As a
consequence of the Dorian establishments in Peloponnesus, several migrations of
the preexisting inhabitants are represented as taking place:
1. The Epeians of Elis are either expelled, or merged in the
new-comers under Oxylus, and lose their separate
name.
2. The Pylians, together with the great heroic family of Neleus and his son Nester, who preside over them, give
place to the Dorian establishment of Messenia, and retire to Athens, where
their leader, Melanthus, becomes king: a large portion of them take part in the
subsequent Ionic emigration.
3. A portion of
the Achaeans, under Penthilus and other descendants
of Orestes, leave Peloponnesus, and form what is called the Eolic emigration,
to Lesbos, the Troad, and the Gulf of Adramyttium:
the name Eolians,
unknown to Homer, and seemingly never applied to any separate tribe at all,
being introduced to designate a large section of the Hellenic name, partly in
Greece Proper, and partly in Asia.
4. Another
portion of Achaeans expel the Ionians from Achaia, properly so called, in the
north of Peloponnesus; the Ionians retiring to Attica.
The Homeric
poems describe Achaeans, Pylians, and Epeians, in Peloponnesus, but take no notice of Ionians in
the northern district of Achaia: on the contrary, the Catalogue in the Iliad
distinctly includes this territory under the dominions of Agamemnon. Though the
Catalogue of Homer is not to be regarded as an historical document, fit to be
called as evidence for the actual state of Peloponnesus at any prior time, it
certainly seems a better authority than the statements advanced by Herodotus
and others respecting the occupation of northern Peloponnesus by the Ionians,
and their expulsion from it by Tisamenus. In so far as the Catalogue is to be
trusted, it negatives the idea of Ionians at Helike,
and countenances what seems in itself a more natural supposition—that the
historical Achaeans in the north part of Peloponnesus are a small undisturbed
remnant of the powerful Achaean population once distributed throughout the
peninsula, until it was broken up and partially expelled by the Dorians.
The Homeric
legends; unquestionably the oldest which we possess, are adapted to a
population of Achaeans, Danaeans, and Argeians, seemingly without any special and recognized
names, either aggregate or divisional, other than the name of each separate
tribe or kingdom. The post-Homeric legends are adapted to a population
classified quite differently—Hellens, distributed
into Dorians, Ionians, and Aeolians. If we knew more of the time and
circumstances in which these different legends grew up, we should probably be
able to explain their discrepancy; but in our present ignorance we can only
note the fact.
Whatever
difficulty modern criticism may find in regard to the event called “The Return
of the Herakleids”, no doubt is expressed about it
even by the best historians of antiquity. Thucydides accepts it as a single and
literal event, having its assignable date, and carrying at one blow the
acquisition of Peloponnesus. The date of it he fixes as eighty years after the
capture of Troy. Whether he was the original determiner of this epoch, or
copied it from some previous author, we do not know. It must have been fixed
according to some computation of generations, for there were no other means
accessible—probably by means of the lineage of the Herakleids,
which, as belonging to the kings of Sparta, constituted the most public and
conspicuous thread of connection between the Grecian real and mythical world,
and measured the interval between the Siege of Troy itself and the first
recorded Olympiad. Heracles himself represents the generation before the siege,
and his son Tlepolemus fights in the besieging army.
If we suppose the first generation after Heracles to commence with the
beginning of the siege, the fourth generation after him will coincide with the
ninetieth year after the same epoch; and therefore, deducting ten years for the
duration of the struggle, it will coincide with the eightieth year after the
capture of the city; thirty years being reckoned for a generation. The date
assigned by Thucydides will thus agree with the distance in which Temenus, Kresphontes, and Aristodemus, stand removed from Heracles.
The interval of eighty years, between the capture of Troy and the Return of the Herakleids, appears to have been admitted by
Apollodorus and Eratosthenes, and some other professed chronologists of
antiquity: but there were different reckonings which also found more or less of
support.
SECTION II.
MIGRATION OF
THESSALIANS AND BEOTIANS.
In the same
passage in which Thucydides speaks of the Return of the Herakleids,
he also marks out the date of another event a little antecedent, which is
alleged to have powerfully affected the condition of Northern Greece. “Sixty
years after the capture of Troy (he tells us) the Boeotians were driven by the
Thessalians from Arne, and migrated into the land then called Kadmeis, but now Boeotia, wherein there had previously
dwelt a section of their race, who had contributed the contingent to the Trojan
war”."
The expulsion
here mentioned, of the Boeotians from Arne “by the Thessalians”, has been
construed, with probability, to allude to the immigration of the Thessalians,
properly so called, from the Thesprotid in Epirus
into Thessaly. That the Thessalians had migrated into Thessaly from the Thesprotid territory, is stated by Herodotus, though he
says nothing about time or circumstances. Antiphus and Pheidippus appear in the Homeric Catalogue as
commanders of the Grecian contingent from the islands of Kos and Karpathus, on the south-east coast of Asia Minor: they are
sons of Thessalus, who is himself the son of
Heracles. A legend ran that these two chiefs, in the dispersion which ensued
after the victory, had been driven by storms into the Ionian Gulf, and cast
upon the coast of Epirus, where they landed and settled at Ephyre in the Thesprotid. It was Thessalus,
grandson of Pheidippus, who was reported to have
conducted the Thesprotians across the passes of
Pindus into Thessaly, to have conquered the fertile central plain of that
country, and to have imposed upon it his own name instead of its previous
denomination Aeolis.
Whatever we may
think of this legend as it stands, the state of Thessaly during the historical
ages renders it highly probable that the Thessalians, properly so called, were
a body of immigrant conquerors. They appear always as a rude, warlike, violent,
and uncivilized race, distinct from their neighbors the Achaeans, the Magnetes, and the Perrhaebians,
and holding all the three in tributary dependence: these three tribes stand to
them in a relation analogous to that of the Lacedoemonian Perioeki towards Sparta, while the Penestae, who cultivated their lands, are almost an exact
parallel of the Helots. Moreover, the low level of taste and intelligence among
the Thessalians, as well as certain points of their costume, assimilates them
more to Macedonians or Epirots than to Hellens. Their position in Thessaly is in many respects
analogous to that of the Spartan Dorians in Peloponnesus, and there seems good
reason for concluding that the former, as well as the latter, were originally
victorious invaders, though we cannot pretend to determine the time at which the
invasion took place. The great family of the Aleuads,
and probably other Thessalian families besides, were descendants of Heracles,
like the kings of Sparta.
There are no
similar historical grounds, in the case of the alleged migration of the
Boeotians from Thessaly to Boeotia, to justify a belief in the main fact of the
legend, nor were the different legendary stories in harmony one with the other.
While the Homeric Epic recognizes the Boeotians in Boeotia, but not in
Thessaly, Thucydides records a statement which he had found of their migration
from the latter into the former; but in order to escape the necessity of flatly
contradicting Homer, he inserts the parenthesis that there had been previously
an outlying fraction of Boeotians in Boeotia at the time of the Trojan war,
from whom the troops who served with Agamemnon were drawn. Nevertheless, the
discrepancy with the Iliad, though less strikingly obvious, is not removed,
inasmuch as the Catalogue is unusually copious in enumerating the contingents from
Thessaly, without once mentioning Boeotian. Homer distinguishes Orchomenus from
Boeotia, and be does not specially notice Thebes in the Catalogue: in other
respects his enumeration of the towns coincides pretty well with the ground
historically known afterwards under the name of Boeotia.
Pausanias gives
us a short sketch of the events which he supposes to have intervened in this
section of Greece between the Siege of Troy and the Return of the Herakleids. Peneleos, the leader of the Boeotians at the
siege, having been slain by Eurypylus the son of Telephus, Tisamenus, son of Thersander and grandson of Polynikes, acted as their commander,
both during the remainder of the siege and after their return. Autesion, his son and successor, became subject to the wrath
of the avenging Erinnyes of Laius and Edipus: the oracle directed him to expatriate, and he
joined the Dorians. In his place, Damasichthon, son
of Opheltas and grandson of Peneleos, became king of
the Boeotians: he was succeeded by Ptolemnus, who was
himself followed by Xanthus. A war having broken out at that time between the
Athenians and Boeotians, Xanthus engaged in single combat with Melanthus son of Andropompus, the champion of Attica, and perished by
the cunning of his opponent. After the death of Xanthus, the Boeotians passed
from kingship to popular government. As Melanthus was of the lineage of the Neleids, and had migrated from Pylus to Athens in consequence of the successful establishment of the Dorians in
Messenia, the duel with Xanthus must have been of course subsequent to the
Return of the Herakleids.
MIGRATION OF
BOEOTIANS FROM THESSALY.
Here, then, we
have a summary of alleged Boeotian history between the Siege of Troy and the
Return of the Herakleids, in which no mention is made
of the immigration of the mass of Boeotians from Thessaly, and seemingly no
possibility left of fitting in so great and capital an incident. The legends
followed by Pausanias are at variance with those adopted by Thucydides, but
they harmonize much better with Homer.
So deservedly
high is the authority of Thucydides, that the migration here distinctly
announced by him is commonly set down as an ascertained datum, historically as
well as chronologically. But on this occasion it can be shown that he only
followed one amongst a variety of discrepant legends, none of which there were
any means of verifying.
Pausanias
recognized a migration of the Boeotians from Thessaly, in early times anterior
to the Trojan war; and the account of Ephorus, as
given by Strabo, professed to record a series of changes in the occupants of
the country. First, the non-Hellenic Aones and Temmikes, Leleges and Hyantes; next, the Kadmeians,
who, after the second siege of Thebes by the Epigoni, were expelled by the
Thracians and Pelasgians, and retired into Thessaly, where they joined in
communion with the inhabitants of Arne— the whole aggregate being called
Boeotians. After the Trojan war, and about the time of the Eolic emigration,
these Boeotians returned from Thessaly and reconquered Boeotia, driving out the
Thracians and Pelasgians—the former retiring to Parnassus, the latter to
Attica. It was on this occasion (he says) that the Minyae of Orchomenus were subdued, and forcibly incorporated with the Boeotians. Ephorus seems to have followed, in the main, the same
narrative as Thucydides, about the movement of the Boeotians out of Thessaly;
coupling it, however, with several details current as explanatory of proverbs
and customs.
The only fact
which we make out, independent of these legends, is, that there existed certain
homonymies and certain affinities of religious worship, between parts of
Boeotia and parts of Thessaly, which appear to indicate a kindred race. A town
named Arne, similar in name to the Thessalian, was enumerated in the Boeotian
Catalogue of Homer, and antiquaries identified it sometimes with the historical
town Charroneia, sometimes with Akraephium.
Moreover, there was near the Boeotian Koroneia a
river named Kuarius, or Koralius,
and a venerable temple dedicated to the Itonian Athene, in the sacred ground of which the Pambeotia,
or public council of the Boeotian name, was held; there was also a temple and a
river of similar denomination in Thessaly, near to a town called Iton, or Itonus. We may from
these circumstances presume a certain ancient kindred between the population of
these regions, and such a circumstance is sufficient to explain the generation
of legends describing migrations backward and forward, whether true or not in
point of fact.
What is most
important to remark is, that the stories of Thucydides and Ephorus bring us out of the mythical into the historical Boeotia. Orchomenus is Boeotized, and we hear no more of the once-powerful Minyae: there are no more Kadmeians at Thebes, nor Beotians in Thessaly. The Minyaa and the Kadmeians disappear in the Ionic emigration, which will be presently adverted to.
Historical Beotia is now constituted, apparently in
its federative league, under the presidency of Thebes, just as we find it in
the time of the Persian and Peloponnesian wars.
SECTION III
EMIGRATIONS
FROM GREECE TO ASIA AND THE ISLANDS OF THE AEGEAN.
To complete the
transition of Greece from its mythical to its historical condition, the
secession of the races belonging to the former must follow upon the introduction
of those belonging to the latter. This is accomplished by means of the Eolic
and Ionic migrations.
The presiding
chiefs of the Aeolic emigration are the representatives of the heroic lineage
of the Pelopids: those of the Ionic emigration belong
to the Neleids; and even in what is called the Doric
emigration to Thera, the Ekist Theras is not a Dorian but a Kadmeian, the legitimate
descendant of Edipus and Kadmus.
The Aeolic,
Ionic, and Doric colonies were planted along the western coast of Asia Minor,
from the coasts of the Propontis southward down to
Lycia (I shall in a future chapter speak more exactly of their boundaries); the
Eolic occupying the northern portion, together with the islands of Lesbos and Tenedos; the Doric occupying the southernmost, together
with the neighboring islands of Rhodes and Kos; and the Ionic being planted
between them, comprehending Chios, Samos, and the Cyclades islands.
1. AEOLIC
EMIGRATION.
The Aeolic
emigration was conducted by the Pelopids: the
original story seems to have been, that Orestes himself was at the head of the
first batch of colonists, and this version of the event is still preserved by
Pindar and by Hellanikus. But the more current
narratives represented the descendants of Orestes as chiefs of the expeditions
to Aeolis—his illegitimate son Penthilus, by Erigone daughter of Egisthus,
together with Echelatus and Gras, the son and
grandson of Penthilus, together with Kleues and Malaus, descendants of
Agamemnon through another lineage. According to the account given by Strabo,
Orestes began the emigration, but died on his route in Arcadia; his son Penthilus, taking the guidance of the emigrants, conducted
them by the long land-journey through Boeotia and Thessaly to Thrace; from
whence Archelaus, son of Penthilus, led them across
the Hellespont, and settled at Daskylium on the Propontis. Gras, son of Archelaus, crossed over to Lesbos
and possessed himself of the island. Kleues and Malaus, conducting another body of Achaeans, were longer on
their journey, and lingered a considerable time near Mount Phrikium,
in the territory of Lokris; ultimately, however, they
passed over by sea to Asia and took possession of Kyme,
south of the Gulf of Adramyttium, the most
considerable of all the Aeolic cities on the continent. From Lesbos and Kyme, the other less considerable Aeolic towns, spreading
over the region of Ida as well as the Troad, and comprehending the island of Tenedas, are said to have derived their origin.
Though there
are many differences in the details, the accounts agree in representing these
Aeolic settlements as formed by the Achaeans expatriated from Laconia under the
guidance of the dispossessed Pelopids. We are told
that in their journey through Boeotia they received considerable
reinforcements, and Strabo adds that the emigrants started from Aulis, the port
from whence Agamemnon departed in the expedition against Troy. He also informs
us that they missed their course and experienced many losses from nautical
ignorance, but we do not know to what particular incidents he alludes.
2. IONIC
EMIGRATION.
The Ionic
emigration is described as emanating from and directed by the Athenians, and
connects itself with the previous legendary history of Athens, which must
therefore be here briefly recapitulated.
The great
mythical hero Theseus, of whose military prowess and errant exploits we have
spoken in a previous chapter, was still more memorable in the eyes of the
Athenians as an internal political reformer. He was supposed to have performed
for them the inestimable service of transforming Attica out of many states into
one. Each deme, or at least a great many out of the whole number, had before
his time enjoyed political independence under its own magistrates and
assemblies, acknowledging only a federal union with the rest under the
presidency of Athens: by a mixture of conciliation and force, Theseus succeeded
in putting down all these separate governments, and bringing them to unite in
one political system, centralized at Athens. He is said to have established a
constitutional government, retaining for himself a defined power as king, or
president, and distributing the people into three classes: Eupatridae, a sort
of sacerdotal noblesse; Geomori and Demiurgi, husbandmen and artisans. Having brought these important
changes into efficient working, he commemorated them for his posterity by
introducing solemn and appropriate festivals. In confirmation of the dominion
of Athens over the Megarid territory, he is said farther to have erected a
pillar at the extremity of the latter towards the Isthmus, marking the boundary
between Peloponnesus and Ionia.
But a
revolution so extensive was not consummated without creating much discontent;
and Menestheus, the rival of Theseus — the first
specimen, as we are told, of an artful demagogue—took advantage of this feeling
to assail and undermine him. Theseus had quitted Attica, to accompany and
assist his friend Peirithous, in his journey down to
the underworld, in order to carry off' the goddess Persephon,—or
(as those who were critical in legendary story preferred recounting) in a
journey to the residence of Aidoneus, king of the Molossians in Epirus, to carry off his daughter. In this
enterprise, Peirithous perished, while Theseus was
cast into prison, from whence he was only liberated by the intercession of
Heracles. It was during his temporary absence, that the Tyndarids Castor and Pollux invaded Attica for the purpose of recovering their
sister Helen, whom Theseus had at a former period taken away from Sparta and
deposited at Aphidnae; and the partisans of Menestheus took advantage both of the absence of Theseus
and of the calamity which his licentiousness had brought upon the country, to
ruin his popularity with the people. When he returned, be found them no longer
disposed to endure his dominion, or to continue to him the honors which their
previous feelings of gratitude had conferred. Having, therefore, placed his
sons under the protection of Elephenor, in Euboea, he
sought an asylum with Lykomedes, prince of Scyros,
from whom, however, he received nothing but an insidious welcome and a
traitorous death.
Menestheus, succeeding to the honors of the expatriated hero,
commanded the Athenian troops at the Siege of Troy. But though he survived the
capture, he never returned to Athens—different stories being related of the
place where he and his companions settled. During this interval, the feelings
of the Athenians having changed, they restored the sons of Theseus, who had
served at Troy under Elephenor, and had returned
unhurt, to the station and functions of their father. The Theseids Demophoon, Oxyntas, Apheidas, and Thymoetes had
successively filled this post for the space of about sixty years when the
Dorian invaders of Peloponnesus (as has been before related) compelled Melanthus
and the Neleid family to abandon their kingdom of Pylus. The refugees found shelter at Athens, where a
fortunate adventure soon raised Melanthus to the throne. A war breaking out
between the Athenians and Boeotians, respecting the boundary tract of Enoe, the Boeotian king Xanthus challenged Thymoetes to single combat: the latter declining to accept
it, Melanthus not only stood forward in his place, but practiced a cunning
stratagem with such success as to kill his adversary. He was forthwith chosen king, Thymoetes being constrained to resign .
Melanthus and
his son Kodrus reigned for nearly sixty years, during which time large bodies
of fugitives, escaping from the recent invaders throughout Greece, were
harbored by the Athenians: so that Attica became populous enough to excite the
alarm and jealousy of the Peloponnesian Dorians. A powerful Dorian force, under
the command of Aletes from Corinth and Althaemenes from Argos, were accordingly dispatched to
invade the Athenian territory, in which the Delphian oracle promised them success, provided they abstained from injuring the person
of Kodrus. Strict orders were given to the Dorian army that Kodrus should be
preserved unhurt; but the oracle had become known among the Athenians, and the
generous prince determined to bring death upon himself as a means of salvation
to his country. Assuming the disguise of a peasant, he intentionally provoked a
quarrel with some of the Dorian troops, who slew him without suspecting his
real character. No sooner was this event known, than the Dorian leaders,
despairing of success, abandoned their enterprise and evacuated the country. In
retiring, however, they retained possession of Megara, where they established
permanent settlers, and which became from this moment Dorian—seemingly at first
a dependency of Corinth, though it afterwards acquired its freedom and became
an autonomous community. This memorable act of devoted patriotism, analogous to
that of the daughters of Erechtheus at Athens, and of Menoekeus at Thebes, entitled Kodrus to be ranked
among the most splendid characters in Grecian legend.
Kodrus is
numbered as the last king of Athens: his descendants were styled Archons, but
they held that dignity for life—a practice which prevailed during a long course
of years afterwards. Medon and Neileus,
his two sons, having quarreled about the succession, the Delphian oracle decided in favor of the former; upon which the latter, affronted at the
preference, resolved upon seeking a new home. There were at this moment many
dispossessed sections of Greeks, and an adventitious population accumulated in
Attica, who were anxious for settlements beyond sea. The expeditions which now
set forth to cross the Aegean, chiefly under the conduct of members of the Kodrid family, composed collectively the memorable Ionic
Emigration, of which the Ionians, recently expelled from Peloponnesus, formed a
part, but, as it would seem, only a small part; for we hear of many quite
distinct races, some renowned in legend, who withdraw from Greece amidst this
assemblage of colonists. The Kadmeians, the Minyae of Orchomenus, the Abantes of Euboea, the Dryopes; the Molossi,
the Phokians, the Boeotians, the Arcadian Pelasgians,
and even the Dorians of Epidaurus — are represented as furnishing each a
proportion of the crews of these emigrant vessel. Nor were the results unworthy
of so mighty a confluence of different races. Not only the Cyclades islands in
the Aegean, but the great islands of Samos and Chios, near the Asiatic coast,
and ten different cities on the coast of Asia Minor, from Miletus in the south
to Phocaea in the north, were founded, and all adopted the Ionic name. Athens
was the metropolis or mother city of all of them: Androklus and Neileus, the Ekists of Ephesus and Miletus,
and probably other Ekists also, started from the Prytaneium at Athens, with
those solemnities, religions and political, which usually marked the departure
of a swarm of Grecian colonists.
Other mythical
families, besides the heroic lineage of Neleus and
Nestor, as represented by the sons of Kodrus, took a leading part in the
expedition. Herodotus mentions Lykian chiefs,
descendants from Glaukus son of Hippolochus,
and Pausanias tells us of Philotas descendant of
Peneleos, who went at the head of a body of Thebans: both Glaukus and Peneleos are commemorated in the Iliad. And it is a remarkable fact
mentioned by Pausanias (though we do not know on what authority), that the
inhabitants of Phocaea,— which was the northernmost city of Ionia on the
borders of Eolis, and one of the last founded —
consisting mostly of Phokian colonists under the
conduct of the Athenians Philogenes and Daemen, were not admitted into the Pan-Ionic Amphiktyony until they consented to choose for themselves
chiefs of the Kodrid family. Prokles,
the chief who conducted the Ionic emigrants from Epidaurus to Samos, was said
to be of the lineage of Ion, son of Xuthus.
Of the twelve
Ionic states constituting the Pan-Ionic Amphiktyony—some
of them among the greatest cities in Hellas —I shall say no more at present, as
I have to treat of them again when I come upon historical ground.
3. DORIC
EMIGRATIONS
The Aeolic and
Ionic emigrations are thus both presented to us as direct consequences of the
event called the Return of the Herakleids: and in
like manner the formation of the Dorian Hexapolis in
the south-western corner of Asia Minor: Kos, Cnidus, Halicarnassus, and Rhodes,
with its three separate cities, as well as the Dorian establishments in Krete, Melos, and Thera, are all
traced more or less directly to the same great revolution.
Thera, more especially, has its root in the legendary world. Its Ekist was Theras, a descendant of the heroic lineage of Edipus and Kadmus, and maternal
uncle of the young kings of Sparta, Eurysthenes and Prokles, during whose minority he had exercised the
regency. On their coming of age, his functions were at an end: but being unable
to endure a private station, he determined to put himself at the head of a body
of emigrants: many came forward to join him, and the expedition was farther
reinforced by a body of interlopers, belonging to the Minyae,
of whom the Lacedaemonians were anxious to get rid. These Minyae had arrived in Laconia, not long before, from the island of Lemnos,
out of which they had been expelled by the Pelasgian fugitives from Attica. They landed without asking permission, took up their
abode and began to “light their fires” on Mount Taygetus.
When the Lacedaemonians sent to ask who they were, and wherefore they had come,
the Minyae replied that they were sons of the
Argonauts who had landed at Lemnos, and that being
expelled from their own homes, they thought themselves entitled to solicit an
asylum in the territory of their fathers: they asked, withal, to be admitted to
share both the lands and the honors of the state. The Lacedaemonians granted
the request, chiefly on the ground of a common ancestry— their own great
heroes, the Tyndarids, having been enrolled in the crew of the Argo: the Minyae were then introduced as citizens into the tribes,
received lots of land, and began to intermarry with the preexisting families.
It was not long, however, before they became insolent: they demanded a share in
the kingdom (which was the venerated privilege of the Herakleids),
and so grossly misconducted themselves in other ways, that the Lacedaemonians
resolved to put them to death, and began by casting them into prison. While the Minyae were thus confined, their wives, Spartans by
birth, and many of them daughters of the principal men, solicited permission to
go in and see them: leave being granted, they made use of the interview to
change clothes with their husbands, who thus escaped and fled again to Mount Taygetus. The greater number of them quitted Laconia, and
marched to Triphylia, in the western regions of
Peloponnesus, from whence they expelled the Paroreatae and the Kaukones, and founded six towns of their own,
of which Lepreum was the chief. A certain proportion,
however, by permission of the Lacedaemonians, joined Theras,
and departed with him to the island of Kalliste, then
possessed by Phoenician inhabitants, who were descended from the kinsmen and
companions of Kadmus, and who had been left there by
that prince, when he came forth in search of Europa, eight generations
preceding. Arriving thus among men of kindred lineage with himself, Theras met with a fraternal reception, and the island
derived from him the name, under which it is historically known, of Thera.
Such is the
foundation-legend of Thera, believed both by the
Lacedaemonians and by the Theraeans, and interesting
as it brings before us, characteristically as well as vividly, the persons and
feelings of the mythical world — the Argonauts, with the Tyndarids as their
companions and Minyae as their children. In Lepreum, as in the other towns of Triphylia,
the descent from the Minyae of old seems to have been
believed in the historical times, and the mention of the river Minyeius in those regions by Homer tended to confirm it.
But people were not unanimous as to the legend by which that descent should be
made out; while some adopted the story just cited from Herodotus, others
imagined that Cloris, who had come from the Minyeian town of Orchomenus as the wife of Neleus to Pylus, had brought with
her a body of her countrymen.
These Minyae from Lemnos and Imbros appear again as portions of another narrative
respecting the settlement of the colony of Melos. It has already been
mentioned, that when the Herakleids and the Dorians
invaded Laconia, Philonomus, an Achean,
treacherously betrayed to them the country, for which he received as his
recompense the territory of Amyklae. He is said to
have peopled this territory by introducing detachments of Minyae;
from Lemnos and Imbros,
who, in the third generation after the return of the Herakleids,
became so discontented and mutinous, that the Lacedaemonians resolved to send
them out of the country as emigrants, under their chiefs Polis and Delphos.
Taking the direction of Crete, they stopped in their way to land a portion of
their colonists on the island of Melos, which remained throughout the
historical times a faithful and attached colony of Lacedaemon. On arriving in
Crete, they are said to have settled at the town of Gortyn.
We find, moreover, that other Dorian establishments, either from Lacedaemon or
Argos, were formed in Crete; and Lyktos in
particular, is noticed, not only as a colony of Sparta, but as distinguished
for the analogy of its laws and customs. It is even said that Crete,
immediately after the Trojan war, had been visited by the wrath of the gods,
and depopulated by famine and pestilence; and that, in the third generation
afterwards, so great was the influx of emigrants, the entire population of the
island was renewed, with the exception of the Eteokretes at Polichnae and Praesus.
There were
Dorians in Crete in the time of the Odyssey: Homer mentions different languages
and different races of men, Eteokretes, Kydones, Dorians, Achaeans, and Pelasgians, as all
coexisting in the island, which he describes to be populous and to contain
ninety cities. A legend given by Andron, based
seemingly upon the statement of Herodotus, that Dorus the son of Hellen had settled in Histiaeotis,
ascribed the first introduction of the three last races to Tektaphus son of Dorus—who had led forth from that country a
colony of Dorians, Achaeans, and Pelasgians, and had landed in Crete during the
reign of the indigenous king Kres. This story of Andron so exactly fits on to the Homeric Catalogue of
Cretan inhabitants, that we may reasonably presume it to have been designedly
arranged with reference to that Catalogue, so as to afford some plausible
account, consistently with the received legendary chronology, how there came to
be Dorians in Crete before the Trojan war— the Dorian colonies after the return
of the Herakleids being of course long posterior in
supposed order of time. To find a leader sufficiently early for his hypothesis, Andron ascends to the primitive Eponymus Dorus, to whose son Tektaphus he ascribes the introduction of a mixed colony of Dorians, Achaeans, and
Pelasgians into Crete: these are the exact three races enumerated in the
Odyssey, and the king Kres, whom Andron affirms to have been then reigning in the island, represents the Eteokretes and Kydenes in the
list of Homer. The story seems to have found favor among native Cretan
historians, as it doubtless serves to obviate what would otherwise be a
contradiction in the legendary chronology.
Another Dorian
emigration from Peloponnesus to Crete, which extended also to Rhodes and Kos,
is farther said to have been conducted by Althaemenes,
who had been one of the chiefs in the expedition against Attica, in which Krodus perished. This prince, a Herakleid,
and third in descent from Temenus, was induced to expatriate by a family
quarrel, and conducted a body of Dorian colonists from Argos first to Crete,
where some of them remained; but the greater number accompanied him to Rhodes,
in which island, after expelling the Karian possessors, he founded the three cities of Lindus, Ialysus, and Kamairus.
It is proper
here to add, that the legend of the Rhodian archaeologists respecting their ekist Althaemenes, who was worshipped in the island with heroic
honors, was something totally different from the preceding. Althaemenes was a Cretan, son of the king Katreus, and grandson
of Minos. An oracle predicted to him that he would one day kill his father:
eager to escape so terrible a destiny, he quitted Crete, and conducted a colony
to Rhodes, where the famous temple of the Atabyrian Zeus, on the lofty summit of Mount Atabyrum, was
ascribed to his foundation, built so as to command a view of Crete. He had been
settled on the island for some time, when his father Katreus,
anxious again to embrace his only son, followed him from Crete: he landed in
Rhodes during the night without being known, and a casual collision took place
between his attendants and the islanders. Althaeenes hastened to the shore to assist in repelling the supposed enemies, and in the
fray had the misfortune to kill his aged father.
