HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHY
ISAAC HUSIK
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER III.
Saadia
was the first important Jewish philosopher. Philo of Alexandria does not come
within our purview as he was not medieval. Besides his work is not systematic,
being in the nature of a commentary on Holy Writ. Though Philo was a good and
loyal Jew, he stood, so to speak, apart from the real centre of Jewish
intellectual and spiritual development. He was on the one hand too closely
dependent on Greek thought and on the other had only a limited knowledge of
Jewish thought and tradition. The Bible he knew only in the Greek translation,
not in the original Hebrew; and of the Halaka, which was still in the making in
Palestine, he knew still less.
It was
different with Saadia. In the tenth century the Mishna and the Talmud had been
long completed and formed theoretically as well as practically the content of
the Jew's life and thought. Sura in Babylonia, where Saadia was the head of the
academy, was the chief centre of Jewish learning, and Saadia was the heir in
the main line of Jewish development as it passed through the hands of lawgiver
and prophet, scribe and Pharisee, Tanna and Amora, Saburai and Gaon. As the
head of the Sura academy he was the intellectual representative of the Jewry
and Judaism of his day. His time was a period of agitation and strife, not only
in Judaism but also in Islam, in whose lands the Jews lived and to whose
temporal rulers they owed allegiance in the East as well as in Spain.
In Islam
we saw in the introduction how the various schools of the Kadariya, the Mutazila
and the Ashariya arose in obedience to the demand of clarifying the chief
problems of faith, science and life. In Judaism there was in addition to this
more general demand the more local and internal conflict of Karaite and
Rabbanite which centred about the problem of tradition. Saadia found himself in
the midst of all this and proved equal to the occasion.
We are
not here concerned with the vicissitudes of Saadia’s personal life or of his
literary career as opponent of the Karaite sect. Nor can we afford more than
merely to state that Jewish science in the larger sense begins with Saadia.
Hebrew grammar and lexicography did not exist before him. The Bible had been
translated into several languages before Saadia’s day, but he was the first to
translate it into Arabic, and the first to write a commentary on it. But the
greatest work of Saadia, that which did the most important service to the
theory of Judaism, and by which he will be best remembered, is his endeavor to
work out a system of doctrine which should be in harmony with the traditions of
Judaism on the one hand and with the most authoritative scientific and
philosophic opinion of the time on the other. Israeli, we have seen, was
interested in science before Saadia. As a physician he was probably more at
home in purely physical discussions than Saadia. But there is no evidence that
he had the larger interest of the Gaon of Sura, namely, to construct a system
of Judaism upon the basis of scientific doctrine. Possibly the example of Islam
was lacking in Israeli's environment, as he does not seem to be acquainted with
the theories and discussions of the Mutakallimun, and draws his information
from Aristotelian and Neo-Platonic sources. Saadia was in the very midst of
Arab speculation as is evident from the composition of his chef d'œuvre, “Emunot
ve-Deot”, Beliefs and Opinions.
The work
is arranged on the Mutazilite model. The two main divisions in works of this
character are Unity and Justice. The first begins with some preliminary
considerations on the nature and sources of knowledge. It proceeds then to
prove the existence of God by showing that the world cannot have existed from
eternity and must have been created in time. Creation implies a creator. This
is followed by arguments showing that God is one and incorporeal. The rest is
devoted to a discussion of the divine attributes with the purpose of showing
that God's unity and simplicity are not affected by them. The section on unity
closes with a refutation of opposing views, such as those of the dualists or
Trinitarians or infidels. The section on Justice centres about the doctrine of
free will. Hence psychology and ethics are treated in this part of the work. To
this may be added problems of a more dogmatic nature, eschatological and
otherwise. We shall see in the sequel that Saadia’s masterpiece is modeled on
the same plan.
But not
merely the plan and arrangement of his work give evidence of the influence upon
Saadia of Islamic schools, many of his arguments, those for example on the
existence of God and the creation of the world, are taken directly from them.
Maimonides, who was a strong opponent of the Mutakallimun, gives an outline of
their fundamental principles and their arguments for the existence, unity and
incorporeality of God. Some of these are identical with those of Saadia.
Saadia, however, is not interested in pure metaphysics as such. His purpose is
decidedly apologetic in the defence of Judaism and Jewish dogma. Hence we look
in vain in his book for definite views on the constitution of existing
substances, on the nature of motion, on the meaning of cause, and so on. We get
a glimpse of his attitude to some of these questions in an incidental way.
The
Mutakallimun were opposed to the Aristotelian theory of matter and form, and
substituted for it the atomic theory. God created atoms without magnitude or
quality, and he likewise created qualities to inhere in groups of atoms. These
qualities they called accidents, and one of their important discussions was
whether an accident can last more than a moment of time. The opinions were
various and the accidents were classified according to their powers of
duration. That is, there were some accidents which once created continued to
exist of their own accord some length of time, and there were others which had
to be recreated anew every moment in order to continue to exist. Saadia does
not speak of matter and form as constituting the essence of existing things; he
does speak of substance and accident, which might lead us to believe that he
held to the atomic theory, since he speaks of the accidents as coming and going
one after the other, which suggests the constant creation spoken of by the
Mutakallimun. On the other hand, when he answers an objection against motion,
which is as old as Zeno, namely, how can we traverse an infinitely divisible
distance, since it is necessary to pass an infinite number of parts, he tells
us that it is not necessary to have recourse to the atomic theory or other
theories adopted by some Mutazilites to meet this objection. We may believe in
the continuity and infinite divisibility of matter, but as long as this
divisibility is only potentially infinite, actually always finite, our ability
to traverse the space offers no difficulty. Finally, in refuting the second
theory of creation, which combines Platonism with atomism, he argues against an
atomic theory primarily because of its implications of eternity of the atoms,
but partly also on other grounds, which would also affect the Kalamistic
conceptions of the atoms. These points are not treated by Saadia expressly but
are only mentioned incidentally in the elucidation of other problems dealing
with the creation of the world and the existence of God.
