READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
ATHENS . 478—401 B.C.
CHAPTER XIII THE AGE OF ILLUMINATION I
THE
REACTION AGAINST THE IONIAN PHILOSOPHY
THE speculations
of the Ionian philosophers, their attempts to make the world intelligible, had
begun early in the sixth century, and by the end of the century had produced an
intellectual movement which was spreading to nearly all parts of civilized
Greece. We may call the period from about 530 to 400 b.c. Greece’s Age of Illumination,
an age in which reason was striving to assert her rule in every sphere, and
many superstitions, inherited from antiquity, were being challenged and
discarded. In this process of enlightenment two phases can be distinguished,
and the dividing line may be drawn roughly about 450 b.c. About that time we become
aware that a certain reaction has set in against Ionian philosophy and Ionian
science. Some thinkers were still working on the old lines, like Anaxagoras,
and it was probably just at this time that the brilliant theory of atoms was
being elaborated in the brain of Leucippus. But in the latter part of the fifth
century the men of intellectual activity most prominent in the eyes of the
public were not a Leucippus or a Diogenes of Apollonia but men who were most
interested in other problems and who played a different kind of role. It was
the age of the Sophists. The results of science were coming into contact with
life. Hellas had passed into an age of sophistication.
There was, as has been
observed above, a certain reaction against the earlier schools of philosophical
speculation, and this reaction was probably due to Zeno of Elea more than to
any other man. His penetrating and lively criticism of the conceptions of
space, time, and motion which are fundamental in physics led to a scepticism which distrusted both cosmology and ontology,
and the influence of Zeno was very wide. He influenced the intellectual
activities of Protagoras, of Gorgias, and of Socrates, and the most impatient
problem of philosophy was no longer, How was the world made? but how is
knowledge of the world possible? Inquiry began to turn from the macrocosm to
the microcosm; and concurrently problems of social conduct began to be
recognized as problems on which there is as much room for argument and as
little reason for dogmatism as in physical matters. It might be put that man
was becoming self-conscious. Awareness of man’s importance is the note of the
beautiful ode of Sophocles which begins, ‘Miracles in the world are many; there
is no greater miracle than man.’
In considering the Hellenic
culture of the fifth century, the extent of geographical knowledge must not be
overlooked. Although at this stage the ideas of the Greeks as to the size and
outlines of the inhabited world were slight and deficient compared with what
they would be two centuries later, they had in the last few generations made
great advances. Delphi was no longer the centre of
the world; Phasis and the straits of Gades were no
longer its extreme limits. The Milesian geographers had learned much about
western Asia, and something was known of north-western Europe through the
merchants of Massilia and the information they
derived from the sailors of Tartessus. Pythagoreans had announced the discovery
that the earth is round. Athens may be said to have taken the place of Miletus,
but she did not carry on the Milesian tradition so far as the progress of
geography is concerned. Geographical knowledge almost stood still till the end
of the fourth century; the Ionian maps continued to be used. This pause was
part of the reaction against Ionian speculation; we can see it in Herodotus who
is always bent on criticizing the geographical views of Hecataeus.
II.
THE SOPHISTS
The researches of
scientific men in Ionia and in Magna Graecia had enlarged the range of
knowledge and the number of subjects of which any one aspiring to be a man of
culture must have some knowledge, and thus a demand arose for higher
education—for instruction in astronomy, geography, mathematics, physics,
history. This demand was met by the Sophists who were simply itinerant
professors; collectively they performed the functions of a university in
Greece. They were polymaths; the Sophist engaged to give a complete training to
a pupil, to impart instruction in every possible subject and prepare him for a
good life, and for all the duties devolving on a citizen. As to the cost of
such an education we have not much evidence. Some of the Sophists had fixed
charges. Those who had a big reputation like Protagoras could charge high fees
and were probably employed only by people of some wealth. The fee of Evenus of Paros was 5 minae; that
of Protagoras is said to have been 100 minae.
Protagoras said himself that it was his habit, in case a pupil demurred to pay
what he asked for, to request him to go into a temple and declare what he
considered the teaching worth, and that he then accepted the sum named. He was
said to have made more money than the artist Pheidias.
With the growth of
democracies in so many cities, ability to speak in public and persuade your
audience, whether in a court of law or in meetings of the Assembly or the
Council or of a political club, was every year becoming more necessary for the
man who wished to take part in public life, and desirable as a weapon of self-defence even for those who had no such ambitions. Instruction
in the art of public speaking—rhetoric—involving not only diction arid
elocution but also the arrangement of the topics and arguments was much sought,
and the art itself was carefully elaborated by its exponents. The greatest of
these was the Sicilian Gorgias, who was one of the two most eminent Sophists of
the fifth century. He made prose a fine art and this is his great title to be
remembered by posterity. In his hands an oration became as technical a
composition as a dithyramb. But while he was first of all a stylist and his
true métier was the teaching of rhetoric, Gorgias, like all these
eminent teachers, had studied deeply the knowledge and philosophy of the day.
He had imbibed the scepticism and learned the method
of Zeno and he wrote a metaphysical book defending three theses which to the
ordinary man were quite incomprehensible and must have sounded appalling: Being
does not exist; if it did exist, it would be unknowable; if it were knowable,
the knowledge of it could not be communicated by one mind to another.