Either the
emigrants who accompanied Althaeenes, or some other
Dorian colonists afterwards, are reported to have settled at Cnidus, Karpathos,
and Halicarnassus. To the last mentioned city, however, Anthes of Troezen is assigned as the ekist: the emigrants who
accompanied him were said to have belonged to the Dymanian tribe, one of the three tribes always found in a Doric state: and the city
seems to have been characterized as a colony sometimes of Troezen,
sometimes of Argos!
We thus have
the Aeolic, the Ionic, and the Doric colonial establishments in Asia, all
springing out of the legendary age, and all set forth as consequences, direct
or indirect, of what is called the Return of the Herakleids,
or the Dorian conquest of Peloponnesus. According to the received chronology,
they are succeeded by a period, supposed to comprise nearly three centuries,
which is almost an entire blank, before we reach authentic chronology and the
first recorded Olympiad,—and they thus form the concluding events of the
mythical world, out of which we now pass into historical Greece, such as it
stands at the last-mentioned epoch. It is by these migrations that the parts of
the Hellenic aggregate are distributed into the places which they occupy at the
dawn of historical daylight,—Dorians, Arcadians, Aetolo-Eleians,
and Achaeans, sharing Peloponnesus unequally . among them — Aeolians, Ionians,
and Dorians, settled both in the islands of the Aegean and the coast of Asia
Minor. The Return of the Herakleids, as well as the
three emigrations, Aeolic, Ionic, and Doric, present the legendary explanation,
suitable to the feelings and belief of the people, showing how Greece passed
from the heroic races who besieged Troy and Thebes, piloted the adventurous
Argo, and slew the monstrous boar of Kalydon - to the
historical races, differently named and classified, who furnished victors to
the Olympic and Pythian games.
A patient and
learned French writer, M. Raoul Rochette —who
construes all the events of the heroic age, generally speaking, as so much real
history, only making allowance for the mistakes and exaggerations of poets — is
greatly perplexed by the blank and interruption which this supposed continuous
series of history presents, from the Return of the Herakleids down to the beginning of the Olympiads. He cannot explain to himself so long a
period of absolute quiescence, after the important incidents and striking
adventures of the heroic age; and if there happened nothing worthy of record
during this long period—as he presumes, from the fact that nothing has been
transmitted—he concludes that this must have arisen from the state of suffering
and exhaustion in which previous wars and revolution had left the Greeks: a
long interval of complete inaction being required to heal such wounds.
Assuming M. Rochette’s view of the heroic ages to be correct, and
reasoning upon the supposition that the adventures ascribed to the Grecian
heroes are matters of historical reality, transmitted by tradition from a
period of time four centuries before the recorded Olympiads, and only
embellished by describing poets — the blank which he here dwells upon is, to
say the least of it, embarrassing and unaccountable. It is strange that the
stream of tradition, if it had once begun to flow, should (like several of the
rivers in Greece) be submerged for two or three centuries and then reappear.
But when we make what appears to me the proper distinction between legend and
history, it will be seen that a period of blank time between the two is
perfectly conformable to the conditions under which the former is generated. It
is not the immediate past, but a supposed remote past, which forms the suitable
atmosphere of mythical narrative—a past originally quite undetermined in
respect to distance from the present, as we see in the Iliad and Odyssey. And
even when we come down to the genealogical poets, who affect to give a certain
measure of bygone time, and a succession of persons as well as of events,
still, the names whom they most delight to honor and upon whose exploits they
chiefly expatiate, are those of the ancestral gods and heroes of the tribe and
their supposed contemporaries; ancestors separated by a long lineage from the
present hearer. The gods and heroes were conceived as removed from him by
several generations, and the legendary matter which was grouped around them
appeared only the more imposing when exhibited at a respectful distance, beyond
the days of father and grandfather, and of all known predecessors. The Odes of
Pindar strikingly illustrate this tendency. We thus see how it happened that, between
the times assigned to heroic adventure and those of historical record, there
existed an intermediate blank, filled with inglorious names; and how, amongst
the same society which cared not to remember proceedings of fathers and
grandfathers, there circulated much popular and accredited narrative respecting
real or supposed ancestors long past and gone. The obscure and barren centuries
which immediately precede the first recorded Olympiad, form the natural
separation between the legendary return of the Herakleids and the historical wars of Sparta against Messene— between the province of
legend, wherein matter of fact (if any there be) is so intimately combined with
its accompaniments of fiction, as to be undistinguishable without the aid of
extrinsic evidence,—and that of history where some matters of fact can be
ascertained, and where a sagacious criticism may be usefully employed in trying
to add to their number.
XVIII
APPLICATION OF CHRONOLOGY TO GRECIAN LEGEND.
I NEED not repeat, what has already
been sufficiently set forth in the preceding pages, that the mass of Grecian
incident anterior to 776 BC appears to me not reducible either to history or to
chronology, and that any chronological systems which may be applied to it must
be essentially uncertified and illusory. It was however chronologised in ancient times, and has continued to be so in modern; and the various schemes
employed for this purpose may be found stated and compared proposed in the
first volume (the last published) of Mr. Fynes Clinton’s Fasti Hellenici.
There were among the Greeks, and there still are among modern scholars,
important differences as to the dates of the principal events. Eratosthenes
dissented both from Herodotus and from Phanias and Callimachus, while Larcher and Raoul Rochette (who
follow Herodotus) stand opposed to O. Müller and to Mr. Clinton. That the
reader may have a general conception of the order in which these legendary
events were disposed, I transcribe from the Fasti Hellenici a double chronological table, in which
the dates are placed in series, from Phoroneus to the
Olympiad of Corcebus in BC 776 - in the first column
according to the system of Eratosthenes, in the second according to that of Kallimachus.
“The following table (says Mr.
Clinton) offers a summary view of the leading periods from Phoroneus to the Olympiad of Coroebus, and exhibits a double
series of dates, the one proceeding from the date of Eratosthenes, the other
from a date founded on the reduced calculations of Phanias and Callimachus,
which strike out fifty-six years from the amount of Eratosthenes. Phanias, as
we have seen, omitted fifty-five years between the Return and the registered
Olympiads; for so we may understand the account : Callimachus, fifty-six years
between the Olympiad in which Coroebus won. The first
column of this table exhibits the current years before and after the
fall of Troy : in the second column of dates the complete intervals are
expressed”.
Wherever chronology is possible,
researches such as those of Mr. Clinton, which have conduced so much to the
better understanding of the later times of Greece, deserve respectful
attention. But the ablest chronologist can accomplish nothing, unless he is
supplied with a certain basis of matters of fact, pure and distinguishable from
fiction, and authenticated by witnesses, both knowing the truth and willing to
declare it. Possessing this preliminary stock, he may reason from it to refute
distinct falsehoods and to correct partial mistakes : but if all the original
statements submitted to him contained truth (at least wherever there is truth),
in a sort of chemical combination with fiction, which he has no means of
decomposing, he is in the condition of one who tries to solve a problem without
data: he is first obliged to construct his own data, and from them to extract
his conclusions.
The statements of the epic poets,
our only original witnesses in this case, correspond to the description here
given. Whether the proportion of truth contained in them be smaller or greater,
it is at all events unassignable, and the constant
and intimate admixture of fiction is both indisputable in itself, and indeed
essential to the purpose and profession of those from whom the tales proceed.
Of such a character are all the deposing witnesses, even where their tales
agree; and it is out of a heap of such tales, not agreeing, but discrepant in a
thousand ways, and without a morsel of pure authenticated truth, that the
critic is called upon to draw out a methodical series of historical events adorned
with chronological dates.
If we could imagine a modern
critical scholar transported into Greece at the time of the Persian war endued
with his present habits of appreciating historical evidence, without sharing in
the religious or patriotic feelings of the country and invited to prepare, out
of the great body of Grecian epic which then existed, a History and Chronology
of Greece anterior to 776 BC, assigning reasons as well for what he admitted as
for what he rejected I feel persuaded that he would have judged the undertaking
to be little better than a process of guess-work. But the modern critic finds
that not only Pherekydes and Hellanikus, but also
Herodotus and Thucydides have either attempted the task or sanctioned the
belief that it was practicable, a matter not at all surprising, when we
consider both their narrow experience of historical evidence and the powerful
ascendency of religion and patriotism in predisposing them to antiquarian
belief, and he therefore accepts the problem as they have bequeathed it, adding
his own efforts to bring it to a satisfactory solution. Nevertheless, he not
only follows them with some degree of reserve and uneasiness, but even admits
important distinctions quite foreign to their habits of thought. Thucydides talks
of the deeds of Hellen and his sons with as much
confidence as we now speak of William the Conqueror; Mr. Clinton recognizes Hellen with his sons Dorus, Eolus
and Nuthus, as fictitious persons. Herodotus recites
the great heroic genealogies down from Kadmus and Danaus with a belief not less complete in the higher
members of the series than in the lower: but Mr. Clinton admits a radical
distinction in the evidence of events before and after the first recorded
Olympiad, or 776 BC, the first date in Grecian chronology which can be fixed
upon authentic evidence, the highest point to which Grecian chronology,
reckoning upward, can be carried. Of this important epoch in Grecian
development, the commencement of authentic chronological life, Herodotus and
Thucydides had no knowledge or took no account : the later chronologists, from
Timaeus downwards, noted it, and made it serve as the basis of their
chronological comparisons, so far as it went : but neither Eratosthenes nor
Apollodorus seems to have recognized (though Varro and Africanus did recognize) a marked difference in respect of certainty or authenticity
between the period before and the period after.
ERATOSTHENES THE FIRST OLYMPIAD.
In further illustration of Mr.
Clinton’s opinion that the first recorded Olympiad is the earliest date which
can be fixed upon authentic evidence, we have the following just remarks in
reference to the dissentient views of Eratosthenes, Phanias and Callimachus,
about the date of the Trojan war : “The chronology of Eratosthenes (he says),
founded on a careful comparison of circumstances, and approved by those to whom
the same stores of information were open, is entitled to our respect. But we
must remember that a conjectural date can never rise to the authority of
evidence; that what is accepted as a substitute for testimony, is not an
equivalent; witnesses only can prove a date, and in the want of these, the
knowledge of it is plainly beyond our reach. If, in the absence of a better
light, we seek for what is probable, we are not to forget the distinction
between conjecture and proof; between what is probable and what is certain. The
computation then of Eratosthenes for the war of Troy is open to inquiry; and if
we find it adverse to the opinions of many preceding writers, who fixed a lower
date, and adverse to the acknowledged length of generation in the most
authentic dynasties, we are allowed to follow other guides, who give us a lower
epoch”.
Here Mr. Clinton again plainly
acknowledges the want of evidence and the irremediable uncertainty of Grecian
chronology before the Olympiads. Now the reasonable conclusion from his
argument is, not simply that "the computation of Eratosthenes was open to
inquiry" (which few would be found to deny), but that both Eratosthenes and
Phanias had delivered positive opinions upon a point on which no sufficient
evidence was accessible, and therefore that neither the one nor the other was a
guide to be followed. Mr. Clinton does indeed speak of authentic dynasties
prior to the first recorded Olympiad, but if there be any such, reaching up
from that period to a supposed point coeval with or anterior to the war of Troy
I see no good reason for the marked distinction which he draws between
chronology before and chronology after the Olympiad of Koroebus,
or for the necessity which he feels of suspending his upward reckoning at the
last-mentioned epoch, and beginning a different process, called “a downward
reckoning”, from the higher epoch (supposed to be somehow ascertained without
any upward reckoning) of the first patriarch from whom such authentic dynasty
emanates. Herodotus and Thucydides might well, upon this supposition, ask of
Mr. Clinton, why he called upon them to alter their method of proceeding at the
year 776 BC, and why they might not be allowed to pursue their “upward
chronological reckoning” without interruption from Leonidas up to Danaus, or from Peisistratus up to Hellen and Deucalion, without any alteration in the point of view. Authentic dynasties
from the Olympiads, up to an epoch above the Trojan war, would enable us to
obtain chronological proof of the latter date, instead of being reduced (as Mr.
Clinton affirms that we are) to “conjecture” instead of proof.
The whole question, as to the value
of the reckoning from the Olympiads up to Phoroneus,
does in truth turn upon this one point : Are those genealogies which profess to
cover the space between the two authentic and trustworthy or not? Mr. Clinton
appears to feel that they are not so, when he admits the essential difference
in the character of the evidence, and the necessity of altering the method of
computation before and after the first recorded Olympiad : yet in his Preface
he labors to prove that they possess historical worth and are in the main
correctly set forth : moreover, that the fictitious persons, wherever any such
are intermingled, may be detected and eliminated. The evidences upon which he
relies, are 1. Inscriptions; 2. The early poets
CHRONOLOGICAL EVIDENCE OF
INSCRIPTIONS.
1. An inscription, being nothing but
a piece of writing on marble, carries evidentiary value under the same
conditions as a published writing on paper. If the inscriber reports a
contemporary fact which he had the means of knowing, and if there be no reason
to suspect misrepresentation, we believe this assertion : if, on the other
hand, he records facts belonging to a long period before his own time, his
authority counts for little, except in so far as we can verify and appreciate
his means of knowledge.
In estimating therefore the
probative force of any inscription, the first and most indispensable point is
to assure ourselves of its date. Amongst all the public registers and
inscriptions alluded to by Mr. Clinton, there is proved not one which can be
positively referred to a date anterior to 776 BC. The quoit of Iphitus, the public registers at Sparta, Corinth, and Elis,
the list of the priestesses of Juno at Argos are all of a date completely
uncertified. O. Müller does indeed agree with Mr. Clinton (though in my opinion
without any sufficient proof) in assigning the quoit of Iphitus to the age ascribed to that prince : and if we even grant thus much, we shall
have an inscription as old (adopting Mr. Clinton’s determination of the age of Iphitus) as 828 BC. But when Mr. Clinton quotes O. Müller
as admitting the registers of Sparta, Corinth, and Elis, it is right to add
that the latter does not profess to guarantee the authenticity of these
documents, or the age at which such registers began to be kept. It is not to be
doubted that there were registers of the kings of Sparta carrying them up to
Heracles, and of the kings of Elis from Oxylus to Iphitus : but the question is, at what time did these lists
begin to be kept continuously? This is a point which we have no means of
deciding, nor can we accept Mr. Clinton’s unsupported conjecture, when he tell
us “Perhaps these were begun to be written as early as BC 1048, the
probable time of the Dorian conquest”. Again he tells us “At Argos a register
was preserved of the priestesses of Juno, which might be more ancient
than the catalogues of the kings of Sparta or Corinth. That register, from
which Hellanikus composed his work, contained the
priestesses from the earliest times down to the age of Hellanikus himself ... But this catalogue might have been commenced as early as the
Trojan war itself, and even at a still earlier date”. Again, respecting the
inscriptions quoted by Herodotus from the temple of the Ismenian Apollo at Thebes, in which Amphitryo and Laodamas are named, Mr. Clinton says “They were ancient in
the time of Herodotus, which may perhaps carry them back 400 years
before his time : and in that case they might approach within 300 years
of Laodamas and within 400 years of the probable time
of Kadmus himself”. “It is granted (he adds in a
note) that these inscriptions were not genuine, that is, not of the date to
which they were assigned by Herodotus himself. But that they were ancient
cannot be doubted”, &c.
The time when Herodotus saw the
temple of the Ismenian Apollo at Thebes can hardly
have been earlier than 450 BC : reckoning upwards from hence to 776 BC, we have
an interval of 326 years : the inscriptions which Herodotus saw may well
therefore have been ancient, without being earlier than the first
recorded Olympiad. Mr. Clinton does indeed tell us that ancient “may
perhaps” be construed as 400 years earlier than Herodotus. But no careful
reader can permit himself to convert such bare possibility into a ground of
inference, and to make it available, in conjunction with other similar
possibilities before enumerated, for the purpose of showing that there really
existed inscriptions in Greece of a date anterior to 776 BC. Unless Mr. Clinton
can make out this, he can derive no benefit from inscriptions, in his attempt
to substantiate the reality of the mythical persons or of the mythical events.
The truth is that the Herakleid pedigree of the Spartan kings (as has been
observed in a former chapter) is only one out of the numerous divine and heroic
genealogies with which the Hellenic world abounded, a class of documents which
become historical evidence only so high in the descending series as the names
composing them are authenticated by contemporary, or nearly contemporary,
enrolment. At what period this enrolment began, we have no information. Two remarks
however may be made, in reference to any approximate guess as to the time when
actual registration commenced : First, that the number of names in the
pedigree, or the length of past time which it professes to embrace, affords no
presumption of any superior antiquity in the time of registration : Secondly,
that looking to the acknowledged paucity and rudeness of Grecian writing even
down to the 60th Olympiad (540 BC), and to the absence of the habit of writing,
as well as the low estimate of its value, which such a state of things argues,
the presumption is, that written enrolment of family genealogies did not
commence until a long time after 776 BC, and the obligation of proof falls upon
him who maintains that it commenced earlier. And this second remark is farther
borne out when we observe, that there is no registered list, except that of the
Olympic victors, which goes up even so high as 776 BC. The next list which O.
Müller and Mr. Clinton produce, is that of the Karneoniks or victors at the Karneian festival, which reaches
only up to 676 BC.
If Mr. Clinton then makes little out
of inscriptions to sustain his view of Grecian history and chronology anterior
to the recorded Olympiads, let us examine the inferences which he draws from
his other source of evidence the early poets. And here it will be found, First,
that in order to maintain the credibility of these witnesses, he lays down
positions respecting historical evidence both indefensible in themselves, and
especially inapplicable to the early times of Greece: Secondly, that his
reasoning is at the same time inconsistent inasmuch as it includes admissions,
which if properly understood and followed out, exhibit these very witnesses, as
habitually, indiscriminately, and unconsciously, mingling truth and fiction,
and therefore little fit to be believed upon their solitary and unsupported
testimony.
To take the second point first, he
says “The authority even of the genealogies has been called in question by many
able and learned persons, who reject Danaus, Kadmus, Hercules, Theseus, and many others, as fictitious
persons. It is evident that any fact would come from the hands of the poets
embellished with many fabulous additions: and fictitious genealogies were undoubtedly
composed. Because, however, some genealogies were fictitious, we are not
justified in concluding that all were fabulous ... In estimating then the
historical value of the genealogies transmitted by the early poets, we may take
a middle course; not rejecting them as wholly false, nor yet implicitly
receiving all as true. The genealogies contain many real persons, but
these are incorporated with many fictitious names. The fictions however
will have a basis of truth : the genealogical expression may be false, but the
connection which it describes is real. Even to those who reject the whole as
fabulous, the exhibition of the early times which is presented in this volume
may still be not unacceptable : because it is necessary to the right
understanding of antiquity that the opinions of the Greeks concerning their own
origin should be set before us, even if these are erroneous opinions, and that
their story should be told as they have told it themselves. The names preserved
by the ancient genealogies may be considered of three kinds; either they were
the name of a race or clan converted into the name of an individual, or they
were altogether fictitious, or lastly, they were real historical names”.
Enough has been said to show that
the witnesses upon whom Mr. Clinton relies blend truth and fiction habitually,
indiscriminately and unconsciously, even upon his own admission. Let us now
consider the positions which he lays down respecting historical evidence. He
says : “We may acknowledge as real persons all those whom there is no reason
for rejecting. The presumption is in favor of the early tradition, if no
argument can be brought to overthrow it. The persons may be considered real,
when the description of them is consonant with the state of the country at that
time, when no national prejudice or vanity could be concerned in inventing
them, when the tradition is consistent and general, when rival or hostile
tribes concur in the leading facts, when the acts ascribed to the person (divested
of their poetical ornament) enter into the political system of the age, or form
the basis of other transactions which fall within known historical times. Kadmus and Danaus appear to be
real persons; for it is conformable to the state of mankind, and perfectly
credible, that Phoenician and Egyptian adventurers, in the ages to which these
persons are ascribed, should have found their way to the coasts of Greece : and
the Greeks (as already observed) had no motive from any national vanity to
feign these settlements. Hercules was a real person. His acts were recorded by
those who were not friendly to the Dorians; by Achaeans and Aeolians and
Ionians, who had no vanity to gratify in celebrating the hero of a hostile and
rival people. His descendants in many branches remained in many states down to
the historical times. His son Tlepolemus and his
grandson and great-grandson Cleodaeus and Aristomachus are acknowledged (i.e. by O. Müller) to be
real persons : and there is no reason that can be assigned for receiving these,
which will not be equally valid for establishing the reality both of Hercules
and Hyllus. Above all, Hercules is authenticated by
the testimonies both of the Iliad and Odyssey”.
These positions appear to me
inconsistent with sound views of the conditions of historical testimony.
According to what is here laid down, we are bound to accept as real all the
persons mentioned by Homer, Arktinus, Lesches, the Hesiodic poets, Eumelus, Asius, &c., unless we can adduce some positive
ground in each particular case to prove the contrary. If this position be a
true one, the greater part of the history of England, from Brute the Trojan
down to Julius Caesar, ought at once to be admitted as valid and worthy of
credence. What Mr. Clinton here calls the early tradition, is in point
of fact the narrative of these early poets. The word tradition is an
equivocal word, and begs the whole question; for while in its obvious and
literal meaning it implies only something handed down, whether truth or fiction
it is tacitly understood to imply a tale descriptive of some real matter of
fact, taking its rise at the time when that fact happened, and originally
accurate, but corrupted by subsequent oral transmission. Understanding
therefore by Mr. Clinton's words early tradition, the tales of the old
poets, we shall find his position totally inadmissible that we are bound to
admit the persons or statements of Homer and Hesiod as real, unless where we
can produce reasons to the contrary. To allow this, would be to put them upon a
par with good contemporary witnesses; for no greater privilege can be claimed
in favor even of Thucydides, than the title of his testimony to be believed
unless where it can be contradicted on special grounds. The presumption in
favor of an asserting witness is either strong, or weak, or positively nothing,
according to the compound ratio of his means of knowledge, his moral and
intellectual habits, and his motive to speak the truth. Thus, for instance,
when Hesiod tells us that his father quitted the Eolic Kyme and came to Askra in Boeotia, we may fully believe
him; but when he describes to us the battles between the Olympic gods and the
Titans, or between Heracles and Kyknus, or when Homer
depicts the efforts of Hector, aided by Apollo, for the defense of Troy, and
the struggles of Achilles and Odysseus, with the assistance of Here and
Poseidon, for the destruction of that city, events professedly long past and
gone we cannot presume either of them to be in any way worthy of belief. It
cannot be shown that they possessed any means of knowledge, while it is certain
that they could have no motive to consider historical truth : their object was
to satisfy an uncritical appetite for narrative, and to interest the emotions
of their hearers. Mr. Clinton says, that “the persons may be considered real
when the description of them is consistent with the state of the country at
that time”. But he has forgotten, first, that we know nothing of the state of
the country except what these very poets tell us; next, that fictitious persons
may be just as consonant to the state of the country as real persons. While
therefore, on the one hand, we have no independent evidence either to affirm or
to deny that Achilles or Agamemnon are consistent with the state of Greece or Asia
Minor at a certain supposed date 1183 BC, so, on the other hand, even assuming
such consistency to be made out, this of itself would not prove them to be real
persons.
PLAUSIBLE FICTION.
Mr. Clinton’s reasoning altogether
overlooks the existence of plausible fiction, fictitious stories which
harmonize perfectly well with the general course of facts, and which are
distinguished from matters of fact not by any internal character, but by the
circumstance that matter of fact has some competent and well-informed witness
to authenticate it, either directly or through legitimate inference. Fiction
may be, and often is, extravagant and incredible; but it may also be plausible
and specious, and in that case there is nothing but the want of an attesting
certificate to distinguish it from truth. Now all the tests, which Mr. Clinton
proposes as guarantees of the reality of the Homeric persons, will be just as
well satisfied by plausible fiction as by actual matter of fact; the
plausibility of the fiction consists in its satisfying those and other similar
conditions. In most cases, the tales of the poets did fall in with the existing
current of feelings in their audience: “prejudice and vanity” are not the only
feelings, but doubtless prejudice and vanity were often appealed to, and it was
from such harmony of sentiment that they acquired their hold on men's belief.
Without any doubt the Iliad appealed most powerfully to the reverence for
ancestral gods and heroes among the Asiatic colonists who first heard it : the
temptation of putting forth an interesting tale is quite a sufficient stimulus
to the invention of the poet, and the plausibility of the tale a sufficient
passport to the belief of the hearers. Mr. Clinton talks of “consistent and
general tradition”. But that the tale of a poet, when once told with effect and
beauty, acquired general belief is no proof that it was founded on fact :
otherwise, what are we to say to the divine legends, and to the large portion
of the Homeric narrative which Mr. Clinton himself sets aside as untrue under
the designation of “poetical ornament”. When a mythical incident is recorded as
“forming the basis” of some known historical fact or institution as for
instance the successful stratagem by which Melanthus killed Xanthus in the battle on the boundary, as recounted in my last chapter,
we may adopt one of two views : we may either treat the incident as real, and
as having actually given occasion to what is described as its effect or we may
treat the incident as a legend imagined in order to assign some plausible
origin of the reality.
In cases where the legendary
incident is referred to a time long anterior to any records as it commonly is
the second mode of proceeding appears to me far more consonant to reason and
probability than the first. It is to be recollected that all the persons and
facts, here defended as matter of real history by Mr. Clinton, are referred to
an age long preceding the first beginning of records.
I have already remarked that Mr.
Clinton shrinks from his own rule in treating Kadmus and Danaus as real persons, since they are as much
eponyms of tribes or races as Dorus and Hellen. And if he can admit Herakles to be a real man, I do not see upon what reason he can consistently disallow
any one of the mythical personages, for there is not one whose exploits are
more strikingly at variance with the standard of historical probability. Mr.
Clinton reasons upon the supposition that “Hercules was a Dorian hero”: but he
was Achaean and Kadmeian as well as Dorian, though the
legends respecting him are different in all the three characters. Whether his
son Tlepolemus and his grandson Kleodaeus belong to the category of historical men, I will not take upon me to say,
though O. Müller (in my opinion without any warranty) appears to admit it; but Hyllus certainly is not a real man, if the canon of Mr.
Clinton himself respecting the eponyms is to be trusted. “The descendants of
Hercules (observes Mr. Clinton) remained in many states down to the historical
times”. So did those of Zeus and Apollo, and of that god whom the historian
Hekataeus recognized as his progenitor in the sixteenth generation : the
titular kings of Ephesus, in the historical times, as well as Peisistratus, the
despot of Athens, traced their origin up to Eolus and Hellen,
yet Mr. Clinton does not hesitate to reject Eolus and Hellen as fictitious persons. I dispute the propriety of quoting the Iliad and Odyssey
(as Mr. Clinton does) in evidence of the historic personality of Hercules. For
even with regard to the ordinary men who figure in those poems, we have no
means of discriminating the real from the fictitious; while the Homeric
Heracles is unquestionably more than an ordinary man, he is the favorite son of
Zeus, from his birth predestined to a life of labor and servitude, as
preparation for a glorious immortality. Without doubt the poet himself believed
in the reality of Hercules, but it was a reality clothed with superhuman
attributes.
Mr. Clinton observes that “because
some genealogies were fictitious, we are not justified in concluding that all
were fabulous”. It is no way necessary that we should maintain so extensive a
position : it is sufficient that all are fabulous so far as concerns from what
gods and heroes, some fabulous throughout, and none ascertainably true, for the
period anterior to the recorded Olympiads. How much, or what particular
portions, may be true, no one can pronounce. The gods and heroes are, from our
point of view, essentially fictitious; but from the Grecian point of view they
were the most real (if the expression may be permitted, i.e. clung to with the
strongest faith) of all the members of the series. They not only formed parts
of the genealogy as originally conceived, but were in themselves the grand
reason why it was conceived, as a golden chain to connect the living man with a
divine ancestor. The genealogy therefore taken as a whole (and its value
consists in its being taken as a whole) was from the beginning a fiction; but
the names of the father and grandfather of the living man, in whose day it
first came forth, were doubtless those of real men. Wherever therefore we can
verify the date of a genealogy, as applied to some living person, we may
reasonably presume the two lowest members of it to be also those of real
persons : but this has no application to the time anterior to the Olympiads
still less to the pretended times of the Trojan war, the Kalydonian boar-hunt, or the deluge of Deucalion. To reason (as Mr. Clinton does),
“Because Aristomachus was a real man, therefore his
father Cleodaeus, his grandfather Hyllus,
and so farther upwards, &c., must have been real men”, is an inadmissible
conclusion. The historian Hekataeus was a real man, and doubtless his father Hegesander also but it would be unsafe to march up his
genealogical ladder fifteen steps to the presence of the ancestorial god of whom he boasted : the upper steps of the ladder will be found broken and
unreal. Not to mention that the inference, from real son to real father, is
inconsistent with the admissions in Mr. Clinton's own genealogical tables; for
he there inserts the names of several mythical fathers as having begotten real
historical sons.