Like
Israeli Saadia shows considerable familiarity with Aristotelian notions as
found in the Logic, the Physics and the Psychology. It is doubtful, however, whether
he really knew Aristotle’s more important treatises at first hand and in
detail. The “Categories”, a small treatise forming the first book of Aristotle’s
logic, he no doubt knew, but the other Aristotelian concepts he probably
derived from secondary sources. For while he passes in review all the ten
categories showing that none of them is applicable to God, we scarcely find any
mention of such important and fundamental Aristotelian conceptions as matter
and form, potentiality and actuality, the four causes, formal, material,
efficient and final—concepts which as soon as Aristotle began to be studied by
Al Farabi and Avicenna became familiar to all who wrote anything at all bearing
on philosophy, theology, or Biblical exegesis. Nay, the very concepts which he
does employ seem to indicate in the way he uses them that he was not familiar
with the context in which they are found in the Aristotelian treatises, or with
the relation they bear to other views of Aristotle. Thus no one who knew
Aristotle at first hand could make the mistake of regarding his definition of
the soul as making the latter an accident. When Saadia speaks of six kinds of
motion instead of three, he shows clearly that his knowledge of the
Aristotelian theory of motion was limited to the little of it that is contained
in the “Categories”.
We are
thus justified in saying, that Saadia’s sources are Jewish literature and
tradition, the works of the Mutakallimun, particularly the Mutazilites, and
Aristotle, whose book on the “Categories” he knew at first hand.
Saadia
tells us he was induced to write his book because he found that the beliefs and
opinions of men were in an unsatisfactory state. While there are some persons
who are fortunate enough to possess the truth and to know that they have it and
rejoice thereat, this is not true of all. For there are others who when they
have the truth know it not, and hence let it slip; others are still less
fortunate and adopt false and erroneous opinions, which they regard as true;
while still others vacillate continually, going from one opinion and belief to
another. This gave him pain and he thought it his duty to make use of his
limited knowledge to help them. A conscientious study of his book will tend to
remove doubt and will substitute belief through knowledge for belief through
tradition. Another result of such study, not less important, will be
improvement of character and disposition, which will affect for the better a
man's life in every respect, in relation to God as well as to his fellowmen.
One may
ask why it is that one encounters so many doubts and difficulties before
arriving at true knowledge. The answer is, a human being is a creature, i. e., a being dependent upon another
for its existence, and it is in the nature of a creature as such that it must
labor for the truth with the sweat of its brow. For whatever a man does or has
to do with is subject to time; each work must be accomplished gradually, step
by step, part by part, in successive portions of time. And as the task before
him is at the beginning complex, he has to analyze and simplify it. This takes
time; while certainty and knowledge cannot come until the task is accomplished.
Before that point is reached he is naturally in doubt.
The
sources of truth are three. First is that to which the senses testify. If our
normal sense perceives under normal conditions which are free from illusion, we
are certain of that perception.
The
judgment is another source of truth. There are certain truths of which we are
certain. This applies especially to such judgments of value, as that truth is
good and falsehood is bad. In addition to these two sources of immediate
knowledge, there is a third source based upon these two. This is logical
inference. We are led to believe what we have not directly perceived or a
matter concerning which we have no immediate knowledge of the second kind,
because we infer it from something else which we have perceived or of which we
have immediate certainty. Thus we believe man has a soul though we have never
seen it because we infer its presence from its activity, which we do see.
These
three sources are universal. They are not peculiar to a given race or religious
denomination, though there are some persons who deny the validity of some or
all of them. We Jews believe in them and in still another source of truth,
namely, authentic tradition.
Some
think that a Jew is forbidden to speculate or philosophize about the truths of
religion. This is not so. Genuine and sincere reflection and speculation is not
prohibited. What is forbidden is to leave the sacred writings aside and rely on
any opinions that occur to one concerning the beginnings of time and space. For
one may find the truth or one may miss it. In any case until a person finds it,
he is without a religious guide; and if he does find what seems to him the
truth and bases his belief and conduct upon it, he is never sure that he may
not later be assailed by doubts, which will lead him to drop his adopted
belief. But if we hold fast to the commandments of the Bible, our own
ratiocination on the truths of religion will be of great benefit to us.
Our
investigation of the facts of our religion will give us a reasoned and
scientific knowledge of those things which the Prophets taught us dogmatically,
and will enable us to answer the arguments and criticisms of our opponents
directed against our faith. Hence it is not merely our privilege but our duty
to confirm the truths of religion by reason.
Here a
question presents itself. If the reason can discover by itself the truths
communicated to us by divine revelation, why was it necessary to have recourse
to the latter? Why was it not left to the reason alone to guide us in our
belief and in our conduct? The answer is, as was suggested before, that human
reason proceeds gradually and does not reach its aim until the end of the
process. In the meantime one is left without a guide. Besides not everybody's
reason is adequate to discover truth. Some are altogether incapable of this
difficult task, and many more are exposed to harassing doubts and perplexities
which hinder their progress. Hence the necessity of revelation, because in the
witness of the senses all are equally at home, men and women, young and old.
The most
important fact of religion is the existence of God. We know it from the Bible,
and we must now prove it by reason. The proof is necessarily indirect because
no one of us has seen God, nor have we an immediate certainty of his existence.
We must prove it then by the method of inference. We must start with something
we do know with certainty and proceed from it through as many steps of logical
inference as may be necessary until we reach the object of our search.
The world
and the things in it are directly accessible to our senses and our judgment.
How long has the world been in existence and how did it come to be? The answers
to these questions also we do not know through our senses, and we must prove
them by a chain of reasoning. There are several possibilities. The world just
as it is may have existed from eternity. If so nobody made it; it just existed,
and we have no proof of God. The world in its present form might have proceeded
from a primitive matter. This hypothesis only removes the problem further back.