The oldest and perhaps the
most eminent and typical of the Sophists was Protagoras of Abdera. He has a
distinct and considerable place in the history of philosophy through having
propounded the doctrine which may be called, in modern jargon, the subjectivity
of knowledge and which he expressed in the formula ‘Man is the measure of all
things; of the being of things that are and of the non-being of things that are
not.’ The meaning of this pronouncement has indeed been disputed, but the most
probable interpretation is that what appears to you to be true, is true for
you, and what appears to me to be true, is true for me; there is no objective
standard to which anyone can appeal. It seems not improbable that Protagoras
may have drawn the conclusion that for practical purposes what seems true to
the majority of minds is true. We do not know how he worked it out. But one
important corollary was deduced. On every and any matter two opposite
statements can be made and maintained, which may be distinguished as the
stronger and the weaker, the stronger being that which is more commonly accepted,
and generally taken for granted as true. But the weaker can always be
strengthened by an able exponent. One of the things which can be learned and
which an expert Sophist can teach is the art of strengthening the weaker
statement—an art indispensable for success in public debates and in litigation—
that dangerous art which is now called sophistry and which in the hands of a
virtuoso can often secure the victory of injustice. This theory of the two
statements was held up to ridicule in a scene of his Clouds by
Aristophanes, where they appear on the stage personified as the Just and the Unjust
Statement.
In ethics and politics,
Protagoras does not appear to have taught or promoted any revolutionary
doctrines but to have been content with explaining the value of conventional
morality and the generally accepted views of political virtue. It is probable
that in religion too he was conventional, so far as practice was concerned, and
believed in the ethics of conformity, although speculatively he was a sceptic.
He wrote a book On the Gods, of which one sentence is preserved:
‘Concerning the gods I am unable to say whether they exist or not, nor, if they
do, what they are like; there are many things which hinder us from knowing;
there is the obscurity of the subject and the shortness of human life’. Such a
statement, taken out of its context, was sure to be interpreted by the public
as a shameless declaration of atheism; and the story was that he was prosecuted
and condemned; whereas it may be compatible with a quite orthodox view if
Protagoras admitted, as he probably did, that where there is no possibility of
knowledge, one opinion may be more probable than another.
As the Sophists professed
to train aspirants to a political career, they were considered experts in
political science, and it is not surprising to find that Protagoras was chosen
by Pericles to draw up a constitution for the colony which was founded at Thurii under Athenian auspices.
Athens was now becoming
the intellectual capital of Greece, the place where ideas were exchanged and
Hellenic public opinion created, drawing from the periphery savants and
thinkers of all kinds and appreciating them. It is significant that she became
the chief centre of the book trade in Greece.
This position of his city as a centre and example of
culture was what Pericles aimed at. Most of the Sophists of the fifth century
are known chiefly in connection with Athens.
It has been said by a
learned modern critic that the Sophists were ‘half-professors,
half-journalists.’ It is difficult, however, to see the aptitude of the
comparison with journalists. It is probable that most of them were publicists;
that was a useful and natural form of self-advertisement, but there is nothing
to show that even the less reputable were newsmongers or political
propagandists. Another Sophist who enjoyed a high reputation at Athens, though
his talents were more commonplace than those of Protagoras and Gorgias, was Prodicus of the island of Ceos.
He was a man of delicate health and a pessimist who maintained that the bad
things in men’s lives are more numerous than the good. He specialized in the
study of diction and wrote a treatise on synonyms; but that he taught cosmology
at Athens and some theory of the origin of the world is evident from a play of
Aristophanes whose Birds, when they propound a fanciful version of the genesis
of the world, urge the audience to bid Prodicus pack
with his preaching.
All the Sophists were
versatile and could teach almost any subject but perhaps the most versatile of
all was the fourth of the great Sophists of pan-Hellenic fame, Hippias of Elis. It was on his versatility that he particularly prided
himself, and he certainly excelled in the variety of his accomplishments. He
was proud to be self-sufficing; he could make all his own clothes. He kept
abreast of mathematical research, worked at the classical problems of finding
geometrical constructions to trisect an angle, and to ‘square the circle and discovered a new curve, the ‘quadratrix,’ with the help of which they might
be solved. He worked also at antiquarian studies, and compiled a chronological
list of victors in the Olympic games, with the help of the inscriptions on
their statues in the Altis, and so laid the
foundations for the later Greek system of dating by Olympiads which was first
introduced by the historian Timaeus. Two other names among the prominent
Sophists may be mentioned, Antiphon of Athens (not to be confounded with the
orator and politician) and Thrasymachus of Chalcedon.
The considerable demand
for the education which such teachers could give shows how enlightenment was
spreading in Greece, and nowhere perhaps are the rationalistic tendencies of
the time more strikingly shown than in the rise of the new medical school of
Cos, inaugurated by Hippocrates, who was born probably about 460 b.c. and had
been profoundly affected by the scientific speculations of the preceding
generation. His treatise on ‘Airs, Waters, and Places,’ dealing with the
effects of climate and locality on the human organism, shows a wide
philosophical view reaching beyond the ordinary outlook of a medical
practitioner. He and his school emancipated themselves from old superstitions,
and a religious man of the stamp, say, of Nicias, would have been quite
justified in calling them godless. They did not believe that particular
diseases were divine visitations. Epilepsy had always been regarded as sent
direct from heaven; its name in Greek was ‘the sacred malady’. The following
comments on this belief indicate the spirit of the new school, and are probably
due to the master himself.
‘With regard to the
so-called “sacred disease” it appears to me to be in no respect more divine or
sacred than other diseases, but to have a natural origin like other complaints.
Men regard its nature and cause as divine, from ignorance and wonder because it
is not like other diseases; and its divine character is maintained because men
find it difficult to understand and easy to cure, since the means used for
curing it are purifications and incantations. But if it is considered divine
because it is wonderful, then sacred maladies will be numerous, not merely one.