The general authority of Mr.
Clinton's book, and the sincere respect which I entertain for his elucidations
of the later chronology, have imposed upon me the duty of assigning those
grounds on which I dissent from his conclusions prior to the first recorded
Olympiad. The reader who desires to see the numerous and contradictory guesses
(they deserve no better name) of the Greeks themselves in the attempt to chronologise their mythical narratives, will find them in
the copious notes annexed to the first half of his first volume. As I consider
all such researches not merely as fruitless in regard to any trustworthy
result, but as serving to divert attention from the genuine form and really
illustrative character of Grecian legend, I have not thought it right to go
over the same ground in the present work. Differing as I do, however, from Mr.
Clinton's views on this subject, I concur with him in deprecating the
application of etymology as a general scheme of explanation to the characters
and events of Greek legend. Amongst the many causes which operated as suggestives and stimulants to Greek fancy in the creation
of these interesting tales, doubtless Etymology has had its share; but it
cannot be applied (as Hermann, above all others, has sought to apply it) for
the purpose of imparting supposed sense and system to the general body of
mythical narrative. I have already remarked on this topic in a former chapter.
It would be curious to ascertain at
what time, or by whom, the earliest continuous genealogies, connecting existing
persons with the supposed antecedent age of legend, were formed and preserved.
Neither Homer nor Hesiod mentioned any verifiable present persons or
circumstances : had they done so, the age of one or other of them could have
been determined upon good evidence, which we methodize the past, even though
they do so on fictitious principles, being as yet unprovided with those records which alone could put them on a better course. The Homeric
man was satisfied with feeling, imagining, and believing, particular incidents
of a supposed past, without any attempt to graduate the line of connection
between them and himself: to introduce fictitious hypotheses and media of
connection is the business of a succeeding age, when the stimulus of rational
curiosity is first felt, without any authentic materials to supply it. We have
then the form of history operating upon the matter of legend the
transition-state between legend and history; less interesting indeed than
either separately, yet accessory as a step between the two.
Years before the Fall of Troy. | BC Eratosthenes | BC Chalimachus | |
570 | Phoroneus | 1753 | 1697 |
283 | Danaus | 1466 | 1410 |
Pelasgus | |||
250 | Deukalion | 1433 | 1377 |
200 | Erechteus | 1383 | 1327 |
Dardanaus | |||
150 | Azan, Aphidas, Elatus | 1333 | 1277 |
130 | Kadmus | 1313 | 1257 |
100 | Pelops | 1283 | 1227 |
78 | Birth of Hercules | 1261 | 1205 |
42 | Argonauts | 1225 | 1169 |
30 | First Theban War | 1213 | 1157 |
26 | Death of Hercules | 1209 | 1153 |
24 | Death of Euristheus | 1207 | 1151 |
20 | Death of Hyllus | 1203 | 1147 |
18 | Accession of Agamemnon | 1200 | 1144 |
16 | Second Theban War | 1198 | 1142 |
10 | Trojan expedition | 1192 | 1136 |
Years after the Fall of Troy | |||
Troy taken | 1183 | 1127 | |
8 | Orestes reign at Argos | 1176 | 1120 |
60 | The Thesali occupy Thesaly | 1124 | 1068 |
The Boeoti return to Boeotia | |||
Eolic migration under Penthilus | |||
80 | Return of the Heracleids | 1104 | 1048 |
109 | Eletes reigns at Corinth | 1075 | 1019 |
110 | Migration of Theras | 1074 | 1018 |
130 | Lesbos occupied | 1053 | 997 |
139 | Death of Codrus | 1045 | 989 |
140 | Ionic migration | 1044 | 988 |
151 | Cyme founded | 1033 | 977 |
169 | Smyrna | 1015 | 959 |
300 | Olympiad of Iphitus | 884 | 828 |
352 | Olimpiad of Coroebus | 776 | 776 |
XIX.
STATE OF SOCIETY AND MANNERS AS EXHIBITED IN GRECIAN LEGEND.
THOUGH the particular persons and events,
chronicled in the legendary poems of Greece, are not to be regarded as
belonging to the province of real history, those poems are, nevertheless, full
of instruction as pictures of life and manners; and the very same
circumstances, which divest their composers of all credibility as historians,
render them so much the more valuable as unconscious expositors of their own
contemporary society. While professedly describing an uncertified past, their
combinations are involuntarily borrowed from the surrounding present: for among
communities, such as those of the primitive Greeks, without books, without
means of extended travel, without acquaintance with foreign languages and
habits, the imagination, even of highly gifted men, was naturally enslaved by
the circumstances around them to a far greater degree than in the later days of
Solon or Herodotus; insomuch that the characters which they conceived and the
scenes which they described would for that reason bear a stronger generic
resemblance to the realities of their own time and locality. Nor was the poetry
of that age addressed to lettered and critical authors, watchful to detect
plagiarism, sated with simple imagery, and requiring something of novelty or
peculiarity in every fresh production. To captivate their emotions, it was
sufficient to depict, with genius and fervor, the more obvious manifestations
of human adventure or suffering, and to idealize that type of society, both
private and public, with which the hearers around were familiar. Even in describing
the gods, where a great degree of latitude and deviation might have been
expected, we see that Homer introduces into Olympus the passions, the caprices,
the love of power and patronage, the alternation of dignity and weakness, which
animated the bosom of an ordinary Grecian chief; and this tendency, to
reproduce in substance the social relations to which he had been accustomed,
would operate still more powerfully when he had to describe simply human
characters,—the chief and his people, the warrior and his comrades, the
husband, wife, father, and son,—or the imperfect rudiments of judicial and
administrative proceeding. That his narrative on all these points, even with
fictitious characters and events, presents a close approximation to general
reality, there can be no reason to doubt. The necessity under which he lay of
drawing from a store, then happily unexhausted, of personal experience and
observation, is one of the causes of that freshness and vivacity of description
for which he stands unrivalled, and which constituted the imperishable charm of
the Iliad and Odyssey from the beginning to the end of Grecian literature.
While, therefore, we renounce the
idea of chronologizing or historicizing the events of
Grecian legend, we may turn them to profit as valuable memorials of that state
of society, feeling, and intelligence, which must be to us the starting-point
of the history of the people. Of course, the legendary age, like all those
which succeeded it, had its antecedent causes and determining conditions; but
of these we know nothing, and we are compelled to assume it as a primary fact,
for the purpose of following out its subsequent changes. To conceive absolute
beginning or origin (as Niebuhr has justly remarked) is beyond the reach of our
faculties: we can neither apprehend nor verify anything beyond progress, or
development, or decay,—change from one set of circumstances to another,
operated by some definite combination of physical or moral laws. In the case of
the Greeks, the legendary age, as the earliest in any way known to us, must be
taken as the initial state from which this series of changes commences. We must
depict its prominent characteristics as well as we can, and show,—partly how it
serves to prepare, partly how it forms a contrast to set off,— the subsequent
ages of Solon, of Pericles, and of Demosthenes.
POLITICAL SOCIETY.
1. The political condition, which
Grecian legend everywhere presents to us, is in its principal features
strikingly different from that which had become universally prevalent among the
Greeks in the time of the Peloponnesian war. Historical oligarchy, as well as
democracy, agreed in requiring a certain established system of government,
comprising the three elements of specialized functions, temporary functionaries,
and ultimate responsibility (under some forms or other) to the mass of
qualified citizens— either a Senate or an Ecclesia, or both. There were, of
course, many and capital distinctions between one government and another, in
respect to the qualification of the citizen, the attributes and efficiency of
the general assembly, the admissibility to power, etc.; and men might often be
dissatisfied with the way in which these questions were determined in their own
city. But in the mind of every man, some determining rule or system—something
like what in modern times is called a constitution—was
indispensable to any government entitled to be called legitimate, or capable of
creating in the mind of a Greek a feeling of moral obligation to obey it. The
functionaries who exercised authority under it might be more or less competent
or popular; but his personal feelings towards them were commonly lost in his
attachment or aversion to the general system. If any energetic man could by
audacity or craft break down the constitution, and render himself permanent
ruler according to his own will and pleasure,—even though he might govern well,
he could never inspire the people with any sentiment of duty towards him. His
scepter was illegitimate from the beginning, and even the taking of his life,
far from being interdicted by that moral feeling which condemned the shedding
of blood in other cases, was considered meritorious. Nor could he be mentioned
in the language except by a name (despot) which branded him as an object of
mingled fear and dislike.
If we carry our eyes back from
historical to legendary Greece, we find a picture the reverse of what has been
here sketched. We discern a government in which there is little or no scheme or
system,—still less any idea of responsibility to the governed,—but in which the
mainspring of obedience on the part of the people consists in their personal
feeling and reverence towards the chief. We remark, first and foremost, the
king; next, a limited number of subordinate kings or chiefs; afterwards, the
mass of armed freemen, husbandmen, artisans, freebooters, etc.; lowest of all,
the free laborers for hire, and the bought slaves. The king is not
distinguished by any broad or impassable boundary from the other chiefs, to
each of whom the title basileus is applicable as well as to himself: his supremacy has been inherited from his
ancestors, and passes by descent, as a general rule, to his eldest son, having
been conferred upon the family as a privilege by the favor of Zeus. In war, he
is the leader, foremost in personal prowess, and directing all military
movements; in peace, he is the general protector of the injured and oppressed;
he farther offers up those public prayers and sacrifices which are intended to
obtain for the whole people the favor of the gods. An ample domain is assigned
to him as an appurtenance of his lofty position, while the produce of his
fields and his cattle is consecrated in part to an abundant, though rude
hospitality. Moreover, he receives frequent presents, to avert his enmity, to
conciliate his favor, or to buy off his exactions; and when plunder is taken
from the enemy, a large previous share, comprising probably the most alluring
female captive, is reserved for him, apart from the general distribution.
Such is the position of the king, in
the heroic times of Greece,—the only person (if we except the heralds and
priests, each both special and subordinate,) who is then presented to us as
clothed with any individual authority,—the person by whom all the executive
functions, then few in number, which the society requires, are either performed
or directed. His personal ascendency—derived from divine countenance, bestowed
both upon himself individually and upon his race, and probably from accredited
divine descent—is the salient feature in the picture. The people hearken to his
voice, embrace his propositions, and obey his orders: not merely resistance,
but even criticism upon his acts, is generally exhibited in an odious point of
view, and is, indeed, never heard of except from some one or more of the
subordinate princes. To keep alive and justify such feelings in the public
mind, however, the king must himself possess various accomplishments, bodily
and mental, and that too in a superior degree. He must be brave in the field, wise
in the council, and eloquent in the agora; he must be endued with bodily
strength and activity above other men, and must be an adept, not only in the
use of his arms, but also in those athletic exercises which the crowd delight
to witness. Even the more homely varieties of manual acquirements are an
addition to his character,—such as the craft of the carpenter or shipwright,
the straight furrowing of the ploughman, or the indefatigable persistence of
the mower without repose or refreshment throughout the longest day. The
conditions of voluntary obedience, during the Grecian heroic times, are family
descent with personal force and superiority mental as well as bodily, in the
chief, coupled with the favor of the gods: an old chief, such as Peleus and Laertes,
cannot retain his position. But, on the other hand, where these elements of
force are present, a good deal of violence, caprice, and rapacity is tolerated:
the ethical judgment is not exact in scrutinizing the conduct of individuals so
preeminently endowed. As in the ease of the gods, the general epithets of good, just, etc., are applied to them as euphemisms arising from
submission and fear, being not only not suggested, but often pointedly belied,
by their particular acts. These words signify the man of birth, wealth,
influence, and daring, whose arm is strong to destroy or to protect, whatever
may be the turn of his moral sentiments; while the opposite epithet, bad, designates the poor, lowly, and
weak; from whose dispositions, be they ever so virtuous, society has little
either to hope or, to fear.
Aristotle, in his general theory of
government, lays down the position, that the earliest sources of obedience and
authority among mankind are personal, exhibiting themselves most perfectly in
the type of paternal supremacy; and that therefore the kingly government, as
most conformable to this stage of social sentiment, became probably the first
established everywhere. And in fact it still continued in his time to be
generally prevalent among the non-Hellenic nations, immediately around; though
the Phoenician cities and Carthage, the most civilized of all non-Hellenic
states, were republics. Nevertheless, so completely were the feelings about
kingship reversed among his contemporary Greeks, that he finds it difficult to
enter into the voluntary obedience paid by his ancestors to their early heroic
chiefs. He cannot explain to his own satisfaction how any one man should have
been so much superior to the companions around him as to maintain such immense
personal ascendency: he suspects that in such small communities great merit was
very rare, so that the chief had few competitors. Such remarks illustrate
strongly the revolution which the Greek mind had undergone during the preceding
centuries, in regard to the internal grounds of political submission But the
connecting link, between the Homeric and the republican schemes of government,
is to be found in two adjuncts of the Homeric royalty, which are now to be
mentioned,—the boulê,
or council of chiefs, and the agora,
or general assembly of freemen.
These two meetings, more or less
frequently convoked, and interwoven with the earliest habits of the primitive
Grecian communities, are exhibited in the monuments of the legendary age as
opportunities for advising the king, and media for promulgating his intentions
to the people, rather than as restraints upon his authority. Unquestionably,
they must have led in practice to the latter result as well as to the former;
but this is not the light in which the Homeric poems describe them. The chiefs,
kings, princes, or gerontes—for
the same word in Greek designates both an old man and a man of conspicuous rank
and position—compose the council, in which, according to the representations in
the Iliad, the resolutions of Agamemnon on the one side, and of Hector on the
other, appear uniformly to prevail. The harshness and even contempt with which
Hector treats respectful opposition from his ancient companion Polydamas,—the desponding tone and conscious inferiority of
the latter, and the unanimous assent which the former obtains, even when quite
in the wrong—all this is clearly set forth in the poem: while in the Grecian
camp we see Nestor tendering his advice in the most submissive and delicate
manner to Agamemnon, to be adopted or rejected, as “the king of men” might
determine. The council is a purely consultative body, assembled, not with any
power of peremptorily arresting mischievous resolves of the king, but solely
for his information and guidance. He himself is the presiding (boulephorus, or)
member of council; the rest, collectively as well as individually, are his
subordinates.
AGORA IN ITHAKA.
We proceed from the council to the
agora: according to what seems the received custom, the king, after having
talked over his intentions with the former, proceeds to announce them to the
people. The heralds make the crowd sit down in order, and enforce silence: any
one of the chiefs or councilors —but as it seems, no one else—is allowed to address
them: the king first promulgates his intentions, which are then open to be
commented upon by others. But in the Homeric agora, no division of affirmative
or negative voices ever takes place, nor is any formal resolution ever adopted.
The nullity of positive function strikes us even more in the agora than in the
council. It is an assembly for talk, communication, and discussion, to a
certain extent, by the chiefs, in presence of the people as listeners and
sympathizers,— often for eloquence, and sometimes for quarrel,—but here its
ostensible purposes end.
The agora in Ithaca, in the second
book of the Odyssey, is convened by the youthful Telemachus, at the instigation
of Athene, not for the purpose of submitting any proposition, but in order to
give formal and public notice to the suitors to desist from their iniquitous
intrusion and pillage of his substance, and to absolve himself farther, before
godsend men, from all obligations towards them, if they refuse to comply. For
the slaughter of the suitors, in all the security of the festive hall and
banquet (which forms the catastrophe of the Odyssey), was a proceeding
involving much that was shocking to Grecian feeling, and therefore required to
be preceded by such ample formalities, as would leave both the delinquents
themselves without the shadow of excuse, and their surviving relatives without
any claim to the customary satisfaction. For this special purpose, Telemachus
directs the heralds to summon an agora: but what seems most of all surprising
is, that none had ever been summoned or held since the departure of Odysseus
himself,—an interval of twenty years. “No agora or session has taken place
amongst us (says the gray-headed Aegyptius, who opens
the proceedings) since Odysseus went on shipboard; and now, who is he that has
called us together? what man, young or old, has felt such a strong necessity?
Has he received intelligence from our absent warriors, or has he other public news to communicate? He is our good friend
for doing this : whatever his projects may be, I pray Zeus to grant him
success”. Telemachus, answering the appeal forthwith, proceeds to tell the
assembled Ithacans that he has no public news to communicate, but that he has
convoked them upon his own private necessities. Next, he sets forth,
pathetically, the wickedness of the suitors, calls upon them personally to
desist, and upon the people to restrain them, and concludes by solemnly warning
them, that, being henceforward free from all obligation towards them, he will
invoke the avenging aid of Zeus, so “that they may be slain in the interior of
his own house, without bringing upon him any subsequent penalty”.
We are not of course to construe the
Homeric description as anything more than an idéal, approximating to actual
reality. But, allowing all that can be required for such a limitation, it
exhibits the agora more as a special medium of publicity and
intercommunication, from the king to the body of the people, than as including
any idea of responsibility on the part of the former or restraining force on
the part of the latter, however such consequences may indirectly grow out of
it. The primitive Grecian government is essentially monarchical, reposing on
personal feeling and divine right: the memorable dictum in the Iliad is borne
out by all that we hear of the actual practice: “The ruler of many is not a
good thing : let us have one ruler only,— one king,—him to whom Zeus has given
the scepter and the tutelary sanctions”.
The second book of the Iliad, full
as it is of beauty and vivacity, not only confirms our idea of the passive,
recipient, and listening character of the agora, but even presents a repulsive
picture of the degradation of the mass of the people before the chiefs.
Agamemnon convokes the agora for the purpose of immediately arming the Grecian
host, under a full impression that the gods have at last determined forthwith
to crown his arms with complete victory. Such impression has been created by a
special visit of Oneirus (the Dream-god), sent by Zeus during his sleep,—being,
indeed, an intentional fraud on the part of Zeus, though Agamemnon does not
suspect its deceitful character. At this precise moment, when he may be
conceived to be more than usually anxious to get his army into the field and
snatch the prize, an unaccountable fancy seizes him, that, instead of inviting
the troops to do what he really wishes, and encouraging their spirits for this
one last effort, he will adopt a course directly contrary: he will try their
courage by professing to believe that the siege had become desperate, and that
there was no choice except to go on shipboard and flee. Announcing to Nestor
and Odysseus, in preliminary council, his intention to hold this strange
language, he at the same time tells them that he relies upon them to oppose it
and counterwork its effect upon the multitude. The agora is presently
assembled, and the king of men pours forth a speech full of dismay and despair,
concluding by a distinct exhortation to all present to go aboard and return
home at once. Immediately the whole army, chiefs as well as people, break up
and proceed to execute his orders: every one rushes off to get his ship afloat,
except Odysseus, who looks on in mournful silence and astonishment. The army
would have been quickly on its voyage home, had not the goddesses Here and
Athene stimulated Odysseus to an instantaneous interference. He hastens among
the dispersing crowd and diverts them from their purpose of retreat: to the
chiefs he addresses flattering words, trying to shame them by gentle expostulation:
but the people he visits with harsh reprimand and blows from his scepter, thus
driving them back to their seats in the agora.
ODYSSEUS AND THERSITES.
Amidst the dissatisfied crowd thus
unwillingly brought back, the voice of Thersites is heard the longest and the
loudest,—a man ugly, deformed, and unwarlike, but fluent in speech, and
especially severe and unsparing in his censure of the chiefs, Agamemnon,
Achilles, and Odysseus. Upon this occasion, he addresses to the people a speech
denouncing Agamemnon for selfish and greedy exaction generally, but
particularly for his recent ill-treatment of Achilles,—and he endeavors,
moreover, to induce them to persist in their scheme of departure. In reply,
Odysseus not only rebukes Thersites sharply for his impudence in abusing the
commander-in-chief, but threatens that, if ever such behavior is repeated, he
will strip him naked, and thrash him out of the assembly with disgraceful
blows; as an earnest of which, he administers to him at once a smart stroke
with the studded scepter, imprinting its painful mark in a bloody weal across
his back. Thersites, terrified and subdued, sits down weeping; while the
surrounding crowd deride him, and express the warmest approbation of Odysseus
for having thus by force put the reviler to silence.
Both Odysseus and Nestor then
address the agora, sympathizing with Agamemnon for the shame which the retreat
of the Greeks is about to inflict upon him, and urging emphatically upon every
one present the obligation of persevering until the siege shall he successfully
consummated. Neither of them animadverts at all upon Agamemnon, either for his
conduct towards Achilles, or for his childish freak of trying the temper of the
army.
There cannot be a clearer indication
than this description—so graphic in the original poem—of the true character of
the Homeric agora. The multitude who compose it are listening and acquiescent,
not often hesitating, and never refractory to the chief: The fate which awaits
a presumptuous critic, even where his virulent reproaches are substantially
well-founded, is plainly set forth in the treatment of Thersites; while the
unpopularity of such a character is attested even more by the excessive pains
which Homer takes to heap upon him repulsive personal deformities, than by the
chastisement of Odysseus;—he is lame, bald, crook-backed, of misshapen head,
and squinting vision.
But we cease to wonder at the
submissive character of the agora, when we read the proceedings of Odysseus
towards the people themselves;—his fine words and flattery addressed to the
chiefs, and his contemptuous reproof and manual violence towards the common
men, at a moment when both were doing exactly the same thing,—fulfilling the
express bidding of Agamemnon, upon whom Odysseus does not offer a single
comment. This scene, which excited a sentiment of strong displeasure among the
democrats of histories: Athens, affords a proof that the feeling of personal
dignity, of which philosophic observers in Greece—Herodotus, Xenophon,
Hippocrates, and Aristotle—boasted, as distinguishing the free Greek citizen
from the slavish Asiatic, was yet undeveloped in the time of Homer. The ancient
epic is commonly so filled with the personal adventures of the chiefs, and the
people are so constantly depicted as simple appendages attached to them, that
we rarely obtain a glimpse of the treatment of the one apart from the other,
such as this memorable Homeric agora affords.
JUDICIAL ATTRIBUTES OF THE AGORA.
There remains one other point of
view in which we are to regard the agora of primitive Greece,—as the scene in
which justice was administered. The king is spoken of as constituted by Zeus
the great judge of society: he has received from Zeus the scepter, and along
with it the powers of command and sanction: the people obey these commands and
enforce these sanctions, under him, enriching him at the same time with
lucrative presents and payments. Sometimes the king separately, sometimes the
kings or chiefs or gerontes in the plural number, are named as deciding disputes and awarding satisfaction
to complainants; always, however, in public, in the midst of the assembled
agora.
In one of the compartments of the
shield of Achilles, the details of a judicial scene are described. While the
agora is full of an eager and excited crowd, two men are disputing about the
fine of satisfaction for the death of a murdered man,—one averring, the other
denying, that the fine had already been paid, and both demanding an inquest.
The gerontes are ranged on stone seats, in the holy circle, with two talents of gold lying
before them, to be awarded to such of the litigants as shall make out his case
to their satisfaction. The heralds with their scepters, repressing the warm
sympathies of the crowd in favor of one or other of the parties, secure an
alternate bearing to both. This interesting picture completely harmonizes with
the brief allusion of Hesiod to the judicial trial—doubtless a real
trial—between himself and his brother Perses. The two
brothers disputed about their paternal inheritance, and the cause was carried
to be tried by the chiefs in agora; but Perses bribed
them, and obtained an unjust verdict for the whole. So at least Hesiod affirms,
in the bitterness of his heart; earnestly exhorting his brother not to waste a
precious time, required for necessary labors, in the unprofitable occupation of
witnessing and abetting litigants in the agora,—for which (he adds) no man has
proper leisure, unless his subsistence for the year beforehand be safely
treasured up in his garners. He repeats, more than once, his complaints of the
crooked and corrupt judgments of which the kings were habitually guilty;
dwelling upon abuse of justice as the crying evil of his day, and predicting as
well as invoking the vengeance of Zeus to repress it. And Homer ascribes the
tremendous violence of the autumnal storms to the wrath of Zeus against those
judges who disgrace the agora “with their wicked verdicts”.
Though it is certain that, in every
state of society, the feelings of men when assembled in multitude will command
a certain measure of attention, yet we thus find the agora, in judicial matters
still more than in political, serving merely the purpose of publicity. It is
the king who is the grand personal mover of Grecian heroic society. He is on
earth, the equivalent of Zeus in the agora of the gods: the supreme god of
Olympus is in the habit of carrying on his government with frequent publicity,
of hearing some dissentient opinions, and of allowing himself occasionally to
be wheedled by Aphrodite, or worried into compliance by Here: but his
determination is at last conclusive, subject only to the overruling
interference of the Mora, or Fates.
Both the society of gods, and the various societies of men, are, according to
the conceptions of Grecian legend, carried on by the personal rule of a
legitimate sovereign, who does not derive his title from the special
appointment of his subjects, though he governs with their full consent. In
fact, Grecian legend presents to us hardly anything else, except these great
individual personalities. The race, or nation, is as it were absorbed into the
prince: eponymous persons, especially, are not merely princes, but fathers and
representative unities, each the equivalent of that greater or less aggregate
to which he gives name.
But though, in the primitive Grecian
government, the king is the legitimate as well as the real sovereign, he is
always conceived as acting through the council and agora. Both the one and the
other are established and essential media through which his ascendency is
brought to bear upon the society: the absence of such assemblies is the test
and mark of savage men, as in the case of the Cyclopes. Accordingly, he must possess qualities fit to act with
effect upon these two assemblies: wise reason for the council, unctuous
eloquence for the agora. Such is the idéal of the heroic government: a king, not merely full of
valor and resource as a soldier, but also sufficiently superior to those around
him to insure both the deliberate concurrence of the chiefs, and the hearty
adhesion of the masses. That this picture is not, in all individual cases,
realized, is unquestionable; but the endowments so often predicated of good
kings show it to have been the type present to the mind of the describer.
Xenophon, in his Cyropaedia, depicts Cyrus as an
improved edition of the Homeric Agamemnon,—“a good king and a powerful
soldier”, thus idealizing the perfection of personal government.
CONTRAST WITH HISTORICAL GREECE.
It is important to point out these
fundamental conceptions of government, discernible even before the dawn of
Grecian history, and identified with the social life of the people. It shows us
that the Greeks, in their subsequent revolutions, and in the political
experiments which their countless autonomous communities presented, worked upon preéxisting materials,—developing and exalting elements which had been at first
subordinate, and suppressing, or remodeling on a totally new principle, that
which had been originally predominant. When we approach historical Greece, we
find that (with the exception of Sparta) the primitive hereditary, unresponsible monarch, uniting in himself all the functions
of government, has ceased to reign,— while the feeling of legitimacy, which
originally induced his people to obey him willingly, has been exchanged for one
of aversion towards the character and title generally. The multifarious
functions which he once exercised, have been parceled out among temporary
nominees. On the other hand, the council, or senate, and the agora, originally
simple media through which the king acted, are elevated into standing and
independent sources of authority, controlling and holding in responsibility the
various special officers to whom executive duties of one kind or another are
confided. The general principle here indicated is common both to the
oligarchies and the democracies which grew up in historical Greece: much as
these two governments differed from each other, and many as were the varieties
even between one oligarchy or democracy and another, they all stood in equal
contrast with the principle of the heroic government. Even in Sparta, where the
hereditary kingship lasted, it was preserved with luster and influence
exceedingly diminished, and such timely diminution of its power seems to have
been one of the essential conditions of its preservation. Though the Spartan
kings had the hereditary command of the military forces, yet, even in all
foreign expeditions, they habitually acted in obedience to orders from home;
while in affairs of the interior, the superior power of the ephors sensibly overshadowed
them. So that, unless possessed of more than ordinary force of character, they
seem to have exercised their chief influence as presiding members of the
senate.
PUBLIC SPEAKING.
There is yet another point of view
in which it behoves us to take notice of the council
and the agora as integral portions of the legendary government of the Grecian
communities. We are thus enabled to trace the employment of public speaking, as
the standing engine of government and the proximate cause of obedience, to the
social infancy of the nation. The power of speech in the direction of public
affairs becomes more and more obvious, developed, and irresistible, as we
advance towards the culminating period of Grecian history, the century
preceding the battle of Chaeronea. That its development was greatest among the
most enlightened sections of the Grecian name, and smallest among the more
obtuse and stationary, is matter of notorious fact; nor is it less true, that the
prevalence of this habit was one of the chief causes of the intellectual
eminence of the nation generally. At a time when all the countries around were
plunged comparatively in mental torpor, there was no motive sufficiently
present and powerful to multiply so wonderfully the productive minds of Greece,
except such as arose from the rewards of public speaking. The susceptibility of
the multitude to this sort of guidance, their habit of requiring and enjoying
the stimulus which it supplied, and the open discussion, combining regular
forms with free opposition, of practical matters, political as well as
judicial,—are the creative causes which formed such conspicuous adepts in the
art of persuasion. Nor was it only professed orators who were thus produced; didactic
aptitude was formed in the background, and the speculative tendencies were
supplied with interesting phenomena for observation and combination, at a time
when the truths of physical science were almost inaccessible. If the primary
effect was to quicken the powers of expression, the secondary, but not less
certain result, was to develop the habits of scientific thought. Not only the
oratory of Demosthenes and Pericles, and the colloquial magic of Socrates, but
also the philosophical speculations of Plato, and the systematic politics,
rhetoric, and logic of Aristotle, are traceable to the same general tendencies
in the minds of the Grecian people: and we find the germ of these expansive
forces in the senate and agora of their legendary government. The poets, first
epic and then lyric, were the precursors of the orators, in their power of
moving the feelings of an assembled crowd; whilst the Homeric poems—the general
training-book of educated Greeks—constituted a treasury of direct and animated
expression, full of concrete forms, and rare in the use of abstractions, and
thence better suited to the workings of oratory. The subsequent critics had no
difficulty in selecting from the Iliad and Odyssey, samples of eloquence in all
its phases and varieties.
