HISTORY OF ANCIENT GREECE |
A HISTORY OF GREECE TO THE DEATH OF ALEXANDER THE GREAT
CHAPTER XIII.
THE REVIVAL OF ATHENS AND HER SECOND LEAGUE
Sect.
1. High-handed Policy of Sparta
The gates of the Peloponnesus were again open to
Sparta without dispute; she was supported by Persia, and she had no
complications in Asia to divide her energy. Accordingly she was able to renew
the despotic policy which had been inaugurated for her by Lysander. Arcadian
Mantinea was the first to suffer. The Mantineans were accused of various acts
of disobedience and disloyalty to Sparta, and commanded to pull down their
walls. When they refused, king Agesipolis—son of the exiled Pausanias—marched
out against them. The city of Mantinea stood in a high plain, without any
natural defences, depending entirely on its walls of
unburnt brick. The river Ophis flowed through the
town; and, a blockade proving tedious, Agesipolis dammed the stream at the
point of issue. The water rose and undermined the walls; and when one of the
towers threatened to fall, the people surrendered. Their punishment was severe.
Mantinea ceased to be a city, and was broken up into its five constituent
villages. Those who originally belonged to the village of Mantinea remained on
the site of the city; the rest had to pull down their houses and move each to
the village where his property was. The loss of civic life meant to a Greek
the loss of all his higher interests.
Agesilaus, who had once gone forth to destroy the
Persian power, zealously supported the King’s Peace. When someone suggested
that it was at least curious to find the Spartans medizing, he rejoined,
“Rather say that the Persians are laconizing.” Each way of putting it expressed
a measure of the truth. But some of the Lacedaemonians, including king
Agesipolis, were opposed to the recent policy of their government, and thought
it ill-done to abandon the Greeks of Asia. Some years after the Peace, there seems
to have been floating in the air a vague idea, which might or might not take
shape, of organising another Asiatic expedition. It
was to animate this idea that the Athenian orator Isocrates published a festal
speech when the Greek nation was assembled at the Olympian festival. He
advocated a grand Panhellenic union against Persia, under the common headship
of Sparta and Athens—Sparta taking the command by land, Athens by sea. It was
the third occasion on which a renowned master of style had broached the same
idea at the same gathering-place. Nearly thirty years ago, it had been
recommended by the florid eloquence of Gorgias; more recently it had been
advocated with gracious simplicity by Lysias; and now the rich periods of
Isocrates urged it once more upon Greece. The project—in the ideal form in
which Isocrates imagined it—was at this moment chimerical. A hundred years
before, it had been hard enough to compass a practical co-operation between
Greek powers of equal strength and pretensions, in a war of defence;
it was hopeless to think of such co-operation now for a war of aggression.
Sparta and Athens were quarrelling, as the orator complains, over the tribute
of the Cyclad islands; and neither was likely to
yield to the other without a clear award of war. And other troubles were
brewing in another quarter.
The contest of east and west had been going on
meanwhile in Cyprus, an island whose geographical situation has marked it out,
like Sicily, to be a meeting-place of races. We have already met a man who
played an eminent part in that struggle, Evagoras the prince of Salamis. He
belonged to the Teucrid family which had reigned
there in the days of Darius and Xerxes, but had been supplanted by a Phoenician
dynasty about the middle of the fifth century. Evagoras, crossing over from the
Cilician Soli, won back the sceptre of his race by a
daring surprise. He governed with conspicuous moderation, discretion, and
success; setting himself to the work of reviving the cause of Hellenism, which
had lost much ground during the past half-century; and pursuing this task by
entirely peaceful means. After Aegospotami, the city of Evagoras became the
refuge for large numbers of Athenians who had settled down in various parts of
the Athenian empire and could no longer remain securely in their homes. For the
first sixteen years of his reign Evagoras was a faithful tributary of the Great
King, and we have seen how his influence at Susa assisted Conon. But soon after
the battle of Cnidus he became involved in war, both with Persia and with some
of the Phoenician cities in the island. The Peace expressly recognised the sovereignty of Artaxerxes over Cyprus, and as soon as it was concluded,
Persia began to concentrate her forces against Evagoras and a recalcitrant king
of Egypt, with whom Evagoras was leagued. A severe defeat at sea shut Evagoras
up in Salamis; but he held out so dauntlessly, and the war had already cost
Persia so much, that Tiribazus agreed to leave him
his principality, on condition that he should pay tribute “as a slave to his
lord.” Evagoras refused; he would only pay it as one king to another. The
negotiations were ruptured for a moment on this point of honour,
but a dispute between the satrap and his subordinate general resulted in the
removal of Tiribazus, and his successor permitted
Evagoras to have his way.
The Salaminian despot had thus gained a moral triumph.
He did not survive it many years, and the story of his death is curious. A
certain man named Nicocreon formed a plot against his
life, and being detected was forced to fly. He left a daughter behind him in
Salamis under the care of a faithful eunuch. This servant privily acquainted
both Evagoras and his son Pytagoras with the
existence of this young lady and her uncommon beauty, and undertook to conduct
them to her bedchamber, each without the knowledge of the other. Both kept the
assignation and were slain by the eunuch, who thus avenged his master’s exile.
Another son of Evagoras, named Nicocles, succeeded him, and pursued the same
Hellenizing policy. One of the great objects of these enlightened princes was
to keep their country in touch with the intellectual and artistic movements of
Greece. Nicocles was a student of Greek philosophy, and a generous friend of
the essayist, Isocrates, to whose pen we are indebted for much of what we know
of the career of Evagoras.
Towards the close of the almost single-handed struggle
of Salamis against Persia, the eyes of Greece were directed to a different
quarter of the world. Events were passing in the north of the Aegean, which
riveted the attention of Sparta and Athens; their Greek brethren of Cyprus and
the Asiatic coast seem to be quite forgotten; for a while the oriental question
almost passes out of the pages of Greek history. Yet it was destined that from
that very region on the north-west comer of the Aegean should issue the force
which should not only reclaim for European influence Cyprus and all the Greek
cities of Asia, but bear Greek light into lands of which Agesilaus had never
dreamed. That force was being forged in the Macedonian uplands; and some who
were children when Isocrates published his Panegyric against the Barbarian
lived to see the Barbarian succumb to a Greek power.
It was indeed only indirectly that the southern Greeks
had now to concern themselves with their backward brethren of Macedonia. One of
the chief obstacles to the development of this country was its constant
exposure to the attacks of its Illyrian neighbours and an Illyrian invasion,
supported by domestic disloyalty, compelled king Amyntas—he was the nephew of
Perdiccas—to flee from his kingdom. Amyntas, soon after his accession, had
concluded a close defensive and commercial alliance for fifty years with the
Chalcidian league, which had been formed by Olynthus and comprised the towns of
the Sithonian promontory. It was, as we observed
already, an age of small federations. At the moment of his retreat Amyntas
handed over to the Chalcidians the lower districts of Macedonia and the cities
lying round the Thermaic gulf. The Macedonian cities
readily embraced an union which could protect them against the Illyrians, and
the league spread from the maritime towns up the country and included even
Pella. Perfect equality and brotherhood between the members was the basis of
this Chalcidian confederacy. All the cities had common laws, common rights of
citizenship, intermarriage and commerce; Olynthus did not assume a privileged
position for herself. The neighbouring Greek cities
were also asked to join, and some of them, Potidaea for instance, accepted the
offer. But it was always a sacrifice for a Greek city to give up its hereditary
laws and surrender any part of its sovereignty, whatever compensating
advantages might be purchased; and there was consequently more reluctance among
the Chalcidians than among the less developed Macedonians to join the league.
The Olynthians, as their work grew, conceived the
idea of a confederate power which should embrace the whole Chalcidic peninsula
and its neighbourhood. Once this ambition took form,
it became necessary to impose by force their propositions upon those who
declined to accept them freely. The strong cities of Acanthus and Apollonia
resisted, and sent envoys to Sparta to obtain her help. Moreover Amyntas had
recovered his throne, and when the Olynthians refused
to abandon the cities which he had handed over to them, he too looked for aid
to Sparta. These appeals directed the eyes of Greece upon the Chalcidian
confederacy. It was the Lacedaemonian policy to oppose all combinations and
keep Greece disunited—a policy which was popular, in so far as it appealed to
that innate love of autonomy which made it so difficult to bring about abiding
federal unions in Greece. The ambassadors had little difficulty in persuading
the Lacedaemonians and their allies that the movement in Chalcidice was
dangerous to the interests of Sparta, and should be crushed at the outset; and
they argued that the very liberality of the principles on which it was founded
made the league more attractive and therefore more dangerous. A vote of
assistance to Acanthus and Apollonia was passed, and a small advance force was
immediately sent under Eudamidas. Though unable to meet the confederate army in
the field, this force was sufficient to protect the cities which had refused to
join the league, and it even induced Potidaea to revolt
The expedition against the Chalcidian Confederacy led
unexpectedly to an important incident elsewhere. Phoebidas,
the brother of Eudamidas, was to follow with larger forces, and, as the line of
march lay through Boeotia, a party in Thebes favourable to Sparta thought to profit by the proximity of Spartan troops for the purpose
of a revolution. Leontiadas, the most prominent
member of this party, was then one of the polemarchs.
He concerted with Phoebidas a plot to seize the
Cadmea—the citadel of Thebes—on the day of the Thesmophoria; for on that day
the citadel was given up to the use of the women who celebrated the feast. The
plot succeeded perfectly; the acropolis was occupied without striking a blow;
the oligarchical Council was intimidated by Leontiadas;
and his colleague, the other polemarch, Ismenias was
arrested. The leading anti-Spartans fled from Thebes, and a government friendly
to Sparta was established. This was a great triumph for Sparta, a great
satisfaction to Agesilaus, although, as a violation of peace, it caused a
moment’s embarrassment. Was the government to recognise the action of Phoebidas and profit by it? Spartan
hypocrisy compromised the matter; Phoebidas was fined
100,000 drachmae for his indiscretion, and the Cadmea was retained. Then Ismenias was tried by a body of judges representing Sparta
and her allies, and was condemned on charges of Medism and executed. That Sparta, after the King’s Peace, should condemn a Theban for Medism, was a travesty of justice.