For, leaving aside the question how did this prime matter develop into the
complex world of our experience, we direct our attention to the prime matter
itself, and ask, Has it existed from eternity or did it come to be? If it
existed from eternity, then nobody made it, and we have no proof of a God, for
by God we mean an intelligent being acting with purpose and design, and the
cause of the existence of everything in creation. The third alternative is that
whether the world was developed out of a primitive matter or not, it at any
rate, or the primitive matter, as the case may be, was made in time, that is,
it was created out of nothing. If so there must have been someone who created
it, as nothing can create itself. Here we have proof of the existence of God.
It follows therefore that we must first show that the world is not eternal,
that it came to be in time, and this is what Saadia does.
Here are
some of his proofs. The world is finite in magnitude. For the world consists of
the earth, which is in the centre, and the heavens surrounding it on all sides.
This shows that the earth is finite, for an infinite body cannot be surrounded.
But the heavens are finite too, for they make a complete revolution in
twenty-four hours. If they were infinite it would take an infinite time to
complete a revolution. A finite body cannot have an infinite power. This Saadia
regards as self-evident, though Aristotle, from whom this statement is derived,
gives the proof. Hence the force or power within the world which keeps it going
is finite and must one day be exhausted. But this shows also that it could not
have gone on from eternity. Hence the world came to be in time.
Another
proof is based on the composite character of all things in heaven and earth.
Minerals, plants and animals are made up of parts and elements. The heavens
consist of spheres, one within the other. The spheres are studded with stars.
But composition implies a time when the composition took place. In other words,
the parts must have been there first and somebody put them together. Hence the
world as we see it now is not eternal.
A special
form of composition, which is universal, is that of substance and accident.
Plants and animals are born (or sprout), grow and decay. These manifestations
are the accidents of the plant or animal's substance. The heavenly bodies have
various motions, lights and colors as their accidents. But these accidents are not
eternal, since they come and go. Hence the substances bearing the accidents,
without which they cannot exist, are also temporal like them. Hence our world
is not eternal.
Finally,
past time itself cannot be eternal. For this would mean that an infinite time
has actually elapsed down to our day. But this is a contradiction in terms.
What is already accomplished cannot be infinite. Infinity is possible only as a
potentiality, for example, we may speak of a given length as infinitely
divisible. This merely means that one may mentally continue dividing it
forever, but we can never say that one has actually made an infinite number of
divisions. Therefore not merely the world, but even time must have begun to be.
It will
be seen that the first three arguments prove only that the world in the form
which it has now is not eternal. The possibility is not yet excluded of an
eternal matter out of which the world proceeded or was made. The fourth
argument proves a great deal. It shows that nothing which is subject to time
can be eternal, hence not even prime matter. God can be eternal because he is
not subject to time. Time, as we shall see later, cannot exist without motion
and moving things, hence before the world there was no time, and the fourth
argument does not apply to premundane existence.
To
complete the first three arguments Saadia therefore proceeds to show that the
world, which we now know came to be in time, must have been made by someone
(since nothing can make itself), and that too out of nothing, and not out of a
pre-existing eternal matter.
If an
eternal matter existed before the world, the explanation of the origin of the
world is open to two possibilities. One is that there is nothing outside of
this matter and the world which came from it. This is absurd, for it would mean
that an unintelligent dead thing is the cause of intelligence and life in the
universe. We must therefore have recourse to the other alternative that
someone, an intelligent being, made the world out of the primitive, eternal
matter. This is also impossible. For if the matter is eternal like the maker of
the world, it is independent of him, and would not be obedient to his will to
adapt itself to his purpose. He could therefore not make the world out of it.
The only
alternative left now is that the author of the universe is an intelligent
being, and that nothing outside of him is eternal. He alone is responsible for
the existence of the world, which was at one time nothing. Whether he first
created a matter and then from it the universe, or whether he made the world
outright, is of secondary importance.
There is
still a possibility that instead of making the world out of nothing, God made
it out of himself, i. e., that it
emanated from him as light from the sun. This, as we know, is the opinion of
the Neo-Platonists; and Israeli comes very close to it as we saw before. Saadia
is strongly opposed to any such doctrine.
It is
unlikely, he says, that an eternal substance having neither form, condition,
measure, place or time, should change into a body or bodies having those
accidents; or that a wise being, not subject to change or influence, or
comprehensibility should choose to make himself into a body subject to all of
these. What could have induced a just being who does no wrong to decree that
some of his parts should be subject to such evils as matter and material beings
are afflicted with? It is conceivable only in one of two ways. Either they
deserved it for having done wrong, or they did not deserve it, and it was an
act of violence that was committed against them. Both suppositions are absurd.
The fact of the matter is that the authors of this opinion to avoid the theory
of creation ex nihilo went from the frying pan into the fire. To be sure,
creation out of nothing is difficult to conceive, but this is the reason why we
ascribe this power to God alone. To demand that we show how this can be done is
to demand that we ourselves become creators.
The
question what existed in place of the earth before it was created evinces
ignorance of the idea of place. By place is meant simply the contact of two
bodies in which the one is the place of the other. When there is no earth and
no bodies there is no such thing as place.
The same
thing applies to time. Time means the persistence of existing things in heaven
and earth under changing conditions. Where there is no world, there is no time.
This answers the objection raised by some, namely, how is it possible that
before all these bodies were made time existed void of objects? Or the other
difficulty which is closely related, viz., Why did not God create the world
before he did? The answer to both is, there was no before and there was no
time, when the world was not.
The
following question is a legitimate one, Why did God create all things? And our answer
is, there was no cause which made him create them, and yet they were not made
in vain. God wished to exhibit his wisdom; and his goodness prompted him to
benefit his creatures by enabling them to worship him.
