HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHY
ISAAC HUSIK
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER IV.
I. Joseph
Al-Basir (11th century)
Joseph
ben Abraham, euphemistically surnamed on account of his blindness, al-Basir
(the seer), was a Karaite and lived in Babylonia or Persia in the beginning of
the eleventh century. His philosophical work is closely modelled on the
writings of the Arabian Mutakallimun, the Mutazilites. Unlike Saadia, who
tacitly accepts some of their methods and views, al-Basir is an avowed follower
of the Kalam and treats only of those questions which are common to Jew and
Mohammedan, avoiding, for example, so important an issue as whether it is
possible that the law of God may be abrogated—a question which meant so much to
Saadia. The division of his investigation into the two parts, Unity and
Justice, is a serious matter with him; and he finds it necessary to tell us in
several instances why he chose to treat a given topic under the one or the
other heading. In spirit and temperament he is a thoroughgoing rationalist.
Brief and succinct to the point of obscurity, he betrays neither partiality nor
emotion, but fearlessly pushes the argument to its last conclusion and reduces
it to its lowest terms.
Saadia
puts revelation as a fourth source of truth parallel to sense, judgment and
logical inference. To be sure he, in one instance, speaks of the reason as
preceding the Bible even as tradition follows it, but this is only a passing
observation, and is properly corrected by the view expressed elsewhere that
while a Jew is not forbidden to speculate, he must not set the Bible aside and
adopt opinions as they occur to him. Al-Basir does not leave the matter in this
unsettled condition. He definitely gives priority—logical priority, to reason.
Knowledge, he says, must precede revelation. The prophet as the messenger of
God cannot be believed on his word, for the opponent may have the same claim.
Not only must the prophet authenticate his mission by the performance of a
miracle which cannot be explained by natural means, but we must know besides
that he who sent him has our good at heart and would not deceive us. A
knowledge of the existence, power and wisdom of the creator must therefore precede
our belief in the prophet’s mission. To take these truths from the words of the
prophet and then give him credence because God sent him would be reasoning in a
circle. The minimum of knowledge therefore which is indispensable before we can
make any appeal to the words of the prophet is rational proof of the existence,
power and wisdom of God. Having this minimum the person who is not practiced in
speculative investigation may rely for the rest of the creed, for example, the
unity of God and his other attributes, upon the words of the Bible. For if we know
independently that God is Omnipotent and Omniscient, and the prophet can
substantiate his claim to be a divine messenger by the performance of genuine
miracles, his reliability is established and we are safe in accepting all that
he has to say without proof; but the fundamental thing to do is to establish
the prophet’s reliability, and for this an independent source of evidence is necessary.
This is the reason.
Our
problem therefore is to prove the power and wisdom of God, which will imply his
existence. We cannot do this directly, for we cannot see God. Hence the only
method is to prove the existence of a powerful and wise creator through his
creation. We must prove his power in doing things which we cannot do, such as
the ability to create our bodies. But for this it is necessary to show that our
bodies—and the same will apply to the other bodies of the world, and hence to
the world as a whole—were created, i. e., that there was a time when they were
not. This leads us to an analysis of the constituents of body. All bodies
consist of atoms and their “accidents”, or conditions and qualities. The
primary accidents, which are presupposed by all the rest, are the following
four, combination, separation, motion and rest. Without these no body can
exist, for body is the result of a combination and separation of atoms at rest
or in motion. But combination and separation are the acts of a combiner and
separater, as we can infer from the analogy of our own acts. Our acts have
ourselves as their creators, hence the acts visible in the combinations and
separations of atoms to form bodies must also have their creator.
The
attributes of the creator we infer from the nature of his work. So we call God “Powerful”,
meaning that he had the power to create the world. As creation denotes power,
so the success and harmony of the product argues wisdom; and this power and
wisdom thus established are not disproved by an occasional production or event
which is not perfect, a monstrosity for example, or disease and suffering. We say
in reference to these that God must have a deeper object in view, to inspire
mankind with the fear of God, and in order to increase their reward in the next
world.
The
attribute of Life follows from the other two, for life denotes the possession
or capacity of power and knowledge.
Thus
al-Basir has the same three essential attributes as Saadia. His proof of the
existence of God is also identical with one of the proofs of Saadia. But he
shows himself a more loyal follower of the Kalam by frankly adopting the atomic
theory, whereas Saadia opposes it .
Other
predicates of God are perception, will, unity, incorporeality and eternity.
Perception
is one of the most important expressions of life, but it must not be confused
with knowledge or wisdom. The latter embraces the non-existent as well as the
existent, the former the existent only. It is in virtue of the former attribute
that we speak of God as “hearing” and “seeing”.