With the fortress of Thebes in her hands, Sparta had a
basis for extending her power in central Greece and might regard her supremacy
as secured. She restored the city of Plataea, which she had herself destroyed
well-nigh fifty years agone, and gathered all the Plataeans who could be found
to their old home. But her immediate attention was fixed on the necessity of
repressing the dangerous league in the north of Greece, and continuing the
measures which had been interrupted by the enterprise of Phoebidas in Boeotia. The popular brother of Agesilaus, Teleutias,
was sent to conduct the war; but, although he was aided by Amyntas, and by
Derdas, a prince of Upper Macedonia, who supplied good cavalry, it proved no
easy matter to make head against the league. In front of the walls of Olynthus, Teleutias sustained a signal defeat and was himself
slain. The war was fatal to a king as well as to a king’s brother. Agesipolis,
who was next sent out at the head of a very large force, caught a fever in the
intolerable summer heat. He was carried to the shady grove of the temple of
Dionysus at Aphytis, but he died there; and his body,
stowed in honey, was brought home for burial. His successor, Polybiadas, was more successful. He forced the Olynthians to sue for peace and dissolve their league. They
and all the Greek cities of the peninsula were constrained to join the
Lacedaemonian alliance, and the maritime cities of Macedonia were restored to
the sway of Amyntas. Thus Sparta put down an attempt to overcome that system of
isolation, which placed Greek cities at a great disadvantage, when they had
barbarian neighbours. If Sparta had not happened to be so strong at this
moment, the Chalcidian league might have grown into a power, which would have
considerably modified the development of Macedonia. All that Sparta did,
although for a moment it made her power paramount in northern Greece, fell out
ultimately to the advancement and profit of Macedon.
About the same time, the Lacedaemonians were making
their heavy hand felt in the Peloponnesus. Soon after the King’s Peace they had
forced the Phliasians to recall a number of banished
aristocrats. Disputes arose about the restoration of confiscated property, and
the exiles appealed to Sparta, where they had a zealous supporter in Agesilaus.
War was declared; Agesilaus reduced the city of Phlius by blockade, and compelled it to receive a Lacedaemonian garrison for six
months, until a commission of one hundred, which he nominated, should have
drawn up a new constitution.
Thus the Lacedaemonians, in alliance with the tyrant
Dionysius and the barbarian Artaxerxes, tyrannised over the Greeks for a space. Some demonstrations were made, some voices of
protest were raised, in the name of the Panhellenic cause. At the Olympian
festival which was held about two years after the King’s Peace, the Athenian
orator Lysias warned the assembled Greeks of the dangers which loomed in the
east and in the west, from Persia and from Sicily, and uttered his amazement at
the policy of Lacedaemon. A magnificent deputation had been sent by Dionysius
to this festival, and the inflammatory words, perhaps the direct instigation,
of the speaker incited some enthusiastic spectators to attack the gorgeous
pavilion of the Syracusan envoys. The outrage was prevented; but the occurrence
shows the beginning of that tide of feeling to which Isocrates appealed, four
years later, when in his festal oration he denounced the Lacedaemonians, as
sacrificing the freedom of Greece to their own interests and treacherously
aiding foreigners and tyrants
Even Xenophon, the friend of Sparta’s king, the
admirer of Sparta’s institutions, is roused to regretful indignation at
Sparta’s conduct, and recognises her fall as a just
retribution. “The Lacedaemonians, who swore to leave the cities independent,
seized the acropolis of Thebes, and they were punished by the very men,
single-handed, whom they had wronged, though never before had they been
vanquished by any single people. It is a proof that the gods observe men who do
irreligious and unhallowed deeds.” In this way the pious historian introduces
the event which prepared the fall of Sparta and the rise of Thebes.
Sect.
2. Alliance of Athens and Thebes
The government of Leontiadas and his party at Thebes, maintained by 1500 Lacedaemonians in the citadel, was
despotic and cruel, like that of the Thirty at Athens. Fear made the rulers
suspicious and oppressive; for they were afraid of the large number of exiles,
who had found a refuge at Athens and were awaiting an opportunity to recover
their city. Athens was now showing the same goodwill to the fugitives from
Thebes which Thebes, when Athens was in a like plight, had shown to Thrasybulus
and his fellows. One of the exiles, named Pelopidas, of more than common daring
and devotion, resolved to take his life in his hands and found six others to
associate in his plans. No open attack was to be thought of; Thebes must be
recovered by guile, even as by guile it had been won. There were many in Thebes
who were bitter foes of the ruling party, such as Epaminondas, the beloved
friend of Pelopidas, but most of them deemed the time unripe for any sudden
stroke for freedom. Yet a few were found ready to run the risk; above all, Phyllidas, who was the secretary of the polemarchs and therefore the most useful of confederates, and Charon, a citizen of good
estate, who offered his house as a place of hiding for the conspirators. The
day on which the two polemarchs, Archias and Philippus, were to go out of office was fixed for the enterprise. On the
day before, Pelopidas and his six comrades crossed Cithaeron in the guise of
huntsmen, and, nearing Thebes at nightfall, mixed with the peasants who were
returning from the fields, got them safely within the gates, and found safe
hiding in the abode of Charon. The secretary Phyllidas had made ready a great banquet for the following night, to which he had bidden
the outgoing polemarchs, tempting them by the promise
of introducing them to some high-born and beautiful women, whose love they
desired. During the carouse a messenger came with a letter for Archias, and said that it concerned serious affairs.
“Business tomorrow,” said Archias, placing it under
his pillow. On the morrow it was found that this letter disclosed the
conspiracy. The polemarchs then called for the women,
who were waiting in an adjoining room. Phyllidas said
that they declined to appear till all the attendants were dismissed. When no
one remained in the dining hall but the polemarchs and a few friends, all flushed with wine, the women entered and sat down beside
the lords. They were covered with long veils; and even as they were bidden lift
them and reveal their charms, they buried daggers in the bodies of the polemarchs. For they were none other than Pelopidas and his
fellows in the guise of women. Then they went and slew in their houses Leontiadas and Hypatas, the two
other chief leaders of the party, and set free the political prisoners. When
all this was done, Epaminondas and the other patriots, who were unwilling to
initiate such deeds themselves, accepted the revolution with joy. When day
dawned, an assembly of the people was held in the Agora, and the conspirators
were crowned with wreaths. Three of them, including Pelopidas, were appointed polemarchs, and a democratic constitution was established.
The rest of the exiles and a body of Athenian
volunteers presently arrived, on the news of the success. The Spartan commander
of the Cadmea had sent hastily, on the first alarm, for reinforcements to Thespiae and Plataea, but those that came were charged and
repelled, outside the gate. Then in the first flush of success the patriots
resolved to storm the Cadmea, strong as the place was. But the labour and the danger were spared them. Amazing as it may
seem Lacedaemonian harmosts decided to capitulate at once. Two of these
commanders were put to death on their return to Sparta, and the third was
banished. The chagrin of the ephors and Agesilaus was intense; king Cleombrotus was immediately sent with an army to Boeotia,
but accomplished nothing.
Athens was formally at peace with Sparta, and was not
disposed to break with her, however great may have been the secret joy felt at
the events of Boeotia. But the march of the Athenian volunteers to Thebes was
an awkward incident, the more so as there were two strategi among them.
Lacedaemonian envoys arrived to demand explanation and satisfaction; and their
statements were reinforced by the neighbourhood of
the army of king Cleombrotus. There was indeed
nothing to be said for the conduct of the two strategi. They had abused their
position and brought their city into danger and embarrassment. We can only
approve the sentence of the Athenians, which executed one and banished the
other.
But if these Athenian generals were indiscreet, it was
as nothing beside the indiscretion of a Lacedaemonian commander, which now
precipitated the breach between the two states. A not ignoble sympathy might
have been pleaded by the two Athenians; but no excuse could be urged for the
rash enterprise of the Spartan harmost of Thespiae,
who aspired to be a second Phoebidas. His name was Sphodrias, and he conceived the plan of making a night
march to Athens and surprising Piraeus on the landside. To seize Piraeus, the
seat of Athenian merchandise, would be a compensation for the loss of Thebes.
But the plan was, if not ill-considered, at least ill carried out. Day dawned
when he had hardly passed Eleusis; and there was nothing to do but to turn
back. He retreated, laying waste the districts through which he passed.
Great wrath was kindled in Athens by this unprovoked
deed of hostility. The envoys had not yet gone; they were immediately thrown
into prison, but escaped by declaring that the Spartan government was not
responsible for the raid, and would speedily prove its innocence by the
condemnation of Sphodrias. The assurance was
belied Sphodrias was not condemned. His son and the son of Agesilaus were lovers, and the king’s
influence saved him. Agesilaus is reported to have said: “Sphodrias is guilty, of course; but it is a hard thing to put to death a man who, as
child, stripling, and man, lived a life of perfect honour;
for Sparta needeth such soldiers.” This miscarriage
of justice was a grave mistake of policy; and the high-handed insolence of the
Spartan oligarchs was set in a more glaring light by contrast with the
fair-mindedness which the Athenian people had displayed in promptly punishing
its own generals for a similar though certainly less heinous act. The Athenian
generals had at least not invaded Lacedaemonian territory. It was debated at
the time, and has been debated since, whether Sphodrias acted wholly of his own accord; some thought that the suggestion came from king Cleombrotus, and the theory was started that the
Thebans were the prime instigators—an unlikely theory, which was evidently
based on the fact that Thebes was the only gainer by the raid. It seems most
probable that the private ambition of Sphodrias, who
thought he had a chance of emulating Phoebidas, was
alone responsible.