We have
now proved the existence of God as the cause of the existence of all things. We
must now try to arrive at some notion of what God is as far as this is in our
power. God cannot be corporeal or body, for in our proof of his existence we
began with the world which is body and arrived at the notion of God as the
cause of all corporeal existence. If God himself is corporeal our search is not
at an end, for we should still want to know the cause of him. Being the cause
of all body, he is not body and hence is for our knowledge ultimate, we cannot
go beyond him. But if God is not corporeal, he is not subject to motion or rest
or anger or favor, for to deny the corporeality of God and still look for these
accidents in him is to change the expression and retain the idea. Bodily
accidents involve body.
The
incorporeality of God proves also his unity. For what is not body cannot have
the corporeal attributes of quantity or number, hence God cannot be more than
one. And there are many powerful arguments besides against a dualistic theory.
A unitary
effect cannot be the result of two independent causes. For if one is
responsible for the whole, there is nothing left for the other, and the
assumption of his existence is gratuitous. If the effect consists of two parts
of which each does one, we have really two effects. But the universe is one and
its parts cannot be separated. Again, if one of them wishes to create a thing
and cannot without the help of the other, neither is all-powerful, which is
inconsistent with the character of deity. If he can compel the other to help
him, they are both under necessity. And if they are free and independent, then
if one should desire to keep a body alive and the other to kill it, the body
would have to be at the same time alive and dead, which is absurd. Again, if
each one can conceal aught from the other, neither is all-knowing. If they cannot,
they are not all-powerful.
Having
proved God's existence, unity and incorporeality, he proceeds to discuss his
most essential attributes, which are, Life, Omnipotence, and Omniscience. These
easily follow from what was said before. We cannot conceive a creator ex nihilo
unless he is all-powerful; power implies life; and the thing made cannot be
perfect unless its maker knows what it is going to be before he makes it.
These
three concepts our reason discovers with one act of its thinking effort, for
they are all involved in the concept, Maker. There is no gradual inference from
one to the other. The reason we are forced to use three expressions is because
of the limitations of language. Hence it must not be thought that they involve
plurality in God. They are simply the implications of the one expression,
Maker, and as that does not suggest plurality in God's essence, but signifies
only that there is a thing made by the maker, so the three derivative terms,
Living, Omnipotent, Omniscient, imply no more.
The
Christians erred in this matter in making God a trinity. They say one cannot
create unless he is living and wise, hence they regard his life and his wisdom
as two other things outside of his essence. But this is a mistake. For in
saying there are several attributes in him distinct one from the other, they
say in effect that he is corporeal—an error which we have already refuted.
Besides they do not understand what constitutes proof: In man we say that his
life and his knowledge are not his essence because we see that he sometimes has
them and sometimes not. In God this is not the case. Again, why only three?
They say essence, life, wisdom; why do they not add power, or hearing and seeing?
If they think that power is implied in life, and hearing and seeing in wisdom,
so is life implied in wisdom.
They
quote Scripture in their support, for example, the verse in II Samuel (23, 2),
“The Spirit of the Lord spoke through me, and his Word was upon my tongue”. “Word”
denotes, they say, his attribute of wisdom, and “Spirit” his life, as distinct
persons. But they are mistaken. The expressions in question denote the words
which God puts into the mouth of his prophets. There are other similar instances
which they cite, and in their ignorance of Hebrew take metaphorical expressions
literally. If they are consistent, they should add many more persons in the
Godhead, in accordance with the many phrases of the Bible concerning the hand
of God, the eye of God, the glory of God, the anger of God, the mercy of God, and
so on.
The above
discussion, as also that of Al-Mukammas, shows clearly the origin of the
doctrine of attributes as well as its motive. Both Al-Mukammas and Saadia and
the later Jewish philosophers owed their interest in this problem primarily to
the Mohammedan schools in which we know it played an important rôle. But there
is no doubt that the problem originated in the Christian schools in the Orient,
who made use of it to rationalize the dogma of the Trinity.
There is
extant a confession of faith attributed to Jacob Baradaeus (sixth century), the
founder of the Syrian Church of the Monophysites or Jacobites, in which the
phrase occurs that the Father is the Intellect, the Son is the Word and the
Holy Ghost is Life. In the works of Elias of Nisibis of the Nestorian Church, who
lived shortly after Saadia (975-1049), we also find a passage in which the
three expressions essence, life and wisdom are applied to the three persons of
the Trinity. The passage is worth quoting. It reads as follows: “As the essence
of God cannot receive accidents, his life and his wisdom cannot be accidents.
But whatever is not accident is either substance or person. Hence as the
essence of the Creator and his life and his wisdom are not three substances or
three accidents, it is proved that they are three persons”.
Monotheism
was a fundamental dogma of the Mohammedan faith. Hence it was necessary for
their rationalizing theologians to meet the Trinitarians with their own weapons
and show that the multiplicity of the divine attributes which they could not
deny, since the Koran was authority for it, does in no way affect God's unity.
The problem was quite as important for Judaism as it was for Islam, and for the
same reason. Hence Saadia’s insistence that inadequacy of language is alone responsible
for our expressing God’s essential attributes in the three words, Living,
Omnipotent, Omniscient; that in reality they are no more than interpretations
of the expression Maker.
We have
now shown that God is one in the two important senses of the word. He is one in
the sense that there is no second God beside him; and he is one in his own
essence, i. e., he is simple and not composed of parts. His Life and his Power
and his Wisdom are not distinct one from the other and from his essence. They
are all one. We have also proved God’s incorporeality. Nevertheless Saadia is
not satisfied until he has shown in detail that God cannot be compared to man
in any sense, and that the anthropomorphic expressions in the Bible must not be
taken literally. In reference to Biblical interpretation Saadia makes the
general remark that whenever a verse of Scripture apparently contradicts the
truths of reason, there is no doubt that it is figurative, and a person who
successfully interprets it so as to reconcile it with the data of sense or
reason will be rewarded for it. For not the Bible alone is the source of
Judaism, Reason is another source preceding the Bible, and Tradition is a third
source coming after the Bible.