“Willing”
is another attribute of God, and those are wrong who identify God’s will with
his knowledge, and define God’s willing to mean that his works take place in
accordance with his knowledge. God’s will must be a special attribute since we
see in creation traces of free will. To be the will of God it must not reside
in anything different from God, and yet it cannot inhere in God as the subject,
for only body is capable of being the subject of accidents. The only solution,
therefore, is that God exercises his voluntary activity through a will which he
creates, a will not residing in any subject.
This discussion
of the nature of God’s will seems a case of hair splitting with a vengeance,
and al-Basir is not the author of it. As in his other doctrines so in this also
he is a faithful follower of the Mutazila, and we shall see more of this method
in his discussion of the unity of God despite the plurality of his attributes.
But we
shall first take up the attributes of incorporeality and eternity, which can be
dismissed in a few words.
God is
eternal because the only other alternative is that he is created. But if so
there is a creator, and if the latter is again created, he must likewise have a
creator, and so we are led to infinity, which cannot be, the infinite regress
being in all cases an impossibility according to an axiom of the Kalam. We must,
therefore, have an eternal creator somewhere, and he is God.
From
God's eternity follows his incorporeality, for we have shown before that all
body is created, since it presupposes combination and separation, and the latter
a combiner and separater.
When we
speak of the unity of God we mean first that there is no second God, and then
that his own essence has no composition or plurality in it. Two Gods is an
absurdity, for the one might desire what the other does not, and he whose will
predominates is the real God. It is no objection to say that in their wisdom
they would never disagree, because the possibility is there, and this makes the
above argument valid. Again, if there were two Gods they would have to be
completely alike in their essential attributes, and as space cannot hold them
apart, since they are not bodies, what is there to constitute them two?
The other
problem, of God’s simplicity, is more difficult. Does not the multiplicity of
attributes make God’s essence multiple and composite? The form which this
question took was this. Shall we say that God is omnipotent through Power,
omniscient through Knowledge, and so on? If so, this Power, Knowledge, etc.,
are created or eternal. If the Power, say, is created, then God must have had
power in order to create it, hence was powerful not through Power. If the Power
is eternal, we have more than one God, and “Power” as an eternal would also be
Wise and Living, etc.; Wisdom would also be powerful, living, etc., and so on
with the other attributes, a doctrine closely bordering on Christianity and
reminding one of Augustine. The principle of monotheism could not allow such a
conception as this. If Power is neither created nor eternal, it follows that
God is omnipotent not through Power as an external cause or a distinct entity,
but through his own essence. The attributes Power, Wisdom, Life, are not
anything distinguishable from each other and from God's essence. They are modes
or conditions of God's essence, and are known along with it.
The same
considerations which prompted us to conceive God as one and simple, make
impossible the belief in the eternity of God's word. This was a point much
discussed in the Mohammedan schools, and was evidently directed against
Christianity, where the Word or Logos was identified with the second person in
the Trinity. Eternity, Al-Basir says, is incompatible with the idea and purpose
of speech. God speaks with a word which he creates. This adds no new predicate
to God, but is implied in his Power. The attribute omnipotent implies that when
he wills he can make himself understood by us as we do through speech.
We notice
that Al-Basir is more elaborate in his discussion of the attributes than
Saadia, and like Al-Mukammas he makes use of the formulae of the Kalam, “omnipotent
not with Power, omniscient not with Wisdom”. Saadia does not follow the Kalam
so closely, but is just as emphatic in his endeavor to show that the three
essential attributes are only verbally three; conceptually and really they are
one.
The
doctrine of the attributes brings to a close the section on unity, and the
second division of the investigation is entitled Justice and Fairness. The main
problems here are the nature of good and evil and the relation of God to them,
the question of free will and other subordinate topics, theological and
eschatological.
With
regard to the first question two extreme positions are possible, which were
actually held by Mohammedan schools of Al-Basir's day. One is that nothing is
good or bad in itself, our reason not recognizing it as such; that the divine
command or prohibition makes the thing good or bad. Hence, the representatives
of this opinion say, God, who stands above his commands and prohibitions, is
not bound by them. Good and bad hold for the subject, not for the author. The
acts of God do not come within the classification, and hence it is possible
that God may do what we regard as injustice. Some, in their endeavor to be
consistent and to carry the argument to its last conclusion, did not even
shrink from the reductio ad absurdum that it is possible God may lie; for, said they, if I promise a boy sweetmeats
and fail to keep my promise, it is no worse than if I beat him.
For this
school there is no problem of evil, because ethical distinctions do not apply
to God’s doings. Whatever God does is good. The other school came under the
influence of Greek thought and identified the idea of God with the idea of the
Good. They maintained that from the nature of God's essence it was not only his
duty to do the good, but that it was impossible for him to do anything else.
Doing good is a necessity of his nature, and our good and evil are also his
good and evil. Ethical values are absolute and not relative.