The raid and acquittal of Sphodrias drove Athens, against her will, into war with Sparta and alliance with Thebes;
it stirred her for a while to leave her role of neutral spectator and assume
that of an active belligerent. For the next six years, Athens and Sparta are at
war, though such a war was contrary to the interests of both states, but
especially to the interests of Sparta.
Sect.
3. The Second Athenian League and the Theban Reforms
The raid of Sphodrias was
the direct occasion of the Second Athenian Confederacy. For many years back,
ever since the battle of Cnidus, Athens had been gradually forming bonds of
alliance with various states in Thrace, the Aegean, and the coasts of Asia
Minor. The breach with Sparta induced her now to gather together these separate connexions into a common league, with the express
object of protecting the independence of the Greek states against the
oppression of Sparta. When men thought of the old Confederacy of Delos, they
might fear that the second Athenian league would be soon converted into a
second Athenian empire. But Athens anticipated such alarms by establishing the
confederacy on a different system, which provided safeguards against the
dangers of Athenian preponderance and Athenian encroachment. In the archonship
of Nausinicus, Aristoteles of the deme of Marathon proposed in the Assembly a
decree which embodied the principles of the league. The sway of Persia over the
Greeks of Asia was explicitly recognised, so that the
field of operations was to be European Greece and the Islands. The league,
which was purely defensive, was constituted in two parts, Athens on one side,
her allies on the other. The allies had their own synedrion or congress which
met in Athens, but in which Athens had no part. Both the synedrion of the
Confederates and the Athenian Assembly had the right of initiating measures,
but no measure passed by either body was valid until it had been approved by
the other body also. While this system gave Athens a weight and dignity equal
to that of all her allies together, it secured for the allies an independence
which they had not possessed under the old league, and they had the right of
absolute veto on any Athenian proposal which they disliked. It was necessary
for the members of the league to form a federal fund; their payments were
called syntaxeis (“contributions”), and the word phoros (“tribut”), which had
odious memories connected with the confederacy of Delos, was avoided. It was especially
enacted that the practice of Athenian outsettling in
the lands of the allies, which had formerly helped and supported the Athenian
empire, was not to be permitted. No Athenian was to acquire home or farm, “by
purchase or mortgage, or any other means whatever,” in the territory of any of
the confederates. But the administration of the federal fund and the leadership
of the federal army were in the hands of Athens.
Good fortune has preserved to us the original stone,
shattered in about twenty pieces, with the decree which founded the
confederacy, and we find the purpose of the league definitely declared: “To
force the Lacedaemonians to allow the Greeks to enjoy peace in freedom and
independence, with their lands unviolated.” It was no doubt Callistratus, the
ablest statesman and orator of the day, who did most to make the new scheme a
success; but, though he may be called the Aristides of the Second Confederacy,
Callistratus certainly did not mean the combination against Sparta as seriously
as Aristides meant the combination against Persia. The policy which
Callistratus generally pursued was based on harmony with Sparta and antagonism
to Thebes. It is sometimes said that at this period there were two parties
contending for the guidance of the foreign policy of Athens, one friendly and
the other obstinately hostile to Boeotia. But, though Thebes had some friends
at Athens, we have no good grounds for speaking of a Theban or Boeotian party.
It might be truer to say that there was an anti-Spartan faction, which might
often seek a Theban alliance as a means to an end. At this juncture
Callistratus was astute enough to see not only that it would be useless to
oppose the feeling against Sparta, but also that an opportunity which might
never recur was offered for increasing the power of Athens. He therefore
abandoned for the time his permanent policy, and threw himself heartily into a
scheme of which the most remarkable feature was union with Thebes.
The chief cities which first joined the new league
were Chios, Byzantium, Mytilene, Methymna, and Rhodes; then most of the towns
of Euboea joined, and, what was most important and wonderful, Thebes enrolled
her name in the list of the confederates. The Thracian cities, and several
other states, including Coreyra, Jason the despot of
Pherae in Thessaly, and Alcetas a prince of Epirus,
presently brought up the whole tale of members to about seventy. But though the
league, drawn on such liberal lines, evoked some enthusiasm at first, and the
adhesion of Thebes gave its inauguration a certain éclat, it had no vital elements of growth or permanence, and never
attained high political importance. The fact is, that the true interest of
Athens, as Callistratus knew, was peace with Sparta, and was consequently
repugnant to the avowed object of the confederacy. Hence the confederacy was
doomed either to fall asunder, or to become the tool of other designs of Athens
as soon as Sparta had been taught a lesson and the more abiding interest of
Athene could safely assert itself again over the temporary expedient of an
unnatural alliance with Thebes.
It was a moment at which the chief Greek states were
setting their houses in order. Thebes was making herself ready and dight for a
new career; Sparta was remodelling her league, and
Athens her finances. A property tax, such as had first been introduced in the
third year of the Peloponnesian war, was revived, and a new assessment of
property was made. One-fifth of the actual capital of each citizen was
inscribed in the register, and the tax (probably about one per cent) was
imposed on this fraction, not on the whole capital. The revenue from this
impost seems to have amounted annually to about sixty talents. For the purpose
of levying the tax the whole body of burghers was divided into 100 symmories, and the richest citizens in each symmory were responsible to the treasury for the total sum
due on the properties of all the citizens who belonged to it. By this means the
State relieved itself from the friction which is generally caused by the
collection of direct imposts, and the revenue accruing from the tax was realised more promptly and easily than if the government
had to deal immediately with the individual burghers. Thus Athens tried the
novel experiment of a system of joint responsibility, such as in later days was
to be introduced and established in an empire of which Athens was only an
insignificant town.
At Thebes the attention of the government was chiefly
bestowed on military affairs. A ditch was dug and a rampart raised round part
of the Theban territory as a defence against the
inevitable Lacedaemonian invasions. But this precaution was of small moment in
comparison with the creation of a new troop of 300 hoplites, all chosen young
men of the noblest families, who had proved their eminent strength and
endurance in a long training in the wrestling school. Each man had his best
friend beside him; so that the Sacred Band, as it was called, consisted of 150
pairs of lovers, prepared to fight and fall together. In battle, it was to
stand in front of the other hoplites. At the same time, we may be sure, much
was done to improve the army in other points. Opportunely for Thebes there had
arisen, to guide her to success when her chance came, a man of rare ability, in
whom nature seemed to have united the best features of Greek character and
discarded the defects. This was Epaminondas, the friend of Pelopidas. He was a
modest, unambitious man, who in other circumstances would probably have
remained in obscurity, unobtrusively fulfilling the duties of a citizen and
soldier. But the revolution stimulated his patriotism and lured him into the
field of public affairs, where his eminent capacity, gradually revealing
itself, made him, before eight years had passed, the most influential man in
his city. He had devoted as much time to musical as to gymnastic training;
unlike most of his countrymen, he could play the lyre as well as the Theban
flute; and he had a genuine interest in philosophical speculation. A Tarentine
friend, who had been much in his company, assevered that he never met a man who knew more and talked less than Epaminondas. But the
Theban statesman could speak when he chose, or when the need demanded; and his
eloquence was extremely impressive. Exceptional in his indifference to the
prizes of ambition, he was also exceptional in his indifference to money, and
he died poor. Not less remarkable was his lack of that party spirit, which led
to so many crimes in Greece. He could not share in strong political hatred or
lust for revenge; and we have already seen that his repugnance to domestic
bloodshed kept him from taking a part in the fortunate conspiracy of Pelopidas.
Sect.
4. The Battle of Naxos and the Peace of Callias
The following eight years are marked by a successful
defensive war of Thebes against Spartan invasions; by a decrease of Spartan
prestige; by the extension of the Theban supremacy over the rest of Boeotia. At
the same time, Athens prosecutes a naval war against the Lacedaemonian
Confederacy, and gains considerable successes; but the strain on her resources
which this war entails, and a growing jealousy of Thebes, combine to induce her
to come to terms with Sparta.
Two invasions of Boeotia conducted by Agesilaus
himself in successive summers achieved nothing; and the Thebans had the
satisfaction of slaying Phoebidas, who had won his
fame by the capture of their acropolis. The other king, Cleombrotus,
did even less than Agesilaus, for he found the passes of Cithaeron held by the
foes, and could not enter Boeotia. After this, the Thebans had time to attack
the Boeotian cities and drive out the Spartan garrison; so that by the end of
four years the Boeotian confederacy once more extended over all Boeotia, the
local governments being overthrown and the foreign harmosts expelled. Only in
the extreme west, in Orchomenus and Chaeronea, were the Lacedaemonians able to
hold their ground. In the course of this resuscitation of the Boeotian league
one notable exploit was wrought by Pelopidas and the Sacred Band. At Tegyra, on the road from Orchomenus to Locris, in a narrow
pass, the Thebans routed twice as many Lacedaemonian troops, and slew both the
Spartan generals. As in the case of all Spartan defeats, the moral effect was
of far greater import than the actual loss in the field. Perhaps it was about
this time that Athens won back Oropus, which had been lost to her in the year
of the Four Hundred.
In the meantime there had been war too on the seas.