For I will show that there are other maladies just as wonderful and amazing
which no one considers sacred. Quotidian, tertian and quartan fevers appear to
be as sacred and as much sent by a god as this disease, even if they be not
wonderful. They who first consecrated this disease appear to me to have been
men of the same kind as the magicians and purifiers and mountebanks and impostors
of the present day who pretend to be extremely religious and to have greater
knowledge than others. They use the divinity as a cloak and screen to cover
their own inability to benefit the patient, and to hide their ignorance, and
consider this affection “sacred”.’
The revolution in medicine
by the adoption of the principle that diseases are always due to natural causes
only is one of the most impressive signs of the growth of the rationalistic
temper. The same spirit manifested itself in the criticism of legendary
traditions. The first drastic critic of Hellenic mythology had been Xenophanes,
but a tendency to deal more or less freely with myth and not to believe all
that is handed down had appeared in Stesichorus and
appears in Pindar, neither of whom had heterodox inclinations. The kind of
speculation which would finally be systematized by Euhemerus had already begun; a well-known example is ‘the story of Heracles’ by Herodorus who, living towards the end of the fifth century,
attempted to produce a biography of the hero that should be humanly credible by
explaining away incidents that were plainly miraculous. But this sophisticated
temper is most clearly and fully shown by the historians, Herodotus who rebels
against accepting things that are miraculous or incredible and tentatively
explains them away, and Thucydides who silently and magisterially ignores them.
III.
BLASPHEMY TRIALS AT ATHENS
In such an age disturbance
was naturally caused in many Hellenic cities to old beliefs and prejudices,
outraged and endangered by new, subversive ideas. Of this conflict it is at
Athens that we can particularly find traces. At Athens during the second third
of the century, the leading statesman’s personal interest in philosophical
questions, his belief in expert knowledge, his freedom from prejudice must have
helped sensibly towards the realization of his great aim to make this city the centre of Hellenic enlightenment, and his political
opponents found it easy to excite ill-will against him on account of his
eccentric intellectual proclivities. Two of his intimate friends were Anaxagoras
the physicist and Damonides, the expert in music, and
it was believed that both of them advised him on political matters. It can be
imagined with what resentment an Aristides or a Cimon would have spoken of
‘those damned professors’ being consulted or allowed to interfere in politics.
Both these friends of Pericles suffered. Damonides was ostracized.
It seems to have been
early in the political career of Pericles that Anaxagoras was
prosecuted for irreligion, and his accusers went to some trouble in the matter.
We do not know what particular offences were comprised under the name asebeia, ‘irreligion’ or ‘impiety,’ by the laws of
Solon, but as the law stood, Anaxagoras had done nothing to expose him to the
charge, for in order to make him liable to prosecution it was found necessary
to pass a special decree through the Assembly, which had the effect of widening
the definition of ‘impiety’. This decree was introduced by one Diopeithes and it authorized the impeachment of persons who
do not conform to the religious observances of the city, or who teach doctrines
concerning things in the sky. The general public in Athens doubtless regarded
the doctrines of Anaxagoras, who denied that the sun and the moon are divine
beings, as extremely irreligious, just as today many people in the United
States of America consider Darwinism irreligious and would like to suppress as
illegal the teaching of Evolution. But Anaxagoras would probably have been suffered
to live and speculate in peace if it had not been for his friendship with
Pericles. It is to be noted that the charge of irreligion was reinforced by a
charge that he had intrigued with Persia. The impeachment of the philosopher
has always been accounted for as an attempt of political opponents to discredit
that statesman. Anaxagoras was condemned to death presumably, and all Pericles
could do was to aid him to escape from Athens, lie withdrew to Lampsacus where he was welcomed and there spent the rest of
his life. It is worthy of notice that in this enlightened age, the study of
astronomy was forbidden for nearly half a century (up to the archonship of Eucleides in 403 b.c.) in
the city which was the centre of Greek culture.
During the latter part of
the fifth century there were some other impeachments for irreligion at Athens,
and of these we know even less. There was the case of Aspasia; we are not told
of what particular blasphemous acts or words she was accused, but the charge of
impiety was reinforced by a charge of a totally different kind. Then there was
a certain Diagoras of Melos (said to have been a
dithyrambic poet), who was prosecuted apparently for making disrespectful and
blasphemous observations about divinities and ceremonies which were recognized bv the Athenian state. He was declared an outlaw at sometime after the reduction of his native island, but his
name had somewhat earlier become associated with atheism and in the Clouds, performed in 423 b.c., Aristophanes can speak of Socrates as ‘the Melian,’ with
this innuendo. The other recorded prosecution is that of Euripides, possibly
the same time as the Clouds, The accuser of Euripides was no less a person than
Cleon the politician. But the prosecution seems to have failed; nothing
happened to interfere with the usual activities of the poet. It is quite
possible that Cleon was a man of very orthodox beliefs, who hated the advanced
views of Euripides and considered them dangerous to society. The extreme
democrats who came of the tradesman class, like Cleon and Lysicles, Eucrates and Hyperbolus,
might resort to the Sophists to learn rhetoric and political craft but were
doubtless as prejudiced against freedom of speculation in matters of religion as
old-fashioned conservatives like Nicias. It is however quite possible that the
charge of blasphemy may have been rather a pretext than the true reason, which
may have been the desire of silencing an influential critic who had access to
the ears of the public, and whose ideas of justice and humanity were outraged
by some political acts of Cleon, as they assuredly must have been by his proposal
to put to death the population of Mitylene.
