HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHY
ISAAC HUSIK
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER II
DAVID BEN MERWAN AL MUKAMMAS
Nothing
was known of Al Mukammas until recently when fragments of his philosophical
work were found in Judah ben Barzilai’s commentary on the Sefer Yezirah. The
latter tells us that David Al Mukammas is said to have associated with Saadia,
who learned a good deal from him, but the matter is not certain. If this
account be true we have a second Jewish philosopher who preceded Saadia. His
chief work is known by the title of “Twenty Chapters”, fifteen of which were
discovered in the original Arabic in 1898 by Abraham Harkavy of St. Petersburg.
Unfortunately they have not yet been published, and hence our account will have
to be incomplete, based as it is on the Hebrew fragments in the Yezirah
commentary above mentioned.
These
fragments are sufficient to show us that unlike Israeli, who shows little
knowledge of the Mutazilite discussions, Al Mukammas is a real Mutazilite and
moves in the path laid out by these Mohammedan rationalists. Whether this
difference is due to their places of residence (Israeli having lived in Egypt
and Kairuan, while Al Mukammas was in Babylon), or to their personal
predilections for Neo-Platonism and the Kalam respectively, is not certain.
Saadia knows the Kalam; but though coming originally from Egypt, he spent his
most fruitful years in Babylonia, in the city of Sura, where he was gaon. The
centres of Arabian rationalism were, as we know, the cities of Bagdad and
Basra, nearer to Babylon and Mesopotamia than to Egypt or Kairuan.
The first
quotation in Judah ben Barzilai has reference to science and philosophy, their
definition and classification. Science is the knowledge of the reality of
existing things. It is divided into two parts, theoretical and practical.
Theoretical science aims at knowledge for its own sake; practical seeks an end
beyond knowledge, viz., the production of something. We call it then art. Thus
geometry is a science in so far as one desires to know the nature and relations
to each other of solid, surface, line, point, square, triangle, circle. But if
his purpose is to know how to build a square or circular house, or to construct
a mill, or dig a well, or measure land, he becomes an artisan. Theoretical
science is three-fold. First and foremost stands theology, which investigates
the unity of God and his laws and commandments. This is the highest and most
important of all the sciences. Next comes logic and ethics, which help men in
forming opinions and guide them in the path of understanding. The last is
physics, the knowledge of created things.
In the
ninth and tenth chapters of his book Al Mukammas discusses the divine
attributes. This was a very important problem in the Mutazilite schools, as we
saw in the Introduction, and was treated in Mutazilite works in the first
division, which went by the title of “Bab al Tauhid”, the chapter on the unity.
God is
one—so Al Mukammas sums up the results of his previous discussions—not in the
sense in which a genus is said to be one, nor in that in which a species is
one, nor as the number one is one, nor as an individual creature is one, but as
a simple unity in which there is no distinction or composition. He is one and
there is no second like him. He is first without beginning, and last without
end. He is the cause and ground of everything caused and effected.
The
question of God’s essence is difficult. Some say it is not permitted to ask
what God is. For to answer the question what a thing is, is to limit it, and
the limited is the created. Others again say that it is permitted to make this
inquiry, because we can use in our answer the expressions to which God himself
testifies in his revealed book. And this would not be limiting or defining his glory
because his being is different from any other, and there is nothing that bears
any resemblance to him. Accordingly we should answer the question what God is,
by saying, he is the first and the last, and the visible and the hidden,
without beginning or end. He is living, but not through life acquired from
without. His life is not sustained and prolonged by food. He is wise, but not
through acquired wisdom. He hears without ears, sees without eyes, is
understanding in all his works, and a true judge in all his judgments. Such
would be our answer in accordance with God's own testimony of himself.
We must
on no account suppose that the expressions living, wise, seeing, hearing, and
so on, when applied to God mean the same thing as when we ascribe them to ourselves.
When we say God is living we do not mean that there was a time when he was not
living, or that there will be a time when he will not be living. This is true
of us but not of God. His life has no beginning or end. The same thing applies
to his wisdom. It is not acquired like ours, it has no beginning or end, and is
not subject to error, forgetfulness, addition or diminution. It is not strange
that his attributes should be so unlike ours, for it is fitting that the
Creator should be different from the thing created, and the Maker from the
thing made.
We must,
however, analyze the matter of divine attributes more closely. When we say God
is living, we may mean he is living with life as his attribute, i. e., that there is an attribute life
which makes him living, or we may deny that there is any such attribute in him
as life, but that he is living through himself and not through life as an
attribute. To make this subtle distinction clear we will investigate further
what is involved in the first statement that God is living with life. It may
mean that there was a time when God was not living and then he acquired life
and became living. This is clearly a wrong and unworthy conception. We must
therefore adopt the other alternative, that the life which makes him living is
eternal like him, and hence he was always living from eternity and will
continue to be living to eternity. But the matter is not yet settled. The
question still remains, Is this life through which he lives identical with his
being, or is it distinct from his being, or is it a part of it? If we say it is
distinct from his being, we are guilty of introducing other eternal beings
beside God, which destroys his unity. The Christians are guilty of this very
thing when they say that God's eternal life is the Holy Ghost, and his eternal
Wisdom is the Son. If we say that his life is a part of his being, we do injury
to the other aspect of his unity, namely, his simplicity. For to have parts in
one's being implies composition. We are forced therefore to conclude that God's
life is identical with his being. But this is really tantamount to saying that
there is no attribute life which makes him living, or that he is living not
through life. The difference is only in expression.