When the invasions of Boeotia fell out so badly, Sparta had had bethought
herself of equipping a naval armament to cut off the corn ships which bore rain
to Attica from the Euxine. The ships reached Geraestus,
the south point of Euboea; but a fleet of sixty galleys under the Spartan
Pollis hindered them from rounding the Cape of Sunium,
and Athens was menaced with famine. Eighty triremes were speedily fitted out
and sent forth from the Piraeus, under the command of Chabrias,
to recover the mastery of the sea. Chabrias sailed to
Naxos, which had seized this moment to desert the Athenian Confederacy, and
beleaguered the city. Pollis hurried to the rescue, and a battle was fought in
the sound between Paros and Naxos. The Athenians gained a complete victory, and
only eleven of the Lacedaemonian vessels escaped. Even these would have been
disabled, had not Chabrias desisted from the action,
for the purpose of saving some of his own men who were overboard or in disabled
ships. The lesson which the Athenian people taught their generals after the
battle of Arginusae had not been forgotten. Though the battle of Naxos had not
the important consequences of the battle of Cnidus, it was more gratifying to
Athens. The Cnidian victory had been won indeed under
the command of an Athenian, but by Persian men and ships; the victory gained by Chabrias was entirely Athenian. It led immediately to
an enlargement of the Confederacy. The triumphant fleet sailed round the
Aegean, enrolled seventeen new cities, and collected a large sum of money.
Athens had also to reassert her authority at Delos. For the inhabitants of the
island who chafed at the administration of their temple by the Athenian amphictiones, as
the sacred overseers were entitled, had attempted, doubtless with Lacedaemonian
help, to recover control of the sanctuary. An interesting entry in the Delian
accounts of these years, preserved on a stone, tells how seven ringleaders of
the movement were punished by fines and perpetual banishment “for having led
the amphictiones forth from the temple and beaten
them.”
Next year, the fleet was sent to sail round the
Peloponnesus under the command of Timotheus, son of Conon, This
circumnavigation of the Peloponnesus was an assertion by Athens that her naval
power was once more dominant; it was intended to frighten Sparta, to extend
Athenian influence in western Greece, and to act in the Corinthian Gulf, in
case the Spartans tried to throw an army into Boeotia by the port of Creusis.
The islands of Corcyra and Cephallenia, the king of
the Molossi, some of the Acarnanians, were won over to the Athenian alliance by
the discreet policy of Timotheus, who also gained a trifling victory over some
hostile ships. But there was a darker side to this triumphant expedition. The
cost of the war was proving to be greater than Athens could well bear, and
Timotheus failed to obtain from home the money requisite to pay his seamen. In
this strait, he was obliged to ask each trierarch to advance seven minae for the payment of his crew; and Athens herself sent
a request to Thebes for some contribution towards the expense of the naval
operations, on the ground that the enterprise of Timotheus had been undertaken
partly at Theban instigation. The refusal of this demand, along with a growing
jealousy of Theban success, and the somewhat grave financial difficulties of
the moment, combined to dispose Athens towards peace with Sparta; and this was
in fact her wisest policy. Negotiations were opened and carried to a successful
issue; but the peace was no sooner made than it was broken. For Timotheus, who
was ordered to return home from Coreyra and
reluctantly obeyed, halted at Zacynthus on his way,
landed some Zacynthian exiles who were with him, and
fortified a post for them on the island. The Zacynthians straightway complained to Sparta; Sparta demanded satisfaction from Athens; and
when this was refused, the incident was treated as a breach of contract and the
war was resumed.
The first object of Sparta was to regain her power in
the west, and undo the work of Timotheus. The best of the winnings of that
general had been Corcyra, and Corcyra once more became the scene of a
“Peloponnesian” war. With the help of their confederates, including Corinth,
the Lacedaemonians launched an armament of sixty ships, conveying 1500
mercenary hoplites, to gain possession of the island; and at the same time a
message was dispatched to Dionysius of Syracuse requesting his aid, on the
ground that Sicily had her interests in Corcyraean politics. The armament was
commanded by the Spartan Mnasippus. He drove the
Corcyraean fleet into the harbour, which he blocked
with his own ships, and he invested the city by land, so that the supplies of
the inhabitants were cut off. The island was a rich prize for the soldiers to
whose depredations it was now given over. The tillage was goodly, the crofts and
farmhouses exceeding fair; and so plentiful was the wine that the troopers
would drink none that was not of the finest sort. Urgent messages were sent to
Athens by the Corcyraeans, who soon began to feel the pinch of famine. So great
was the misery that slaves were cast out of the gates; even some citizens
deserted, but were whipped back to the walls by the Lacedaemonian commander.
But he deeming that he had the city in his hands grew careless in his
confidence; and from the watch-towers on their walls the besieged could observe
that the watch was sometimes relaxed. An opportune moment was seized for a
sally, which resulted in a completer success than they looked for. The
professional soldiers, who had not been paid and detested their general, showed
no zeal in withstanding the hot onslaught of the desperate men who poured forth
from the gates. Mnasippus was slain, and the
besiegers fell back to their camp. The beleaguerment was thus broken up, and
the Corcyraeans were safe until the coming of the expected help from Athens.
But they were delivered from all constraint even before that tardy help came;
for the Lacedaemonians evacuated the island almost immediately after the
defeat. Then at last the Athenian fleet sailed into the roads of Corcyra.
It was from no want of goodwill on the part of the
Athenian people that the help had not come in time to save Corcyra much of the
misery which she had suffered. A tale hangs by the delay of the fleet. On the
first appeal, it was resolved to send sixty ships at once, and 600 peltasts
were sent in advance and successfully introduced into the city. It was
befitting that Timotheus should return to the scene of his former achievements,
and the command of the fleet was entrusted to him. He found himself in an awkward
position, owing to one of the gravest defects in the machinery of Athenian
administration. The people had voted a certain measure, appointing him to carry
it out; but had omitted to vote or consider the necessary ways and means. It
consequently devolved upon Timotheus to find the men and the money. For this
purpose he cruised with some of his ships in the Northern Aegean, visiting
Thessaly, Macedonia, and Thrace, while the main part of the fleet awaited his
return at the island of Calauria. But meanwhile the
need of Corcyra was sore, and more pressing messengers were arriving in Athens.
The long tarrying of the general excited public indignation; his appointment
was annulled; and Iphicrates, in conjunction with Chabriasand Callistratus, was charged to sail at once to Corcyra.
Callistratus was the most eloquent orator of the day. Chabrias, a tried soldier who had served under Cypriote and
Egyptian kings, we have already met as the victor of Naxos. Iphicrates, who had
come to the front by his boldness and success in the Corinthian war, had for
the last fifteen years served as a captain of peltasts under the princes of
Thrace, and had married a daughter of king Cotys. A comic poet gives a
picturesque description of his barbaric wedding. In the market-place a
plentiful feast is set out for a throng of wildhaired Thracians. There are immense brazen cauldrons of broth, and the king, girding
himself up, serves it with his own hands in a golden basin. Then the wine and
water are tempered in the mixing-bowls, and the king goes around tasting each
bowl, until he is the first drunk. But an adventurous life among the
“butter-eating” barbarians does not seem to have wholly satisfied Iphicrates.
He served the King of Persia in Egypt and then returned to Athens, and this
expedition to Corcyra seems to have been his first service after his return. It
was well and capably performed. The people in their excitement gave him a freer
hand than they had given to Timotheus. He was able to put hard pressure on the trierarchs; he was allowed to impress seamen, and to make
use of the galleys which guarded the Attic coast, and even the two sacred
vessels, the Salaminia and Paralus. By these unusual efforts
a fleet of seventy triremes was put together, but before it was quite ready to
sail Timotheus returned. His cruise had been successful in raising money and
men, and adding new members to the Confederacy; but it was thought that neither
necessity nor success could excuse the singular inopportuneness of the delay.
Ill-luck seemed to wait upon Timotheus. The funds which he brought back proved
unable to meet the obligations which they ought to have defrayed, and a fraud
was suspected. Iphicrates and Callistratus, his political rivals, lodged an
indictment against him, but as they had to sail immediately to the west, the
trial was postponed till the autumn.
On his way out Iphicrates learned the news of the
deliverance of Corcyra, so that he was able to send back those ships whose true
duty was the defence of Attica. But there was still
work to be done. The appeal which the Lacedaemonians sent to the tyrant
Dionysius had not been in vain, and ten Syracusan triremes were even then
approaching Corcyra. They stopped at a point in the north of the island, that
the crews might rest after the long voyage; and there Iphicrates whose scouts
had watched for their approach captured them, all but one vessel. This prize
raised the welcome sum of sixty talents, but it was not long before Iphicrates,
even as Timotheus, found himself embarrassed for want of money. Callistratus
went back to Athens, promising to persuade the people either to keep the fleet
regularly paid or to make peace. Meanwhile the crews of Iphicrates obtained
subsistence by labour on the Corcyraean farms.
If Corcyra had fallen, there can be little question
that Timotheus would have been sacrificed to the displeasure of the Athenian
people. But the good tidings from the west restored the public good-humour, and this was fortunate for the discredited general.
His trial came on towards the end of the year. His military treasurer was tried
at the same time, found guilty of malversation, and condemned to death. But
Timotheus himself was acquitted. He had indeed unusually powerful support. Two
foreign monarchs had condescended to come to Athens to bear testimony in his favour, the Epirot king Alcetas,
and Jason the despot of Thessalian Pherae. It was through Timotheus that these
potentates had joined the Athenian league; and it was through them that he had
been able to transport across Thessaly and Epirus the 600 peltasts who had been
sent in advance to Corcyra. The interest of Jason—of whom more will have to be
said presently—was particularly effective. Timotheus entertained these
distinguished guests in his house in Piraeus, but he was obliged to borrow
bedding, two silver bowls, and other things from his rich neighbour, the banker
Pasion, in order to lodge them suitably. Though acquitted, Timotheus was
discredited in public opinion, and he soon left Athens to take service in Egypt
under the Great King.
Sparta had lost heart at the decisive check which she
had received in Corcyra, and the discouragement was increased by a series of
terrible earthquakes, in which Poseidon seemed to declare his wrath. She was
therefore disposed to peace, and she thought to bring peace about, as before,
through the mediation of Persia. Antalcidas was once more sent up to the
Persian court. But this intervention from without was not really needed.