Another blasphemy trial
has been recorded, but the record is open to suspicion. Protagoras is said to
have been indicted for irreligion, on account of his treatise On the, by Pythodorus and to have escaped from Athens before the trial
came on, and the story adds that all copies of the book that could be found
were burned publicly in the market place. The occurrence was dated at the time
of the oligarchic revolution of 411 b.c. and
what we otherwise know of the chronology of the Sophist’s life makes the whole
story dubious.
So little information is
preserved as to the details of any of these prosecutions that it is difficult
to judge them, especially as we do not know the laws of Solon on the offence of asebeia, or precisely what that term included.
But our short review of the cases recorded seems to point to the conclusion
that under the early Athenian democracy there was nothing that could be called
a policy of religious intolerance, and that when a prosecution for blasphemy
occurred there was usually some other interest than that of religion in the
background.
It is only in a highly
sophisticated society that it would occur to people to ask the question whether
punishment is justifiable, and on what grounds. It is still debated, and it was
debated in the fifth century b.c.—probably
for the first time in man’s history —by Pericles and other thinkers. The
vindictive or retributive theory which is the primitive and natural view was
considered unsatisfactory, and it is interesting to find that in the speech
placed by Thucydides in the mouth of Diodotus, the
speaker, discussing punishment, ignores entirely the retributive theory and
tacitly assumes that the only reason for punishment is the prevention of crime.
This is what he says: “no law will ever prevent people from committing offences
and doing wrong to others, whatever penalties it impose”.
It is the nature of all
men, individually and collectively, to do wrong. Society, in the endeavour to suffer less injury from evildoers, has
exhausted the whole gamut of punishments. In ancient times punishments were
lighter; as time went on, they were made severer, and now death is the penalty
in most cases, but crimes are still committed. Something more fearful than
death must be discovered to outweigh the motives of desire and hope which
prompt evildoing.
Another question which
exercised men’s minds and lent itself to sophistical discussion was the
justification of law, as against nature, which is violated for instance by the
restraints which law lays upon those who are stronger and abler than their
fellows, thus preventing them from reaping the fruits of their superior
strength and ability. The right of the superior man to exercise tyranny and
commit acts of injustice could be defended by an appeal to nature, and the
prevailing doctrine of Equality of rights in a community be discredited as a
principle which had no other basis than an unnatural convention. The best
presentation of the argument in favour of the
superior man is that which Plato puts in the mouth of Callicles in the Gorgias.
Of the Athenian
representatives of the Illumination, who were active during the last thirty
years of the fifth century, the three names most eminent and most important for
posterity are Socrates, Euripides, and Thucydides. Of these, Thucydides, the
founder of critical history, was then still obscure, composing his work in
exile, and we know little of him personally. The two most important things we
know about him are, as will be shown in the following chapter, that he would
not have the gods and would not have women at any price in history. They both
represented the irrational, and this was the age of reason. Of Euripides,
whose influence in literature was to be immense for centuries after his death,
we know little, apart from his extant plays; these show us that he was a man
unchained by conventional views, that he was not a sound polytheist, that he
was sceptical about oracles and omens, that he looked
with wavering complacency on the institution of slavery, that his men and
women were in the habit of saying things which provoked the audience to think
dangerously. Of Socrates we know a good deal, much more than we know of any
other man of the time. His trial and death have always been remembered as one
of the notable events in the history of civilization.
IV.
THE LIFE AND DEATH OF SOCRATES
The book of Xenophon on
the life and teaching of Socrates, known as the Memorabilia, would, if it stood
alone, give us little idea of what Socrates was like, and no idea of the secret
of his greatness. Xenophon belonged (probably for a very short time) to the
Socratic circle, but he had no notion of what philosophy really means and but a
slight first-hand knowledge of the master. He produced a portrait such as a
journalist with a commonplace mind might contribute to a gallery of ‘good men,’
and in his endeavour to show that Socrates was a good
man he succeeds in concealing the fact that he was a great man. Most of the
anecdotes he tells are uninstructive or insignificant, and some, as edifying
stories are apt to be, simply tedious, like the remonstrances of Socrates with
his son Lamprocles who could not put up with the
rough side of his mother Xanthippe’s tongue. Discerning as Xenophon was in many
practical things he displays conspicuous want of discernment here: and for
appreciating the personality of Socrates his book is almost negligible, while
for most of the bare external incidents of his life that are interesting and
which a biographer ought to supply, we go to him in vain. He was not present at
the trial of Socrates.
It is in the Dialogues of his companion Plato that a figure probably resembling the real Socrates
appears. There we find his animae figura, his mind and methods, and the features of his
personality, and also many details of his life. At all events, it is very
difficult to resist the impression that the Platonic Socrates is a genuine
life-like portrait of the original man, however unsocratically Platonic may be the argument and ideas of which he is made the spokesman.
Socrates was born about
470 b.c., and since he served as a hoplite he
must have inherited some property from his father, Sophroniscus.
He is said to have possessed a house and a capital sum of 70 minae which was invested for him by his friend Crito, who
belonged to the same deme (Alopece). He witnessed the
development of the Athenian democracy under Pericles and lived through the
Peloponnesian War, serving in some of the earlier campaigns. He was a man of
strong physical constitution, and of eccentric appearance and habits. His
features are well known from portrait busts which are probably faithful enough
to reality. With his flat nose and prominent eyes he was compared by his contemporaries
to a satyr. He was subject to trances of meditation; when rapt in thought he
would stand for hours, unconscious of what was going on around him. He said
that from his childhood he used to hear from time to time the monition of an
inner voice; its monitions were always negative, never prompting him to an
action, but always restraining him from doing things.