We may
make this conception clearer by illustrations from other spheres, inadequate
though they be. The soul is the cause of life to the body, i. e., the body lives through the soul, and when the latter
leaves it, the body loses its life and dies. But the soul itself does not live through
anything else, say through another soul. For if this were the case this other
soul would need again another soul to make it live and this again another, and
so on ad infinitum, which is absurd. The soul lives through itself. The same
thing applies to angels. They live through their own being; and that is why
souls and angels are called in the Sacred Scriptures spirits. A spirit is
something that is fine and light and incomposite. Hence their life cannot be
due to anything distinct from their being, for this would make them composite.
This
statement, however, that souls and angels are living through their own being
must not be understood as meaning that they have no creator who gave them being
and life. The meaning merely is that the being which God gave them is different
from the being he gave to bodies. Bodies need a soul to become living, the soul
is itself living. So in material things, also, the sun shines with its own
light and not with light acquired. The odor of myrrh is fragrant through itself,
not through anything else. The eye sees with its own power, whereas man sees
with the eye. The tongue does not speak with another tongue, man speaks with a
tongue, and so on. So we say of God, though in a manner a thousand-fold more
sublime, that he is living, but not with a life which is distinct from his
being; and so of the other attributes, hearing, seeing, and so on, that we find
in the Scriptural praises of him.
It is
necessary to add that as on the one hand we have seen that God's attributes are
identical with his being, so it follows on the other that the various
attributes, such as wise, seeing, hearing, knowing, and so on, are not
different from each other in meaning, though distinct in expression. Otherwise
it would make God composite. The reason we employ a number of distinct
expressions is in order to remove from God the several opposites of the terms
used. Thus when we say God is living we mean to indicate that he is not dead.
The attribute wise excludes folly and ignorance; hearing and seeing remove
deafness and blindness. The philosopher Aristotle says that it is truer and
more appropriate to apply negative attributes to God than positive. Others have
said that we must not speak of the Creator in positive terms for there is
danger of endowing him with form and resemblance to other things. Speaking of
him negatively we imply the positive without risking offence.
In the
sequel Al Mukammas refutes the views of the dualists, of the Christians and
those who maintain that God has form. We cannot afford to linger over these
arguments, interesting though they be, and must hurry on to say a word about
the sixteenth chapter, which deals with reward and punishment. This no doubt
forms part of the second Mutazilite division, namely, the “Bab al ʿAdl”,
or section concerning God's justice.
He
defines reward as the soul’s tranquillity and infinite joy in the world to come
in compensation for the sojourn in this world which she endured and the
self-control she practiced in abstaining from the pleasures of the world.
Punishment, on the other hand, is the soul's disquietude and sorrow to the end
of days as retribution for indulging in the world's evil pleasures. Both are
imposed by God with justice and fairness. It is fitting that the promises of
reward and threats of punishment consequent upon obedience and disobedience
should be specified in connection with the commandments and prohibitions in the
Scriptures, because this is the only way to train the soul to practice
self-control. A child who does not fear his teacher's punishment, or has no
confidence in his good will will not be amenable to instruction. The same is
true of the majority of those who serve kings. It is fear alone which induces
them to obey the will of their masters. So God in commanding us to do what is
worthy and prohibiting what is unworthy saw fit in his wisdom to specify the
accompanying rewards and punishments that he who observes may find pleasure and
joy in his obedience, and the unobservant may be affected with sorrow and fear.
As the world
to come has no end, so it is proper that the reward of the righteous as well as
the punishment of the wicked should be without end. Arguments have been
advanced to show that unlike reward which is properly infinite as is becoming
to God's goodness, punishment should have a limit, for God is merciful. On the
other hand, it is claimed on the basis of the finiteness of human action that
both reward and punishment should be finite. But in reality it can be shown in
many ways that reward and punishment should be infinite. Without naming all the
arguments—as many as ten have been advanced—in favor of this view, we may urge
some of the more important.
It was
God’s own goodness that prompted him to benefit mankind by giving them laws for
their guidance, and not any prior merits on their part which gave them a claim
on God's protection. God himself is not in any way benefited by man's obedience
or injured by his disobedience. Man knows that it is for his own good that he
is thus admonished; and if he were asked what reward he would like to have for
his good deeds he would select no less than infinite happiness. Justice demands
that punishment be commensurate with reward. The greater the reward and the
punishment the more effective are the laws likely to be. Besides in violating
God’s law a person virtually denies the eternity of him who gave it, and is
guilty of contempt; for he hides himself from men, fearing their displeasure,
whereas the omnipresence of God has no deterring effect upon him. For such
offence infinite punishment is the only fit retribution.
The
question whether the soul alone is rewarded or the body alone or both has been
answered variously. In favor of the soul alone as the subject of reward and
punishment it has been urged that reward raises man to the grade of angels, who
are pure spirits. How then can the body take part? And punishment must be of
the same nature as reward. On the other hand, it is claimed that the Bible says
nothing of man being raised to the status of angels, and we know in this world
of physical reward and punishment only. The Garden of Eden of which the Bible
speaks is not peopled with angels, and that is where the righteous go after
death.
The true
solution is that as man is composed of body and soul, and both share in his conduct,
reward and punishment must attach to both. As we do not understand the nature
of spiritual retribution so the composite is equally inconceivable to us. But
everyone who believes in the resurrection of the dead has no difficulty in
holding that the body has a share in future reward and punishment.
SAADIA BEN JOSEPH AL-FAYYUMI (892-942)
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|