Athens, uneasy under the burdens of the war and feeling rather jealousy of Thebes
than bitterness against Sparta, was also well inclined to peace, and the
influential orator Callistratus made it the object of his policy. The recent
aggressions of Thebes against the Phocians, who were old allies of Athens,
tended to estrange the two cities; and to this was added the treatment of that
unfortunate little mountain burg, Plataea, by her Theban enemies. Restored
Plataea had perforce been enrolled in the Boeotian confederacy, but she was
secretly scheming for annexation to Attica. Suspecting these plots, Thebes
determined to forestall them, and a small Theban force, surprising the town one
day when the men were in the fields, took possession of it and drove all the
Plataeans forth from Plataean soil. Many of the
people, thus bereft of land and city, found a refuge at Athens; where the
publicist Isocrates took up their cause and wrote his Plataeic Discourse, a denunciation of Thebes. This incident definitely,
though not formally, loosened the bonds between the two northern powers.
The overtures came from Athens and her Confederacy.
When the Lacedaemonian allies met at Sparta in spring, three Athenian envoys
appeared at the congress. Of these the chief spokesman was Callistratus, and
one of his associates was Callias, Torchbearer of the Eleusinian Mysteries, who
had also worked to bring about the abortive peace three years before. Thebes
likewise sent ambassadors, one of whom was Epaminondas. The basis of the peace
which was now concluded was the principle which had been affirmed by the King’s
Peace, the principle of the autonomy of every Hellenic city. The Athenian and
Lacedaemonian Confederacies were thus both rendered invalid. No compulsion
could be exercised on any city to fulfil engagements as member of a league.
Cities might co-operate with each other freely so far as they chose, but no
obligation could be contracted or enforced. Yet while Athens and Sparta
resigned empire, they mutually agreed to recognise each other’s predominance, that of Athens by sea, that of Sparta on land—a
predominance which must never be asserted by aggression and must always be
consistent with the universal autonomy.
The question immediately arose whether the Boeotian
League was condemned by this doctrine of universal autonomy. Sparta and Athens,
of course, intended to condemn it. But it might be pleaded that the Confederacy
of Boeotian cities under the presidency of Thebes was not on the same footing
as the Confederacies which had been formed, for temporary political purposes,
without any historical or geographical basis of union, under the presidencies
of Athens and Sparta. It might be contended that Boeotia was a geographical
unity, like Attica and Laconia, and had a title to political unity too,
especially as the League was an ancient institution. The question came to the
issue when it was the turn of Thebes to take the oath. Her representative
Epaminondas claimed to take it on behalf of the Boeotian cities; and Thebes,
represented by him, was not so easily cowed as when she made the same claim at
the conclusion of the King’s Peace. He seems to have developed the view that
Boeotia was to be compared to Laconia, not to the Lacedaemonian Confederacy;
and when Agesilaus asked him, curtly and angrily: “Will you leave each of the
Boeotian towns independent?” he retorted: “Will you leave each of the Laconian
towns independent?” The name of Thebes was thereupon struck out of the treaty.
There was an argument as well as a sting in this
retort of Epaminondas. The argument was: Sparta has no more right to interfere
in the internal affairs of Boeotia than we have to interfere in the domestic
administration of Laconia; Laconia, Boeotia, Attica, each represents a distinct
kind of constitution, and each constitution is justified; the union of Boeotia
in a federation is as natural as the union of Attica in a single city, as
legitimate as the union of Laconia in its subjection to the Spartan oligarchy.
The union of Boeotia, like the union of Laconia, could not have been realised and could not be maintained without the
perpetration of outrages upon the freewill of some communities. Yet it is
hardly legitimate for one state to say to another: “We have committed certain
acts of violence, but you must not interfere for at a remote period of history which none of us remember, your
ancestors used even more high-handed methods for similar purposes, and you now
maintain what they established.” But the tyrannical method by which Laconia was
governed was certainly a weak point in the Spartan armour;
and the reply of Epaminondas may have well set Greece thinking over a question
of political science. Setting aside the arguments of diplomacy, the point of
the situation was this: Thebes could never become a strong power, the rival of
Sparta or of Athens, except at the head of an united Boeotia, and it was the
interest of Athens and Sparta to hinder her from becoming such a power.
So far as the two chief contracting parties were
concerned, this bargain—which is often called the “Peace of Callias”—put an end
to a war which was contrary to the best interests of both. They were both
partly to blame, but Sparta was far more to blame than her old rival. Her
witless policy in overlooking the raid of Sphodrias had caused the war; for it left to Athens no alternative but hostility. At the
end of four years, they seemed to have come to their senses; they made peace,
but they were stupid enough to allow the incident of Zacynthus to annul the bargain. Three more years of fighting were required to restore
their wits. But, although Athens was financially exhausted by her military
efforts, the war had brought its compensations to her. The victory of Naxos,
the circumnavigation of the Peloponnesus and revival of her influence in
Western Greece, were achievements which indisputably proved that Athens was
once more a first-rate Hellenic power, the peer of Sparta; and this fact was
fully acknowledged in the Peace of Callias. But the true policy of Athens—from
which the raid of Sphodrias had forced her—was that
of a watchful spectator; and this policy she now resumes, though only for a
brief space, leaving Sparta and Thebes in the arena. As for Sparta, she had
lost as much as Athens had gained; the defeat of Naxos, the defeat of Tegyra, the failure at Corcyra, had dimmed her prestige.
After the King’s Peace, she had begun her second attempt to dominate Greece ;
her failure is confessed by the Peace of Callias. If a third attempt was to be
successful, it was obvious that it must begin by the subjugation of Thebes.
Sect. 5. Athens
under the Restored Democracy
When Pericles declared that Athens was the school of
Greece, this was rather his ideal of what she should be than a statement of a
reality. It would have surprised him to learn that, when imperial Athens fell
from her throne, his ideal would be fulfilled. This was what actually happened.
It was not until Athens lost her empire that she began to exert a great
decisive influence on Greek thought and civilisation.
This influence was partly exerted by the establishment of schools in the
strict sense—the literary school of Isocrates and the philosophical school of
Plato—which attracted to Athens men from all quarters of the Hellenic world.
But the increase in the intellectual influence of Athens was largely owing to
the fact that she was becoming herself more receptive of influence from
without. She was becoming Hellenic as well as Athenian; she was beginning to
become even something more than Hellenic. This tendency towards cosmopolitanism
had been promoted by philosophical speculation, which rises above national
distinctions; and it is manifested variously in the pan-Hellenism of Isocrates,
in the attitude of such different men as Plato and Xenophon towards Athens, in
the increasing number of foreign religious worships established at Athens or
Piraeus, in a general decline of local patriotism, and in many other ways.
There was perhaps no institution which had a wider influence in educating Greek
thought in the fourth century than the theatre; its importance in city life was recognised by practical statesmen. It was therefore a
matter of the utmost moment that the old Athenian comedy, turning mainly on
local politics, ceased to be written, and a new school of comic poets arose who
dealt with subjects of general human interest. Here Athens had a most effectual
instrument for spreading ideas. And the tragedies of the fourth century, though
as literature they were of less note and consequence than the comedies, were
not less significant of the spirit of the time. They were all dominated by the
influence of Euripides, the great teacher of rationalism, the daring critic of
all established institutions and beliefs. And the comic poets were also under
his spell.
It can easily be seen that the cultivation of these
wider sympathies was connected with the growth of what is commonly called
“individualism.” By this it is meant that the individual citizen no longer
looks at the outside world through the medium of his city, but regards it
directly, as it were, with his own eyes and in its bearings on him
individually. He is no longer content to express his religious feelings, simply
as one member of the state, in the common usages of the state religion, but
seeks to enter into an immediate personal relation with the supernatural world.
And since his own life has thus become for him something independent of the
city, his attitude to the city itself is transformed. The citizen of Athens has
become a citizen of the world. His duty to his country may conflict with his
duty to himself as a man; and thus patriotism ceases to be unconditionally the
highest virtue. Again, men begin to put to themselves, more or less explicitly,
the question, whether the state is not made for the individual and not the
individual for the state,— a complete reversal of the old unquestioning
submission to the authority of the social organism. It followed that greater
demands were made upon the state by the citizen for his own private welfare;
and that the citizen, feeling himself tied by no indissoluble bond to his
country, was readier than formerly to seek his fortune elsewhere. Thus we find,
in the single field of military service, Athenian officers acting independently
of their country, in the pay of foreign powers, whenever it suited them—Conon,
Xenophon, Iphicrates, Chabrias, and others.
A vivid exaggerated description of this spirit has
been drawn by Plato in one of his famous contributions to political science,
the Republic. “The horses and asses,”
he says, have a way of marching along
with all the rights and dignities of freemen; and they will run at anybody whom
they meet in the street if he does not leave the road clear for them: and all
things are just ready to burst with liberty.” When he describes the excessive
freedom of democracy, he is dealing with the growth of individualism, as a
result of freedom in its constitutional sense; but his argument that
individualism is the fatal fruit of a democratic constitution rests largely on
the double sense of the word “freedom.” The notable thing is that no man did
more to promote the tendencies which are here deplored by Plato than Plato
himself and his fellow philosophers. If any single man could be held
responsible for the inevitable growth of individualism, it would be perhaps
Euripides; but assuredly, next to Euripides, it would be Plato’s revered
master, Socrates, the son of Sophroniscus.