What we know of the
external events of his life is not a great deal but it is interesting. In his
youth he was a pupil of Archelaus, who was a disciple of Anaxagoras, and
accompanied him to Samos in 440 b.c. when the Athenians were blockading it. In 437-6 b.c. he may have served as hoplite at
Amphipolis, and in 432 b.c. he served at Potidaea; again in 424 b.c. at Delium where he exhibited remarkable presence of mind in
the retreat. On these military occasions he showed extraordinary powers of
endurance in sustaining cold, hunger, and fatigue; barefooted in a severe
frost he could outmarch the other soldiers who were shod.
Perhaps it was
not till he was an elderly man that he was called upon to perform any public
duty, beyond serving in the army. In 406 b.c. he was a member of the
Council of Five Hundred, being one of the fifty representatives of his tribe (Antiochis). It was the year of Arginusae,
and when the unhappy Generals were tried, Socrates was the only member who
stood out in refusing to agree with the illegal resolution that all should be
tried together. Under the Thirty he risked his life by refusing to carry out
an order which was illegal. In all the public affairs in which he happened to
be concerned he displayed moral and physical courage and respect for the laws
of his city. Thus remarkable for courage and justice, Socrates was no less
distinguished for his sobriety and temperance, but he was not an ascetic nor a
spoilsport. He would take part in potations, but his head was strong, and he
was never the worse for them.
Athenians had taken no
part in the scientific speculations which had been so vigorously pursued by men
of Ionia and in far western Greece. Archelaus, the instructor of Socrates, was
the earliest, and not a very eminent exception. The sharp intellectual
curiosity of Socrates was accompanied by a sane spirit of scepticism which was confirmed by the influence of Zeno. He cannot have been much over
twenty when he came under that influence which was powerful in determining the
direction of his thought.
Parmenides, with his young
friend Zeno, may have visited Athens not long after 450 b.c. and, if so, every Athenian
of inquiring mind was interested in their visit. In any case, Zeno seems to
have resided at Athens for several years; he was the inventor of dialectic and
Socrates learned his method.
In the course of time a
small circle of friends gathered around Socrates, drawn to him by the stimulus
of his conversation. Knowledge he consistently professed himself unable to
impart, and these friends were associated with him not as disciples but as
fellow-inquirers. Their inquiries appear to have been chiefly concerned with
mathematical and physical questions, the doctrines of Anaxagoras and Archelaus
and Diogenes of Apollonia and of Pythagoras. In fact during the first half of
his life the studies of Socrates were devoted chiefly to physical science; it
was in his later years that he turned to the logical and ethical problems with
which we chiefly associate his name.
Socrates and his circle
became notorious in Athens as the Thinkers, and comic poets seized on them as
an obvious and legitimate subject for ridicule. In 423 b.c. Ameipsias produced his Connus, in which the chorus consisted of Thinkers
and Socrates was derided, and in the same year was acted the Clouds of
Aristophanes in which the scene was laid in the Thinking-shop of Socrates and
his fellow-workers.
The most devoted in this
group of students was a certain Chaerephon who adored
Socrates so sincerely that he went to Delphi and put to the oracle the amazing
question “Is any man wiser than Socrates?”. More amazing still was the
categorical answer of the oracle, without any reservations, “No one is wiser”.
Socrates said that he was greatly puzzled by this reply, being acutely
conscious how little he knew. If the oracle were true, it must mean that others
were not so wise as they seemed, or imagined themselves to be; and in order to
test its truth, he states that he went about questioning and cross-examining
persons who were eminent as proficients in their
special subjects—politicians, poets, handicraftsmen. None of them stood the
test; they were all convinced that they were wise, but none possessed more
wisdom than Socrates himself, but he was superior in that he was fully aware of
his own ignorance. In this way the oracle was justified. We do not know at what
time it was given, but in the later portion of his life Socrates seems to have
spent much of his time, not only in his accustomed haunts, the gymnasia of the
Academy and the Lyceum, but also in the market-place and the workshops of
artisans, cross-examining people and exposing their erroneous convictions that
they were wise, thus fulfilling, as he put it, a duty imposed upon him by the
god. Defending himself at his trial he said: “People suppose that I am wise
myself in those things in which I convict another of ignorance. They are mistaken.
The god alone is wise, and his oracle declares that human wisdom is worth
little or nothing, using the name of Socrates as an example. That man is wisest
who like Socrates knows that he is worthless so far as wisdom is concerned. The
disgraceful ignorance is to think you know what you do not know”. Sceptical as Socrates was and always careful to appeal to
reason, we cannot fail to sec, in some parts of his defence,
that there was a side of his nature which was moved by reasons that reason does
not know.
In all ages of active
progress, the warfare between the ideas and fashions of a young critical
generation, and the old strongly entrenched opinions and customs which the
innovators mock and assail, always presents amusing and humorous pictures which
can furnish material for comedy. Comic poets can laugh impartially at the
extravagances and the prejudices of both the combatants. If Aristophanes held
up to ridicule the scientific Thinkers and the modern critics of society, he
did not spare the praisers of the past, the old
fogies whose ideas are out of date who bore you with faded memories of the
veterans of Marathon, and descant on bygone virtues and modern degeneracy.