On the whole, then, the society
depicted in the old Greek poems is loose and unsettled, presenting very little
of legal restraint, and still less of legal protection,—but concentrating such
political power as does exist in the hands of a legitimate hereditary king,
whose ascendency over the other chiefs is more or less complete according to
his personal force and character. Whether that ascendency be greater or less,
however, the mass of the people is in either ease politically passive and of
little account. Though the Grecian freeman of the heroic age is above the
degraded level of the Gallic plebs, as described by Caesar, he is far from
rivaling the fierce independence and sense of dignity, combined with individual
force, which characterize the Germanic tribes before their establishment in the
Roman empire. Still less does his condition, or the society in which he moves,
correspond to those pleasing dreams of spontaneous rectitude and innocence, in
which Tacitus and Seneca indulge with regard to primitive man.
MORAL AND SOCIAL FEELING.
2. The state of moral and social
feeling, prevalent in legendary Greece, exhibits a scene in harmony with the
rudimentary political fabrics just described. Throughout the long stream of
legendary narrative on which the Greeks looked back as their past history, the
larger social motives hardly ever come into play: either individual valor and
cruelty, or the personal attachments and quarrels of relatives and
war-companions, or the feuds of private enemies, are ever before us. There is
no sense of obligation then existing, between man and man as such,—and very
little between each man and the entire community of which he is a member; such
sentiments are neither operative in the real world, nor present to the
imaginations of the poets. Personal feelings, either towards the gods, the
king, or some near and known individual, fill the whole of a man's bosom: out
of them arise all the motives to beneficence, and all the internal restraints
upon violence, antipathy, or rapacity: and special communion, as well as
special solemnities, are essential to their existence. The ceremony of an oath,
so imposing, so paramount, and so indispensable in those days, illustrates
strikingly this principle. And even in the case of the stranger suppliant,—in
which an apparently spontaneous sympathy manifests itself;—the succor and
kindness shown to him arise mainly from his having gone through the consecrated
formalities of supplication, such as that of sitting down in the ashes by the
sacred hearth, thus obtaining a sort of privilege of sanctuary. That ceremony
exalts him into something more than a mere suffering man,—it places him in
express fellowship with the master of the house, under the tutelary sanctions
of Zeus Hiketesios. There is great difference between
one form of supplication and another; the suppliant, however, in any form,
becomes more or less the object of a particular sympathy.
The sense of obligation towards the
gods manifests itself separately in habitual acts of worship, sacrifice, and libations,
or by votive presents, such as that of the hair of Achilles, which he has
pledged to the river-god Spercheius, and such as the
constant dedicated offerings which men who stand in urgent need of the divine
aid first promise and afterwards fulfill. But the feeling towards the gods also
appears, and that not less frequently, as mingling itself with and enforcing
obligations towards some particular human person. The tie which binds a man to
his father, his kinsman, his guest, or any special promise towards whom he has
taken the engagement of an oath, is conceived in conjunction with the idea of
Zeus, as witness and guarantee; and the intimacy of the association is attested
by some surname or special appellation of the god. Such personal feelings composed
all the moral influences of which a Greek of that day was susceptible,—a state
of mind which we can best appreciate by contrasting it with that of the
subsequent citizen of historical Athens. In the view of the latter, the great
impersonal authority, called “The Laws”, stood out separately, both as guide
and sanction, distinct from religious duty or private sympathies: but of this
discriminated conception of positive law and positive morality, the germ only
can be detected in the Homeric poems. The appropriate Greek word for human laws
never occurs. Amidst a very wavering phraseology, we can detect a gradual
transition from the primitive idea of a personal goddess Themis, attached to
Zeus, first to his sentences or orders called Themistes,
and next by a still farther remove to various established customs, which those
sentences were believed to sanctify, —the authority of religion and that of
custom coalescing into one indivisible obligation.
FAMILY RELATIONS.
The family relations, as we might
expect, are set forth in our pictures of the legendary world as the grand
sources of lasting union and devoted attachment. The paternal authority is
highly reverenced: the son who lives to years of maturity, repays by affection
to his parents the charge of his maintenance in infancy, which the language
notes by a special word; whilst on the other hand, the Erinnys,
whose avenging hand is put in motion by the curse of a father or mother, is an
object of deep dread.
In regard to marriage, we find the
wife occupying a station of great dignity and influence, though it was the
practice for the husband to purchase her by valuable presents to her parents, a
practice extensively prevalent among early communities, and treated by
Aristotle as an evidence of barbarism. She even seems to live less secluded and
to enjoy a wider sphere of action than was allotted to her in historical
Greece. Concubines are frequent with the chiefs, and occasionally the jealousy
of the wife breaks out in reckless excess against her husband, as may be seen
in the tragic history of Phoenix. The continence of Laertes, from fear of
displeasing his wife Antikleia, is especially
noticed. A large portion of the romantic interest which Grecian legend inspires
is derived from the women: Penelope, Andromache, Helen, Clytemnestra, Eriphyle, Iokasta, Hekabe, etc., all stand in the foreground of the picture,
either from their virtues their beauty, their crimes, or their sufferings.
Not only brothers, but also cousins,
and the more distant blood-relations and clansmen, appear connected together by
a strong feeling of attachment, sharing among them universally the obligation
of mutual self-defense and revenge, in the event of injury to any individual of
the race. The legitimate brothers divide between them by lot the paternal
inheritance,—a bastard brother receiving only a small share; he is, however,
commonly very well treated, though the murder of Phokus,
by Telamon and Peleus, constitutes a flagrant
exception. The furtive pregnancy of young women, often by a god, is one of the
most frequently recurring incidents in the legendary narratives; and the
severity with which such a fact, when discovered, is visited by the father, is
generally extreme. As an extension of the family connection, we read of larger
unions, called the phratry and the tribe, which are respectfully, but not frequently, mentioned.
The generous readiness with which
hospitality is afforded to the stranger who asks for it, the facility with
which he is allowed to contract the peculiar connection of guest with his host,
and the permanence with which that connection, when created by partaking of the
same food and exchanging presents, is maintained even through a long period of
separation, and even transmitted from father to son—these are among the most captivating
features of the heroic society. The Homeric chief welcomes the stranger who
comes to ask shelter in his house, first gives him refreshment, and then
inquires his name and the purpose of his voyage. Though not inclined to invite
strangers to his house, he cannot repel them when they spontaneously enter it
craving a lodging. The suppliant is also commonly a stranger, but a stranger
under peculiar circumstances; who proclaims his own calamitous and abject
condition, and seeks to place himself in a relation to the chief whom be
solicits, something like that in which men stand to the gods. Onerous as such
special tie may become to him, the chief cannot decline it, if solicited in the
proper form: the ceremony of supplication has a binding effect, and the Erinnys punish the hardhearted person who disallows it. A
conquered enemy may sometimes throw himself at the feet of his conqueror, and
solicit mercy, but he cannot by doing so acquire the character and claims of a
suppliant properly so called: the conqueror has free discretion either to kill
him, or to spare him and accept a ransom.
PERSONAL SYMPATHIES.
There are in the legendary
narratives abundant examples of individuals who transgress in particular acts
even the holiest of these personal ties, but the savage Cyclops is the only
person described as professedly indifferent to them, and careless of that
sanction of the gods which in Grecian belief accompanied them all. In fact, the
tragic horror which pervades the lineage of Athamas or Kadmus, and which attaches to many of the acts of
Heracles, of Peleus and Telamon, of Jason and Medea,
of Atreus and Thyestes, etc., is founded upon a deep feeling and sympathy with
those special obligations, which conspicuous individuals, under the temporary
stimulus of the maddening Ate, are driven to violate. In such conflict of
sentiments, between the obligation generally reverenced and the exceptional
deviation in an individual otherwise admired, consists the pathos of the story.
These feelings—of mutual devotion between
kinsmen and companions in arms—of generous hospitality to the stranger, and of
helping protection to the suppliant,—constitute the bright spots in a dark age.
We find them very generally prevalent amongst communities essentially rude and
barbarous,—amongst the ancient Germans as described by Tacitus, the Druses in
Lebanon, the Arabian tribes in the desert, and even the North American Indians.
They are the instinctive
manifestations of human sociality, standing at first alone, and for that reason
appearing to possess a greater tutelary force than really belongs to them
-beneficent, indeed, in a high degree, with reference to their own appropriate
period, but serving as a very imperfect compensation for the impotence of the
magistrate, and for the absence of any all-pervading sympathy or sense of
obligation between man and man. We best appreciate their importance when we
compare the Homeric society with that of barbarians like the Thracians, who
tattooed their bodies, as the mark of a generous lineage,—sold their children
for export as slaves,—considered robbery, not merely as one admissible
occupation among others, but as the only honorable mode of life; agriculture
being held contemptible,—and above all, delighted in the shedding of blood as a
luxury. Such were the Thracians in the days of Herodotus and Thucydides: and
the Homeric society forms a mean term between that which these two historians
yet saw in Thrace, and that which they witnessed among their own civilized
countrymen.
FEROCIOUS PASSIONS UNRESTRAINED.
When, however, among the Homeric men
we pass beyond the influence of the private ties above enumerated, we find
scarcely any other moralizing forces in operation. The acts and adventures
commemorated imply a community wherein neither the protection nor the
restraints of law are practically felt, and where in ferocity, rapine, and the
aggressive propensities generally, seem restrained by no internal
counterbalancing scruples. Homicide, especially, is of frequent occurrence,
sometimes by open violence, sometimes by fraud: expatriation for homicide is
among the most constantly recurring acts of the Homeric poems: and savage
brutalities are often ascribed, even to admired heroes, with apparent
indifference. Achilles sacrifices twelve Trojan prisoners on the tomb of Patroklus, while his son Neoptolemus not only slaughters the aged Priam, but also seizes
by the leg the child Astyanax (son of the slain
Hector) and hurls him from one of the lofty towers of Troy. Moreover, the
celebrity of Autolykus, the maternal grandfather of
Odysseus, in the career of wholesale robbery and perjury, and the wealth which
it enabled him to acquire, are described with the same unaffected admiration as
the wisdom of Nestor or the strength of Ajax. Achilles, Menelaus, Odysseus,
pillage in person, wherever they can find an opportunity, employing both force
and stratagem to surmount resistance. The vocation of a pirate is recognized
and honorable, so that a host, when he asks his guest what is the purpose of
his voyage, enumerates enrichment by indiscriminate maritime plunder as among
those projects which may naturally enter into his contemplation. Abduction of
cattle, and expeditions for unprovoked ravage as well as for retaliation,
between neighboring tribes, appear ordinary phenomena; and the established
inviolability of heralds seems the only evidence of any settled feeling of
obligation between one community and another. While the house and property of
Odysseus, during his long absence, enjoys no public protection, those unprincipled
chiefs, who consume his substance, find sympathy rather than disapprobation
among the people of Ithaca. As a general rule, he who cannot protect himself
finds no protection from society: his own kinsmen and immediate companions are
the only parties to whom he can look with confidence for support. And in this
respect, the representation given by Hesiod makes the picture even worse. In
his emphatic denunciation of the fifth age, that poet deplores not only the
absence of all social justice and sense of obligation among his contemporaries,
but also the relaxation of the ties of family and hospitality. There are marks
of querulous exaggeration in the poem of the Works and Days; yet the author
professes to describe the real state of things around him, and the features of
his picture, soften them as we may, will still appear dark and calamitous. It
is, however, to he remarked, that he contemplates a state of peace,—thus
forming a contrast with the Homeric poems. His copious catalogue of social
evils scarcely mentions liability to plunder by a foreign enemy, nor does he
compute the chances of predatory aggression as a source of profit.
There are two special veins of
estimable sentiment, on which it may be interesting to contrast heroic and
historical Greece, and which exhibit the latter as an improvement on the
former, not less in the affections than in the intellect.
The law of Athens was peculiarly
watchful and provident with respect both to the persons and the property of
orphan minors; but the description given in the Iliad of the utter and hopeless
destitution of the orphan boy, despoiled of his paternal inheritance, and
abandoned by all the friends of his father, whom he urgently supplicates, and
who all harshly cast him off, is one of the most pathetic morsels in the whole
poem. In reference again to the treatment of the dead body of an enemy we find
all the Greek chiefs who come near (not to mention the conduct of Achilles
himself) piercing with their spears the corpse of the slain Hector, while some
of them even pass disgusting taunts upon it. We may add, from the lost epics,
the mutilation of the dead bodies of Paris and Deiphobus by the hand of Menelaus. But at the time of the Persian invasion, it was
regarded as unworthy of a right-minded Greek to maltreat in any way the dead
body of an enemy, even where such a deed might seem to be justified on the plea
of retaliation. After the battle of Plataea, a proposition was made to the
Spartan king Pausanias, to retaliate upon the dead body of Mardonius the indignities which Xerxes had heaped upon that of Leonidas at Thermopylae.
He indignantly spurned the suggestion, not without a severe rebuke, or rather a
half-suppressed menace, towards the proposer: and the feeling of Herodotus
himself goes heartily along with him.
COMPOSITION FOR CRIMES.
The different manner of dealing with
homicide presents a third test, perhaps more striking yet, of the change in
Grecian feelings and manners during the three centuries preceding the Persian
invasion. That which the murderer in the Homeric times had to dread, was, not
public prosecution and punishment, but the personal vengeance of the kinsmen
and friends of the deceased, who were stimulated by the keenest impulses of
honor and obligation to avenge the deed, and were considered by the public as
specially privileged to do so. To escape from this danger, he is obliged to
flee the country, unless he can prevail upon the incensed kinsmen to accept of
a valuable payment (we must not speak of coined money, in the days of Homer) as
satisfaction for their slain comrade. They may, if they please, decline the
offer, and persist in their right of revenge; but if they accept, they are
bound to leave the offender unmolested, and he accordingly remains at home
without farther consequences. The chiefs in agora do not seem to interfere,
except to insure payment of the stipulated sum.
Here we recognize once more the
characteristic attribute of the Grecian heroic age,—the omnipotence of private
force, tempered and guided by family sympathies, and the practical nullity of
that collective sovereign afterwards called The City, who in historical Greece becomes the central and paramount
source of obligation, but who appears yet only in the background, as a germ of
premise for the future. And the manner in which, in the case of homicide, that
germ was developed into a powerful reality, presents an interesting field of
comparison with other nations.
For the practice, here designated,
of leaving the party guilty of homicide to compromise by valuable payment with
the relatives of the deceased, and also of allowing to the latter a free choice
whether they would accept such compromise or enforce their right of personal
revenge,—has been remarked in many rude communities, but is particularly
memorable among the early German tribes. Among the many separate Teutonic
establishments which rose upon the ruins of the Western Empire of Rome, the
right as well as duty of private revenge, for personal injury or insult offered
to any member of a family,—and the endeavor to avert its effects by means of a
pecuniary composition levied upon the offender, chiefly as satisfaction to the
party injured, but partly also as perquisite to the king,—was adopted as the
basis of their legislation. This fundamental idea was worked out in elaborate
detail as to the valuation of the injury inflicted, where in one main
circumstance was the rank, condition, and power of the sufferer. The object of
the legislator was to preserve the society from standing feuds, but at the same
time to accord such full satisfaction as would induce the injured person to
waive his acknowledged right of personal revenge,—the full luxury of which, as
it presented itself to the mind of an Homeric Greek, may be read in more than
one passage of the Iliad. The German codes begin by trying to bring about the
acceptance of a fixed pecuniary composition as a constant voluntary custom, and
proceed ultimately to enforce it as a peremptory necessity: the idea of society
is at first altogether subordinate, and its influence passes only by slow
degrees from amicable arbitration into imperative control.
The Homeric society, in regard to
this capital point in human progression, is on a level with that of the German
tribes as described by Tacitus. But the subsequent course of Grecian
legislation takes a direction completely different from that of the German
codes: the primitive and acknowledged right of private revenge (unless where
bought off by pecuniary payment), instead of being developed into practical
working, is superseded by more comprehensive views of a public wrong requiring
public intervention, or by religious fears respecting the posthumous wrath of
the murdered person. In historical Athens, this right of private revenge was
discountenanced and put out of sight, even so early as the Draconian
legislation, and at last restricted to a few extreme and special cases; while
the murderer came to be considered, first as having sinned against the gods,
next as having deeply injured the society, and thus at once as requiring
absolution and deserving punishment. On the first of these two grounds, he is
interdicted from the agora and from all holy places, as well as from public
functions, even while yet untried and simply a suspected person; for if this
were not done, the wrath of the gods would manifest itself in bad crops and
other national calamities. On the second ground, he is tried before the council
of Areiopagus, and if found guilty, is condemned to
death, or perhaps to disfranchisement and banishment. The idea of a propitiatory
payment to the relatives of the deceased has ceased altogether to be admitted:
it is the protection of society which dictates, and the force of society which
inflicts, a measure of punishment calculated to deter for the future.
SOCIETY OF LEGENDARY GREECE.
3. The society of legendary Greece
includes, besides the chiefs, the general mass of freemen, among whom stand out
by special names certain professional men, such as the carpenter, the smith,
the leather-dresser, the leech, the prophet, the bard, and the fisherman. We
have no means of appreciating their condition. Though lots of arable land were
assigned in special property to individuals, with boundaries both carefully
marked and jealously watched, yet the larger proportion of surface was devoted
to pasture. Cattle formed both the chief item in the substance of a wealthy
man, the chief means of making payments, and the common ground of
quarrels,—bread and meat, in large quantities, being the constant food of every
one. The estates of the owners were tilled, and their cattle tended, mostly by
bought slaves, but to a certain degree also by poor freemen called Thetes, working
for hire and for stated periods. The principal slaves, who were entrusted with
the care of large herds of oxen, swine, or goats, were of necessity men worthy
of confidence, their duties placing them away from their master’s immediate
eye. They had other slaves subordinate to them, and appear to have been
well-treated: the deep and unshaken attachment of Eumaeus the swineherd and Philoetius the neat herd to the family and affairs of the
absent Odysseus, is among the most interesting points in the ancient epic.
Slavery was a calamity, which in that period of insecurity might befall any
one: the chief who conducted a freebooting expedition, if he succeeded, brought
back with him a numerous troop of slaves, as many as he could seize,— if he
failed, became very likely a slave himself: so that the slave was often by
birth of equal dignity with his master: Eumaeus was himself the son of a chief,
conveyed away when a child by his nurse, and sold by Phoenician kidnappers to
Laertes. A slave of this character, if he conducted himself well, might often
expect to be enfranchised by his master and placed in an independent holding.
On the whole, the slavery of
legendary Greece does not present itself as existing under a peculiarly harsh
form, especially if we consider that all the classes of society were then very
much upon a level in point of taste, sentiment, and instruction. In the absence
of legal security or an effective social sanction, it is probable that the
condition of a slave under an average master, may have been as good as that of
the free Thete. The class of slaves whose lot appears
to have been the most pitiable were the females,—more numerous than the males,
and performing the principal work in the interior of the house. Not only do
they seem to have been more harshly treated than the males, but they were
charged with the hardest and most exhausting labor which the establishment of a
Greek chief required: they brought in water from the spring, and turned by hand
the house-mills, which ground the large quantity of flour consumed in his
family. This oppressive task was performed generally by female slaves, in
historical as well as legendary Greece. Spinning and weaving was the constant
occupation of women, whether free or slave, of every rank and station: all the
garments worn both by men and women were fashioned at home, and Helen as well
as Penelope is expert and assiduous at the occupation. The daughters of Keleos at Eleusis go to the well with their basins for
water, and Nausikaa, daughter of Alkinous,
joins her female slaves in the business of washing her garments in the river.
If we are obliged to point out the fierceness and insecurity of an early
society, we may at the same time note with pleasure its characteristic
simplicity of manners: Rebecca, Rachel, and the daughters of Jethro, in the early Mosaic narrative, as well as the wife
of the native Macedonian chief (with whom the Temenid Perdiccas, ancestor of Philip and Alexander, first took service on retiring
from Argos), baking her own cakes on the hearth, exhibit a parallel in this
respect to the Homeric pictures.
We obtain no particulars respecting
either the common freemen generally, or the particular class of them called Thetes. These latter, engaged for special jobs, or at the
harvest and other busy seasons of field labor, seem to have given their labor
in exchange for board and clothing: they are mentioned in the same line with
the slaves, and were (as has been just observed) probably on the whole little
better off. The condition of a poor freeman in those days, without a lot of
land of his own, going about from one temporary job to another, and having no
powerful family and no social authority to look up to for protection, must have
been sufficiently miserable. When Eumaeus indulged his expectation of being
manumitted by his masters, he thought at the same time that they would give him
a wife, a house, and a lot of land near to themselves; without which collateral
advantages, simple manumission might perhaps have been no improvement in his
condition. To be Thete in the service of a very poor
farmer is selected by Achilles as the maximum of human hardship: such a person
could not give to his Thete the same ample food, and
good shoes and clothing, as the wealthy chief Eurymachus,
while he would exact more severe labor. It was probably among such smaller
occupants, who could not advance the price necessary to purchase slaves, and
were glad to save the cost of keep when they did not need service, that the Thetes found employment: though we may conclude that the
brave and strong amongst these poor freemen found it preferable to accompany
some freebooting chief and to live by the plunder acquired. The exact Hesiod
advises his farmer, whose work is chiefly performed by slaves, to employ and
maintain the Thete during summertime, but to dismiss
him as soon as the harvest is completely got in, and then to take into his
house for the winter a woman “without any child”; who would of course be more
useful than the Thete for the indoor occupations of
that season.
COMMERCE AND NAVIGATION.
In a state of society such as that
which we have been describing, Grecian commerce was necessarily trifling and
restricted. The Homeric poems mark either total ignorance or great vagueness of
apprehension respecting all that lies beyond the coasts of Greece and Asia
Minor, and the islands between or adjoining them. Libya and Egypt are supposed
so distant as to be known only by name and hearsay: indeed, when the city of
Cyrene was founded, a century and a half after the first Olympiad, it was
difficult to find anywhere a Greek navigator who had ever visited the coast of
Libya, or was fit to serve as guide to the colonists. The mention of the Sikels in the Odyssey, leads us to conclude that Corcyra,
Italy, and Sicily were not wholly unknown to the poet: among seafaring Greeks,
the knowledge of the latter implied the knowledge of the two former, since the
habitual track, even of a well-equipped Athenian trireme during the
Peloponnesian war, from Peloponnesus to Sicily, was by Corcyra and the Gulf of
Tarentum. The Phokians, long afterwards, were the
first Greeks who explored either the Adriatic or Tyrrhenian sea. Of the Euxine
sea no knowledge is manifested in Homer, who, as a general rule, presents to us
the names of distant regions only in connection with romantic or monstrous
accompaniments. The Cretans, and still more the Taphians (who are supposed to have occupied the western islands off the coast of
Acarnania), are mentioned as skillful mariners, and the Taphian Mentes professes to be conveying iron to Temesa to be there exchanged for copper but both Taphians and Cretans are more corsairs than traders. The strong
sense of the dangers of the sea, expressed by the poet Hesiod, and the
imperfect structure of the early Grecian ship, attested by Thucydides (who
points out the more recent date of that improved ship-building which prevailed
in his time, concur to demonstrate the then narrow range of nautical
enterprise.
Such was the state of the Greeks, as
traders, at a time when Babylon combined a crowded and industrious population
with extensive commerce, and when the Phoenician merchantships visited in one direction the Southern coast of Arabia, perhaps even the island
of Ceylon,—in another direction, the British islands.
THE PHOENICIANS.—INTERCHANGE.
The Phoenician, the kinsman of the
ancient Jew, exhibits the type of character belonging to the latter, with greater
enterprise and ingenuity, and less of religious exclusiveness, yet still
different from, and even antipathetic to, the character of the Greeks. In the
Homeric poems, he appears somewhat like the Jew of the Middle Ages, a crafty
trader, turning to profit the violence and rapacity of others,—bringing them
ornaments, decorations, the finest and brightest products of the loom, gold,
silver, electrum, ivory, tin, etc., in exchange for which he received landed
produce, skins, wool, and slaves, the only commodities which even a wealthy
Greek chief of those early times had to offer,—prepared at the same time for
dishonest gain, in any manner which chance might throw in his way. He is,
however, really a trader, not undertaking expeditions with the deliberate purpose
of surprise and plunder, and standing distinguished in this respect from the
Tyrrhenian, Cretan, or Taphian pirate. Tin, ivory,
and electrum, all of which are acknowledged in the Homeric poems, were the
fruit of Phoenician trade with the West as well as with the East.
Thucydides tells us that the
Phoenicians and Carians, in very early periods, occupied many of the islands of
the Aegean, and we know, from the striking remnant of their mining works which
Herodotus himself saw in Thasus, off the coast of
Thrace, that they had once extracted gold from the mountains of that island,—at
a period indeed very far back, since their occupation must have been abandoned
prior to the settlement of the poet Archilochus. Yet
few of the islands in the Aegean were rich in such valuable products, nor was
it in the usual course of Phoenician proceeding to occupy islands, except where
there was an adjoining mainland with which trade could be carried on. The
traffic of these active mariners required no permanent settlement, but as
occasional visitors they were convenient, in enabling a Greek chief to turn his
captives to account,—to get rid of slaves or friendless Thetes who were troublesome,—and to supply himself with the metals, precious as well
as useful. The halls of Alkinous and Menelaus glitter
with gold, copper, and electrum; while large stocks of yet unemployed
metal—gold, copper, and iron—are stored up in the treasure-chamber of Odysseus
and other chiefs. Coined money is unknown to the Homeric age,—the trade carried
on being one of barter. In reference also to the metals, it deserves to be
remarked that the Homeric description universally suppose copper, and not iron,
to be employed for arms, both offensive and defensive. By what process the
copper was tempered and hardened, so as to serve the purposes of the warrior,
we do not know; but the use of iron for these objects belongs to a later age,
though the Works and Days of Hesiod suppose this change to have been already
introduced.
MILITARY AND CIVIL RETROSPECT.
The mode of fighting among the
Homeric heroes is not less different from the historical times, than the
material of which their arms were composed. The Hoplites, or heavy-armed
infantry of historical Greece, maintained a close order and well-dressed line,
charging the enemy with their spears portended at even distance, and coming
thus to close conflict without breaking their rank: there were special troops,
bowmen, slingers, etc. armed with missiles, but the hoplite had no weapon to
employ in this manner. The heroes of the Iliad and Odyssey, on the contrary,
habitually employ the spear as a missile, which they launch with tremendous
force: each of them is mounted in his war-chariot, drawn by two horses, and
calculated to contain the warrior and his charioteer; in which latter capacity
a friend or comrade will sometimes consent to serve. Advancing in his chariot
at full speed, in front of his own soldiers, he hurls his spear against the
enemy: sometimes, indeed, he will fight on foot, and hand to hand, but the chariot
is usually near to receive him if he chooses, or to insure his retreat. The
mass of the Greeks and Trojans, coming forward to the charge, without any
regular step or evenly-maintained line, make their attack in the same way by
hurling their spears. Each chief wears habitually a long sword and a short
dagger, besides his two spears to be launched forward,—the spear being also
used, if occasion serves, as a weapon for thrust. Every man is protected by
shield, helmet, breastplate, and greaves: but the armor of the chiefs is
greatly superior to that of the common men, while they themselves are both
stronger and more expert in the use of their weapons. There are a few bowmen,
as rare exceptions, but the general equipment and proceeding is as here
described.
Such loose array, immortalized as it
is in the Iliad, is familiar to everyone; and the contrast which it presents,
with those inflexible ranks, and that irresistible simultaneous charge which
bore down the Persian throng at Plataea and Cunaxa, is such as to illustrate
forcibly the general difference between heroic and historical Greece. While in
the former, a few splendid figures stand forward, in prominent relief, the
remainder being a mere unorganized and ineffective mass, in the latter, these
units have been combined into a system, in which every man, officer and
soldier, has his assigned place and duty, and the victory, when gained, is the
joint work of all. Preeminent individual prowess is indeed materially abridged,
if not wholly excluded, no man can do more than maintain his station in the
line; but on the other hand, the grand purposes, aggressive or defensive, for
which alone arms are taken up, become more assured and easy, and long-sighted
combinations of the general are rendered for the first time practicable, when
he has a disciplined body of men to obey him. In tracing the picture of civil
society, we have to remark a similar transition—we pass from Heracles, Theseus,
Jason, Achilles, to Solon, Pythagoras, and Pericles—from “the shepherd of his people”,
(to use the phrase in which Homer depicts the good side of the heroic king) to
the legislator who introduces, and the statesman who maintains, a preconcerted system by which willing citizens consent to
bind themselves. If commanding individual talent is not always to be found, the
whole community is so trained as to be able to maintain its course under
inferior leaders; the rights as well as the duties of each citizen being
predetermined in the social order, according to principles more or less wisely
laid down. The contrast is similar, and the transition equally remarkable, in
the civil as in the military picture. In fact, the military organization of the
Grecian republics is an element of the greatest importance in respect to the
conspicuous part which they have played in human affairs,—their superiority
over other contemporary nations in this respect being hardly less striking than
it is in many others, as we shall have occasion to see in a subsequent stage of
this history.