When the history of Greece was being directed by
Pericles and, Cleon, Nicias and Lysander, men little dreamed either at Athens
or elsewhere that the interests of the world were far more deeply concerned in
the doings of one eccentric Athenian who held aloof from public affairs. The
work of Pericles and Lysander affected a few generations in a small portion of
the globe; but the spirit of that eccentric Athenian was to lay an impress,
indelible for ever, upon the thought of mankind. The ideas which we owe to
Socrates are now so organically a part of the mind of civilised men, so familiar and commonplace, that it is hard to appreciate the
intellectual power which was required to originate them. Socrates was the first
champion of the supremacy of the intellect as a court from which there is no
appeal; he was the first to insist, without modification or compromise, that a
man must order his life by the guidance of his own intellect, without any
regard for mandates of external authority or for the impulses of emotion,
unless his intellect approves. Socrates was thus a rebel against authority as
such; and he shrank from no consequences. He did not hesitate to show his
companions that an old man has no title to respect because he is old, unless he
is also wise; or that an ignorant parent has no claim to obedience on the mere
account of the parental relation. Knowledge and veracity, the absolute
sovereignty of the understanding, regardless of consequences, regardless of all
prejudices connected with family or city—this was the ideal of Socrates,
consistently and uncompromisingly followed.
But men using their intellects often come to different
conclusions. The command issued by an authority which Socrates may reject has
been, directly or ultimately, the result of some mental process. It is manifest
that we require a standard of truth and an explanation of the causes of error.
The solution of Socrates is, briefly, this. When we make a judgment, we compare
two ideas ; and in order to do so correctly it is obvious that these ideas must
be clear and distinct; error arises from comparing ideas that are undefined and
vague. Definition was thus the essential point—and it was an essential
novelty—in the Socratic method for arriving at truth. Its necessity is a
commonplace now; and we have rather to guard against its dangers. The
application of this method to ethics was the chief occupation of Socrates, for
the interests of human life and its perplexities entirely absorbed him. In the
history of ethics his position is supreme; he was the founder of
utilitarianism. He arrived at the doctrine by analysing the notion of “good”; the result of his analysis was that “the good is the
useful.” Closely connected was the principle that virtue is happiness, and this
was the basis of the famous Socratic paradox that no man willingly does wrong,
but only through ignorance, for there is no man who would not will his own
happiness. It is easy to point out the errors of this startling statement; it
is perhaps easier to forget how much wrong-doing is due to the confused
thinking of clouded brains and the ignorance of untrained minds.
The man who had no respect for authority was not
likely to except the gods from the range of his criticism; and the popular
religion could not sustain examination. Socrates was as little orthodox as
Anaxagoras and other “impious” philosophers; but he made no new departure in
the field of theology. He doubtless believed in the existence of a God; but as
to the nature of the divine principle he was probably what we call an
“agnostic,” as he certainly was in regard to the immortality of the soul.
Socrates then was the originator of a new logical
method, the founder of utilitarianism, and, above all, the unsparing critic of
all things in heaven and earth—or rather on earth only, for he disdained things
in heaven as uninteresting and irrelevant,—a fearless critic, undeterred by any
feeling of piety or prejudice. He never wrote anything, he only conversed. But
he conversed with the ablest young men of the day who were destined afterwards
to become immortal themselves as thinkers; he communicated to them—to Plato, to
Aristippus, to Euclides—his own spirit of scepticism and criticism; he imbued them with intellectual courage and intellectual
freedom. He never preached, he only discussed; that was the Socratic
method—dialectic or the conversational method. He did not teach, for he
professed to have no knowledge; he would only confess that he was exceptional
in knowing that he knew nothing: this was the Socratic irony. He went about
showing that most popular notions, as soon as they are tested, prove to be inconsistent
and untenabl ; he wished to convince every man he met
that his convictions would not stand examination. We can easily conceive how
stimulating this was to the young men, and how extremely irritating to the old.
Haunting the market-places and the gymnasia Socrates was always ready to entrap
men of all ages and ranks into argument, and many a grudge was owed him by
reverend and conceited seniors, whose foggy minds he exposed to ridicule by
means of his prudent interrogations. Though no man ever taught more effectually
than Socrates, he was not a teacher, he had no course of lectures to give, and
therefore he took no fee. Herein lay his distinction from the sophists, to whom
by his speculation, his scepticism, his mastery of
argument, his influence over young men, he naturally belongs, and with whom he
was generally classed. He soon became a notorious figure in the streets of
Athens; nature had marked him out among other men by his grotesque satyr-like
face.
Though he was the child of democracy, born to a
heritage of freedom in a city where the right of free discussion was
unrestrained, the sacred name of democracy was not more sheltered than anything
else from the criticism of Socrates. He railed, for instance, at the system of
choosing magistrates by lot, one of the protections of democracy at Athens. He
was unpopular with the mass, for he was an enemy of shams and ignorance and
superstition. Honest democrats of the type of Thrasybulus and Anytus, who did
their duty but had no desire to probe its foundations, regarded him as a
dangerous freethinker who spent his life in diffusing ideas subversive of the
social order. They might point to the ablest of the young men who had kept
company with him, and say: “Behold the fruits of his conversation! Look at
Alcibiades, his favourite companion, who has done
more than any other man to ruin his country. Look at Critias,
who, next to Alcibiades, has wrought the deepest harm to Athens; who, brought
up in the Socratic circle, first wrote a book against democracy, then visited
Thessaly and stirred up the serfs against their masters, and finally, returning
here, inaugurated the reign of terror. Look, on the other hand, at Plato, an
able young man, whom the taste for idle speculation, infused by Socrates, has
seduced from the service of his country. Or look at Xenophon, who, instead of
serving Athens, has gone to serve her enemies. Truly Socrates and his
propaganda have done little good to the Athenian state.” However unjust any
particular instance might seem, it is easy to understand how considerations of
this kind would lead many practical unspeculative men to look upon Socrates and
his ways with little favour. And from their point of
view, they were perfectly right. His spirit, and the ideas that he made
current, were an insidious menace to the cohesion of the social fabric, in
which there was not a stone or a joint that he did not question. In other
words, he was the active apostle of individualism, which led in its further development
to the subversion of that local patriotism which had inspired the cities of
Greece in her days of greatness.
And this thinker, whose talk was shaking the Greek
world in its foundations, though none guessed it, was singled out by the
Delphic Priesthood for a distinguished mark of approbation. In the truest
oracle that was ever uttered from the Pythian tripod, it was declared that no
one in the world was wiser than Socrates. We know not at what period of the
philosopher’s career this answer was given, but, if it was seriously meant, it
showed a strange insight which we should hardly have looked for at the shrine
of Delphi. The Delphic priesthood were skilful enough
in adjusting their policy to the changing course of events; but they cannot be
suspected of brooding over the mysteries of things to come, or feeling the
deeper pulsations of the thoughts of men. The motive of the oracle concerning
the wisdom of Socrates is an unsolved problem. If it were an attempt to enlist
his support, in days when religion was threatened by such men as Anaxagoras, it
shows an unexpected perception of his importance, united with a by no means
surprising blindness to the significance of his work.
Socrates died five years after the fall of the
Athenian empire, and the manner of his death set a seal upon his life. Anytus,
the honest democratic politician who had been prominent in the restoration of
the democracy, came forward, with some others, as a champion of the state
religion, and accused Socrates of impiety. The accusation ran: “Socrates is
guilty of crime, because he does not believe in the gods recognised by the city, but introduces strange supernatural beings; he is also guilty,
because he corrupts the youth.” The penalty proposed was death; but the
accusers had no desire to inflict it; they expected that, when the charge was
lodged in the archon’s office, Socrates would leave Attica, and no one would
have hindered him from doing so. But Socrates was full of days—he had reached
the age of seventy—and life spent otherwise than in conversing in the streets
of Athens would have been worthless to him. He surprised the city by remaining
to answer the charge. The trial was heard in a court of 501 judges, the
king-archon presiding, and the old philosopher was found guilty by a majority
of sixty. It was a small majority, considering that the general truth of the
accusation was undeniable. According to the practice of Athenian law, it was
open to a defendant when he was condemned to propose a lighter punishment than
that fixed by the accuser, and the judges were required to choose one of the
two sentences. Socrates might have saved his life if he had proposed an
adequate penalty, but he offered only a small fine, and was consequently
condemned, by a much larger majority, to death. He drank the cup of doom a
month later, discoursing with his disciples as eagerly as ever till his last
hour.
The actual reply of Socrates at his trial has not been
preserved, but we know its tone and spirit and much of its tenor. For it
supplied his companion Plato, who was
present, with the material of a work which stands absolutely alone in
literature. In the Apology of Socrates,
Plato has succeeded in catching the personality of the master and conveying its
stimulus to his readers. There can be no question that this work reproduces the
general outline of the actual defence, which is here
wrought into an artistic form. And we see how utterly impossible it was for
Socrates to answer the accusation. He enters into an explanation of his life
and motives, and has no difficulty in showing that many things popularly
alleged against him are false. But with the actual charge of holding and
diffusing Socrates heterodox views he deals briefly and unsatisfactorily. He
was not condemned unjustly—according to the law. And that is the intensity of
the tragedy. There have been no better men than Socrates; and yet his accusers
were perfectly right. It is not clear why their manifesto for orthodoxy was
made at that particular time; but it is probable that twenty years later such
an action would have been a failure. Perhaps the facts of the trial justify us
in the rough conclusion that two out of every five Athenian citizens then were
religiously indifferent. In any case the event had a wider than a merely
religious significance. The execution of Socrates was the protest of the spirit
of the old order against the growth of individualism.
Seldom in the course of history have violent blows of
this kind failed to recoil upon the striker and serve the cause they were meant
to harm. Socrates was remembered at Athens with pride and regret. His spirit
began to exercise an influence which the tragedy of his death enhanced. His
companions never forgave the democracy for putting their master to death; he
lived and grew in the study of their imaginations; and they spent their lives
in carrying on his work.