We are told nothing of
personal relations between Socrates and Pericles, but it is difficult to think
that they were not acquainted. Socrates, though he belonged to a different
class of society, had such a high repute as a thinker and talker that he could
hardly have failed to arouse the curiosity and interest of Pericles, and they
had many common friends. On the other hand, we hear of an intimacy between
Socrates and Aspasia, who, it was even supposed, gave him instruction in the
art of rhetoric.
Though Socrates
consistently disclaimed the possession of knowledge and therefore of the power
of imparting it, he was a master of dialectic, for which he had a natural gift,
and he was really teaching all the time, disguising the instruction and the
ideas which he communicated under the form of question and answer. Many young
men attached themselves to him and were his constant companions, and among them
were the men, both Athenians and foreigners, who in the next generation were to
be the great thinkers of Greece, the founders of philosophical schools, each
emphasizing according to his own temperament a different side of the master’s
teaching. Plato, son of Ariston, the greatest of them all; Antisthenes, a poor
man, who founded the school of the Cynics, which was the parent of Stoicism;
Aristippus of Cyrene, whose Cyrenaic school was to be the parent of Epicureanism; Eucleides of Megara; Phaedo of Eretria; Aeschines, generally called ‘the Socratic,’ to distinguish
him from Aeschines the orator. Thus Socrates was in
some sense the ancestor of all the later philosophies of Greece. Outside this
circle of companions, who were virtually disciples, his society was sought by
men who were not interested much in philosophical questions but who were
interested in listening to him cross-examining people and perhaps hoped to
learn the secret of his skill. Two of the most distinguished were the versatile
man of letters, Critias, and Alcibiades, of whom the
second was an ardent admirer and an intimate friend of the philosopher. It was
natural that Socrates should, in the popular mind, have to bear some ill fame
for associating with these enemies of the democracy and be held responsible for
their mischievous conduct. Although he was always loyal to existing authorities
he never concealed his unfavourable opinion of
democracy, which must have seemed to him an irrational form of government;
Alcibiades called it bluntly “acknowledged folly”.
Throughout the
Peloponnesian War Socrates had with perfect impunity pursued his unpopular
mission. But under the restored democracy it seemed to some of the democratic
leaders that he was a dangerous and insidious anti-democratic influence and
that it was desirable to silence him. The fact that he had remained at Athens
unharmed during the government of the Thirty could not be made a charge against
him on account of the amnesty. As a matter of fact he had barely escaped with
his life from the despotism of the Thirty. Two of these oligarchs had been his
friends, Critias the leader, and Charmides the uncle
of Plato, and knowing that he was no admirer of the democracy they thought they
were sure of his adhesion. They did not realize the unshakable strength of his
respect for law and his love of justice. But they would not tolerate free
speech and Critias thought it well to warn the
philosopher that his discussions with the young men who sought his society must
cease, and the government then made an effort to associate him with their
unjust and tyrannous acts. The tyrants ordered him and four others to go to
Salamis and arrest there a certain Leon whom they had resolved to put to death.
Socrates said nothing and simply went home. Ide would have been executed for
his disobedience to the government, if it had not fallen. This notorious
incident however did not convince the people in power that Socrates stood quite
outside party sympathies, and cared only for justice and right. They considered
him disloyal to democracy, and that his criticisms were more to be feared than
the plots of an oligarchical conspirator. It was therefore deemed highly
desirable to rid Athens of a citizen whose influence and fearless tongue were
felt to be a danger, though he took no part in politics and was the least
likely of men to do anything contrary to the law. Anytus, an honest and
moderate democrat and at this moment perhaps the most important Athenian
statesman next to Thrasybulus, was the prime mover in preparing a prosecution
intended to silence the embarrassing philosopher. No one was more determined
than Anytus to observe honestly and to interpret strictly the terms of the
amnesty; so that he was concerned carefully to keep out of sight the political
motive for the action. He decided that the best ground of attacking Socrates
successfully would be irreligion; it was common knowledge that the philosopher
was far from orthodox. Accordingly an arrangement was made with a minor poet
named Meletus, who was a fanatical champion of religion, that he
should bring against Socrates a public suit for irreligion and that Anytus
should support it by acting as an advocate for the prosecution. Anytus associated
with himself a second advocate, a rhetorician named Lycon of whom otherwise we know nothing.
Legal actions having to do
with religion came into the court of the King archon. The charge which Meletus
lodged against Socrates was formulated thus: “Socrates is guilty of not worshipping
the gods whom the city worships, and of introducing religious novelties. He is
guilty also of corrupting the young men”. This accusation seems to prove that
neglect of the worship of the gods was an indictable offence under the laws of
Solon; for no one could now be indicted under the decree of Diopeithes which had been passed to meet the case of Anaxagoras, inasmuch as the effect of
the settlement of 403 b.c. was that no prosecution could be based solely on one decree passed before that
date.
Meletus, in the writ of
indictment, named death as the penalty which he demanded, for irreligion was
one of the offences for which there was no punishment fixed by the code; the
court itself determined the penalty on each occasion. But the court was limited
to a choice between two penalties, that which was demanded by the prosecutor and
one which it was the right of the prisoner himself to propose in case he were
found guilty. It was the prisoner’s interest to name a substantial penalty
milder than that named in the indictment, yet not so light that it could not be
entertained by the jury. A result of this curious judicial method was that the
prosecutor generally assessed a penalty greater than he expected or wished to
inflict. This is emphatically a case in point. There is no reason to suppose
that Anytus wished Socrates to be put to death. It was doubtless expected that
if he were convicted he would, as he had a right to do, propose exile as an
alternative penalty and the court would assuredly be satisfied with that. To
have him out of Athens was the object.