Neither
of these radical views can be maintained. The first is refuted by its own
consequences which only very few of its advocates were bold enough to adopt.
The possibility of God telling a falsehood, which is implied in the purely
human validity of good and evil, is subversive of all religion. God would then
cease to be trustworthy, and there would be no reason for giving him obedience.
Besides, if revelation alone determines right and wrong, it would follow that
if God chose to reverse his orders, our moral judgments would be turned the
other way around, good would be evil, and evil good. Finally, if good and bad
are determined by the will of God only, those who do not believe in revelation
would be without an idea of right and wrong, but this is manifestly not true.
But the
other opinion, that God is compelled by the necessity of his nature to do the
good, is also erroneous. In the first place it detracts from God's omnipotence
to say he cannot do wrong. Besides, if he is compelled by an inner necessity to
do the good, he must always have done this, and the world would have existed
from eternity. It is just as wrong to say that it is the duty of God to do what
is good and useful for man. For this is due to a confusion of the good or
generous with the obligatory. Any deed to which no blame attaches may be called
good. If no praise attaches to it either, it is indifferent. If it is deserving
of praise and its omission does not call forth blame, it is a generous act. A
duty is an act the omission of which deserves blame.
Now the
truth in the question under discussion is midway between the two extremes. God
is able to do good as well as evil, and is under no necessity. The notions of
right and wrong are absolute and not merely relative. God never does wrong
because evil has no attractive power per se. Wrong is committed always as a
means to an end, namely, to gain an advantage or avoid an injury. God is not
dependent upon anything; he needs no advantages and fears no injuries. Hence
there is nothing to prompt him to do wrong. The good on the other hand attracts
us by its inherent goodness, not for an ulterior end. If the good were done
only for the sake of deriving some benefit external to the good itself, God,
who is self-sufficient, would not do anything either good or evil. God does the
good always and not the bad, because in his wisdom he sees the difference
between them. It was a deed of generosity in God to have created the world and
given life to his creatures, but it was not a duty.
This
conception of the nature of good and evil leaves on our hands the problem of
evil. Why does a good God permit disease and suffering to exist in the world?
In particular, how explain the suffering and death of innocent children and
harmless animals?
The
answer of Al-Basir is that infliction of pain may under certain circumstances
be a good instead of an evil. In human relations a person is permitted to
inflict pain on another in self-defence, or to prevent the pain from becoming
worse, as, for example, when a finger is amputated to save the hand. The
infliction of pain is not only permitted, it becomes a duty in case of
retribution, as in a court of justice; and finally it is permitted to inflict
temporary pain if it will result in a greater advantage in the future. The last
two cases apply also to God's treatment of his creatures. Disease and suffering
are either punishment for offences committed, or are imposed with a view to
later reward. In the case of children the last explanation alone is applicable.
They will be rewarded in the next world. At the same time the parents are
admonished to repentance and good conduct.
The most
difficult question of the section on justice is that of free will and
foreknowledge. Is man master of his actions? If so, how can we reconcile this
with God's omniscience, who knows beforehand how the person will act at a given
moment? Is man free to decide at the last moment in a manner contrary to God’s
knowledge? If so, we defend freedom at the expense of God's omniscience. If man
is bound to act as God foreknew he would act, divine knowledge is saved, man's
freedom lost. Al-Basir has no doubt man is free. Our own consciousness
testifies to this. When we cut off our finger bitten by a snake, we know that
we ourselves did it for a purpose, and distinguish it from a case of our finger
being cut off by order of an official, before whom we have been accused or
maligned. One and the same act can have only one author and not two, and we
know that we are the authors of our acts. There is a much closer connection
between an agent and his act than between a knower and his knowledge, which may
be the common property of many, and no one doubts that a man's knowledge is his
own.
The
dilemma above mentioned with its two horns, of which one denies God's
knowledge, the other man's freedom, is puzzling enough, to be sure. But we are
not bound to answer it since it is purely hypothetical. We do not know of a
real instance in which a man's decision tended to be contrary to God's
foreknowledge of its outcome. Just as we should refuse to answer the question
whether an actual case of injustice on the part of God would prove his
ignorance or dependence, because we know through irrefutable proofs that God is
wise and without need; so here we say man has freedom though God knows he will
act thus and so, and refuse to say whether in case the unbeliever turned
believer it would prove God's ignorance or change in his knowledge.
God's
creation was a pure act of grace. But once having done this and communicated to
us a knowledge of himself and his will, it is now his duty to guide us in the
right path, by sending us his prophets. The commandments and prohibitions must
never be contrary to the knowledge of reason. We must see in the commandments
means of guidance, in the prohibitions a protection against destructive
influences. If they had not this rational basis, we do not see why God should
have imposed them upon us.