They carried forward his work, but they knew not what
they were doing. They had no suspicion that in pursuing those speculations to
which they were stimulated by the Socratic method they were sapping the roots
of Greek city life as it was known to the men who fought at Marathon. Plato was
a true child of Socrates, and yet he was vehement in condemning that
individualism which it had been the lifework of Socrates to foster. Few sights
are stranger than Plato and Xenophon turning their eyes away from their own
free country to regard with admiration the constitution of Sparta, where their
beloved master would not have been suffered so much as to open his mouth. It
was a triumph indeed for the Lacedaemonians when their constitution, which the
Athenians of the age of Pericles regarded as old-fashioned machinery, was
selected by the greatest thinker of Athens as the nearest existing approach to
the ideal. Indeed the Spartan organisation, at the
very time when Sparta was making herself detested throughout Greece, seems to
have attracted general admiration from political thinkers. It attracted them
because the old order survived there,—the citizen absolutely submissive to the
authority of the state, and not looking beyond it. Elsewhere they were troubled
by the problem of reconciling the authority of the state with the liberty of
the individual citizen; at Sparta there was no such trouble, for the state was
absolute. Accordingly they saw in Sparta the image of what a state should be;
just because it was relatively free from that individualism which they were
themselves actively promoting by their speculations in political philosophy.
How freely such speculations ranged at this time is illustrated by the fact
that the fundamental institution of ancient society, slavery, was called in
question. It had indeed been called in question by Euripides, and the heterodox
“modern” views of Euripides were coming into fashion. One thinker expounded the
doctrine that slavery was unnatural. Speculation even went so far as to stir the
question of the political subjection of women. The Parliament of Women, a comedy of Aristophanes, ridicules
women’s rights; and in Plato’s ideal Republic women are on a political equality with men. Socialistic theories were also
rife, and were a mark for the mockery of Aristophanes in the same play. Plato
seized upon the notion of communism and made it one of the principles of his
ideal state. But his object was not that of the ordinary “collectivist,” to
promote the material well-being of all; but rather to make his citizens better,
by defending them against poverty and ambition. Before he died, Plato had come
to the conviction that communism was impracticable, and in the state which he
adumbrated in his old age he recognised private
property—though he vested the ownership not in the individual but in the
family.
In this period—during the fifty years after the battle
of Aegospotami—the art of writing prose was brought to perfection at Athens;
and this is closely connected with the characteristic tendency which has
engaged our attention. While Socrates and others had been bringing about a
revolution in thought, the Sicilian Gorgias and other professors of rhetoric or
style had been preparing an efficient vehicle for diffusing ideas. Prose is the
natural instrument of criticism and argument; it is a necessary weapon for
intellectual persuasion; and therefore the fourth century is an age of prose.
The circumstance that the great Athenian poets of the fifth century had no
successors in the fourth does not prove any decline in brains or in
imagination. If Plato had been born half a century earlier he would have been a
rival of Aeschylus and Sophocles. If Aeschylus and Sophocles had been born two
or three generations later they would have expressed their, genius in prose.
Euripides, who has come under the influence of the critical spirit, seems
sometimes like a man belated; he uses the old vehicle to convey thoughts for
which it was hardly suited. It must always be remembered that the great
dramatic poems of the fifth century bore an inalienable religious character;
and, as soon as the day came when the men of the highest literary faculty were
no longer in touch with the received religion, drama of the old kind ceased to
be written. That is why the fourth century is an age of prose; tragic poetry
owes its death to Euripides and the Socratic spirit. The eager individualism of
the age found its natural expression in prose, whose rhythmical periods
demanded almost as much care and art as poetry; and the plastic nature of the
Greek language rendered it a most facile instrument for the purposes of free
thought and criticism.
Thus Athens became really a school for Greece, as soon
as that individualism prevailed which Pericles had unwittingly foreshadowed in
the very same breath: “I say that Athens is the school of Hellas, and that the
individual Athenian in his own person seems to have the power of adapting
himself to the most varied forms of action with the utmost versatility and
grace.”[
It must never be forgotten that it is to the
democratic Athenian law-courts that the perfecting of Attic prose was mainly
due. This institution had, as we saw, called into being a class of professional
speech-writers. But there were many who were not content with learning off, and
reciting in court, speeches which a speech-writer like Lysias wrote for them,
but wished to learn themselves the art of speaking. For those who aspired to
make their mark in debates in the Assembly, this was a necessity. The most illustrious
instructor in oratory at this period was Isocrates. But the school of Isocrates
had a far wider scope and higher aim than to teach the construction of
sentences or the arrangement of topics in a speech. It was a general school of
culture, a discipline intended to fit for public life. Questions of political
science were studied, and Isocrates likes to describe his course of studies as
“philosophy.” But it was to Plato’s school in the Academy that the youths of
the day went to study “philosophy” in the stricter sense. The discipline of
these two rival schools—for there was rivalry between them, though their aims
were different—was what corresponded at Athens to our university education.
And the pupils of Isocrates, as well as those of Plato, had to work hard. For
thoroughness of method was one of the distinctive characteristics of Isocrates.
His school attained a panHellenic reputation; pupils
came to him from all quarters of the world. “Our city,” he says, “is regarded
as the established teacher of all who speak or teach others to speak. And
naturally so, since men see that our city offers the greatest prizes to those
who possess this faculty—provides the most numerous and various schools for
those who having resolved to enter the real contests desire a preparatory
discipline—and further affords to all men that experience which is the main
secret of success in speaking.” The tone of the teaching of Isocrates harmonised with the national position which he held. He
took a large view of all things; there was nothing narrow or local in his
opinions. And not less important than the width of his horizon was the high
moral tone in which his thoughts were consistently pitched. Isocrates
discharged not only the duties which are in modem times discharged by
university teachers, but also the functions of a journalist of the best kind.
Naturally nervous and endowed with a poor voice, he did not speak in the
Assembly, but when any great question moved him he would issue a pamphlet, in
the form of a speech, for the purpose of influencing public opinion. We may
suspect that the Athenians appreciated these publications more for their
inimitable excellence of style than for their political wisdom.
A highly remarkable passage of Isocrates expresses and
applauds the wide-minded cosmopolitanism which was beginning to prevail in
Greece. He says that “Athens has so distanced the rest of the world in power of
thought and speech that her disciples have become the teachers of all other
men. She has brought it to pass that the name of Greek should be thought no
longer a matter of race but a matter of intelligence ; and should be given to
the participators in our culture rather than to the sharers of our common
origin.” Thirty or forty years earlier, no one perhaps, except Euripides, would
have been bold enough to speak like that. But Isocrates did not see that this
enlightenment which he admires was closely connected with the decay of public
spirit which he elsewhere deplores. It is curious to find the man who approves
of citizenship of the world looking back with regret to the days of Solon and
proposing to revive the old powers of censorship which the court of the
Areopagus possessed over the lives of Athenian citizens.
The form and features of an age are wont to be
mirrored in its art; and one effective means of winning a concrete notion of
the spirit of the fourth century is to study the works of Praxiteles and
compare them with the sculptures which issued from the workshop of Phidias.
Just as the citizen was beginning to assert his own individuality as more than
a mere item in the state, so the plastic artist was emancipating his art from
its intimate connexion with the temples of the gods,
and its subordination to architecture. For in the fifth century, apart from a
few colossal statues like those which Phidias wrought for Athens and Olympia,
the finest works of the sculptor's chisel were to decorate frieze or pediment.
In the fourth century the architect indeed still required the sculptor’s
service; Scopas, for instance, was called upon in his youth to decorate the
temple of Athena Aiea at Tegea, in his later years to make a frieze for the
tomb of a Carian prince; but, in general, the sculptor developed his art more
independently of architecture, and all the great works of Praxiteles were
complete in themselves and independent. And, as sculpture was emancipating
itself from the old subordination to architecture, so it also emancipated
itself from the religious ideal. In the age of Phidias, the artist who
fashioned a god sought to express in human shape the majesty and immutability
of a divine being; and this ideal had been perfectly achieved. In the fourth
century the deities lose their majesty and changelessness; they are conceived
as physically perfect men and women, with human feelings though without human
sorrows; they are invested with human personalities. The contrast may be seen
by looking at the group of gods in the frieze of the Parthenon, and then at
some of the works of Praxiteles: the Hermes, which was set up in the temple of
Hera at Olympia, and is preserved there the Aphrodite of Cnidus—a woman shrinking from revealing her beauty as
she enters the bath; or the Satyr, with the shape of a man and the mind of a beast.
Thus sculpture is marked by “individualism” in a double sense. Each artist is
freer to work out an individual path of his own; and the tendency of all
artists is to pourtray the individual man or woman
rather than the type, and even the individual phase of emotion rather than the
character.
The general spirit of the Athenians in their political
life corresponds to this change. Men came more and more to regard the state as
a means for administering to the needs of the individual. We might almost say
that they conceived it as a co-operative society for making profits to be
divided among the members; this at least was the tendency of public opinion.
They were consequently more disinclined to enter upon foreign undertakings
which were not either necessary for the protection and promotion of their commerce
or likely to fill their purses. The fourth century was therefore for Athens an
age of less ambition and glory, but of greater happiness and freedom, than the
fifth.