SITES OF TOWNS.
Even at the most advanced point of
their tactics, the Greeks could effect little against
a walled city, whilst the heroic weapons and array were still less available
for such an undertaking as a siege. Fortifications are a feature of the age
deserving considerable notice. There was a time, we are told, in which the
primitive Greek towns or villages derived a precarious security, not from their
walls, but merely from sites lofty and difficult of access. They were not built
immediately upon the shore, or close upon any convenient landing-place, but at
some distance inland, on a rock or elevation which could not be approached
without notice or scaled without difficulty. It was thought sufficient at that
time to guard against piratical or marauding surprise: but as the state of
society became assured,—as the chance of sudden assault comparatively
diminished and industry increased,—these uninviting abodes were exchanged for
more convenient sites on the plain or declivity beneath; or a portion of the
latter was enclosed within larger boundaries and joined on to the original
foundation, which thus became the Acropolis of the new town. Thebes, Athens,
Argos, etc., belonged to the latter class of cities; but there were in many
parts of Greece deserted sites on hilltops, still retaining, even in
historical times, the traces of former habitation, and some of them still
bearing the name of the old towns. Among the mountainous parts of Crete, in
Aegina and Rhodes, in portions of Mount Ida and Parnassus, similar remnants
might be perceived.
Probably, in such primitive hill
villages, a continuous circle of wall would hardly be required as an additional
means of defense, and would often be rendered very difficult by the rugged
nature of the ground. But Thucydides represents the earliest Greeks—those whom
he conceives anterior to the Trojan war—as living thus universally in
unfortified villages, chiefly on account of their poverty, rudeness, and
thorough carelessness for the morrow. Oppressed, and held apart from each other
by perpetual fear, they had not yet contracted the sentiment of fixed abodes:
they were unwilling even to plant fruit-trees because of the uncertainty of
gathering the produce,—and were always ready to dislodge, because there was
nothing to gain by staying, and a bare subsistence might be had anywhere. He
compares them to the mountaineers of Aetolia and of the Ozolian Lokris in his own time, who dwelt in their
unfortified hill villages with little or no intercommunication, always armed
and fighting, and subsisting on the produce of their cattle and their
woods,—clothed in undressed hides, and eating raw meat.
The picture given by Thucydides, of
these very early and unrecorded times, can only be taken as conjectural,—the
conjectures, indeed, of a statesman and a philosopher,—generalized too, in
part, from the many particular instances of contention and expulsion of chiefs
which he found in the old legendary poems. The Homeric poems, however, present
to us a different picture. They recognize walled towns, fixed abodes, strong
local attachments, hereditary individual property in land, vineyards planted
and carefully cultivated, established temples of the gods, and splendid palaces
of the chiefs. The description of Thucydides belongs to a lower form of
society, and bears more analogy to that which the poet himself conceives as
antiquated and barbarous,—to the savage Cyclopes, who dwell on the tops of
mountains, in hollow caves, without the plough, without vine or fruit culture,
without arts or instruments,—or to the primitive settlement of Dardanus son of Zeus, on the higher ground of Ida, while it
was reserved for his descendants and successors to found the holy Ilium on the
plain. Ilium or Troy represents the perfection of Homeric society. It is a
consecrated spot, containing temples of the gods as well as the palace of Priam, and surrounded by walls which are the fabric of the
gods; while the antecedent form of ruder society, which the poet briefly
glances at, is the parallel of that which the theory of Thucydides ascribes to
his own early semi-barbarous ancestors.
DEFENCE AGAINST AGGRESSION.
Walled towns serve thus as one of
the evidences, that a large part of the population of Greece had, even in the
Homeric times, reached a level higher than that of the Aetolians and Lokrians of the days of Thucydides. The remains of Mycenae
and Tiryns demonstrate the massy and Cyclopean style of architecture employed
in those early days: but we may remark that, while modern observers seem
inclined to treat the remains of the former is very imposing, and significant
of a great princely family, Thucydides, on the contrary, speaks of it as a
small place, and labors to elude the inference, which might be deduced from its
insignificant size, in disproof of the grandeur of Agamemnon. Such fortifications
supplied a means of defense incomparably superior to those of attack. Indeed,
even in historical Greece, and after the invention of battering engines, no
city could be taken except by surprise or blockade, or by ruining the country
around, and thus depriving the inhabitants of their means of subsistence. And
in the two great sieges of the legendary time, Troy and Thebes, the former is
captured by the stratagem of the wooden horse, while the latter is evacuated by
its citizens, under the warning of the gods, after their defeat in the field.
This decided superiority of the
means of defense over those of attack, in rude ages, has been one of the grand promotive causes both of the growth of civic life and of
the general march of human improvement. It has enabled the progressive portions
of mankind not only to maintain their acquisitions against the predatory
instincts of the ruder and poorer, and to surmount the difficulties of
incipient organization,—but ultimately, when their organization has been matured,
both to acquire predominance, and to uphold it until their own disciplined
habits have in part passed to their enemies. The important truth here stated is
illustrated not less by the history of ancient Greece, than by that of modern
Europe during the Middle Ages. The Homeric chief, combining superior rank with
superior force, and ready to rob at every convenient opportunity, greatly
resembles the feudal baron of the Middle Ages, but circumstances absorb him
more easily into a city life, and convert the independent potentate into the
member of a governing aristocracy. Traffic by sea continued to be beset with
danger from pirates, long after it had become tolerably assured by land: the
“wet ways” have always been the last resort of lawlessness and violence, and
the Aegean, in particular, has in all times suffered more than other waters
under this calamity.
PIRACY
Aggressions of the sort here
described were of course most numerous in those earliest times when the Aegean
was not yet an Hellenic sea, and when many of the Cyclades were occupied, not
by Greeks, but by Carians,—perhaps by Phoenicians the number of Carian
sepulchers discovered in the sacred island of Delos seems to attest such
occupation as an historical fact. According to the legendary account, espoused
both by Herodotus and by Thucydides, it was the Cretan Minos who subdued these
islands and established his sons as rulers in them; either expelling the Carians,
or reducing them to servitude and tribute. Thucydides presumes that he must of
course have put down piracy, in order to enable his tribute to be remitted in
safety, like the Athenians during the time of their hegemony. Upon the
legendary thalassocracy of Minos, I have already
remarked in another place: it is sufficient here to repeat, that, in the
Homeric poems (long subsequent to Minos in the current chronology), we find
piracy both frequent and held in honorable estimation, as Thucydides himself
emphatically tells us,—remarking, moreover, that the vessels of those early
days were only half-decked, built and equipped after the piratical fashion, in
a manner upon which the nautical men of his time looked back with disdain.
Improved and enlarged shipbuilding, and the trireme, or ship with three banks
of oars, common for warlike purposes during the Persian invasion, began only
with the growing skill, activity, and importance of the Corinthians, three
quarters of a century after the first Olympiad. Corinth, even in the Homeric
poems, is distinguished by the epithet of wealthy, which it acquired
principally from its remarkable situation on the Isthmus, and from its two
harbors of Lechaeum and Kenchreae,
the one on the Corinthian, the other on the Saronic gulf. It thus supplied a convenient connection between Epirus and Italy on the
one side, and the Aegean sea on the other, without imposing upon the unskillful
and timid navigator of those days the necessity of circumnavigating
Peloponnesus.
The extension of Grecian traffic and
shipping is manifested by a comparison of the Homeric with the Hesiodic poems;
in respect to knowledge of places and countries,—the latter being probably
referable to dates between BC 740 and BC 640. In Homer, acquaintance is
shown (the accuracy of such acquaintance, however, being exaggerated by Strabo
and other friendly critics) with continental Greece and its neighboring
islands, with Crete and the principal islands of the Aegean, and with Thrace,
the Troad, the Hellespont, and Asia Minor between Paphlagonia northward and
Lycia southward. The Sikels are mentioned in the
Odyssey, and Sikania in the last book of that poem,
but nothing is said to evince a knowledge of Italy or the realities of the
western world. Libya, Egypt, and Phoenike, are known
by name and by vague hearsay, but the Nile is only mentioned as “the river Egypt”
: while the Euxine sea is not mentioned at all. In the Hesiodic poems, on the
other hand, the Nile, the Ister, the Phasis, and the Eridanus, are all
specified by name; Mount Etna, and the island of Ortygia near to Syracuse, the Tyrrhenians and Ligurians in the west, and the Scythians in the north, were
also noticed. Indeed, within forty years after the first Olympiad, the cities
of Corcyra and Syracuse were founded from Corinth,—the first of a numerous and
powerful series of colonies, destined to impart a new character both to the
south of Italy and to Sicily.
HOMERIC ASTRONOMY.
In reference to the astronomy and
physics of the Homeric Greek, it has already been remarked that be connected
together the sensible phenomena which form the subject matter of these sciences
by threads of religious and personifying fancy, to which the real analogies
among them were made subordinate; and that these analogies did not begin to be
studied by themselves, apart from the religious element by which they had been
at first overlaid, until the age of Thales,—coinciding as that period did with
the increased opportunities for visiting Egypt and the interior of Asia. The
Greeks obtained access in both of these countries to an enlarged stock of
astronomical observations, to the use of the gnomon, or sundial, and to a more
exact determination of the length of the solar year, than that which served as
the basis of their various lunar periods. It is pretended that Thales was the
first who predicted an eclipse of the sun,—not, indeed. accurately, but with
large limits of error as to the time of its occurrence,—and that he also
possessed so profound an acquaintance with meteorological phenomena and
probabilities, as to be able to foretell an abundant crop of olives for the
coming year, and to realize a large sum of money by an olive speculation.
From Thales downward we trace a
succession of astronomical and physical theories, more or less successful, into
which I do not intend here to enter: it is sufficient at present to contrast the
father of the Ionic philosophy with the times preceding him, and to mark the
first commencement of scientific prediction among the Greeks, however imperfect
at the outset, as distinguished from the inspired dicta of prophets or oracles,
and from those special signs of the purposes of the gods, which formed the
habitual reliance of the Homeric man We shall see these two modes of
anticipating the future,—one based upon the philosophical, the other upon the
religious appreciation of nature,—running simultaneously on throughout Grecian
history, and sharing between them in unequal portions the empire of the Greek
mind; the former acquiring both greater predominance and wider application
among the intellectual men, and partially restricting, but never abolishing,
the spontaneous employment of the latter among the vulgar.
Neither coined money, nor the art of
writing, nor painting, nor sculpture, nor imaginative architecture, belong to
the Homeric and Hesiodic times. Such rudiments of arts, destined ultimately to
acquire so great a development in Greece, as may have existed in these early
days, served only as a sort of nucleus to the fancy of the poet, to shape out
for himself the fabulous creations ascribed to Hephaetus or Daelalus. No statues of the gods, not even of
wood, are mentioned in the Homeric poems. All the many varieties, in Grecian
music, poetry, and dancing,—the former chiefly borrowed from Lydia and
Phrygia,—date from a period considerably later than the first Olympiad: Terpander, the earliest musician whose date is assigned,
and the inventor of the harp with seven strings instead of that with four
strings, does not come until the 26th Olympiad, or 676 BC; the poet Archilochus is nearly of the
same date. The iambic and elegiac metres—the first
deviations from the primitive epic strain and subject—do not reach up to the
year 700 BC.
It is this epic poetry which forms
at once both the undoubted prerogative and the solitary jewel of the earliest
era of Greece. Of the many epic poems which existed in Greece during the eight
century before the Christian era, none have been preserved except the Iliad and
Odyssey: the Athiopis of Arktinus,
the Ilias Minor of Lesches,
the Cyprian Verses, the Capture of Oechalia, the
Returns of the Heroes from Troy, the Maas and the Epigoni,—several of them
passing in antiquity under the name of Homer,—have all been lost. But the two
which remain are quite sufficient to demonstrate in the primitive Greeks, a
mental organization unparalleled in any other people, and powers of invention
and expression which prepared, as well as foreboded, the future eminence of the
nation in all the various departments to which thought and language can be
applied. Great as the power of thought afterwards became among the Greeks, their
power of expression was still greater: in the former, other nations have built
upon their foundations and surpassed them,— in the latter, they still remained
unrivalled. It is not too much to say that this flexible, emphatic, and
transparent character of the language as an instrument of communication,—its perfect aptitude for narrative and discussion, as well
as for stirring all the veins of human emotion without ever forfeiting that
character of simplicity which adapts it to all men and all times,—may be traced
mainly to the existence and the widespread influence of the Iliad and Odyssey.
To us, these compositions are interesting as beautiful poems, depicting life
and manners, and unfolding certain types of character with the utmost vivacity
and artlessness to their original hearer; they possessed all these sources of
attraction, together with others more powerful still, to which we are now
strangers. Upon him, they bore with the full weight and solemnity of history
and religion combined, while the charm of the poetry was only secondary and
instrumental. The poet was then the teacher and preacher of the community, not
simply the amuser of their leisure hours : they looked to him for revelations
of the unknown past and for expositions of the attributes and dispensations of
the gods, just as they consulted the prophet for his privileged insight into
the future. The ancient epic comprised many different poets and poetical
compositions, which fulfilled this purpose with more or less completeness: but
it is the exclusive prerogative of the Iliad and Odyssey, that, after the minds
of men had ceased to be in full harmony with their original design, they yet
retained their empire by the mere force of secondary excellences: while the
remaining epics—though serving as food for the curious, and as storehouses for
logographers, tragedians, and artists—never seem to have acquired very wide
popularity even among intellectual Greeks.
AT the head of the once abundant
epics’ compositions of Greece, most of them unfortunately lost, stand the Iliad
and Odyssey, with the immortal name of Homer attached to each of them,
embracing separate portions of the comprehensive legend of Troy. They form the
type of what may be called the heroic epic of the Greeks, as distinguished from
the genealogical, in which latter species some of the Hesiodic poems—the
Catalogue of Women, the Eoiai, and the Naupaktia—stood conspicuous. Poems of the Homeric character
(if so it may be called, though the expression is very indefinite), being
confined to one of the great events, or great personages of Grecian legendary
antiquity, and comprising a limited number of characters, all contemporaneous,
made some approach, more or less successful, to a certain poetical unity; while
the Hesiodic poems, tamer in their spirit, and unconfined both as to time and
as to persons, strung together distinct events without any obvious view to
concentration of interest, without legitimate beginning or end. Between these
two extremes there were many gradations: biographical poems, such as the
Herakleia, or Theseis, recounting all the principal
exploits performed by one single hero, present a character intermediate between
the two, but bordering more closely on the Hesiodic. Even the hymns to the
gods, which pass under the name of Homer, are epical fragments, narrating
particular exploits or adventures of the god commemorated.
Both the didactic and the mystico-religious poetry of Greece began in Hexameter
verse—the characteristic and consecrated measure of the epic but they belong to
a different species, and burst out from a different vein in the Grecian mind.
It seems to have been the more common belief among the historical Greeks, that
such mystic effusions were more ancient than their narrative poems, and that
Orpheus, Musaeus, Linus, Olen, Pamphus, and even
Hesiod, etc., etc., the reputed composers of the former, were of earlier date
than Homer. But there is no evidence to sustain this opinion, and the
presumptions are all against it. Those compositions, which in the sixth century
before the Christian era passed under the name of Orpheus and Musaeus, seem to
have been unquestionably post-Homeric, nor can we even admit the modified
conclusion of Hermann, Ulrici, and others, that the
mystic poetry as a genus (putting aside the particular compositions falsely
ascribed to Orpheus and others) preceded in order of time the narrative.
Beside the Iliad and Odyssey, we
make out the titles of about thirty lost epic poems, sometimes with a brief
hint of their contents.
Concerning the legend of Troy there
were five : the Cyprian Verses, the Ethiopis, and the
Capture of Troy, both ascribed to Arktinus; the
lesser Iliad, ascribed to Lesches; the Returns (of
the Heroes from Troy), to which the name of Hagias of Troezen is attached; and the Telegonia, by Eugammon, a
continuation of the Odyssey. Two poems,—the Thebais and the Epigoni (perhaps
two parts of one and the same poem) were devoted to the legend of Thebes,—the
two sieges of that city by the Argeians. Another
poem, called Edipodia, had for its subject the tragical destiny of Oedipus and his family; and perhaps
that which is cited as Europia, or verses on Europa,
may have comprehended the tale of her brother Cadmus, the mythical founder of
Thebes.
The exploits of Heracles were
celebrated in two compositions, each called Herakleia, by Kinaethon and Pisander,—probably also in many others, of which
the memory has not been preserved. The capture of Echalia,
by Heracles, formed the subject of a separate epic. Two other poems, the
Aegimius and the Minyas, are supposed to have been
founded on other achievements of this hero,—the effective aid which he lent to
the Dorian king Aegimius against the Lapithae, his descent
to the underworld for the purpose of rescuing the imprisoned Theseus, and his
conquest of the city of the Minyae, the powerful Orchomenus.
Other epic poems : the Phoronis, the Danais, the Alkmaeonis, the Atthis, the
Amazonia, we know only by name, and can just guess obscurely at their contents
so far as the name indicates. The Titanomachia, the Gigantomachia, and the Corinthiaca, three compositions all ascribed to Eumelus, afford by means of their titles an idea somewhat
clearer of the matter which they comprised. The Theogony ascribed to Hesiod
still exists, though partially corrupt and mutilated: but there seem to have
been other poems, now lost, of the like import and title.
Of the poems composed in the
Hesiodic style, diffusive and full of genealogical detail, the principal were,
the Catalogue of Women and the Great Eoiai; the
latter of which, indeed, seems to have been a continuation of the former. A
large number of the celebrated women of heroic Greece were commemorated in
these poems, one after the other, without any other than an arbitrary bond of
connection. The Marriage of Keyx,—the Melampodia—and a string of fables called Astronomia, are farther ascribed to Hesiod: and the poem
above mentioned, called Aegimius, is also sometimes connected with his name,
sometimes with that of Kerkops. The Naupaktian Verses (so called, probably, from the birthplace
of their author), and the genealogies of Kinaethon and Asius, were compositions of the same rambling
character, as far as we can judge from the scanty fragments remaining. The Orchomenian epic poet Chersias,
of whom two lines only are preserved to us by Pausanias, may reasonably be
referred to the same category.
The oldest of the epic poets, to
whom any date, carrying with it the semblance of authority, is assigned, is Arktinus of Miletus, who is placed by Eusebius in the first
Olympiad, and by Suidas in the ninth. Eugammon, the author of the Telegonia, and the latest of
the catalogue, is placed in the fifty-third Olympiad, BC 566. Between these two
we find Asius and Lesches,
about the thirtieth Olympiad,—a time when the vein of the ancient epic was
drying up, and when other forms of poetry—elegiac, iambic, lyric, and
choric—had either already arisen, or were on the point of arising, to compete
with it .
EPIC CYCLE.
It has already been stated in a
former chapter, that in the early commencements of prose-writing, Hekataeus,
Pherekydes, and ether logographers, made it their business to extract from the
ancient fables something like a continuous narrative, chronologically arranged.
It was upon a principle somewhat analogous that the Alexandrine literati, about
the second century before the Christian era, arranged the multitude of old epic
poets into a series founded on the supposed order of time in the events
narrated,— beginning with the intermarriage of Uranus and Gaea, and the
Theogony,—and concluding with the death of Odysseus by the hands of his son
Telegonus. This collection passed by the name of the Epic Cycle, and the poets,
whose compositions were embodied in it, were termed Cyclic poets. Doubtless,
the epical treasures of the Alexandrine library were larger than had ever
before been brought together and submitted to men both of learning and leisure
: so that multiplication of such compositions in the same museum rendered it
advisable to establish some fixed order of perusal, and to copy them in one
corrected and uniform edition. It pleased the critics to determine precedence,
neither by antiquity nor by excellence of the compositions themselves, but by
the supposed sequence of narrative so that the whole taken together constituted
a readable aggregate of epical antiquity.
Much obscurity exists, and many
different opinions have been expressed, respecting this Epic Cycle. I view it,
not as an exclusive canon, but simply as an all-comprehensive classification,
with a new edition founded thereupon. It would include all the epic poems in
the library older than the Telegonia, and apt for continuous narrative; it
would exclude only two classes; first, the recent epic poets, such as Panyasis and Antimachus; next, the genealogical and
desultory poems, such as the Catalogue of Women, the Eoiai,
and others, which could not be made to fit in to any chronological sequence of
events. Both the Iliad and the Odyssey were comprised in the Cycle, so that the
denomination of cyclic poet did not originally or designedly carry with it any
association of contempt. But as the great and capital poems were chiefly spoken
of by themselves, or by the title of their own separate authors, so the general
name of poets of the Cycle came gradually to be applied only to the worst, and
thus to imply vulgarity or common-place; the more so, as many of the inferior
compositions included in the collection seem to have been anonymous, and their
authors in consequence describable only under some such common designation as
that of the cyclic poets. It is in this manner that we are to explain the
disparaging sentiment connected by Horace and others with the idea of a cyclic
writer, though no such sentiment was implied in the original meaning of the
Epic Cycle.
The poems of the Cycle were thus
mentioned in contrast and antithesis with Homer, though originally the Iliad
and Odyssey had both been included among them: and this alteration of the meaning
of the word has given birth to a mistake as to the primary purpose of the
classification, as if it had been designed especially to part off the inferior
epic productions from Homer. But while some critics are disposed to distinguish
the cyclic poets too pointedly from Homer, I conceive that Welcker goes too much into the other extreme, and identifies the Cycle too closely with
that poet. He construes it as a classification deliberately framed to comprise
all the various productions of the Homeric epic, with its unity of action and
comparative paucity, both of persons and adventures, —as opposed to the
Hesiodic epic, crowded with separate persons and pedigrees, and destitute of
central action as well as of closing catastrophe. This opinion does, indeed,
coincide to a great degree with the fact, inasmuch as few of the Hesiodic epics
appear to have been included in the Cycle : to say that none were included,
would be too much, for we cannot venture to set aside either the Theogony or
the Aegimius; but we may account for their absence perfectly well without
supposing any design to exclude them, for it is obvious that their rambling
character (like that of the Metamorphoses of Ovid) forbade the possibility of
interweaving them in any continuous series. Continuity in the series of
narrated events, coupled with a certain degree of antiquity in the poems, being
the principle on which the arrangement called the Epic Cycle was based, the
Hesiodic poems generally were excluded, not from any preconceived intention, but
because they could not be brought into harmony with such orderly reading.
What were the particular poems which
it comprised, we cannot now determine with exactness. Welcker arranges them as follows : Titanomachia, Donais,
Amazonia (or Atthis), Edipodia,
Thebais (or Expedition of Amphiaraus), Epigoni (or Alcmeonis), Minyas (or Phokais), Capture of Oechalia,
Cyprian Verses, Iliad, Athiopis, Lesser Iliad, Iliupersis or the Taking of Troy, Returns of the Heroes,
Odyssey, and Telegonia. Wuellner, Lange, and Mr. Fynes Clinton enlarge the list of cyclic poems still
farther. But all such reconstructions of the Cycle are conjectural and
destitute of authority : the only poems which we can affirm on positive grounds
to have been comprehended in it, are, first, the series respecting the heroes
of Troy, from the Cypria to the Telegonia, of which
Proclus has preserved the arguments, and which includes the Iliad and
Odyssey,—next, the old Thebais, which is expressly termed cyclic, in order to
distinguish it from the poem of the same name composed by Antimachus. In regard
to other particular compositions, we have no evidence to guide us, either for
admission or exclusion, except our general views as to the scheme upon which
the Cycle was framed. If my idea of that scheme be correct, the Alexandrine
critics arranged therein all their old epical treasures, down to the
Telegonia,—the good as well as the bad; gold, silver, and iron,—provided only
they could be pieced in with the narrative series. But I cannot venture to include,
as Mr. Clinton does, the Europia, the Phoronis, and other poems of which we know only the names,
because it is uncertain whether their contents were such as to fulfill their
primary condition : nor can I concur with him in thinking that, where there were
two or more poems of the same title and subject, one of them must necessarily
have been adopted into the Cycle to the exclusion of the others. There may have
been two Theogonies, or two Herakleias,
both comprehended in the Cycle; the purpose being (as I before remarked), not
to sift the better from the worse, but to determine some fixed order,
convenient for reading and reference, amidst a multiplicity of scattered
compositions, as the basis of a new, entire, and corrected edition.
HOMER.
Whatever may have been the principle
on which the cyclic poems were originally strung together, they are all now
lost, except those two unrivalled diamonds, whose brightness, dimming all the
rest, has alone sufficed to confer imperishable glory even upon the earliest
phase of Grecian life. It has been the natural privilege of the Iliad and
Odyssey, from the rise of Grecian philology down to the present day, to provoke
an intense curiosity, which, even in the historical and literary days of
Greece, there were no assured facts to satisfy. These compositions are the
monuments of an age essentially religious and poetical, but essentially also unphilosophical, unreflecting, and unrecording : the nature of the case forbids our having any authentic transmitted knowledge
respecting such a period; and the lesson must be learned, hard and painful
though it be, that no imaginable reach of critical acumen will of itself enable
us to discriminate fancy from reality, in the absence of a tolerable stock of
evidence. After the numberless comments and acrimonious controversies I to
which the Homeric poems have given rise, it can hardly be said that any of the
points originally doubtful have obtained a solution such as to command
universal acquiescence. To glance at all these controversies, however briefly,
would far transcend the limits of the present work; but the most abridged
Grecian history would be incomplete without some inquiry respecting the Poet
(so the Greek critics in their veneration denominated Homer), and the productions
which pass now, or have heretofore passed, under his name.
Who or what was Homer? What date is
to be assigned to him? What were his compositions?
A person, putting these questions to
Greeks of different towns and ages, would have obtained answers widely
discrepant and contradictory. Since the invaluable labors of Aristarchus and
the other Alexandrine critics on the text of the Iliad and Odyssey, it has,
indeed, been customary to regard those two (putting aside the Hymns, and a few
other minor poems) as being the only genuine Homeric compositions : and the
literary men called Chorizontes, or the Separators,
at the head of whom were Xenon and Hellanikus,
endeavored still farther to reduce the number by disconnecting the Iliad and
Odyssey, and pointing out that both could not be the work of the same author.
Throughout the whole course of Grecian antiquity, the Iliad and the Odyssey,
and the Hymns, have been received as Homeric : but if we go back to the time of
Herodotus, or still earlier, we find that several other epics also were
ascribed to Homer, —and there were not wanting critics, earlier than the
Alexandrine age, who regarded the whole Epic Cycle, together with the satirical
poem called Margites, the Batrachomyomachia,
and other smaller pieces, as Homeric works. The cyclic Thebais and the Epigoni
(whether they be two separate poems, or the latter a second part of the former)
were in early days currently ascribed to Homer : the same was the case with the
Cyprian Verses : some even attributed to him several other poems, the Capture
of Oechalia, the Lesser Iliad, the Phokais, and the Amazonia. The title of the poem called
Thebais to be styled Homeric, depends upon evidence more ancient than any which
can be produced to authenticate the Iliad and Odyssey : for Kallinus,
the ancient elegiac poet (BC. 640), mentioned Homer as the author of it,—and
his opinion was shared by many other competent judges. From the remarkable
description given by Herodotus, of the expulsion of the rhapsodes from Sicyon,
by the despot Kleisthenes, in the time of Solon
(about BC 580), we may form a probable judgment that the Thebais and the
Epigoni were then rhapsodized at Sicyon as Homeric productions. And it is clear
from the language of Herodotus, that in his time the general opinion ascribed
to Homer both the Cyprian Verses and the Epigoni, though he himself dissents.
In spite of such dissent, however, that historian must have conceived the names
of Homer and Hesiod to be nearly coextensive with the whole of the ancient epic;
otherwise, he would hardly have delivered his memorable judgment, that they two
were the framers of Grecian theogony.
The many different cities which laid
claim to the birth of Homer (seven is rather below the truth, and Smyrna and
Chios are the most prominent among them), is well known, and most of them had
legends to tell respecting his romantic parentage, his alleged blindness, and
his life of an itinerant bard, acquainted with poverty and sorrow. The
discrepancies of statement respecting the date of his reputed existence are no
less worthy of remark; for out of the eight different epochs assigned to him,
the oldest differs from the most recent by a period of four hundred and sixty
years.
Thus conflicting would have been the
answers returned in different portions of the Grecian world to any questions
respecting the person of Homer. But there were a poetical gens (fraternity or
guild) in the Ionic island of Chios, who, if the question had been put to them,
would have answered in another manner. To them, Homer was not a mere antecedent
man, of kindred nature with themselves, but a divine or semi-divine eponymous
and progenitor, whom they worshipped in their gentile sacrifices, and in whose ascendant
name and glory the individuality of every member of the gens was merged. The
compositions of each separate Homerid, or the
combined efforts of many of them in conjunction, were the works of Homer: the
name of the individual bard perishes and his authorship is forgotten, but the
common gentile father lives and grows in renown, from generation to generation,
by the genius of his self-renewing sons.