Having
given us reason to know his being, and having announced his truth through the
prophets, it is his duty to reward those who knew him and were obedient,
eternally in the next world, and to punish eternally the unbeliever. If one has
merits and sins, they are balanced against each other. If the sinner repents of
his evil deeds, it is the duty of God to accept his repentance and remit his
punishment.
2. Jeshua
ben Judah
Jeshua
ben Judah or, as he is known by his Arabic name, Abu al-Faraj Furkan ibn Asad,
was likewise a Karaite, a pupil of Joseph Al-Basir, and flourished in Palestine
in the second half of the eleventh century. His point of view is essentially
the same as that of his teacher, Al-Basir. He is also a follower of the Mutazilite
Kalam and as strong a rationalist as his master. He agrees with Al-Basir that
we cannot get certain knowledge of the creation of the world and the existence
of God from the Bible. This information must come originally from rational
speculation. It should then be applied to the miracles of the prophets so as to
prove the authenticity of their mission and the truth of their announcements.
He adopts
the atomic theory, though he is opposed to the view that atoms are created ever
anew by God from moment to moment, and that there is no natural and necessary
sequence or continuity in the phenomena of the world or qualities of bodies,
all being due to habit, and custom induced in us by God's uninterrupted creations.
As in his philosophical discussions he is a follower of the Kalam, so in his
legalistic works he is indebted to the Mohammedan schools of religious law.
Like
Al-Basir, Jeshua ben Judah regards as the corner stone of his religious
philosophy the proof that the world was created, i. e., that it is not eternal. His arguments are in essence the
same, though differently formulated. In their simplest form they are somewhat
as follows. The world and its bodies consist of atoms and their accidents.
Taking a given atom for the sake of argument we know that it is immaterial to
it, so far as its own essence is concerned, whether it occupy one place or
another. As a fact, however, it does occupy a definite place at a given moment.
This must be due to a cause. And as the atom in question in the course of time
changes its place, this shows that the cause which kept it in the former place
has disappeared and given way to a new cause, and so on. In other words, the
successive causes which determine the positions and motions of the atoms are
not permanent, hence not eternal but created. The necessary inference is that
the atoms or the bodies, which cannot exist without these created causes (else
they could not occupy one place rather than another), must also be created.
Another
form of the argument for creation is this. The eternal has no cause. It exists
by virtue of its own essence, and is not dependent on anything else. If now the
atoms were eternal, they would have to persist in the same condition all the
time; for any change would imply a cause upon which the atom is dependent, and
this is fatal to its eternity. But the atoms do constantly change their
condition and place. Hence they are created.
If the
things of the world are created, someone must have created them. This is clear.
But there may be room for the supposition that this creative agency is a “cause”, i. e., an impersonal entity, which by
necessity produces other things from itself. Hence we must hasten to say that
this conception of the Creator is impossible because incompatible with our
results so far. A necessarily producing cause cannot be without creating, hence
an eternal cause implies an eternal effect—which contradicts our idea of a
created world proved above. We say, therefore, that the Creator is not a “cause”
but an “agent”, i. e., one acting
with will and choice.
God is
incorporeal because body consists of atoms, and atoms, we have shown, are
created. Besides, if he were corporeal, he could not create bodies any more
than we can. He would furthermore be limited to a definite place, and the same
arguments cited above to prove that atoms are dependent on a cause would apply
to him. Finally we as corporeal beings cannot exert an influence on objects
except by coming in contact with them. God causes the seed to grow without
being in contact with it. Hence he is not body, and the scriptural passages
apparently teaching the contrary must be explained otherwise.
Jeshua
ben Judah likewise agrees with Al-Basir in regarding the nature of good and
evil as absolute, not relative. Like his master he opposes those who make God's
command and prohibition the sole creators of good and evil respectively, as on
the other hand he refuses to agree with the view that God is bound by necessity
to do the good. Our reason distinguishes between good and evil as our senses
between white and black.
Among
other arguments in favor of the absolute character of right and wrong, which we
have already found in Al-Basir, appears the following. If good and evil mean
simply that which God commands and prohibits respectively, and the distinction
holds only for us but not for God, it follows that God may do what we think is
evil. If this be so, we have no ground for believing in the good faith of the
prophet—God might have sent him to deceive us—and the alleged basis of right
and wrong is removed.
We
conclude therefore that good and evil are absolute and are binding upon God as
well. God can do evil as well as good, but being omnipotent he can accomplish
his purpose just as easily by doing good as by doing evil, and hence surely
prefers to do good. Besides, all evil doing is the result of some need, but God
has no needs, being self-sufficient, hence he does not do evil.
It
follows from the above that God had a purpose in creating the world. For an act
without a purpose is vain and hence bad. This purpose cannot have been
egoistic, since God is without need, being above pleasure and pain. The purpose
must therefore have been the well-being of his creatures.
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|