In order
to show that God is not to be compared to any other thing in creation Saadia
finds it convenient to use Aristotle’s classification of all existing things
under the ten categories. Everything that exists is either a substance, or it
is an accident, i. e., an attribute or quality of a substance. Substance is
therefore the first and most important of the categories and is exemplified by
such terms as man, horse, city. Everything that is not substance is accident,
but there are nine classes of accident, and with substance they make up the ten
categories. The order of the categories as Aristotle gives them in his treatise
of the same name is, substance, quantity, quality, relation, place, time,
position, possession, action, passion. If these categories include all existing
things and we can prove that God is not any of them, our object is
accomplished. The one general argument is one with which we are already
familiar. It is that God is the cause of all substance and accident, hence he
is himself neither the one nor the other. Scripture supports our view, as in
Deuteronomy 4, 15: “Take ye therefore good heed of yourselves; for ye saw no
manner of form on the day that the Lord spake unto you in Horeb out of the
midst of the fire: lest ye corrupt yourselves, and make you a graven image in
the form of any figure, the likeness of male or female, the likeness of any
beast that is on the earth, the likeness of any winged fowl that flieth in the
heaven; the likeness of anything that creepeth on the ground, the likeness of
any fish that is in the water under the earth: and lest thou lift up thine eyes
unto heaven, and when thou seest the sun and the moon and the stars, even all
the host of heaven, thou be drawn away”, etc. And tradition is equally emphatic
in this regard. Our sages, who were the disciples of the prophets, render the
anthropomorphic passages in the Bible so as to avoid an objectionable
understanding. This is particularly true of the Aramaic translation of the
Targum.
Such
terms as head, eye, ear, mouth, lip, face, hand, heart, bowels, foot, which are
used in relation to God in the Bible, are figurative. For it is the custom of
language to apply such terms metaphorically to certain ideas like elevation,
providence, acceptance, declaration, command, favor, anger, power, wisdom,
mercy, dominion. Language would be a very inadequate instrument if it confined
itself to the literal meaning of the words it uses; and in the case of God we
should be limited to the statement that he is.
What was
said of the nouns above mentioned applies also to other parts of speech, such
as verbs attributing human activity to God. Such phrases as “incline thine ear”,
“open thine eyes”, “he saw”, “he heard”, “he spoke” are figurative. So the
expression, “the Lord smelled”, which sounds especially objectionable, denotes
acceptance.
The
theophanies in the Bible, where God is represented under a certain form, as in
Ezekiel, Isaiah and Kings, do not argue against our view, for there are meant
specially created forms for the benefit and honor of the prophet. This is what
is meant by the “Glory of the Lord”, and “Shekinah”. Sometimes it is simply a
created light without an individual form. When Moses asked to see God, he meant
the created light. God cannot be seen with the eye nor can he be grasped in
thought or imagination. Hence Moses could not have meant to see God, but the
created light. His face was covered so that he should not be dazzled by the
exceeding splendor of the beginning of the light, which is too much for a
mortal to endure; but later when the brightest part passed by, the covering was
taken off and Moses saw the last part of the light. This is the meaning of the
expression in Exodus 33, 23, “And I will take away mine hand, and thou shalt
see my back: but my face shall not be seen”.
Having
treated of God as the creator of the world and having learned something about
his attributes, we must now proceed to the study of man, or which is the same
thing, to an investigation of God's relations to the rational part of his
creation in the sublunar world. That man is endowed with a soul cannot be doubted,
for the activities of man’s soul are directly visible. The problem which is
difficult is concerning the nature of the soul. Here opinions differ, and some
regard the soul as an accident of the body, some think it is a corporeal
substance like air or fire, while others believe there is more than one soul in
man. It will be our task to vindicate our own view against these erroneous
ideas. The soul is too important in its functions to be an accident. It is
neither air nor fire because it has not the properties of these bodies. And if
the soul consisted of two or more distinct parts, the perceptions of sense
would not reach the reason, and there would be no cooperation between these two
powers. The true view is therefore that the soul of man is a substance created
by God at the time when the human body is completed. The soul has no eternal
existence before the body as Plato thought, for nothing is eternal outside of
God, as we saw before. Nor does it enter the soul from the outside, but is
created with and in the body. Its substance is as pure as that of the celestial
spheres, receiving its light like them, but is much finer than the substance of
the spheres, for the latter are not rational, whereas the soul is. The soul is
not dependent for its knowledge upon the body, which without the latter has
neither life nor knowledge, but it uses the body as an instrument for its
functions. When connected with the body the soul has three faculties, reason,
spirit and desire. But we must not think with Plato that these powers form so
many divisions or parts of the soul, residing in different parts of the body.
All the three faculties belong to the one soul whose seat is in the heart; for
from the heart issue the arteries, which give the body sense and motion.
The soul
was put in the body because from its nature it cannot act by itself; it must
have the body as its instrument in order thereby to attain to perfect
happiness, for the soul’s functions either purify or defile it. When the soul
leaves the body she can no longer repent; all this must be done while she is in
the body. Being placed in the body is therefore a good for the soul. If she
were left alone, there would be no use in her existence or in that of the body,
and hence the entire creation would be in vain, which was made for the sake of
man. To ask why was not the soul made so as to be independent of the body is
foolish and tantamount to saying why was not the soul made something else than
soul. The soul is not in any way harmed by being with the body, for the injury
of sin is due to her own free will and not to the body. Moreover, the body is
not unclean, nor are the fluids of the body unclean while in the body; some of
them are declared in the Bible to cause uncleanness when they leave the body,
but this is one of those ordinances which, as we shall see later, are not
demanded by the reason for their own sake, but are specially commanded for a
different purpose. As for the sufferings which the soul undergoes by reason of
her connection with the body, some are due to her own negligence, such as cold,
heat, and so on, others are inflicted by God for the soul's own good so that
she may be later rewarded.