Such was the conception entertained
of Homer by the poetical gens called Homerids; and in the general obscurity of
the whole case, I lean towards it as the most plausible conception. Homer is
not only the reputed author of the various compositions emanating from the
gentile members, but also the recipient of the many different legends and of
the divine genealogy, which it pleases their imagination to confer upon him.
Such manufacture of fictitious personality, and such perfect incorporation of
the entities of religion and fancy with the real world, is a process familiar,
and even habitual, in the retrospective vision of the Greeks.
PERSONALITY OF HOMER.
It is to be remarked, that the
poetical gens here brought to view, the Homerids, are of indisputable
authenticity. Their existence and their considerations were maintained down to
the historical times in the island of Chios. If the Homerids were still
conspicuous, even in the days of Akusilaus, Pindar, Hellanikus, and Plato, when their productive invention had
ceased, and when they had become only guardians and distributors, in common
with others, of the treasures bequeathed by their predecessors,—far more
exalted must their position have been three centuries before, while they were
still the inspired creators of epic novelty, and when the absence of writing
assured to them the undisputed monopoly of their own compositions.
Homer, then, is no individual man,
but the divine or heroic father (the ideas of worship and ancestry coalescing,
as they constantly did in the Grecian mind) of the gentile Homerids, and he is
the author of the Thebais, the Epigoni, the Cyprian Verses, the Proems, or
Hymns, and other poems, in the same sense in which he is the author of the
Iliad and Odyssey,—assuming that these various compositions emanate, as perhaps
they may, from different individuals numbered among the Homerids. But this
disallowance of the historical personality of Homer is quite distinct from the
question, with which it has been often confounded, whether the Iliad and
Odyssey are originally entire poems, and whether by one author or otherwise. To
us, the name of Homer means these two poems, and little else : we desire to
know as much as can be learned respecting their date, their original
composition, their preservation, and their mode of communication to the public.
All these questions are more or less complicated one with the other.
Concerning the date of the poems, we
have no other information except the various affirmations respecting the age of
Homer, which differ among themselves (as I have before observed) by an interval
of four hundred and sixty years, and which for the most part determine the date
of Homer by reference to some other event, itself fabulous and
unauthenticated,— such as the Trojan war, the Return of the Herakleids,
or the Ionic migration. Krates placed homer earlier
than the Return of the Herakleids, and less than
eighty years after the Trojan war: Eratosthenes put him one hundred years after
the Trojan war : Aristotle, Aristarchus, and Castor made his birth contemporary
with the Ionic migration, while Apollodorus brings him down to one hundred
years after that event, or two hundred and forty years after the taking of
Troy. Thucydides assigns to him a date much subsequent to the Trojan war. On
the other hand, Theopompus and Euphorion refer his age to the far more recent period of the Lydian king, Gyges, (Ol. 18-23, BC 708-688,)
and put him five hundred years after the Trojan epoch. What were the grounds of
these various conjectures, we do not know; though in the statements of Krates and Eratosthenes, we may pretty well divine. But the
oldest dictum preserved to us respecting the date of Homer,—meaning thereby the
date of the Iliad and Odyssey,— appears to me at the same time the most
credible, and the most consistent with the general history of the ancient epic.
Herodotus places Homer four hundred years before himself; taking his departure,
not from any fabulous event, but from a point of real and authentic time. Four
centuries anterior to Herodotus would be a period commencing with 880 BC so
that the composition of the Homeric poems would thus fall in a space between
850 and 800 BC. We may gather from the language of Herodotus that this was his
own judgment, opposed to a current opinion, which assigned the poet to an
earlier epoch.
To place the Iliad and Odyssey at
some periods between 850 BC and 776 BC., appears to me more probable than any
other date, anterior or posterior, more probable than the latter, because we
are justified in believing these two poems to be older than Arktinus,
who comes shortly after the first Olympiad; more probable than the former,
because, the farther we push the poems back, the more do we enhance the wonder
of their preservation, already sufficiently great, down from such an age and
society to the historical times.
HOMERIC POEMS INTENDED FOR HEARERS.
The mode in which these poems, and
indeed all poems, epic as well as lyric, down to the age (probably) of
Peisistratus, were circulated and brought to bear upon the public, deserves
particular attention. They were not read by individuals alone and apart, but
sung or recited at festivals or to assembled companies. This seems to be one of
the few undisputed facts with regard to the great poet : for even those who
maintain that the Iliad and Odyssey were preserved by means of writing, seldom
contend that they were read.
In appreciating the effect of the
poems, we must always take account of this great difference between early
Greece and our own times; between the congregation mustered at a solemn
festival, stimulated by community of sympathy, listening to a measured and
musical recital from the lips of trained bards or rhapsodes, whose matter was
supposed to have been inspired by the Muse, and the solitary reader, with a
manuscript before him; such manuscript being, down to a very late period in
Greek literature, indifferently written, without division into parts, and
without marks of punctuation. As in the case of dramatic performances, in all
ages, so in that of the early Grecian epic, a very large proportion of its
impressive effect was derived from the talent of the reciter and the force of
the general accompaniments, and would have disappeared altogether in solitary
reading.
Originally, the bard sung his own
epical narrative, commencing with a proemium or hymn
to one of the gods : his profession was separate and special, like that of the
carpenter, the leech, or the prophet: his manner and enunciation must have
required particular training no less than his imaginative faculty. His
character presents itself in the Odyssey as one highly esteemed; and in the
Iliad, even Achilles does not disdain to touch the lyre with his own hands, and
to sing heroic deeds?
Not only did the Iliad and Odyssey,
and the poems embodied in the Epic Cycle, produce all their impression and gain
all their renown by this process of oral delivery, but even the lyric and
choric poets who succeeded them were known and felt in the same way by the
general public, even after the full establishment of habits of reading among
lettered men. While in the ease of the epic, the recitation or singing had been
extremely simple, and the measure comparatively little diversified, with no other
accompaniment than that of the four-stringed harp,—all the variations superinduced upon the original hexameter, beginning with
the pentameter and iambus, and proceeding step by step to the complicated
strophes of Pindar and the tragic writers, still left the general effect of the
poetry greatly dependent upon voice and accompaniments, and pointedly
distinguished from mere solitary reading of the words. And in the dramatic
poetry, the last in order of time, the declamation and gesture of the speaking
actor alternated with the song and dance of the chorus, and with the
instruments of musicians, the whole being set off by imposing visible
decorations. Now both dramatic effect and song are familiar in modern times, so
that every man knows the difference between reading the words and bearing them
under the appropriate circumstances : but poetry, as such, is, and has now long
been, so exclusively enjoyed by reading, that it requires an especial memento
to bring us back to the time when the Iliad and Odyssey were addressed only to
the ear and feelings of a promiscuous and sympathizing multitude.
Readers there were none, at least
until the century preceding Solon and Peisistratus : from that time forward,
they gradually increased both in number and influence; though doubtless small,
even in the most literary period of Greece, as compared with modern European
society. So far as the production of beautiful epic poetry was concerned,
however, the select body of instructed readers, furnished a less potent
stimulus than the unlettered and listening crowd of the earlier periods. The
poems of Choerilus and Antimachus, towards the close
of the Peloponnesian war, though admired by erudite men, never acquired
popularity; and the emperor Hadrian failed in his attempt to bring the latter
poet into fashion at the expense of Homer.
It will be seen by what has been
here stated, that that class of men, who formed the medium of communication
between the verse and the ear, were of the highest importance in the ancient
world, and especially in the earlier periods of its career,— the bards and
rhapsodes for the epic, the singers for the lyric, the actors and singers
jointly with the dancers for the chorus and drama. The lyric and dramatic poets
taught with their own lips the delivery of their compositions, and so
prominently did this business of teaching present itself to the view of the
public, that the name Didaskalia, by which the
dramatic exhibition was commonly designated, derived from thence its origin.
UNDESERVED CONDEMNATION OF
RHAPSODES.
Among the number of rhapsodes who
frequented the festivals at a time when Grecian cities were multiplied and easy of access, for the recitation of the ancient epic,
there must have been of course great differences of excellence; but that the more
considerable individuals of the class were elaborately trained and highly
accomplished in the exercise of their profession, we may assume as certain. But
it happens that Socrates, with his two pupils Plato and Xenophon, speak
contemptuously of their merits; and many persons have been disposed, somewhat
too readily, to admit this sentence of condemnation as conclusive, without
taking account of the point of view from which it was delivered. These
philosophers considered Homer and other poets with a view to instruction,
ethical doctrine, and virtuous practice: they analyzed the characters whom the
poet described, sifted the value of the lessons conveyed, and often struggled
to discover a hidden meaning, where they disapproved that which was apparent.
When they found a man like the rhapsode, who professed to impress the Homeric
narrative upon an audience, and yet either never meddled at all, or meddled
unsuccessfully, with the business of exposition, they treated him with
contempt; indeed, Socrates depreciates the poets themselves, much upon the same
principle, as dealing with matters of which they could render no rational
account. It was also the habit of Plato and Xenophon to disparage generally
professional exertion of talent for the purpose of gaining a livelihood,
contrasting it often in an indelicate manner with the gratuitous teaching and
ostentatious poverty of their master. But we are not warranted in judging the
rhapsodes by such a standard. Though they were not philosophers or moralists,
it was their province—and it had been so, long before the philosophical point
of view was opened—to bring their poet home to the bosoms and emotions of an
assembled crowd, and to penetrate themselves with his meaning so far as was
suitable for that purpose, adapting to it the appropriate graces of action and
intonation. In this their genuine task they were valuable members of the
Grecian community, and seem to have possessed all the qualities necessary for
success.
These rhapsodes, the successors of
the primitive aoedi,
or bards, seem to have been distinguished from them by the discontinuance of
all musical accompaniment. Originally, the bard sung, enlivening the song with
occasional touches of the simple four-stringed harp: his successor, the
rhapsode, recited, holding in his hand nothing but a branch of laurel and
depending for affect upon voice and manner,—a species of musical and
rhythmical declamation, which gradually increased in vehement emphasis and
gesticulation until it approached to that of the dramatic actor. At what time
this change took place, or whether the two different modes of enunciating the
ancient epic may for a certain period have gone on simultaneously, we have no
means of determining. Hesiod receives from the Muse a branch of laurel, as a token
of his ordination into their service, which marks him for a rhapsode; while the
ancient bard with his harp is still recognized in the Homeric Hymn to the Delian Apollo, as efficient and popular at the Panionic festivals in the island of Delos. Perhaps the
improvements made in the harp, to which three strings, in addition to the
original four, were attached by Terpander (BC 660),
and the growing complication of instrumental music generally, may have
contributed to discredit the primitive accompaniment, and thus to promote the
practice of recital : the story, that Terpander himself composed music, not only for hexameter poems of his own, but also for
those of Homer, seems to indicate that the music which preceded him was ceasing
to find favor. By whatever steps the change from the bard to the rhapsode took
place, certain it is that before the time of Solon, the latter was the
recognized and exclusive organ of the old Epic; sometimes in short fragments
before private companies, by single rhapsodes, sometimes several rhapsodes in
continuous succession at a public festival.
HOMERIC POEMS. WRITTEN OR UNWRITTEN
Respecting the mode in which the
Homeric poems were preserved, during the two centuries (or as some think,
longer interval) between their original composition and the period shortly
preceding Solon, and respecting their original composition and subsequent
changes, there are wide differences of opinion among able critics. Were they
preserved with or without being written? Was the Iliad originally composed as
one poem, and the Odyssey in like manner, or is each of them an aggregation of
parts originally self-existent and unconnected? Was the authorship of each poem
single-headed or many-headed?
Either tacitly or explicitly, these
questions have been generally coupled together and discussed with reference to
each other, by inquiries into the Homeric poems; though Mr. Payne Knight's
Prolegomena have the merit of keeping them distinct. Half a century ago, the
acute and valuable Prolegomena of F. A. Wolf, turning to account the Venetian Scholia which had then been recently published, first
opened philosophical discussion as to the history of the Homeric text. A
considerable part of that dissertation (though by no means the whole) is
employed in vindicating the position, previously announced by Bentley, among
others, that the separate constituent portions of the Iliad and Odyssey had not
been cemented together into any compact body and unchangeable order until the
days of Peisistratus, in the sixth century before Christ. As a step towards
that conclusion, Wolf maintained that no written copies of either poem could be
shown to have existed during the earlier times to which their composition is
referred, and that without writing, neither the perfect symmetry of so complicated
a work could have been originally conceived by any poet, nor, if realized by
him, transmitted with assurance to posterity. The absence of easy and
convenient writing, such as must be indispensably supposed for long
manuscripts, among the early Greeks, was thus one of the points in Wolf's case
against the primitive integrity of the Iliad and Odyssey. By Nitzsch and other leading opponents of Wolf, the connection
of the one with the other seems to have been accepted as he originally put it;
and it has been considered incumbent, on those who defended the ancient
aggregate character of the Iliad and Odyssey, to maintain that they were
written poems from the beginning.
To me it appears that the
architectonic functions ascribed by Wolf to Peisistratus and his associates, in
reference to the Homeric poems, are nowise admissible. But much would
undoubtedly be gained towards that view of the question, if it could be shown
that, in order to controvert it, we were driven to the necessity of admitting
long written poems in the ninth century before the Christian era. Few things,
in my opinion, can be more improbable : and Mr. Payne Knight, opposed as he is
to the Wolfian hypothesis, admits this no less than
Wolf himself. The traces of writing in Greece, even in the seventh century
before the Christian era, are exceedingly trifling. We have no remaining
inscription earlier than the 40th Olympiad, and the early inscriptions are rude
and unskillfully executed: nor can we even assure ourselves whether Archilochus, Simonides of Amorgus, Kallinus, Tyrtxus, Xanthus, and the other early elegiac and lyric
poets, committed their compositions to writing, or at what time the practice of
doing so became familiar. The first positive ground, which authorizes us to
presume the existence of a manuscript of Homer, is in the famous ordinance of
Solon with regard to the rhapsodes at the Panathenma;
but for what length of time, previously, manuscripts had existed, we are unable
to say.
Those who maintain the Homeric poems
to have been written from the beginning, rest their case, not upon positive
proofs, nor yet upon the existing habits of society with regard to poetry, for
they admit generally that the Iliad and Odyssey were not read, but recited and
heard, but upon the supposed necessity that there must have been manuscripts,
to insure the preservation of the poems, the unassisted memory of reciters
being neither sufficient nor trustworthy. But here we only escape a smaller
difficulty by running into a greater; for the existence of trained bards,
gifted with extraordinary memory, is far less astonishing than that of long
manuscripts in an age essentially non-reading and non-writing, and when even
suitable instruments and materials for the process arc not obvious. Moreover,
there is a strong positive reason for believing that the bard was under no
necessity for refreshing his memory by consulting a manuscript. For if such had
been the fact, blindness would have been a disqualification for the profession,
which we know that it was not; as well from the example of Demodokus in the Odyssey, as from that of the blind bard of Chios, in the hymn to the Delian Apollo, whom Thucydides, as well as the general
tenor of Grecian legend, identifies with Homer himself: The author of that
Hymn, be he who he may, could never have described a blind man as attaining the
utmost perfection in his art, if he had been conscious that the memory of the
bard was only maintained by constant reference to the manuscript in his chest.
Nor will it be found, after all,
that the effort of memory required, either from bards or rhapsodes, even for
the longest of these old Epic poems, though doubtless great, was at all superhuman.
Taking the case with reference to the entire Iliad and Odyssey, we know that
there were educated gentlemen at Athens who could repeat both poems by heart:
but in the professional recitations, we are not to imagine that the same person
did go through the whole : the recitation was essentially a joint undertaking,
and the rhapsodes who visited a festival would naturally understand among
themselves which part of the poem should devolve upon each particular
individual. Under such circumstances, and with such means of preparation
beforehand, the quantity of verse which a rhapsode could deliver would be
measured, not so much by the exhaustion of his memory, as by the physical
sufficiency of his voice, having reference to the sonorous, emphatic, and
rhythmical pronunciation required from him.
But what guarantee have we for the
exact transmission of the text for a space of two centuries by simply oral
means? It may be replied, that oral transmission would hand down the text as
exactly as in point of fact it was handed down. The great lines of each poem,
the order of parts, the vein of Homeric feeling, and the general style of
locution, and, for the most part, the true words, would be maintained : for the
professional training of the rhapsode, over and above the precision of his
actual memory, would tend to Homerize his mind (if
the expression may be permitted), and to restrain him within this magic circle.
On the other hand, in respect to the details of the text, we should expect that
there would be wide differences and numerous inaccuracies : and so there really
were, as the records contained in the Scholia,
together with the passages cited in ancient authors, but not found in our
Homeric text, abundantly testify.
Moreover, the state of the Iliad and
Odyssey, in respect to the letter called the Digamma, affords a proof that they
were recited for a considerable period before they were committed to writing,
insomuch that the oral pronunciation underwent during the interval a sensible
change. At the time when these poems were composed, the Digamma was an
effective consonant, and figured as such in the structure of the verse: at the
time when they were committed to writing, it had ceased to be pronounced, and
therefore never found a place in any of the manuscripts, insomuch that the
Alexandrine critics, though they knew of its existence in the much later poems
of Alkaeus and Sappho, never recognized it in Homer.
The hiatus, and the various perplexities of metre occasioned by the loss of the Digamma, were corrected by different grammatical
stratagems. But the whole history of this lost letter is very curious, and is
rendered intelligible only by the supposition that the Iliad and Odyssey
belonged for a wide space of time to the memory, the voice, and the ear,
exclusively.
COMMENCEMENT OF WRITING
At what period these poems, or,
indeed, any other Greek poems, first began to be written, must be matter of
conjecture, though there is ground for assurance that it was before the time of
Solon. If, in the absence of evidence, we may venture upon naming any more
determinate period, the question at once suggests itself, what were the
purposes which, in that stage of society, a manuscript at its first
commencement must have been intended to answer? For whom was a written Iliad necessary?
Not for the rhapsodes; for with them it was not only planted in the memory, but
also interwoven with the feelings, and conceived in conjunction with all those flexions and intonations of voice, pauses, and other oral
artifices, which were required for emphatic delivery, and which the naked
manuscript could never reproduce. Not for the general public, they were
accustomed to receive it with its rhapsodic delivery, and with its
accompaniments of a solemn and crowded festival. The only persons for whom the
written Iliad would be suitable, would be a select few; studious and curious
men, a class of readers, capable of analyzing the complicated emotions which
they had experienced as hearers in the crowd, and who would, on perusing the
written words, realize in their imaginations a sensible portion of the
impression communicated by the reciter.
Incredible as the statement may seem
in an age like the present, there is in all early societies, and there was in
early Greece, a time when no such reading class existed. If we could discover
at what time such a class first began to be formed, we should be able to make a
guess at the time when the old Epic poems were first committed to writing. Now
the period which may with the greatest probability be fixed upon as having
first witnessed the formation even of the narrowest reading class in Greece, is
the middle of the seventh century before the Christian era (B. 660 to BC 630),
the age of Terpander, Kallinus, Archilochus, Simonides of Amorgus, etc. I ground this supposition on the change then
operated in the character and tendencies of Grecian poetry and music, the
elegiac and iambic measures having been introduced as rivals to the primitive
hexameter, and poetical compositions having been transferred from the epical
past to the affairs of present and real life. Such a change was important at a
time when poetry was the only known mode of publication (to use a modern phrase
not altogether suitable, yet the nearest approaching to the sense). It argued a
new way of looking at the old epical treasures of the people, as well as a
thirst for new poetical effect; and the men who stood forward in it may well be
considered as desirous to study, and competent to criticize, from their own
individual point of view, the written words of the Homeric rhapsodes, just as
we are told that Kallinus both noticed and eulogized
the Thebais as the production of Homer. There seems, therefore, ground for
conjecturing, that (for the use of this newly-formed and important, but very
narrow class) manuscripts of the Homeric poems and other old epics, the Thebais
and the Cypria as well as the Iliad and the Odyssey,
began to be compiled towards the middle of the seventh century BC, and the
opening of Egypt to Grecian commerce, which took place about the same period,
would furnish increased facilities for obtaining the requisite papyrus to write
upon. A reading class, when once formed, would doubtless slowly increase, and
the number of manuscripts along with it; so that before the time of Solon,
fifty years afterwards, both readers and manuscripts, though still
comparatively few, might have attained a certain recognized authority, and
formed a tribunal of reference, against the carelessness of individual
rhapsodes.
We may, I think, consider the Iliad
and Odyssey to have been preserved without the aid of writing, for a period
near upon two centuries. But is it true, as Wolf imagined, and as other able
critics have imagined, also, that the separate portions of which these two
poems are composed were originally distinct epical ballads, each constituting a
separate whole and intended for separate recitation? Is it true, that they had
not only no common author, but originally, neither common purpose nor fixed
order, and that their first permanent arrangement and integration was delayed
for three centuries, and accomplished at last only by the taste of Peisistratus
conjoined with various lettered friends?
This hypothesis, to which the genius
of Wolf first gave celebrity, but which has been since enforced more in detail
by others, especially by William Muller and Laehmann,
appears to me not only unsupported by any sufficient testimony, but also
opposed to other testimony as well as to a strong force of internal
probability. The authorities quoted by Wolf are Josephus, Cicero, and Pausanias
: Josephus mentions nothing about Peisistratus, but merely states (what we may
accept as the probable fact) that the Homeric poems were originally unwritten,
and preserved only in songs or recitations, from which they were at a subsequent
period put into writing : hence many of the discrepancies in the text. On the
other hand, Cicero and Pausanias go farther, and affirm that Peisistratus both
collected, and arranged in the existing order, the rhapsodies of the Iliad and
Odyssey, (implied as poems originally entire, and subsequently broken into
pieces,) which he found partly confused and partly isolated from each other,
each part being then remembered only in its own portion of the Grecian world.
Respecting Hipparchus the son of Peisistratus, too, we are told in the
Pseudo-Platonic dialogue which bears his name, that he was the first to
introduce into Attica, the poetry of Homer, and that he prescribed to the
rhapsodes to recite the parts of the Panathenaic festival in regular sequence.
Wolf and William Muller occasionally
speak as if they admitted something like an Iliad and Odyssey as established
aggregates prior to Peisistratus; but for the most part they represent him or
his associates as having been the first to put together Homeric poems which
were before distinct and self-existent compositions. And Lachmann, the recent
expositor of the same theory, ascribes to Peisistratus still more unequivocally
this original integration of parts in reference to the Iliad, —distributing the
first twenty-two books of the poem into sixteen separate songs, and treating it
as ridiculous to imagine that the fusion of these songs, into an order such as
we now read, belongs to any date earlier than Peisistratus.
REGULATIONS OF SOLON.
Upon this theory we may remark,
first, that it stands opposed to the testimony existing respecting the
regulations of Solon; who, before the time of Peisistratus, had enforced a
fixed order of recitation on the rhapsodes of the Iliad at the Panathenaic
festival; not only directing that they should go through the rhapsodies
seriatim, and without omission or corruption, but also establishing a prompter
or censorial authority to insure obedience, which implies the existence (at the
same time that it proclaims the occasional infringement) of an orderly
aggregate, as well as or manuscripts professedly complete. Next, the theory
ascribes to Peisistratus a character not only materially different from what is
indicated by Cicero and Pausanias, who represent him, not as having put
together atoms originally distinct, but as the renovator of an ancient order
subsequently lost, but also in itself unintelligible, and inconsistent with
Grecian habit and feeling. That Peisistratus should take pains to repress the
license, or make up for the unfaithful memory, of individual rhapsodes, and to
ennoble the Panathenaic festival by the most correct recital of a great and
venerable poem, according to the standard received among the best judges in
Greece, this is a task both suitable to his position, and requiring nothing
more than an improved recension, together with exact
adherence to it on the part of the rhapsodes.
But what motive had he to string
together several poems, previously known only as separate, into one new whole?
What feeling could he gratify by introducing the extensive changes and
transpositions surmised by Lachmann, for the purpose of binding together
sixteen songs, which the rhapsodes are assumed to have been accustomed to
recite, and the people to hear, each by itself apart?
Peisistratus was not a poet, seeking
to interest the public mind by new creations and combinations, but a ruler,
desirous to impart solemnity to a great religious festival in his native city.
Now such a purpose would be answered by selecting, amidst the divergences of
rhapsodes in different parts of Greece, that order of text which intelligent
men could approve as a return to the pure and pristine Iliad; but it would be
defeated if he attempted large innovations of his own, and brought out for the
first time a new Iliad by blending together, altering, and transposing, many
old and well-known songs. A novelty so bold would have been more likely to
offend than to please both the critics and the multitude. And if it were even
enforced, by authority, at Athens, no probable reason can be given why all the
other towns, and all the rhapsodes throughout Greece, should abnegate their
previous habits in favor of it, since Athens at that time enjoyed no political
ascendency such as she acquired during the following century. On the whole, it
will appear that the character and position of Peisistratus himself go far to
negative the function which Wolf and Lachmann put upon him. His interference
presupposes a certain foreknown and ancient aggregate, the main lineaments of which
were familiar to the Grecian public, although many of the rhapsodes in their
practice may have deviated from it both by omission and interpolation. In
correcting the Athenian recitations conformably with such understood general
type, he might hope both to procure respect for Athens, and to constitute a
fashion for the rest of Greece. But this step of "collecting the torn body
of sacred Homer," is something generically different from the composition
of a new Iliad out of preexisting songs, the former is as easy, suitable, and
promising, as the latter is violent and gratuitous.
To sustain the inference, that
Peisistratus was the first architect of the Iliad and Odyssey, it ought at
least to be shown that no other long and continuous poems existed during the
earlier centuries. But the contrary of this is known to be the fact. The Aethiopis of Arktinus, which
contained nine thousand one hundred verses, dates from a period more than two
centuries earlier than Peisistratus : several other of the lost cyclic epics,
some among them of considerable length, appear during the century succeeding Arktinus; and it is important to notice that three or four
at least of these poems passed currently under the name of Homer. There is no
greater intrinsic difficulty in supposing long epics to have begun with the
Iliad and Odyssey than with the Ethiopis : the
ascendency of the name of Homer and the subordinate position of Arktinus, in the history of early Grecian poetry, tend to
prove the former in preference to the latter.
AGGREGATE ILIAD AND ODYSSEY.
Moreover, we find particular
portions of the Iliad, which expressly pronounce themselves, by their own
internal evidence, as belonging to a large whole, and not as separate integers.
We can hardly conceive the Catalogue in the second book, except as a fractional
composition, and with reference to a series of approaching exploits; for, taken
apart by itself, such a barren enumeration of names could have stimulated
neither the fancy of the poet, nor the attention of the listeners. But the
Homeric Catalogue had acquired a sort of canonical authority even in the time
of Solon, insomuch that he interpolated a line into it, or was accused of doing
so, for the purpose of gaining a disputed point against the Megarians,
who, on their side, set forth another version. No such established reverence
could have been felt for this document, unless there had existed for a long
time prior to Peisistratus, the habit of regarding and listening to the Iliad
as a continuous poem. And when the philosopher Xenophanes, contemporary with
Peisistratus, noticed Homer as the universal teacher, and denounced him as an
unworthy describer of the gods, he must have connected this great mental sway,
not with a number of unconnected rhapsodies, but with an aggregate Iliad and
Odyssey; probably with other poems, also, ascribed to the same author, such as
the Cypria, Epigoni, and Thebais.
We find, it is true, references in
various authors to portions of the Iliad, each by its own separate name, such
as the Teichomachy, the Aristeia (preeminent exploits) of Diomedes, or Agamemnon, the Doloneia,
or Night-expedition (of Dolon as well as of Odysseus
and Diomedes), etc., and hence, it has been concluded, that these portions
originally existed as separate poems, before they were cemented together into
an Iliad. But such references prove nothing to the point; for until the Iliad
was divided by Aristarchus and his colleagues into a given number of books, or
rhapsodies, designated by the series of letters in the alphabet, there was no
method of calling attention to any particular portion of the poem except by
special indication of its subject-matter. Authors subsequent to Peisistratus,
such as Herodotus and Plato, who unquestionably conceived the Iliad as a whole,
cite the separate fractions of it by designations of this sort.
The foregoing remarks on the Wolfian hypothesis respecting the text of the Iliad, tend
to separate two points which are by no means necessarily connected, though that
hypothesis, as set forth by Wolf himself, by W. Muller, and by Lachmann,
presents the two in conjunction. First, was the Iliad originally projected and
composed by one author, and as one poem, or were the different parts composed
separately and by unconnected authors, and subsequently strung together into an
aggregate? Secondly, assuming that the internal evidence of the poem negative
the former supposition, and drive us upon the latter, was the construction of
the whole poem deferred, and did the parts exist only in their separate state,
until a period so late as the reign of Peisistratus? It is obvious that these
two questions are essentially separate, and that a man may believe the Iliad to
have been put together out of preexisting songs, without recognizing the age of
Peisistratus as the period of its first compilation. Now, whatever may be the
steps through which the poem passed to its ultimate integrity, there is
sufficient reason for believing that they had been accomplished long before
that period : the friends of Peisistratus found an Iliad already existing and
already ancient in their time, even granting that the poem had not been
originally born in a state of unity. Moreover, the Alexandrine critics, whose
remarks are preserved in the Scholia, do not even
notice the Peisistratic recension among the many manuscript, which they had before them: and Mr. Payne Knight
justly infers from their silence that either they did not possess it, or it was
in their eyes of no great authority; which could never have been the case if it
had been the prime originator of Homeric unity.