The decisive circumstance for Athens was that, while
she lost her empire, she did not lose her commerce. This was a cruel blow to
Corinth, since it was to destroy Athenian trade that Corinth had brought about
the war. The fact shows on how firm foundations Athenian commerce rested. The
only rival Athens had to fear was Rhodes, which was becoming a centre of traffic in the south-eastern Mediterranean, but
was not destined to interfere seriously with Athenian trade for a long time
yet. The population of Attica had declined; plague and war reduced the number
of adult male citizens from at least 35,000 to 21,000. But that was not
unfortunate, for there were no longer outsettlements to receive the surplus of the population; and even with the diminished numbers
there was a surplus which sought employment in foreign mercenary service. The
mercantile development of Athens is shown by the increase of the Piraeus at the
expense of the city, in which many plots of ground now became deserted, and by
the growth of private banks. It had long been a practice to deposit money in
temples, and the priesthoods used to lend money on interest. This suggested to
money-changers the idea of doing likewise; and Pasion founded a famous house at
Athens, which operated with a capital of fifty talents, and had credit at all
Greek centres of commerce. Thus business could be
transacted by exchanging letters of credit instead of paying in coin; and the
introduction of this system, even on such a small scale, shows the growth of
mercantile activity. Money was now much more plentiful, and prices far higher,
than before. This was due to the large amount of the precious metals, chiefly
gold, which had been brought into circulation in the Greek world in the last
quarter of the fifth century. The continuous war led to the coining of the
treasures which had been accumulating for many years in temples ; and the
banking system circulated the money which would otherwise have been hoarded in
private houses. But, although the precious metals became plentiful, the rate of
interest did not fall; men could still get 12 per cent for a loan of their
money. This fact is highly significant; it shows clearly that industries were
more thriving and trade more active, and consequently capital in greater
demand. The high rate of interest must always be remembered when we read of a
Greek described as wealthy with a capital which would nowadays seem small. Thus
a fortune of 50 talents, little more than 10,000 English pounds, would yield an
income of nearly £1500; and that sum had an enormously greater purchasing power
than the equivalent weight of gold today. Such incomes were extremely rare.
Communistic ideas were a consequence, perhaps
inevitable, of the growth of individualism and the growth of capital. The
poorer burghers became more and more acutely alive to the inconsistency between
the political equality of all citizens and the social and economical advantages
enjoyed by the rich. Political equality seemed to point to social equality as
its logical sequel; in fact, full and equal political equality could not be
secured without social equality also, since the advantages of wealth necessarily
involve superiorities in political influence. Thus, just as in modern Europe,
so in ancient Greece, capital and democracy produced socialists, who pleaded
for a levelling of classes by means of a distribution of property by the state.
Aristophanes mocked these speculations in his Parliament of Women and his Wealth.
The idea of communism which Plato develops on lines of his own in the Republic was not an original notion of
the philosopher’s brain, but was suggested by the current communistic theories
of the day. It is well worthy of consideration that the Athenians did not take
the step from political to social democracy; and this discretion may have been
partly due to the policy of those statesmen who, doubtless conscious of the
danger, regarded the theoric fund as an indispensable
institution.
The changed attitude of the individual to the state is
shown by the introduction of a fixed remuneration of half a drachma to Athenian
citizens for attending the meetings of the Assembly; and the rise in prices is
illustrated by the subsequent increase of this remuneration. For the regular
sessions, in which the proceedings were unattractive, the pay was raised to a
drachma and a half; for the other meetings, which were more exciting, it was
fixed at a drachma. The remuneration for serving in the law-courts was not
increased; it was found that half a drachma was sufficient to draw applicants
for the judge’s ticket. Payment for the discharge of political duties was part
of the necessary machinery of the democracy, but the distribution of
“spectacle-money” to the poor citizens was a luxury which involved an entirely
different principle. It is uncertain when the practice of giving the price of
his theatre ticket to the poor Athenian was first introduced; it has been
attributed to Pericles, but it is possible that it was not introduced till
Athens began to recover after the fall of her empire. In any case, the
principle became established in the fourth century of distributing “theoric ” moneys, which were supposed to be spent on
religious festivals; the citizens came to look forward to frequent and large
distributions; the surplus revenue of the state, instead of being saved for
emergencies, was placed in the theoric fund; and this theoric fund became so important that it ultimately
required a special minister of finance to manage it. Those statesmen under
whose guidance the theoric doles were most liberal
had naturally the greatest influence with the mass of the citizens; and
consequently finance acquired a new importance, and financial ability was
developed in a very high degree. The state thus assumed the character of a
commercial society; dividends were a political necessity, and in order to meet
it heavier taxation was demanded. We have seen how, when war broke with Sparta,
in the year in which the Second Athenian Confederacy was formed, a property-tax
was imposed, and the properties of the citizens were assessed anew for this
purpose.
Thus the state provided for the comfort of its poorer
burghers at the expense of their wealthier fellows. It is, as it were, publicly recognised as a principle of political science that
the end of the state is the comfort and pleasure of its individual members; and
everything has to be made subordinate to this principle which is outwardly
embodied in the theoric fund. This principle affected
the foreign policy of Athens, as we have already observed. When she took the
step of sending outsettlers to Samos and elsewhere,
in defiance of the public opinion of Greece, her chief motive was doubtless
pecuniary profit.
Constitutionally, the restored Athenian democracy was
a remarkable success. The difficulties which the democratic statesmen
encountered after the overthrow of the Thirty had been treated with a wisdom
and moderation which are in striking contrast with the violence and
vengefulness shown in other Greek states at similar crises. Most democratic men
of means had been robbed of property under the tyranny of the oligarchs, and
the property had been sold. Were the purchasers to be compelled to restore it
without compensation? Were all the acts of the Thirty to be declared illegal?
Such a measure would have created a bitter and discontented party in the state.
Some of the chief democratic leaders voluntarily resigned all claim to
compensation for the property they had lost, and this example promoted a
general inclination on both sides to concession and compromise. The wisdom and
tact displayed in this matter were not the least of the services which
Thrasybulus and his fellows conferred on their country. No oligarchical
conspiracy endangered the domestic peace of Athens again; no citizen, if it
were not a philosophical speculator, called the democracy in question.
At this epoch the laws were revised, and the register
of burghers was revised, but the constitution was left practically unaltered. A
change, indeed, was made in the presidency of the Assembly, which had hitherto
belonged to the prytaneis or board of Ten, selected every seven days from the presiding tribe in the
Council. The close organic relation between the Council and Assembly rendered
it needful that members of the Council should preside in the Assembly; but
the presidency of the Assembly was now divorced from the presidency of the
Council and invested in a body of nine, selected one from each of the nine
tribes which were not presiding. This change was proobviously designed to form a check on the administration. The presiding tribe in the
Council could no longer deal directly with the Assembly, but was obliged to
present its measures to the people through an intermediate body, which belonged
indeed to the Council but not to its own part of the Council. The year in which
these reforms were probably made witnessed also the introduction of a new
alphabet as the official script of the state. The old Attic alphabet, with its
hard-worked vowels doing duty for more than one sound, was discontinued; and
henceforward the stones which record the public acts archonship of the Athenian
people are inscribed in the Ionic alphabet, with separate signs for the long
and short e and o, and distinct symbols for the double consonants.
It is plain that Athens needed, at this period, not
men of genius or enthusiasm, but simply men of ability, for the conduct of her
affairs. She had no great aims to achieve, no grave dangers to escape, which
demanded a Pericles or a Themistocles; a man of genius would have found no
scope in the politics of Athens for two generations after the fall of her
empire. Men of great ability she had, men who were thoroughly adequate to the
comparatively unambitious rôle which she had wisely
imposed upon herself—Agyrrhius, Callistratus, and
afterwards Eubulus. To us they are all shadowy figures. Agyrrhius inaugurated the profit-system which afterwards resulted in the institution of
the theoric fund; and it was he who opposed and
discredited the extreme anti-Spartan policy of the heroes of Phyle. His nephew
Callistratus enjoyed a longer career and played a greater part in the affairs
of Greece, conspicuous as the founder of the Second Confederacy, as the
negotiator of the Peace of Callias, and then as the opponent of Epaminondas.
His policy throughout was consistent and reasonable. He aimed at rendering
Athens powerful enough to be independent of Sparta; he desired that Sparta and
Athens should stand side by side as the two leading states in Greece; and he recognised that the neighbourhood of Attica to Boeotia necessarily laid upon Athens the policy of opposing the aggrandisement of Thebes.
Agyrrhius and Callistratus might once and again fill the office of strategos ;
but, like Cleon and Hyperbolus, they exercised their influence as recognised—practically, official—advisers of the Assembly
The art of war became every year more and more an art, and little could be
accomplished except by generals who devoted their life to the military
profession. Such were Timotheus, the hero of Leucas; Chabrias,
the victor of Naxos; and above all Iphicrates, whom we have met in so many
places and in so many guises. Timotheus was a rich man his father Conon had left him a fortune, and
he could afford to serve his country and his country only. But Chabrias and Iphicrates enriched themselves by taking
temporary service under foreign masters; Iphicrates even went so far as to
Support the Thracian king, whose daughter he had wedded, against Athens. All
these military men preferred to dwell elsewhere than at Athens. Abroad they
could live in luxury and ostentation; while at Athens men lived simply and
moderately, and public opinion was unfavourable to
sumptuous establishments. The attitude of the generals to the city became much
more independent when the citizens themselves ceased to serve abroad regularly,
and hired mercenaries instead. The hiring of the troops and their organisation devolved upon the general, and he was often
expected to provide the means for paying them too. Here we touch on a vice in
the constitutional machine, which was the cause of frequent failures in the
foreign enterprises of Athens during this period. No systematic provision was
made that, when the people voted that a certain thing should be done, the
adequate moneys at the same time should be voted. Any one might propose a
decree, without responsibility for its execution; and at the next meeting of
the Assembly the people might refuse to allow the necessary supplies, or no one
might be ready to move the grant. In the same way, supplies might be cut off in
the middle of a campaign. This defect had not made itself seriously felt in the
fifth century, when the leading generals were always statesmen too, with
influence in the Assembly; but it became serious when the generals were
professional soldiers whom the statesmen employed. During the ten years after
the Peace of Callias, Athens was actively engaged in a multitude of enterprises
of foreign aggrandisement; but she achieved little,
and the reason is that her armaments were hardly ever adequate. The
difficulties of her financiers, who had always to keep a theoric reserve, must be taken into consideration.
CHAPTER XIV.
THE HEGEMONY OF THEBES
|