Our knowledge of this famous
trial is derived from one of the most memorable and impressive books in the
literature of the world, Plato’s Apology of Socrates. The view that it was
Plato’s own composition used generally to be held although it was never doubted
that it was based on the facts of the trial, but some critics now believe that
it is the actual speech of Socrates, edited by Plato for publication, and as
near to what was said as, say, a speech of Demosthenes or Cicero in its
published form to the speech the orator actually delivered. The truth probably
lies between these two views. We cannot suppose that the prisoner was allowed
to make an address to the court after the sentence was passed. The epilogue is
an addition imagined by Plato, an artistic and moving conclusion. If this is
admitted, it must also be allowed that Plato may have taken other liberties
with the Defence; he may have left out parts of it
and considerably expanded other parts. The most grave and perilous of the
charges brought against Socrates was that of being a corrupter of youth. That
would count for much with the judges because they knew that leading politicians
who were enemies of the democracy had cultivated his society—Critias, Alcibiades, Charmides. But this was just the proof
of the accusation which Meletus and his two advocates were prohibited from
touching on. The amnesty forbade them to pronounce these names. They must
however have made an attempt to show in what ways the conversation of Socrates
misled and injured the young men. Of this there are no indications in the Defence according to Plato, nor can we discover from that defence how Meletus explained what were the strange
religious practices which he alleged that Socrates introduced, as he assuredly
must have done, producing some proof of his statements. It seems to follow that
the Apology does not supply a full account of the trial.
Socrates was found guilty
by a majority of 60 votes, for he mentions in his Defence that he would have been acquitted if 30 of the votes recorded against him had
been for acquittal. It is probable, though not certain, that the number of
Athenians in the jury appointed by the king to try the case was 501. If that
was so, 225 must have voted in his favour, and it is
quite likely that he would have been acquitted if he had assumed a different
attitude and had really been concerned to secure a verdict of ‘not guilty.’ But
he adopted throughout a very high tone, which was far from calculated to
conciliate the court though he expressed himself with his usual urbanity and
politeness. He had not condescended to make the conventional appeal to pity by
bringing into court his wife and children to excite the compassion of the
judges by family tears, as was almost invariably done by prisoners tried on a
grave issue, and the omission of which many of the judges might consider an
affront to themselves.
When the verdict of his
guilt was pronounced, it was for Socrates to submit a punishment less drastic
than death, and there can be no question that he could have saved his life if
he had proposed banishment. But Socrates was not as other men. His tone now
became higher than ever and to the ears of his judges more offensive. “Meletus”,
he said, “assesses the penalty at death. What fair counter-assessment then
shall I make, Athenians? What do I deserve to suffer, or what fine to pay, because
during my life I would not keep quiet, but neglecting the things that most people
care for—making money, managing their property, public offices and political
clubs—I considered myself really too good for such things, and instead of
entering upon these ways of life in which I should have been no good either to
you or to myself I set myself on the way of benefaction, to confer the greatest
of all benefactions as I assert, by attempting to persuade each of you
individually not to care for any of his own belongings before he cares for
himself—for his being as good and as wise as possible, nor for any of the
city’s belongings before he cares for the city, and on the same principle in
all other matters. What then do I deserve for this? Something good surely,
Athenians, and a good that would be suitable to me personally, suitable to a poor
man who is a benefactor and requires leisure. There is nothing so suitable than
that such a man should have free commons in the Prytaneum, far more than for
one of you who has won a victory at Olympia in a horse-race or a chariotrace; because while he makes you appear happy, I
make you be happy, and he does not need public support while I do. Accordingly,
if I am to propose what I deserve, I propose that my sentence be free board in
the Prytaneum”.
This was not calculated to
conciliate the judges; it was an undisguised ‘contempt of court’ and was quite
unnecessary; it seemed as if the prisoner was determined to make it certain
that he should be condemned to death. Having by this digression done what he
could to dispose the judges against him he returned to business and considered
possible penalties which the court might accept. He knew quite well that
banishment would probably be considered adequate. ‘Perhaps,’ he said,
‘banishment is what you think I deserve. Yet I should be fond indeed of life,
Athenians, if I were so poor a reckoner as to calculate that if you who are my
fellow citizens could not put up with my lectures and discourses, and if they
have become so onerous and offensive, that you are now wishing to rid
yourselves of them, other people will readily tolerate them. Nay, a fine life I
should have, leaving my own city at my age and moving from one city to another
and continually being driven out. I know that wheresoever I came the young men
would listen to my talk as they do here. If I repulse them they will persuade
the older men to expel me, and if I do not, their fathers and relatives will do
so for their sakes.
“But it will be said: But,
Socrates, when you leave Athens, why not keep quiet and hold your tongue? This
is just what is so difficult to make you understand. To do that would be to disobey
the god, and therefore it is impossible to keep quiet. When I say this, you
will not believe me, you will take it as irony. And again if I say that a man’s
greatest good is to debate every day concerning virtue and the other things you
hear me discussing and cross-examining myself and others about, and that the
life which is not tested and proved by such examination is not worth
living—when I say this, still less do you believe me to be in earnest. If I hid money I should be ready to offer all I
have as a fine; paving it would do me no harm. I could pay a mina. Plato,
however, and Crito and two other friends bid me name 30 minae and will stand as sureties for the payment. They are solvent. So I propose this
fine”.
The majority voted for
death and this majority was greater than the previous one. We can understand
that the tone which Socrates had adopted caused resentment among some of those
who had originally voted for acquittal. One knows the type of persons who would
be reasonable and fair enough to see that the accuser had failed to prove his
case and would vote accordingly, yet would feel it an outrage that any prisoner
should value his life so little as to neglect all the customary and obvious
methods of trying to save it and take no trouble to conciliate the judges. Such
an attitude was indecent and dangerous. If prisoners were not afraid of death,
what could any one do? Socrates, it almost seemed,
was so impertinent as to reverse the roles of judge and accused; he had treated
them as if it was they who were on trial, and had gone too far in his insolent
assumption that he was a great and good man.
A month intervened between
the sentence and the execution, because it happened to be the feast of the
Delian Apollo when every year Athens sent a ship to Delos, and the law was that
from the time the ship set sail till it returned to the Piraeus the city should
not be polluted by any death inflicted by the authority of the State. The ship
had been adorned with the official garlands on the day before the trial of
Socrates, and, as it turned out, a month elapsed before it returned, a month
which he had to spend in the public prison in chains. He seems to have been
treated there with much consideration; the overseer of the prison was a humane
man and did what he could to make the confinement as little irksome as
possible. His friends came daily to visit him and his last days were passed in
philosophical discussion. Some of his companions, particularly Crito, urged him
to escape; a plan was prepared, and there is little doubt that it could easily
have been managed; even the authorities might not have been very unwilling to
connive; but Socrates refused to consent. It had always been his principle to
obey the laws and had he not been legally condemned? And to flee from prison
and death would have been glaringly inconsistent with his own attitude at the
trial and rendered it obviously absurd. If to live was such an important
consideration as to prompt escape, which meant abiding in exile, he ought
clearly to have proposed exile as the alternative penalty.
The last hours and death
of Socrates have been described by Plato in his Phaedo. His friends were with
him to the end, and he was killed by the painless method of a draught of
hemlock poison which produced a gradual paralysis. It is the one famous
execution, recorded in history, of which the circumstances are quite ideal; the
end of Socrates is marred, for our memory, by no violence or shedding of blood;
and modern critics have often praised the Athenians for their humane methods of
punishment. But it would be an error to suppose that the ways of brutal evildoers
at Athens were made so easy for them, or that robbers and assassins were
treated like Socrates. It is not long ago since excavations near Phalerum revealed evidence that the Athenians used to
inflict punishments which in agony rivalled crucifixion and hardly fell short
of Assyrian atrocity. We do not know on what principle or in what cases
execution by hemlock was adopted.
Among the companions of
Socrates his memory was piously cherished, while they were stirred by a deep
resentment against the democracy of Athens for the crime of his death. Seen
through their eyes, the trial of Socrates by a jury of average practical
citizens at the prosecution of an honest politician seems as absurd an event
as, to use Plato’s comparison, the trial of a physician in a court of little
boys at the instance of a confectioner. The great memorial of Socrates is the
body of Plato’s works; no other man has had a more wonderful monument. Having
described the last moments of his master, Plato wrote, ‘Such was the end of our
friend, whom I may truly call the wisest, the justest and the best of all the men I have ever known.’ In the study of his imagination
the revered master grew into the ideal figure of a perfect philosopher and as
such has passed into history. The tragedy changed the course of Plato’s own
life. He had always meant to enter political life. The behaviour of the oligarchs during their short tenure of power, in which his relatives Critias and Charmides had been conspicuous, disgusted him
so deeply that he was probably inclined to support the democracy, but the
crowning injustice of the condemnation of Socrates decided him to abandon the
idea of a political career. More than forty years later, in a letter addressed
to ‘the friends and associates’ of Dion of Syracuse, he recalled his
experience at this time, and his decision to embrace a life of philosophy. Phis is what he says: “Socrates an elderly friend of mine who,
I should not be ashamed to say, was the justest man
among the men of the time, was sent with others by the Thirty to arrest one of
the citizens, to be executed, in order that he (Socrates) might himself share
in their actions whether he wished it or not; he refused and ran the extreme
risk, rather than become a participant in their wicked deeds. Seeing all these
things, and other similar things which were not trifling, I was disgusted and
withdrew and stood aloof from the crimes of that Government. Not long
afterwards the Thirty fell and the existing constitution was changed. I felt
myself again drawn though slowly towards public life. The new Government had
merits, though it had also defects, but it so happened that this companion of
ours, Socrates, was brought into court by certain men who were in power. They
preferred against him a most wicked charge and one which was least applicable
to Socrates of all men in the world. They accused him of impiety, and he was
condemned and put to death, the man who had refused to take part in the wicked
arrest of one of their friends who was trying to flee at the time when they
were themselves unfortunate”.
He goes on to explain how
this experience of the new democracy finally decided him to give up the idea
of a political career.
How great Socrates was as
an original thinker, whether he can be set beside Pythagoras, for instance, is
a question that is open to dispute, and depends much on the view that is taken
of the Platonic Dialogues. But there can be only one opinion as to the
greatness and the unique quality of his personality, and his unrivalled power
as a stimulator of thought. The Athenians, with the exception of his personal
friends, were quite unconscious of his greatness. Posterity looks back at him
as the most remarkable figure of the Illumination; the contemporary man in the
market-place of Athens probably remembered him merely as an eccentric Sophist.
One can imagine what he would have said: “Socrates—yes, an incessant talker,
who fancied himself as a good-mixer. He was really an expert bore preaching for ever about virtue and other wearisome things. He got at
last what he probably had richly deserved”.
CHAPTER XIVHERODOTUS AND THUCYDIDES
|