The line of argument, by which the
advocates of Wolf's hypothesis negative the primitive unity of the poem,
consists in exposing gaps, incongruities, contradictions, etc., between the
separate parts. Now, if in spite of all these incoherencies, standing mementos
of an antecedent state of separation, the component poems were made to coalesce
so intimately as to appear as if they had been one from the beginning, we can
better understand the complete success of the proceeding and the universal
prevalence of the illusion, by supposing such coalescence to have taken place
at a very early period, during the productive days of epical genius, and before
the growth of reading and criticism. The longer the aggregation of the separate
poems was deferred, the harder it would be to obliterate in men's minds the
previous state of separation, and to make them accept the new aggregate as an
original unity. The bards or rhapsodes might have found comparatively little
difficulty in thus piecing together distinct songs, during the ninth or eighth
century before Christ; but if we suppose the process to be deferred until the
latter half of the sixth century, if we imagine that Solon, with all his
contemporaries and predecessors, knew nothing about any aggregate Iliad, but
was accustomed to read and hear only those sixteen distinct epical pieces into
which Lachmann would dissect the Iliad, each of the sixteen bearing a separate
name of its own, no compilation then for the first time made by the friends of
Peisistratus could have effaced the established habit, and planted itself in
the general convictions of Greece as the primitive Homeric production. Had the
sixteen pieces remained disunited and individualized down to the time of
Peisistratus, they would in all probability have continued so ever afterwards;
nor could the extensive changes and transpositions which (according to Lachmann’s theory) were required to melt them down into our
present Iliad, have obtained at that late period universal acceptance. Assuming
it to be true that such changes and transpositions did really take place, they
must at least be referred to a period greatly earlier than Peisistratus or
Solon.
The whole tenor of the poems
themselves confirms what is here remarked. There is nothing either in the Iliad
or Odyssey which savors of modernism, applying that term to the age of
Peisistratus; nothing which brings to our view the alterations, brought about
by two centuries, in the Greek language, the coined money, the habits of writing
and reading, the despotisms and republican governments, the close military
array, the improved construction of ships, the Amphiktyonic convocations, the mutual frequentation of religious festivals, the Oriental and
Egyptian veins of religion, etc., familiar to the latter epoch. These
alterations Onomakritus and the other literary
friends of Peisistratus, could hardly have failed to notice even without
design, had they then for the first time undertaken the task of piecing
together many self-existent epics into one large aggregate. Everything in the
two great Homeric poems, both in substance and in language, belongs to an age
two or three centuries earlier than Peisistratus. Indeed, even the
interpolations (or those passages which on the best grounds are pronounced to
be such) betray no trace of the sixth century before Christ, and may well have
been heard by Archilochus and Kallinus,
in some cases even by Arktinus and Hesiod, as genuine
Homeric matter. As far as the evidences on the case, as well internal as
external, enable us to judge, we seem warranted in believing that the Iliad and
Odyssey were recited substantially as they now stand, (always allowing for
partial divergences of text, and interpolations,) in 776 BC, our first
trustworthy mark of Grecian time. And this ancient date, let it be added, as it
is the best-authenticated fact, so it is also the most important attribute of
the Homeric poems, considered in reference to Grecian history. For they thus
afford us an insight into the ante-historical character of the Greeks, enabling
us to trace the subsequent forward march of the nation, and to seize
instructive contrasts between their former and their later condition.
DIFFICULTIES INVOLVING THE SUBJECT.
Rejecting, therefore, the idea of
compilation by Peisistratus, and referring the present state of the Iliad and
Odyssey to a period more than two centuries earlier, the question still
remains, by what process, or through whose agency, they reached that state? Is
each poem the work of one author, or of several? If the latter, do all the
parts belong to the same age? What ground is there for believing, that any or
all of these parts existed before, as separate poems, and have been
accommodated to the place in which they now appear, by more or less systematic
alteration?
The acute and valuable Prolegomena
of Wolf, half a century ago, powerfully turned the attention of scholars to the
necessity of considering the Iliad and Odyssey with reference to the age and
society in which they arose, and to the material differences in this respect
between Homer and more recent epic poets. Since that time, an elaborate study
has been bestowed upon the early manifestations of poetry (Sagen-poesie)
among other nations; and the German critics especially, among whom this description
of literature has been most cultivated, have selected it as the only
appropriate analogy for the Homeric poems. Such poetry, consisting for the most
part of short, artless effusions, with little of deliberate or far-sighted
combination, has been assumed by many critics as a fit standard to apply for
measuring the capacities of the Homeric age; an age exclusively of speakers,
singers, and hearers, not of readers or writers. In place of the unbounded
admiration which was felt for Homer, not merely as a poet of detail, but as
constructor of a long epic, at the time when Wolf wrote his Prolegomena, the
tone of criticism passed to the opposite extreme, and attention was fixed
entirely upon the defects in the arrangement of the Iliad and Odyssey. Whatever
was to be found in them of symmetry or pervading system, was pronounced to be
decidedly post-Homeric. Under such preconceived anticipations, Homer seems to
have been generally studied in Germany, during the generation succeeding Wolf;
the negative portion of whose theory was usually admitted, though as to the
positive substitute, what explanation was to be given of the history and
present constitution of the Homeric poems, there was by no means the like
agreement. Dining the last ten years, however, a contrary tendency has
manifested itself; the Wolfian theory has been
reexamined and shaken by Nitzsch, who, as well as 0.
Muller, Welcker, and other scholars, have revived the
idea of original Homeric unity, under certain modifications. The change in
Goethe's opinion, coincident with this new direction, is recorded in one of his
latest works. On the other hand, the original opinion of Wolf has also been
reproduced within the last five years, and fortified with several new
observations on the text of the Iliad, by Lachmann.
The point is thus still under
controversy among able scholars, and is probably destined to remain so. For, in
truth, our means of knowledge are so limited, that no man can produce arguments
sufficiently cogent to contend against opposing preconceptions; and it creates
a painful sentiment of diffidence when we read the expressions of equal and
absolute persuasion with which the two opposite conclusions have both been
advanced. We have nothing to teach us the history of these poems except the poems
themselves. Not only do we possess no collateral information respecting them or
their authors, but we have no one to describe to us the people or the age in
which they originated; our knowledge respecting contemporary Homeric society,
is collected exclusively from the Homeric compositions themselves. We are
ignorant whether any other, or what other, poems preceded them, or divided with
them the public favor; nor have we anything better than conjecture to determine
either the circumstances under which they were brought before the hearers, or
the conditions which a bard of that day was required to satisfy. On all these
points, moreover, the age of Thucydides and Plato seems to have been no better
informed than we are, except in so far as they could profit by the analogies of
the cyclic and other epic poems, which would doubtless in many cases have
afforded valuable aid.
Nevertheless, no classical scholar
can be easy without some opinion respecting the authorship of these immortal
poems. And the more defective the evidence we possess, the more essential is it
that all that evidence should be marshaled in the clearest order, and its
bearing upon the points in controversy distinctly understood beforehand. Both
these conditions seem to have been often neglected, throughout the
long-continued Homeric discussion.
To illustrate the first point :
Since two poems are comprehended in the problem to be solved, the natural
process would be, first, to study the easier of the two, and then to apply the
conclusions thence deduced as a means of explaining the other. Now, the
Odyssey, looking at its aggregate character, is incomparably more easy to
comprehend than the Iliad. Yet most Homeric critics apply the microscope at
once, and in the first instance, to the Iliad.
To illustrate the second point :
What evidence is sufficient to negative the supposition that the Iliad or the
Odyssey is a poem originally and intentionally one? Not simply particular gaps
and contradictions, though they be even gross and numerous; but the preponderance
of these proofs of mere unprepared coalescence over the other proofs of
designed adaptation scattered throughout the whole poem. For the poet (or the
cooperating poets, if more than one) may have intended to compose an harmonious
whole, but may have realized their intention incompletely, and left partial
faults; or, perhaps, the contradictory lines may have crept in through a
corrupt text. A survey of the whole poem is necessary to determine the
question; and this necessity, too, has not always been attended to.
HOMERIC UNITY.
If it had happened that the Odyssey
had been preserved to us alone, without the Iliad, I think the dispute
respecting Homeric unity would never have been raised. For the former is, in my
judgment, pervaded almost from beginning to end by marks of designed adaptation;
and the special faults which Wolf, W. Muller, and B. Thiersch,
have singled out for the purpose of disproving such unity of intention, are so
few, and of so little importance, that they would have been universally
regarded as mere instances of haste or unskillfulness on the part of the poet,
had they not been seconded by the far more powerful battery opened against the
Iliad. These critics, having laid down their general presumptions against the
antiquity of the long epopee, illustrate their principles by exposing the many
flaws and fissures in the Iliad, and then think it sufficient if they can show
a few similar defects in the Odyssey,— as if the breaking up of Homeric unity
in the former naturally entailed a similar necessity with regard to the latter;
and their method of proceeding, contrary to the rule above laid down, puts the
more difficult problem in the foreground, as a means of solution for the
easier. We can hardly wonder, however, that they have applied their
observations in the first instance to the Iliad, because it is in every man's
esteem the more marked, striking, and impressive poem of the two,—and the
character of Homer is more intimately identified with it than with the Odyssey.
This may serve as an explanation of the course pursued; but be the case as it
may in respect to comparative poetical merit, it is not the less true, that, as
an aggregate, the Odyssey is more simple and easily understood, and, therefore,
ought to come first in the order of analysis.
Now, looking at the Odyssey by
itself, the proofs of an unity of design seem unequivocal and everywhere to be
found. A premeditated structure, and a concentration of interest upon one prime
hero, under well-defined circumstances, may be traced from the first book to
the twenty-third. Odysseus is always either directly or indirectly kept before
the reader, as a warrior returning from the fullness of glory at Troy, exposed
to manifold and protracted calamities during his return home, on which his
whole soul is so bent that he refuses even the immortality offered by Calypso;
a victim, moreover, even after his return, to mingled injury and insult from
the suitors, who have long been plundering his property, and dishonoring his
house; but at length obtaining, by valor and cunning united, a signal revenge,
which restores him to all that he had lost. All the persons and all the events
in the poem are subsidiary to this main plot : and the divine agency, necessary
to satisfy the feeling of the Homeric man, is put forth by Poseidon and Athene,
in both cases from dispositions directly bearing upon Odysseus. To appreciate
the unity of the Odyssey, we have only to read the objections taken against
that of the Iliad, especially in regard to the long withdrawal of Achilles, not
only from the scene, but from the memory, together with the independent
prominence of Ajax, Diomedes, and other heroes. How far we are entitled from
hence to infer the want of premeditated unity in the Iliad, will be presently
considered; but it is certain that the constitution of the Odyssey, in this
respect, everywhere demonstrates the presence of such unity. Whatever may be
the interest attached to Penelope, Telemachus, or Eumaeus, we never disconnect
them from their association with Odysseus. The present is not the place for
collecting the many marks of artistical structure
dispersed throughout this poem; but it may be worthwhile to remark, that the
final catastrophe realized in the twenty-second book, the slaughter of the
suitors in the very house which they were profaning; is distinctly and
prominently marked out in the first and second books, promised by Teiresias in the eleventh, by Athene in the thirteenth, and
by Helen in the fifteenth, and gradually. matured by a series of suitable
preliminaries, throughout the eight books preceding its occurrence. Indeed,
what is principally evident, and what has been often noticed, in the Odyssey,
is the equable flow both of the narrative and the events; the absence of that
rise and fall of interest which is sufficiently conspicuous in the Iliad.
To set against these evidences of
unity, there ought, at least, to be some strong cases produced of occasional
incoherence or contradiction. But it is remarkable how little of such
counter-evidence is to be found, although the arguments of Wolf, W. Muller, and
B. Thiersch stand so much in need of it. They have
discovered only one instance of undeniable inconsistency in the parts, the
number of days occupied by the absence of Telemachus at Pylus and Sparta. That young prince, though represented as in great haste to depart,
and refusing pressing invitations to prolong his stay, must, nevertheless, be
supposed to have continued for thirty days the guest of Menelaus, in order to
bring his proceedings into chronological harmony with those of Odysseus, and to
explain the first meeting of father and son in the swine-fold of Eumaeus. Here
is undoubtedly an inaccuracy, (so Nitzsch treats it,
and I think justly) on the part of the poet, who did not anticipate, and did
not experience in ancient times, so strict a scrutiny; an inaccuracy certainly
not at all wonderful; the matter of real wonder is, that it stands almost
alone, and that there are no others in the poem.
UNITY OF THE ODYSSEY.
Now, this is one of the main points
on which W. Muller and B. Thiersch rest their theory,
explaining the chronological confusion by supposing that the journey of
Telemachus to Pylus and Sparta, constituted the
subject of an epic originally separate (comprising the first four books and a
portion of the fifteenth), and incorporated at second-hand with the remaining
poem. And they conceive this view to be farther confirmed by the double
assembly of the gods, (at the beginning of the first book as well as of the
fifth,) which they treat as an awkward repetition, such as could not have
formed part of the primary scheme of any epic poet. But here they only escape a
small difficulty by running into another and a greater. For it is impossible to
comprehend how the first four books and part of the fifteenth can ever have
constituted a distinct epic; since the adventures of Telemachus have no
satisfactory termination, except at the point of confluence with those of his
father, when the unexpected meeting and recognition takes place under the roof
of Eumaeus, nor can any epic poem ever have described that meeting and
recognition without giving some account how Odysseus came thither. Moreover,
the first two books of the Odyssey distinctly lay the ground, and carry
expectation forward, to the final catastrophe of the poem, treating Telemachus
as a subordinate person, and his expedition as merely provisional towards an
ulterior result. Nor can I agree with W. Muller, that the real Odyssey might
well be supposed to begin with the fifth book. On the contrary, the exhibition
of the suitors and the Ithakesian agora, presented to
us in the second book, is absolutely essential to the full comprehension of the
books subsequent to the thirteenth. The suitors are far too important
personages in the poem to allow of their being first introduced in so informal
a manner as we read in the sixteenth book: indeed, the passing allusions of
Athene, (xiii. 310, 375) and Eumaeus (xiv. 41, 81) to the suitors, presuppose
cognizance of them on the part of the hearer.
Lastly, the twofold discussion of
the gods, at the beginning of the first and fifth books, and the double
interference of Athene, far from being a needless repetition, may be shown to
suit perfectly both the genuine epical conditions and the unity of the poem.
For although the final consummation, and the organization of measures against
the suitors, was to be accomplished by Odysseus and Telemachus jointly, yet the
march and adventures of the two, until the moment of their meeting in the
dwelling of Eumaeus, were essentially distinct. But, according to the religious
ideas of the old epic, the presiding direction of Athena was necessary for the
safety and success of both of them. Her first interference arouses and inspires
the son, her second produces the liberation of the father, constituting a point
of union and common origination for two lines of adventures, in both of which
she takes earnest interest, but which ate necessarily for a time kept apart in
order to coincide at the proper moment.
It will thus appear that the
twice-repeated agora of the gods in the Odyssey, bringing home, as it does to
one and the same divine agent, that double start which is essential to the
scheme of the poem, consists better with the supposition of premeditated unity
than with that of distinct self-existent parts. And, assuredly, the manner in
which Telemachus and Odysseus, both by different roads, are brought into
meeting and conjunction at the dwelling of Eumaeus, is something not only
contrived, but very skillfully contrived. It is needless to advert to the highly
interesting character of Eumaeus, rendered available as a rallying-point,
though in different ways, both to the father and the son, over and above the
sympathy which he himself inspires.
If the Odyssey be not an original
unity, of what self-existent parts can we imagine it to have consisted? To this
question it is difficult to imagine a satisfactory reply : for the supposition
that Telemachus and his adventures may once have formed the subject of a
separate epos, apart from Odysseus, appears inconsistent with the whole
character of that youth as it stands in the poem, and with the events in which
he is made to take part. We could better imagine the distribution of the
adventures of Odysseus himself into two parts, one containing his wanderings
and return, the other handling his ill-treatment by the suitors, and his final
triumph. But though either of these two subjects might have been adequate to
furnish out a separate poem, it is nevertheless certain that, as they are
presented in the Odyssey, the former cannot be divorced from the latter. The
simple return of Odysseus, as it now stands in the poem, could satisfy no one
as a final close, so long as the suitors remain in possession of his house, and
forbid his reunion with his wife. Any poem which treated his wanderings and
return separately, must have represented his reunion with Penelope and
restoration to his house, as following naturally upon his arrival in Ithaca,
thus taking little or no notice of the suitors. But this would be a capital
mutilation of the actual epical narrative, which considers the suitors at home
as an essential portion of the destiny of the much-suffering hero, not less
than his shipwrecks and trials at sea. His return (separately taken) is
foredoomed, according to the curse of Polyphemus, executed by Poseidon, to be
long deferred, miserable, solitary, and ending with destruction in his house to
greet him; and the ground is thus laid, in the very recital of his wanderings,
for a new series of events which are to happen to him after his arrival in
Ithaca. There is no tenable halting-place between the departure of Odysseus
from Troy, and the final restoration to his house and his wife. The distance
between these two events may, indeed, be widened, by accumulating new
distresses and impediments, but any separate portion of it cannot be otherwise
treated than as a fraction of the whole. The beginning and the end are here the
data in respect to epical genesis, though the intermediate events admit of
being conceived as variables, more or less numerous : so that the conception of
the whole may be said without impropriety both to precede and to govern that of
the constituent parts.
STRUCTURE OF THE ODYSSEY.
The general result of a study of the
Odyssey may be set down as follows : 1. The poem, as it now stands, exhibits
unequivocally adaptation of parts and continuity of structure, whether by one
or by several consentient hands : it may, perhaps, be a secondary formation,
out of a preexisting Odyssey of smaller dimensions; but, if so, the parts of
the smaller whole must have been so far recast as to make them suitable members
of the larger, and are noway recognizable by us. 2.
The subject-matter of the poem not only does not favor, but goes far to
exclude, the possibility of the Wolfian hypothesis.
Its events cannot be so arranged as to have composed several antecedent
substantive epics, afterwards put together into the present aggregate. Its
authors cannot have been mere compilers of preexisting materials, such as
Peisistratus and his friends : they must have been poets, competent to work
such matter as they found, into a new and enlarged design of their own. Nor can
the age in which this long poem, of so many thousand lines, was turned out as a
continuous aggregate, be separated from the ancient, productive, inspired age
of Grecian epic.
Arriving at such conclusions from
the internal evidence of the Odyssey, we can apply them by analogy to the
Iliad. We learn something respecting the character and capacities of that early
age which has left no other mementos except these two poems. Long continuous
epics (it is observed by those who support the views of Wolf), with an artistical structure, are inconsistent with the capacities
of a rude and non-writing age. Such epics (we may reply) are not inconsistent
with the early age of the Greeks, and the Odyssey is a proof of it; for in that
poem the integration of the whole, and the composition of the parts, must have
been simultaneous. The analogy of the Odyssey enables us to rebut that
preconception under which many ingenious critics sit down to the study of the
Iliad, and which induces them to explain all the incoherencies of the latter by
breaking it up into smaller unities, as if short epics were the only
manifestation of poetical power which the age admitted. There ought to be no
reluctance in admitting a presiding scheme and premeditated unity of parts, in
so far as the parts themselves point to such a conclusion.
That the Iliad is not so essentially
one piece as the Odyssey, every man agrees. It includes a much greater
multiplicity of events, and what is yet more important, a greater multiplicity
of prominent personages: the very indefinite title which it bears, as
contrasted with the specialty of the name, Odyssey, marks the difference at
once. The parts stand out more conspicuously from the whole, and admit more
readily of being felt and appreciated in detached recitation. We may also add,
that it is of more unequal execution than the Odyssey, often rising to a far
higher pitch of grandeur, but also, occasionally, tamer : the story does not
move on continuously; incidents occur without plausible motive, nor can we shut
our eyes to evidences of incoherence and contradiction.
To a certain extent, the Iliad is
open to all these remarks, though Wolf and William Muller, and above all
Lachmann, exaggerate the case in degree. And from hence has been deduced the
hypothesis which treats the parts in their original state as separate integers,
independent of, and unconnected with, each other, and forced into unity only by
the afterthought of a subsequent age; or sometimes, not even themselves as
integers, but as aggregates grouped together out of fragments still smaller,
short epics formed by the coalescence of still shorter songs. Now there is some
plausibility in these reasonings, so long as the
discrepancies are looked upon as the whole of the case. But in point of fact
they are not the whole of the case : for it is not less true, that there are
large portions of the Iliad which present positive and undeniable evidences of
coherence as antecedent and consequent, though we are occasionally perplexed by
inconsistencies of detail. To deal with these latter, is a portion of the
duties of the critic. But he is not to treat the Iliad as if inconsistency
prevailed everywhere throughout its parts; for coherence of parts—symmetrical
antecedence and consequence—is discernible throughout the larger half of the
poem.
STRUCTURE OF THE ILIAD.
Now the Wolfian theory explains the gaps and contradictions throughout the narrative, but it
explains nothing else. If (as Lachmann thinks) the Iliad originally consisted
of sixteen song or little substantive epics, (Lachmann’s sixteen songs cover the space only as far as the 22d book, or the death of
Hector, and two more songs would have to be admitted for the 23d and 24th
books),—not only composed by different authors, but by each without any view to
conjunction with the rest, — we have then no right to expect any intrinsic
continuity between them; and all that continuity which we now find must be of
extraneous origin. Where are we to look for the origin? Lachmann follows Wolf,
in ascribing the whole constructive process to Peisistratus and his associates,
at a period when the creative epical faculty is admitted to have died out. But
upon this supposition, Peisistratus (or his associates) must have done much
more than omit, transpose, and interpolate, here and there; he must have gone
far to rewrite the whole poem. A great poet might have recast preexisting
separate songs into one comprehensive whole, but no mere arrangers or compilers
would be competent to do so : and we are thus left without any means of
accounting for that degree of continuity and consistence which runs through so
large a portion of the Iliad, though not through the whole. The idea that the
poem, as we read it, grew out of atoms not originally designed for the places
which they now occupy, involves us in new and inextricable difficulties, when
we seek to elucidate either the mode of coalescence or the degree of existing
unity.
Admitting then premeditated
adaptation of parts to a certain extent as essential to the Iliad, we may yet
inquire, whether it was produced all at once, or gradually enlarged, whether by
one author, or by several; and, if the parts be of different age, which is the
primitive kernel, and which are the additions.
Welcker, Lange, and Nitzsch treat the Homeric poems as representing a second step in advance, in the
progress of popular poetry. First, comes the age of short narrative songs;
next, when these have become numerous, there arise constructive minds, who
recast and blend together many of them into a larger aggregate, conceived upon
some scheme of their own. The age of the epos is followed by that of the epopee,
short, spontaneous effusions preparing the way, and furnishing materials, for
the architectonic genius of the poet. It is farther presumed by the
above-mentioned authors, that the pre-Homeric epic included a great abundance
of such smaller songs, a fact which admits of no proof, but which seems
countenanced by some passages in Homer, and is in itself no way improbable. But
the transition from such songs, assuming them to be ever so numerous, to a
combined and continuous poem, forms an epoch in the intellectual history of the
nation, implying mental qualities of a higher order than those upon which the
songs themselves depend. Nor is it to be imagined that the materials pass
unaltered from their first state of isolation into their second state of
combination. They must of necessity be recast, and undergo an adapting process,
in which the genius of the organizing poet consists; nor can we hope, by simply
knowing them as they exist in the second stage, ever to divine how they stood
in the first. Such, in my judgment, is the right conception of the Homeric
epoch, an organizing poetical mind, still preserving that freshness of
observation and vivacity of details which constitutes the charm of the ballad.
Nothing is gained by studying the
Iliad as a congeries of fragments once independent of each other : no portion
of the poem can be shown to have ever been so, and the supposition introduces
difficulties greater than those which it removes. But it is not necessary to affirm
that the whole poem as we now read it, belonged to the original and
preconceived plan. In this respect, the Iliad produces, upon my mind, an
impression totally different from the Odyssey. In the latter poem, the
characters and incidents are fewer, and the whole plot appears of one
projection, from the beginning down to the death of the suitors : none of the
parts look as if they had been composed separately, and inserted by way of
addition into a preexisting smaller poem. But the Iliad, on the contrary,
presents the appearance of a house built upon a plan comparatively narrow, and
subsequently enlarged by successive additions. The first book, together with
the eighth, and the books from the eleventh to the twenty-second, inclusive,
seem to form the primary organization of the poem, then properly an Achilleis :
the twenty-third and twenty-fourth books are, perhaps, additions at the tail of
this primitive poem, which still leave it nothing more than an enlarged
Achilleis. But the books from the second to the seventh, inclusive, together
with the tenth, are of a wider and more comprehensive character, and convert
the poem from an Achilleis into an Iliad. The primitive frontispiece, inscribed
with the anger of Achilles, and its direct consequences, yet remains, after it
has ceased to be coextensive with the poem. The parts added, however, are not
necessarily inferior in merit to the original poem : so far is this from being
the case, that amongst them are comprehended some of the noblest efforts of the
Grecian epic. Nor are they more recent in date than the original ; strictly
speaking, they must be a little more recent, but they belong to the same
generation and state of society as the primitive Achilles. These qualifications
are necessary to keep apart different questions, which, in discussions of
Homeric criticism, are but too often confounded.
If we take those portions of the
poem which I imagine to have constituted the original Achilleis, it will be
found that the sequence of events contained in them is more rapid, more
unbroken, and more intimately knit together in the way of cause and effect,
than in the other books. Heyne and Lachmann, indeed,
with other objecting critics, complains of the action in them as being too much
crowded and hurried, since one day lasts from the beginning of the eleventh
book to the middle of the eighteenth, without any sensible halt in the march
throughout so large a portion of the journey. Lachmann, likewise, admits that
those separate songs, into which he imagines that the whole Iliad may be
dissected, cannot be severed with the same sharpness, in the books subsequent
to the eleventh, as in those before it. There is only one real halting-place
from the eleventh book to the twenty-second—the death of Patroclus; and this
can never be conceived as the end of a separate poem, though it is a capital
step in the development of the Achilleis, and brings about that entire
revolution in the temper of Achilles which was essential for the purpose of the
poet. It would be a mistake to imagine that there ever could have existed a
separate poem called Patrocleia, though a part of the
Iliad was designated by that name. For Patroclus has no substantive position :
he is the attached friend and second of Achilles, but nothing else, standing to
the latter in a relation of dependence resembling that of Telemachus to
Odysseus. And the way in which Patroclus is dealt with in the Iliad, is, (in my
judgment,) the most dexterous and artistical contrivance in the poem, that which approaches nearest to the neat tissue of
the odyssey.
The great and capital misfortune
which prostrates the strength of the Greeks, and renders them incapable of
defending themselves without Achilles, is the disablement, by wounds, of
Agamemnon, Diomedes, and Odysseus; so that the defense of the wall and of the
ships is left only to heroes of the second magnitude (Ajax alone excepted),
such as Idomeneus, Leonteus, Polypoetes, Meriones,
Menelaus, etc. Now, it is remarkable that all these three first-rate chiefs are
in full force at the beginning of the eleventh book : all three are wounded in
the battle which that book describes, and at the commencement of which
Agamemnon is full of spirits and courage.