We see
here, and we shall learn more definitely later, that Saadia is opposed to the
view of the ascetics—a view Neo-Platonic in its origin—that matter and body as
such are evil, and that the constant effort of man must be to free the soul
from the taint of the body in which it is imprisoned, and by which it is
dragged down from its pristine nobility and purity. Saadia’s opposition to the
belief in the pre-existence of the soul at once does away with the Neo-Platonic
view that the soul was placed in the body as a punishment for wrongdoing. The
soul was created at the same time with the body, and the two form a natural
unit. Hence complete life involves both body and soul.
We have
seen that God's creation of the world is due to his goodness. His first act of
kindness was that he gave being to the things of the world. He showed himself
especially beneficent to man in enabling him to attain perfect happiness by
means of the commandments and prohibitions which were imposed upon him. The
reward consequent upon obedience was the real purpose of the commandments.
The laws
which God gave us through the prophets consist of two groups. The first
embraces such acts as our reason recognizes to be right or wrong, good or bad,
through a feeling of approval or disapproval which God planted in our minds.
Thus reason demands that a benefactor should receive in return for his goodness
either a kind reward if he needs it, or thanks if he needs no reward. As this
is a general demand of the reason, God could not have neglected it in his own
case, and hence the commandments that we should serve him, that we should not
offend or revile him and the other laws bearing on the same subject.
It is
likewise a demand of the reason that one should prevent the creatures from
sinning against one another in any way. Murder is prohibited because it would
lead to the destruction of the race and the consequent frustration of God’s
purpose in creating the world. Promiscuous association of the sexes is
prohibited in order that man may be different from the lower animals, and shall
know his father and other relatives that he may show them honor and kindness.
Universal stealing would lead to indolence, and in the end would destroy itself
when there is nothing more to steal. In a similar way we can explain all laws
relating to social dealings among mankind.
The
second group of laws has reference to acts which are inherently neither right
nor wrong, but are made so by the act of God’s commandment or prohibition. This
class may be called Traditional in contrast to the first, which we shall name
Rational.
The
traditional laws are imposed upon us primarily so that we may be rewarded for
obeying them. At the same time we shall find on careful examination of these
laws that they also have a rational signification, and are not purely
arbitrary. Thus the purpose of sanctifying certain days of the year, like
Sabbaths and holy days, is that by resting from labor we may devote ourselves
to prayer, to the acquisition of wisdom, and to converse with our fellows in
the interest of religion. Laws of ceremonial purity have for their purpose to
teach man humility, and to make prayer and the visitation of holy places more
precious in his eyes after having been debarred from his privileges during the
period of his uncleanness.
It is
clear that we should not know how to perform the traditional commandments
without divine revelation since our own reason would not have suggested them.
But even in the case of the rational laws the general principles alone are
known to us from our own reason but not the details. We know in general that
theft, unchastity, and so on, are wrong, but the details of these matters would
lead to disagreement among mankind, and hence it was necessary that the
rational laws also be directly communicated to us by divine messengers.
The
divine messengers are the prophets. They knew that their revelations came from God
through a sign which appeared at the beginning of the communication and lasted
to the end. The sign was a pillar of cloud or of fire, or an extraordinary
bright light, as we learn in the case of Moses.
The
genuineness of a prophet’s message is tested first of all by the nature of the
content, and then by his ability to perform miracles. The Israelites would not
have believed Moses, notwithstanding his miracles, if he had commanded them to
commit murder or adultery. It is because his teaching was found acceptable to
the reason that the miracles accompanying it were regarded as a confirmation of
Moses’s divine mission.
The
Jewish Law contains three elements, all of which are necessary for effective
teaching. First, the commandments and prohibitions, or the laws proper; second,
the reward and punishment consequent upon obedience and disobedience; and
third, examples of historical characters in which the laws and their consequences
are illustrated.
But the
written law would not accomplish its purpose without belief in tradition. This
is fundamental, for without it no individual or society can exist. No one can
live by what he perceives with his own senses alone. He must depend upon the
information he receives from others. And while this information is liable to
error either by reason of the informant being mistaken or his possible purpose
to deceive, these two possibilities are eliminated in case the tradition is
vouched for not by an individual, but by a whole nation, as in the case of the
Jewish revelation.
As
Saadia’s emphasis on tradition, apart from its intrinsic importance for
Judaism, has its additional motive in refuting Karaism, so the following
discussion against the possibility of the Law being abrogated is directed no
doubt against the claims of the two sister religions, Christianity and
Mohammedanism.
Abrogation
of the law, Saadia says, is impossible. For in the first place tradition has
unanimously held to this view, and in the second place the Law itself assures
us of its permanent validity, “Moses commanded us a law, an inheritance for the
assembly of Jacob” (Deut. 33, 4). The law constitutes the national existence of
our people; hence as we are assured by the Prophets that the Jewish nation is
eternal, the Law must be likewise. We must not even accept the evidence of
miracles in favor of a new law abrogating the old. For as we saw before, it was
not primarily Moses’s miracles that served to authenticate his teaching, but
the character of the teaching itself. Now that the law of Moses stood the test
of internal acceptability and external confirmation by the performance of
miracles, its declaration of permanent validity cannot be upset by any new
evidence even if it be miraculous.
Man alone
of all created things was given commandments and prohibitions, because he is
superior to all other creatures by reason of the rational faculty which he
possesses, and the world was created for him. Man's body is small, but his mind
is great and comprehensive. His life is short, but it was given him to assist
him to the eternal life after death. The diseases and other dangers to which he
is subject are intended to keep him humble and God-fearing. The appetites and
passions have their uses in the maintenance of the individual and the race.
If it is
true that God gave man commandments and that he rewards and punishes him
according to his conduct, it follows that unless we attribute injustice to God
he must have given man the power to do and to refrain in the matters which form
the subject of the commandments. This is actually the case and can be proven in
many ways. Everyone is conscious of freedom in his actions, and is not aware of
any force preventing him in his voluntary acts. The Bible testifies to this
when it says (Deut. 30, 19), “I have set before you life and death ...
therefore choose thou life”, or (Malachi 1, 9), “From your hand has this thing
come”. Tradition is equally explicit in the statement of the Rabbis (Berakot
33b), “Everything is in the hands of God except the fear of God”. To be sure
God is omniscient and knows how a given individual will act in a given case,
but this does not take away from the freedom of the individual to determine his
own conduct. For God's knowledge is not the cause of a man’s act, or in general
of a thing’s being. If that were so, all things would be eternal since God
knows all things from eternity. God simply knows that man will choose of his
own free will to do certain things. Man as a matter of fact never acts contrary
to God’s knowledge, but this is not because God’s knowledge determines his act,
but only because God knows the final outcome of a man’s free deliberation.
Since it
is now clear from every point of view that God does not interfere with a man’s
freedom of action, any passages in the Bible which seem to indicate the
contrary are not properly understood, and must needs be interpreted in
accordance with the evidence we have adduced from various sources including the
Bible itself. Thus when God says (Exod. 7, 3) “I will harden the heart of
Pharaoh”, it does not mean, as many think, that God forced Pharaoh to refuse to
let Israel go. The meaning rather is that he gave Pharaoh strength to withstand
the plagues without succumbing to them, as many of the Egyptians did. The same
method should be followed with all the other expressions in the Bible which
appear to teach determinism.
A man’s
conduct has an influence upon the soul, making it pure or impure as the case
may be. Though man cannot see this effect, since the soul is an intellectual
substance, God knows it. He also keeps a record of our deeds, and deals out
reward and punishment in the world to come. This time will not come until he
has created the number of souls which his wisdom dictates. At the same time
there are also rewards and punishments in this world as an earnest of what is
to come in the hereafter.
A man is
called righteous or wicked according as his good or bad deeds predominate. And
the recompense in the next world is given for this predominating element in his
character. A righteous man is punished for his few bad deeds in this world, and
rewarded for his many good deeds in the world to come. Similarly the wicked man
is paid for his good deeds in this world, while the punishment for his
wickedness is reserved. This answers the old problem of the prosperity of the
wicked and the misery of the righteous in this world.
There are
also sufferings of the righteous which are not in the nature of punishment for
past conduct, but in view of the future so as to increase their reward in the
world to come for the trials they endured without murmuring. The sufferings of
little children come under this head.
On the
other hand, a sinner is sometimes well treated and his life prolonged for one
of the following reasons: To give him time to repent, as in the case of
Manasseh; that he may beget a righteous son, like Ahaz, the father of Hezekiah;
to use him as God's tool to punish others more wicked than he—witness the rôle
of Assyria as Isaiah describes it in chapter ten of his prophecies; for the
sake of the righteous who is closely related to him, as Lot was saved for the
sake of Abraham; or in order to make the punishment more severe later, as in
the case of Pharaoh.
That
there is another world after this one in which man is rewarded and punished can
be proved from reason, from Scripture and from tradition. It is not likely from
what we know of God's wisdom and goodness that the measure of happiness
intended for the soul is what it gets in this world. For every good here is
mixed with evil, the latter even predominating. No one is really content and at
peace in this world even if he has reached the top of the ladder of prosperity
and honor. There must be a reason for this, which is that the soul has an intuitional
longing for the other world which is destined for it. There are many things
from which the soul is bidden to abstain, such as theft, adultery, and so on,
which it desires, and abstention from which causes it pain. Surely there must
be reward awaiting the soul for this suffering. Often the soul suffers hatred,
persecution and even death for pursuing justice as she is bidden to do. Surely
she will be rewarded. Even when a person is punished with death for a crime
committed in this world, the same death is inflicted for one crime as for ten
crimes. Hence there must be another world where all inequalities are adjusted.
It is
also evident that the men of the Bible believed in a hereafter. Else why should
Isaac have consented to be sacrificed, or why should God have expected it? The
same applies to Hananiah, Mishael, and Azariah, who preferred to be thrown into
the fiery furnace rather than fall down in worship before the golden image of
Nebuchadnezzar; and to Daniel who was thrown into the den of lions for
disobeying the order of the king and praying to God. They would not have done
this if they did not believe in another world, where they would be rewarded for
their sufferings in this one.
Tradition
and the Rabbinical literature are filled with reference to a future world. We
need mention only one or two. In the Ethics of the Fathers we read that this
world is like the vestibule to the other world. Another statement in the
Talmudic treatise Berakot reads that “in the world to come there is no eating
and drinking, nor giving in marriage, nor buying and selling, but the righteous
sit with their crowns on their heads and enjoy the splendor of the Shekinah”.
With
regard to the condition of the soul after death and the nature of reward and
punishment in the next world, there is a variety of opinions. Those who hold
that the soul is corporeal or that it is an accident of the body believe it is
destroyed with the death of the body. We have already refuted their opinion.
Others, like the Platonists, the Dualists and the Pantheists, who believe in
the preexistence of the soul either as a separate entity or as a part of God,
hold that after the death of the body the soul returns to its original
condition. Our belief as stated above is opposed to this. But there are some
calling themselves Jews who believe in metempsychosis, that the soul migrates
from one person to another and even from man to beast, and that in this way it
is punished for its sins and purged. They see a confirmation of their view in
the fact that some persons exhibit qualities which are characteristic of lower
animals. But this is absurd. The soul and the body form a natural unit, the one
being adapted to the other. A human body cannot unite with the soul of an
animal, nor an animal body with a human soul. They try to account by their
theory for the suffering of little children, who could not have sinned in their
own person. But we have already explained that the suffering of children is not
in the nature of punishment, but with a view to subsequent reward, and they
must admit that the first placing of the soul in the body and giving it
commandments is not in the nature of compensation for any past merit, but with
a view to later reward. Why not then explain the suffering of children in the
same way?
As the
body and the soul form a natural unit during life and a man's conduct is the
combined effort of the two constituent parts of his being, it stands to reason
that future reward and punishment should be imposed upon body and soul in
combination. Hence the doctrine of the resurrection of the body, which is
alluded to in the Bible and made into a religious dogma by the Rabbis, has
support also in the reason. Many objections have been advanced against it, but
they can be easily answered. The strongest objection might seem to be that
which attempts to show that resurrection is a logical contradiction. The
argument is that the elements making up a given body during life find their way
after the death of the person into the body of another, to which they are assimilated
and of which they form a part. Hence it is impossible to resurrect two bodies
out of the material common to both. But this argument is untrue to fact. Every
human body has its own matter, which never enters into the composition of any
other body. When the person dies and the body decomposes, each element returns
to its place in nature, where it is kept until the resurrection.
But there
is another event which will happen to Israel before the time of the
resurrection. In accordance with the promises of the Prophets we believe that
Israel will be delivered from exile by the Messiah. Reason also supports this
belief, for God is righteous, and since he has placed us in exile partly as a
punishment for wrongdoing, partly for the purpose of trying us, there must be a
limit to both.
Messiah
the son of David will come, will deliver Jerusalem from the enemy and settle
there with his people. When all the believing Israelites have been gathered
from all the nations to the land of Palestine, then will come the resurrection.
The Temple will be rebuilt, the light of the Shekinah will rest upon it, and
the spirit of prophecy will be vouchsafed to all Israel, young and old, master
and servant. This blessed period will last until the end of time, i. e., until this world will give place
to the next, which is the place of reward and punishment.
We
describe the future habitation and status of the soul as Garden of Eden
(Paradise) and Gehenna. The former expression is intended to suggest happiness,
there being nothing pleasanter in the world than a garden. The term Gehenna is
associated in the Bible with Tofteh, which was a place of impurity not far from
the Temple. In reality, however, God will create a substance which will combine
light and heat in such a way that the righteous will enjoy the light only,
while the wicked will be tortured by the heat. All this Saadia infers from
Biblical passages.
There
will be no eating and drinking in the next world, and hence no need of a heaven
and an earth like ours, but there will be place and time, since creatures
cannot do without it. There will be no succession of day and night, for these
are of use only for our present life and occupations, but will be unnecessary
there. There will, however, be a special period for worship.
Reward
and punishment in the next world will both be eternal. It stands to reason that
God should promise eternal reward and punishment so as to inspire mankind with
the highest possible degree of hope and fear, that they may have no excuse for
not heeding the commandments so forcibly impressed upon them. Having made the
promise, his justice prompts him to fulfil it, and those who suffer have
themselves to blame.
We have now
completed in outline Saadia’s system of Judaism. There are many details which
we necessarily had to leave out, especially in the more dogmatic part of his
work, that dealing with specific Jewish doctrines, which he constructs on the
basis of Rabbinical literature and Biblical allusions interpreted so as to
harmonize with the statements of the Rabbis. Many questions specifically
theological and eschatological assumed importance in his mind by reason of his
surroundings. I mean the Mohammedan schools and sects, and the Karaite
discussions which were closely modelled after them. The most important part of
his system philosophically is that which deals with creation and the attributes
of God. His discussions of the soul and of free will are less thorough, and the
details of his doctrines of resurrection, future reward and punishment, the
redemption of Israel and the Messiah are almost purely dogmatic. For a
scientific ethic there is no room at all in the body of his work. A man's
conduct is prescribed for him in the divine commandments, though in a general
way the reason sees the right and the wrong of the so-called rational group of
laws. Still as an afterthought Saadia added a chapter to the “Emunot ve-Deot”
in which he attempts to give a psychological basis for human conduct. Noting
the various tendencies of individuals and sects in his environment to extremes
in human behavior, some to asceticism, some to self-indulgence, be it the lust
of love or of power, he lays emphasis on the inadequacy of any one pursuit for
the demands of man’s complex nature, and recommends a harmonious blending of all
things for which men strive.
God
alone, he says, is a real unity, everything else is by the very reason of its
being a creature essentially not one and simple, but composite and complex. So
man has a love and desire for many things, and also aversion for many things.
And as in other objects in nature it takes a combination of several elements to
constitute a given thing, so in man it is by a proper systematization of his
likes and dislikes that he can reach perfection of character and morals. It
cannot be that God intended man to pursue one object all his life to the
exclusion of all others, for in that case he would have implanted only one
desire in man instead of many. You cannot build a house of stones alone neither
can you develop a perfect character by one pursuit and one interest.
Pursuit
of one thing is likely to result in harm, for example, over-indulgence in eating
brings on disease. Wisdom is therefore needed in regulating one's conduct. The
principle here is control of one's likes and dislikes. Of the three faculties
of the soul, reason, spirit and desire, reason must be the master of the other
two. If any matter occurs to a person’s imagination, he must try it with his
reason to see whether it is likely to benefit or injure him, and pursue or
avoid it accordingly. If, on the other hand, he allows the lower parts of his
soul to rule his reason, he is not a moral man.
The
reader will recognize Plato in the last statement. The division of the soul
into the three faculties of reason, spirit and desire is Platonic, as we have
already seen, and the attempt to base an ethic on the proper relation between
the powers of the soul also goes back to Plato. But Saadia tries to show that
the Bible too favors this conception.
When
Ecclesiastes tells us (1, 14), “I have seen all the works that are done under
the sun; and, behold, all is vanity and a striving after wind”, he does not
mean that there is nothing worth striving after, for he would then be
condemning the objects of God’s creation. His meaning is that it is vain to
pursue any one thing to the exclusion of every other. He then proceeds to name
three prominent objects of pursuit, wisdom, pleasure and worldly gain—all is
vain when taken by itself. A proper combination of all is to be recommended as
is delicately hinted in the same book (2, 3), “I searched in mine heart how to
cheer my flesh with wine, mine heart yet guiding me with wisdom, and how to lay
hold on folly”.
JOSEPH AL-BASIR AND JESHUA BEN JUDAH
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|