Nothing can be more striking than
the manner in which Homer concentrates our attention in the first book upon
Achilles as the hero, his quarrel with Agamemnon, and the calamities to the
Greeks which are held out as about to ensue from it, through the intercession
of Thetis with Zeus. But the incidents dwelt upon from the beginning of the
second book down to the combat between Hector and Ajax in the seventh, animated
and interesting as they are, do nothing to realize this promise. They are a
splendid picture of the Trojan war generally, and eminently suitable to that
larger title under which the poem has been immortalized,—but the consequences
of the anger of Achilles do not appear until the eighth book. The tenth book,
or Doloneia, is also a portion of the Iliad, but not
of the Achilleis : while the ninth book appears to me a subsequent addition,
nowise harmonizing with that main stream of the Achilleis which flows from the
eleventh book to the twenty-second. The eighth book ought to be read in
immediate connection with the eleventh, in order to see the structure of what
seems the primitive Achilleis; for there are several passages in the eleventh
and the following books, which prove that the poet who composed them could not
have had present to his mind the main event of the ninth book, the outpouring
of profound humiliation by the Greeks, and from Agamemnon, especially, before
Achilles, coupled with formal offers to restore Briseis, and pay the amplest
compensation for past wrong. The words of Achilles (not less than those of
Patroclus and Nestor) in the eleventh and in the following books, plainly imply
that the humiliation of the Greeks before him, for which he thirsts, is as yet
future and contingent; that no plenary apology has yet been tendered, nor any
offer made of restoring Briseis; while both Nestor and Patroclus, with all their
wish to induce him to take arms, never take notice of the offered atonement and
restitution, but view him as one whose ground for quarrel stands still the same
as it did at the beginning. Moreover, if we look at the first book,— the
opening of the Achilles, — we shall see that this prostration of Agamemnon and
the chief Grecian heroes before Achilles, would really be the termination of
the whole poem; for Achilles asks nothing more from Thetis, nor Thetis anything
more from Zeus, than that Agamemnon and the Greeks may be brought to know the
wrong they have done to their capital warrior, and humbled in the dust in
expiation of it. We may add, that the abject terror in which Agamemnon appears
in the ninth book, when he sends the supplicatory message to Achilles, as it is
not adequately accounted for by the degree of calamity which the Greeks have
experienced in the preceding (eighth) book, so it is inconsistent with the
gallantry and high spirit with which lie shines at the beginning of the
eleventh. The situation of the Greeks only becomes desperate when the three
great chiefs, Agamemnon, Odysseus, and Diomedes, are disabled by wounds; this
is the irreparable calamity which works upon Patroclus, and through him upon
Achilles. The ninth book, as it now stands, seems to me an addition, by a
different hand, to the original Achilles, framed so as both to forestall and to
spoil the nineteenth book, which is the real reconciliation of the two inimical
heroes. I will venture to add, that it carries the pride and egotism of
Achilles beyond even the largest exigencies of insulted honor, and is shocking
to that sentiment of Nemesis which was so deeply seated in the Grecian mind. We
forgive any excess of fury against the Trojans and Hector, after the death of
Patroclus; but that he should remain unmoved by restitution, by abject
supplications, and by the richest atoning presents, tendered from the Greeks,
indicates an implacability such as neither the first book, nor the books
between the eleventh and seventeenth, convey.
ENLARGEMENT OF ACHILLEIS INTO ILIAD.
It is with the Grecian agora, in the
beginning of the second book, that the Iliad (as distinguished from the
Achilleis) commences,—continued through the Catalogue, the muster of the two
armies, the single combat between Menelaus and Paris, the renewed promiscuous
battle caused by the arrow of Pandarus, the (Epipolesis,
or) personal circuit of Agamemnon round the army, the Aristeia,
or brilliant exploits of Diomedes, the visit of Hector to Troy for the purposes
of sacrifice, his interview with Andromache, and his combat with Ajax,—down to
the seventh book. All these are beautiful poetry, presenting to us the general
Trojan war, and its conspicuous individuals under different points of view, but
leaving no room in the reader's mind for the thought of Achilles. Now, the
difficulty for an enlarging poet, was, to pass from the Achilleis in the first
book, to the Iliad in the second, and it will accordingly be found that here is
an awkwardness in the structure of the poem, which counsel on the poet's behalf
(ancient or modern) do not satisfactorily explain.
In the first book, Zeus has promised
Thetis, that he will punish the Greeks for the wrong done to Achilles : in the
beginning of the second book, he deliberates how he shall fulfill the promise,
and sends down for that purpose “mischievous Oneirus” (the Dream-god) to visit
Agamemnon in his sleep, to assure him that the gods have now with one accord
consented to put Troy into his hands, and to exhort him forthwith to the
assembling of his army for the attack. The ancient commentators were here
perplexed by the circumstance that Zeus puts a falsehood into the mouth of
Oneirus. But there seems no more difficulty in explaining this, than in the
narrative of the book of 1 Kings (chap. XXII. 20), where Jehovah is mentioned
to have put a lying spirit into the mouth of Ahab’s prophets,—the real
awkwardness is that Oneirus and his falsehood produce no effect. For in the
first place, Agamemnon takes a step very different from that which his dream
recommends,—and in the next place, when the Grecian army is at length armed and
goes forth to battle, it does not experience defeat, (which would be the case
if the exhortation of Oneirus really proved mischievous,) but carries on a
successful day's battle, chiefly through the heroism of Diomedes. Instead of
arming the Greeks forthwith, Agamemnon convokes first a council of chiefs, and
next an agora of the host. And though himself in a temper of mind highly elate
with the deceitful assurances of Oneirus, he deliberately assumes the language
of despair in addressing the troops, having previously prepared Nestor and
Odysseus for his doing so, merely in order to try the courage of the men, and
with formal instructions, given to these two other chiefs, that they are to
speak in opposition to him. Now this intervention of Zeus and Oneirus,
eminently unsatisfactory when coupled with the incidents which now follow it,
and making Zeus appear, but only appear, to realize his promise of honoring
Achilles as well as of hurting the Greeks, forms exactly the point of junction
between the Achilleis and the Iliad.
The freak which Agamemnon plays off
upon the temper of his army, though in itself childish, serves a sufficient
purpose, not only because it provides a special matter of interest to be
submitted to the Greeks, but also because it calls forth the splendid
description, so teeming with vivacious detail, of the sudden breaking up of the
assembly after Agamemnon's harangue, and of the decisive interference of Odysseus
to bring the men back, as well as to put down Thersites.
This picture of the Greeks in agora, bringing out the two chief speaking and counselling heroes, was so important a part of the general
Trojan war, that the poet has permitted himself to introduce it by assuming an
inexplicable folly on the part of Agamemnon; just as he has ushered in another
fine scene in the third book, — the Teichoskopy, or
conversation, between Priam and Helen on the walls of
Troy,—by admitting the supposition that the old king, in the tenth year of the
war, did not know the persons of Agamemnon and the other Grecian chiefs. This
may serve as an explanation of the delusion practiced by Agamemnon towards his
assembled host; but it does not at all explain the tame and empty intervention
of Oneirus.
FORTIFICATION OF THE GRECIAN CAMP.
If the initial incident of the
second book, whereby we pass out of the Achilleis into the Iliad, is awkward,
so also the final incident of the seventh book, immediately before we come back
into the Achilleis, is not less unsatisfactory, I mean, the construction of the
wall and ditch round the Greek camp. As the poem now stands, no plausible
reason is assigned why this should be done. Nestor proposes it without any
constraining necessity : for the Greeks are in a career of victory, and the
Trojans are making offers of compromise which imply conscious weakness, —while
Diomedes is so confident of the approaching ruin of Troy that he dissuades his
comrades from receiving even Helen herself, if the surrender should be
tendered. "Many Greeks have been slain," it is true, as Nestor
observes; but an equal or greater number of Trojans have been slain, and all
the Grecian heroes are yet in full force : the absence of Achilles is not even
adverted to.
Now this account of the building of
the fortification seems to be an after-thought, arising out of the enlargement
of the poem beyond its original scheme. The original Achilleis, passing at once
from the first to the eighth, and from thence to the eleventh book, might well
assume the fortification, and talk of it as a thing existing, without adducing
any special reason why it was erected. The hearer would naturally comprehend
and follow the existence of a ditch and wall round the ships, as a matter of
course, provided there was nothing in the previous narrative to make him believe
that the Greeks had originally been without these bulwarks. And since the
Achilleis, immediately after the promise of Zeus to Thetis, at the close of the
first book, went on to describe the fulfillment of that promise and the ensuing
disasters of the Greeks, there was nothing to surprise anyone in hearing that
their camp was fortified. But the case was altered when the first and the
eighth books were parted asunder, in order to make room for descriptions of
temporary success and glory on the part of the besieging army. The brilliant
scenes sketched in the books, from the second to the seventh, mention no
fortification, and even imply its nonexistence; yet, since notice of it occurs
amidst the first description of Grecian disasters in the eighth book, the
hearer, who had the earlier books present to his memory, might be surprised to
find a fortification mentioned immediately afterwards, unless the construction
of it were specially announced to have intervened. But it will at once appear,
that there was some difficulty in finding a good reason why the Greeks should
begin to fortify at this juncture, and that the poet who discovered the gap
might not be enabled to fill it up with success. As the Greeks have got on, up
to this moment, without the wall, and as we have heard nothing but tales of
their success, why should they now think farther laborious precautions for
security necessary? We will not ask, why the Trojans should stand quietly by
and permit a wall to be built, since the truce was concluded expressly for
burying the dead.
THE DOLONEIA.
The tenth book, or Doloneia, was considered by some of the ancient scholiasts,
and has been confidently set forth by the modern Wolfian critics, as originally a separate poem, inserted by Peisistratus into the Iliad.
How it can ever have been a separate poem, I do not understand. It is framed
with great specialty for the antecedent circumstances under which it occurs,
and would suit for no other place; though capable of being separately recited,
inasmuch as it has a definite beginning and end, like the story of Nisus and
Euryalus in the Aeneid. But while distinctly
presupposing and resting upon the incidents in the eighth book, and in line 88
of the ninth, (probably, the appointment of sentinels on the part of the Greeks,
as well of the Trojans, formed the close of the battle described in the eighth
book,) it has not the slightest bearing upon the events of the eleventh or the
following books : it goes to make up the general picture of the Trojan war, but
lies quite apart from the Achilleis. And this is one mark of a portion
subsequently inserted, that, though fitted on to the parts which precede, it
has no influence on those which follow.
If the proceedings of the combatants
on the plain of Troy, between the first and the eighth book, have no reference
either to Achilles, or to an Achilleis, we find Zeus in Olympus still more
completely putting that hero out of the question, at the beginning of the
fourth book. He is in this last mentioned passage the Zeus of the Iliad, not of
the Achilleis. Forgetful of his promise to Thetis, in the first book, he
discusses nothing but the question of continuance or termination of the war,
and manifests anxiety only for the salvation of Troy, in opposition to the Trojan
goddesses, who prevent him from giving effect to the victory of Menelaus over
Paris, and the stipulated restitution of Helen, in which case, of course, the
wrong offered to Achilles would remain unexpiated. An
attentive comparison will render it evident that the poet who composed the
discussion among the gods, at the beginning of the fourth book, has not been
careful to put himself in harmony either with the Zeus of the first book, or
with the Zeus of the eighth.
So soon as we enter upon the
eleventh book, the march of the poem becomes quite different. We are then in a
series of events, each paving the way for that which follows, and all conducing
to the result promised in the first book, the reappearance of Achilles, as the
only means of saving the Greeks from ruin, preceded by ample atonement, and
followed by the maximum both of glory and revenge. The intermediate career of
Patroclus introduces new elements, which, however, are admirably woven into the
scheme of the poem, as disclosed in the first book. I shall not deny that there
are perplexities in the detail of events, as described in the battles at the
Grecian wall, and before the ships, from the eleventh to the sixteenth books,
but they appear only cases of partial confusion, such as may be reasonably
ascribed to imperfections of text : the main sequence remains coherent and
intelligible. We find no considerable events which could be left out without
breaking the thread, nor any incongruity between one considerable event and
another. There is nothing between the eleventh and twenty-second books, which
is at all comparable to the incongruity between the Zeus of the fourth book and
the Zeus of the first and eighth. It may, perhaps, be true, that the shield of
Achilles is a super-added amplification of that which was originally announced
in general terms, because the poet, from the eleventh to the twenty-second
books, has observed such good economy of his materials, that he is hardly
likely to have introduced one particular description of such disproportionate
length, and having so little connection with the series of events. But I see no
reason for believing that it is an addition materially later than the rest of
the poem.
It must be confessed, that the
supposition here advanced, in reference to the structure of the Iliad, is not
altogether free from difficulties, because the parts constituting the original
Achilleis have been more or less altered or interpolated, to suit the additions
made to it, particularly in the eighth book. But it presents fewer difficulties
than any other supposition, and it is the only means, so far as I know, of
explaining the difference between one part of the Iliad and another; both the
continuity of structure, and the conformity to the opening promise, which are
manifest when we read the books in the order I, VIII, XI, to XXII, as
contrasted with the absence of these two qualities in books II to VII, IX and
X. An entire organization, preconceived from the beginning, would not be likely
to produce any such disparity, nor is any such visible in the Odyssey; still
less would the result be explained by supposing integers originally separate,
and brought together without any designed organization. And it is between these
three suppositions that our choice has to be made. A scheme, and a large scheme
too, must unquestionably be admitted as the basis of any sufficient hypothesis.
But the Achilleis would have been a long poem, half the length of the present
Iliad, and probably not less compact in its structure than the Odyssey.
Moreover, being parted off only by an imaginary Line from the boundless range
of the Trojan war, it would admit of enlargement more easily, and with greater
relish to hearers, than the adventures of one single hero; while the expansion
would naturally take place by adding new Grecian victory, since the original
poem arrived at the exaltation of Achilles only through a painful series of
Grecian disasters. That the poem under these circumstances should have received
additions, is no very violent hypothesis : in fact, when we recollect that the
integrity both of the Achilleis and of the Odyssey was neither guarded by
printing nor writing, we shall perhaps think it less wonderful that the former
was enlarged, than that the latter was not. Any relaxation of the laws of
epical unity is a small price to pay for that splendid poetry, of which we find
so much between the first and the eighth books of our Iliad.
The question respecting unity of
authorship is different, and more difficult to determine, than that respecting
consistency of parts, and sequence in the narrative. A poem conceived on a
comparatively narrow scale may be enlarged afterwards by its original author,
with greater or less coherence and success : the Faust of Goethe affords an
example even in our own generation. On the other hand, a systematic poem may
well have been conceived and executed by prearranged concert between several
poets; among whom probably one will be the governing mind, though the rest may
be effective, and perhaps equally effective, in respect to execution of the
parts. And the age of the early Grecian epic was favorable to such
fraternization of poets, of which the Gens called Homerids probably exhibited
many specimens. In the recital or singing of a long unwritten poem, many bards
must have conspired together, and in the earliest times the composer and the
singer were one and the same person. Now the individuals comprised in the Homerid Gens, though doubtless very different among
themselves in respect of mental capacity, were yet homogeneous in respect of
training, means of observation and instruction, social experience, religious
feelings and theories, etc., to a degree much greater than individuals in
modern times. Fallible as our inferences are on this point, where we have only
internal evidence to guide us, without any contemporary points of comparison,
or any species of collateral information respecting the age, the society, the
poets, the hearers, or the language, we must nevertheless, in the present case,
take coherence of structure, together with consistency in the tone of thought,
feeling, language, customs, etc., as presumptions of one author; and the
contrary as presumptions of severalty; allowing, as well as we can, for that
inequality of excellence which the same author may at different times present.
Now, the case made out against
single-headed authorship of the Odyssey, appears to me very weak; and those who
dispute it, are guided more by their a priori rejection of ancient epical
unity, than by any positive evidence which the poem itself affords. It is
otherwise with regard to the Iliad. Whatever presumptions a disjointed
structure, several apparent inconsistencies of parts, and large excrescence of
actual matter beyond the opening promise, can sanction, may reasonably be
indulged against the supposition that this poem all proceeds from a single
author. There is a difference of opinion on the subject among the best critics,
which is, probably, not destined to be adjusted, since so much depends partly
upon critical feeling, partly upon the general reasonings,
in respect to ancient epical unity, with which a man sits down to the study.
For the champions of unity, such as Mr. Payne Knight, are very ready to strike
out numerous and often considerable passages as interpolations, thus meeting
the objections raised against unity of authorship, on the ground of special
inconsistencies. Hermann and Boeckh, though not going
the length of Lachmann in maintaining the original theory of Wolf, agree with
the latter in recognizing diversity of authors in the poem, to an extent
overpassing the limit of what can fairly be called interpolation. Payne Knight
and Nitzsch are equally persuaded of the contrary.
Here, then, is a decided contradiction among critics, all of whom have minutely
studied the poems since the Wolfian question was
raised. And it is such critics alone who can be said to constitute authority;
for the cursory reader, who dwells upon the parts simply long enough to relish
their poetical beauty, is struck only by that general sameness of coloring which
Wolf himself admits to pervade the poem.
UNITY OF AUTHORSHIP.
Having already intimated that, in my
judgment, no theory of the structure of the poem is admissible which does not
admit an original and preconcerted Achilleis,— a
stream which begins at the first book and ends with the death of Hector, in the
twenty-second, although the higher parts of it now remain only in the condition
of two detached lakes, the first book and the eighth, —I reason upon the same
basis with respect to the authorship.
Assuming continuity of structure as
a presumptive proof, the whole of this Achilleis must be treated as composed by
one author. Wolf, indeed, affirmed, that he never read the poem continuously
through without being painfully impressed with the inferiority and altered
style of the last six books,— and Lachmann carries this feeling farther back,
so as to commence with the seventeenth book. If I could enter fully into this
sentiment, I should then be compelled, not to deny the existence of a
preconceived scheme, but to imagine that the books from the eighteenth to the
twenty-second, though forming part of that scheme, or Achilleis, had yet been
executed by another and an inferior poet. But it is to be remarked, first, that
inferiority of poetical merit, to a certain extent, is quite reconcilable with
unity of authorship; and, secondly, that the very circumstances upon which
Wolf's unfavorable judgment is built, seem to arise out of increased difficulty
in the poet's task, when he came to the crowning cantos of his designed
Achilleis. For that which chiefly distinguishes these books, is the direct,
incessant, and manual intervention of the gods and goddesses, formerly
permitted by Zeus, and the repetition of vast and fantastic conceptions to
which such superhuman agency gives occasion; not omitting the battle of
Achilles against Skamander and Simois,
and the burning up of these rivers by Hephaestus. Now, looking at this vein of
ideas with the eyes of a modern reader, or even with those of a Grecian critic
of the literary ages, it is certain that the effect is unpleasing : the gods,
sublime elements of poetry when kept in due proportion, are here somewhat
vulgarized. But though the poet here has not succeeded, and probably success
was impossible, in the task which he has prescribed to himself,— yet the mere
fact of his undertaking it, and the manifest distinction between his employment
of divine agency in these latter cantos as compared with the preceding, seems
explicable only on the supposition that they are the latter cantos, and come in
designed sequence, as the continuance of a previous plan. The poet wishes to
surround the coming forth of Achilles with the maximum of glorious and terrific
circumstance; no Trojan enemy can for a moment hold out against him : the gods
must descend to the plain of Troy and fight in person, while Zeus, who at the
beginning of the eighth book, had forbidden them to take part, expressly
encourages them to do so at the beginning of the twentieth. If, then, the nineteenth
book (which contains the reconciliation between Achilles and Agamemnon, a
subject naturally somewhat tame) and the three following books (where we have
before us only the gods, Achilles, and the Trojans, without hope or courage)
are inferior in execution and interest to the seven preceding books (which
describe the long-disputed and often doubtful death-struggle between the Greeks
and Trojans without Achilles), as Wolf and other critics affirm,—we may explain
the difference without supposing a new poet as composer; for the conditions of
the poem bad become essentially more difficult, and the subject more
unpromising. The necessity of keeping Achilles above the level, even of heroic
prowess, restricted the poet's means of acting upon the sympathy of his
hearers.
The last two books of the Iliad may
have formed part of the original Achilleis. But the probability rather is, that
they are additions; for the death of Hector satisfies the exigencies of a
coherent scheme, and we are not entitled to extend the oldest poem beyond the limit
which such necessity prescribes. It has been argued on one side by Nitzsch and 0. Muller, that the mind could not leave off
with satisfaction at the moment in which Achilles sates his revenge, and while
the bodies of Patroclus and Hector are lying unburied, also, that the more
merciful temper which he exhibits in the twenty-fourth book, must always have
been an indispensable sequel, in order to create proper sympathy with his
triumph. Other critics, on the contrary, have taken special grounds of exception
against the last book, and have endeavored to set it aside as different from
the other books, both in tone and language. To a certain extent, the
peculiarities of the last book appear to me undeniable, though it is plainly a
designed continuance, and not a substantive poem. Some weight also is due to
the remark about the twenty-third book, that Odysseus and Diomedes, who have
been wounded and disabled during the fight, now reappear in perfect force, and
contend in the games : here is no case of miraculous healing, and the
inconsistency is more likely to have been admitted by a separate enlarging
poet, than by the schemer of the Achilles.
The splendid books from the second
to v. 322 of the seventh, are equal, in most parts, to any portion of the
Achilleis, and are pointedly distinguished from the latter by the broad view
which they exhibit of the general Trojan war, with all its principal
personages, localities, and causes,—yet without advancing the result promised
in the first book, or, indeed, any final purpose whatever. Even the desperate
wound inflicted by Tlepolemus on Sarpedon,
is forgotten, when the latter hero is called forth in the subsequent Achilleis.
The arguments of Lachmann, who dissects these six books into three or four
separate songs, carry no conviction to my mind; and I see no reason why we
should not consider all of them to be by the same author, bound together by the
common purpose of giving a great collective picture which may properly be
termed an Iliad. The tenth book, or Doloneia, though
adapted specially to the place in which it stands, agrees with the books
between the first and eighth in belonging only to the general picture of the
war, without helping forward the march of the Achilles; yet it seems conceived
in a lower vein, in so far as we can trust our modern ethical sentiment. One is
unwilling to believe that the author of the fifth book, or Aristeia of Diomedes, would condescend to employ the hero whom he there so brightly
glorifies, the victor even over Ares himself, in slaughtering newly-arrived
Thracian sleepers, without any large purpose or necessity. The ninth book, of
which I have already spoken at length, belongs to a different vein of
conception, and seems to me more likely to have emanated from a separate
composer.
While intimating these views
respecting the authorship of the Iliad, as being in my judgment the most
probable, I must repeat that, though the study of the poem carries to my mind a
sufficient conviction respecting its structure, the question between unity and
plurality of authors is essentially less determinable. The poem consists of a
part original, and other parts superadded; yet it is certainly not impossible
that the author of the former may himself have composed the latter; and such
would be my belief, if I regarded plurality of composers as an inadmissible
idea. On this supposition, we must conclude that the poet, while anxious for
the addition of new, and for the most part, highly interesting matter, has not
thought fit to recast the parts and events in such manner as to impart to the
whole a pervading thread of consensus and organization, such as we see in the
Odyssey.
AGE OF ILIAD AND ODYSSEY
That the Odyssey is of later date
than the Iliad, and by a different author, seems to be now the opinion of most
critics, especially of Payne Knightl and Nitzsch; though 0. Muller leans to a contrary conclusion,
at the same time adding that he thinks the arguments either way not very
decisive. There are considerable differences of statement in the two poems in regard
to some of the gods : Iris is messenger of the gods in the Iliad, and Hermes in
the Odyssey : Eolus, the dispenser of the winds is the Odyssey, is not noticed
in the twenty-third book of the Iliad, but, on the contrary, Iris invites the
winds, as independent gods, to come and kindle the funeral pile of Patroclus;
and, unless we are to expunge the song of Demodokus in the eighth book of the Odyssey, as spurious, Aphrodite there appears as the
wife of Hephaestus,— a relationship not known to the Iliad. There are also some
other points of difference enumerated by Mr. Knight and others, which tend to
justify the presumption that the author of the Odyssey is not identical either
with the author of the Achilleis or his enlargers, which G. Hermann considers to
be a point unquestionable. Indeed, the difficulty of supposing a long coherent
poem to have been conceived, composed, and retained, without any aid of
writing, appears to many critics even now, insurmountable, though the evidences
on the other side, are, in my view, sufficient to outweigh any negative
presumption thus suggested. But it is improbable that the same person should
have powers of memorial combination sufficient for composing two such poems,
nor is there any proof to force upon us such a supposition.
Presuming a difference of authorship
between the two poems, I feel less convinced about the supposed juniority of the Odyssey. The discrepancies in manners and
language in the one and the other, are so little important, that two different
persons, in the same age and society, might well be imagined to exhibit as
great or even greater. It is to be recollected that the subjects of the two are
heterogeneous, so as to conduct the poet, even were he the same man, into totally different veins of imagination and illustration.
The pictures of the Odyssey seem to delineate the same heroic life as the
Iliad, though looked at from a distinct point of view : and the circumstances
surrounding the residence of Odysseus, in Ithaca, are just such as we may
suppose him to have left in order to attack Troy. If the scenes presented to us
are for the most part pacific, as contrasted with the incessant fighting of the
Iliad, this is not to be ascribed to any greater sociality or civilization in
the real hearers of the Odyssey, but to the circumstances of the hero whom the
poet undertakes to adorn : nor can we doubt that the poems of Arktinus and Lesches, of a later
date than the Odyssey, would have given us as much combat and bloodshed as the
Iliad. I am not struck by those proofs of improved civilization which some
critics affirm the Odyssey to present : Mr. Knight, who is of this opinion,
nevertheless admits that the mutilation of Melanthius,
and the hanging up of the female slaves by Odysseus, in that poem, indicate greater
barbarity than any incidents in the fights before Troy. The more skillful and
compact structure of the Odyssey, has been often considered as a proof of its juniority in age: and in the case of two poems by the same
author, we might plausibly contend that practice would bring with it
improvement in the combining faculty. But in reference to the poems before us,
we must recollect, first, that in all probability the Iliad (with which the
comparison is taken) is not a primitive but an enlarged poem, and that the
primitive Achilleis might well have been quite as coherent as the Odyssey;
secondly, that between different authors, superiority in structure is not a
proof of subsequent composition, inasmuch as, on that hypothesis, we should be
compelled to admit that the later poem of Arktinus would be an improvement upon the Odyssey; thirdly, that, even if it were so, we
could only infer that the author of the 0dyssey had heard the Achilleis or the
Iliad; we could not infer that he lived one or two generations afterwards.
On the whole, the balance of
probabilities seems in favor of distinct authorship for the two poems, but the
same age, and that age a very early one, anterior to the first Olympiad. And
they may thus be used as evidences, and contemporary evidences, for the
phenomena of primitive Greek civilization; while they also show that the power
of constructing long premeditated epics, without the aid of writing, is to be
taken as a characteristic of the earliest known Greek mind. This was the point
controverted by Wolf, which a full review of the case (in my judgment) decides
against him: it is, moreover, a valuable result for the historian of the
Greeks, inasmuch as it marks out to him the ground from which he is to start in
appreciating their ulterior progress.
Whatever there may be of truth in
the different conjectures of critics respecting the authorship and structure of
these unrivalled poems, we are not to imagine that it is the perfection of
their epical symmetry which has given them their indissoluble hold upon the
human mind, as well modern as ancient. There is some tendency in critics, from
Aristotle downwards, to invert the order of attributes in respect to the
Homeric poems, so as to dwell most on recondite excellences which escape the
unaided reader, and which are even to a great degree disputable. But it is
given to few minds (as Goethe has remarked), to appreciate fully the mechanism
of a long poem; and many feel the beauty of the separate parts, who have no
sentiment for the aggregate perfection of the whole.
Nor were the Homeric poems
originally addressed to minds of the rarer stamp. They are intended for those
feelings which the critic has in common with the unlettered mass, not for that
enlarged range of vision and peculiar standard which he has acquired to
himself. They are of all poems the most absolutely and unreservedly popular :
had they been otherwise, they could not have lived so long in the mouth of the
rhapsode, and the ear and memory of the people : and it was then that their
influence was first acquired, never afterwards to be shaken. Their beauties
belong to the parts taken separately, which revealed themselves spontaneously
to the listening crowd at the festival,—far more than to the whole poem taken
together, which could hardly be appreciated unless the parts were dwelt upon
and suffered to expand in the mind. The most unlettered hearer of those times
could readily seize, while the most instructed reader can still recognize, the
characteristic excellence of Homeric narrative, its straightforward,
unconscious, unstudied simplicity, its concrete forms of speech and happy
alternation of action with dialogue, its vivid pictures of living agents,
always clearly and sharply individualized, whether in the commanding
proportions of Achilles and Odysseus, in the graceful presence of Helen and
Penelope, or in the more humble contrast of Euzmaeus and Melanthius; and always, moreover, animated by the
frankness with which his heroes give utterance to all their transient emotions
and even all their infirmities, its constant reference to those coarser veins
of feeling and palpable motives which belong to all men in common, its fullness
of graphic details, freshly drawn from the visible and audible world, and
though often homely, never tame, nor trenching upon that limit of satiety to
which the Greek mind was so keenly alive, lastly, its perpetual junction of
gods and men in the same picture, and familiar appeal to ever-present divine
agency, in harmony with the interpretation of nature at that time universal.
It is undoubtedly easier to feel
than to describe the impressive influence of Homeric narrative : but the time
and circumstances under which that influence was first, and most powerfully
felt, preclude the possibility of explaining it by comprehensive and elaborate
comparisons, such as are implied in Aristotle's remarks upon the structure of
the poems. The critic who seeks the explanation in the right place will not
depart widely from the point of view of those rude auditors to whom the poems
were originally addressed, or from the susceptibilities and capacities common
to the human bosom in every stage of progressive culture. And though the
refinements and delicacies of the poems, as well as their general structure,
are a subject of highly interesting criticism,—yet it is not to these that
Homer owes his widespread and imperishable popularity. Still less is it true,
as the well-known observations of Horace would lead us to believe, that Homer
is a teacher of ethical wisdom akin and superior to Chrysippus or Crantor. No didactic purpose is to be found in the
Iliad and Odyssey; a philosopher may doubtless extract, from the incidents and
strongly marked characters which it contains, much illustrative matter for his
exhortations, —but the ethical doctrine which he applies must emanate from his
own reflection. The homeric hero manifests virtues or
infirmities, fierceness or compassion, with the same straightforward and
simple-minded vivacity, unconscious of any ideal standard by which his conduct
is to be tried nor can we trace in the poet any ulterior function beyond that
of the inspired organ of the Muse; and the nameless, but eloquent, herald of
lost adventures out of the darkness of the past.
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |