HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
MEDIEVAL JEWISH PHILOSOPHY
ISAAC HUSIK
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER I.
We know
next to nothing about the condition of the Jews in Mohammedan Egypt in the
ninth and tenth centuries. But the fact that the two first Jewish writers who
busied themselves with philosophical problems came from Egypt would indicate
that the general level of intellectual culture among the Jews at that time was
not so low as the absence of literary monuments would lead us to believe. Every
one knows of Saadia, the first Hebrew grammarian, the first Hebrew
lexicographer, the first Bible translator and exegete, the first Jewish
philosopher of medieval Jewry. He was born in Egypt and from there was called
to the Gaonate of Sura in Babylonia. But not so well known is his earlier
contemporary, Isaac ben Solomon Israeli, who also was born in Egypt and from
there went later to Kairuan, where he was court physician to several of the
Fatimide Califs. The dates of his birth and death are not known with certainty,
but he is said to have lived to the age of one hundred years, and to have
survived the third Fatimide Calif Al-Mansur, who died in 953. Accordingly we
may assume the years of his birth and death as 855 and 955 respectively.
His fame
rests on his work in theory and practice as a physician; and as such he is
mentioned by the Arab annalists and historians of medicine. To the Christian
scholastics of medieval Europe he is known as the Jewish physician and
philosopher next in importance to Maimonides. This is due to the accident of
his works having been translated into Latin by Constantinus Afer, and thus made
accessible to men like Albertus Magnus, Vincent of Beauvais, Thomas Aquinas and
others. For his intrinsic merits as a philosopher, and particularly as a Jewish
philosopher, do not by any means entitle him to be coupled with Maimonides. The
latter, indeed, in a letter which he wrote to Samuel Ibn Tibbon, the translator
of the “Guide of the Perplexed”, expresses himself in terms little flattering
concerning Israeli's worth as a philosopher. He is a mere physician, Maimonides
says, and his treatises on the Elements,
and on Definitions consist of windy
imaginings and empty talk. We need not be quite as severe in our judgment, but
the fact remains that Israeli is little more than a compiler and, what is more
to the purpose, he takes no attitude in his philosophical writings to Judaism
as a theological doctrine or to the Bible as its source. The main problem,
therefore, of Jewish philosophy is not touched upon in Israeli’s works, and no
wonder Maimonides had no use for them. For the purely scientific questions
treated by Israeli could in Maimonides’s day be studied to much better
advantage in the works of the great Arabian Aristotelians, Al Farabi and
Avicenna, compared to whom Israeli was mediocre. We are not to judge him,
however, from Maimonides’s point of view. In his own day and generation he was
surpassed by none as a physician; and Saadia alone far outstrips him as a
Jewish writer, and perhaps also David Al Mukammas, of whom we shall speak
later. Whatever may be said of the intrinsic value of the content of his
philosophical work, none can take away from him the merit of having been the
first Jew, so far as we know, to devote himself to philosophical and scientific
discussions, though not with the avowed aim of serving Judaism. The rest was
bound to come later as a result of the impulse first given by him.
The two
works of Israeli which come in consideration for our purpose are those
mentioned by Maimonides in his letter to Samuel Ibn Tibbon spoken of above,
namely, the “Book of the Elements”, and the “Book of Definitions”. Like all
scientific and philosophic works by Jews between the ninth and thirteenth
centuries with few exceptions, these were written in Arabic. Unfortunately,
with the exception of a fragment recently discovered of the “Book of Definitions”,
the originals are lost, and we owe our knowledge of their contents to Hebrew
and Latin translations, which are extant and have been published. We see from
these that Israeli was a compiler from various sources, and that he had a
special predilection for Galen and Hippocrates, with whose writings he shows
great familiarity. He makes use besides of Aristotelian notions, and is
influenced by the Neo-Platonic treatise, known as the “Liber de Causis”, and
derived from a work of Proclus. It is for this reason difficult to characterize
his standpoint, but we shall not go far wrong if we call him a Neo-Platonist,
for reasons which will appear in the sequel.
It would
be useless for us here to reproduce the contents of Israeli’s two treatises,
which would be more appropriate for a history of medieval science. A brief
résumé will show the correctness of this view. In his “Book of the Elements”
Israeli is primarily concerned with a definite physical problem, the definition
of an element, and the number and character of the elements out of which the
sublunar world is made. He begins with an Aristotelian definition of element,
analyzes it into its parts and comes to the conclusion that the elements are
the four well-known ones, fire, air, water, earth. Incidentally he seizes
opportunities now and then, sometimes by force, to discuss points in logic,
physics, physiology and psychology. Thus the composition of the human body, the
various modes in which a thing may come into being, that the yellow and black
galls and the phlegm are resident in the blood, the purpose of phlebotomy, the
substantial character of prime form, that the soul is not an accident, the two
kinds of blood in the body, the various kinds of “accident”, the nature of a “property”
and the manner in which it is caused—all these topics are discussed in the
course of proof that the four elements are fire, air, water, earth, and not
seed or the qualities of heat, cold, dryness and moisture. He then quotes the
definitions of Galen and Hippocrates and insists that though the wording is
different the meaning is the same as that of Aristotle, and hence they all
agree about the identity of the elements. Here again he takes occasion to
combat the atomic theory of the Mutazila and Democritus, and proves that a line
is not composed of points. In the last part of the treatise he refutes contrary
opinions concerning the number and identity of the elements, such as that there
is only one element which is movable or immovable, finite or infinite, namely,
the power of God, or species, or fire, or air, or water, or earth; or that the
number is two, matter and God; or three, matter, form and motion; or six, viz.,
the four which he himself adopts, and composition and separation; or the number
ten, which is the end and completion of number. In the course of this
discussion he takes occasion to define pain and pleasure, the nature of
species, the difference between element and principle. And thus the book draws
to a close. Not very promising material this, it would seem, for the ideas of
which we are in search.
The other
book, that dealing with definitions of things, is more promising. For while
there too we do not find any connected account of God, of the world and of man,
Israeli's general attitude can be gathered from the manner in which he explains
some important concepts. The book, as its title indicates, consists of a series
of definitions or descriptions of certain terms and ideas made use of by
philosophers in their construction of their scheme of the world—such ideas and
terms as Intelligence, science, philosophy, soul, sphere, spirit, nature, and
so on. From these we may glean some information of the school to which Israeli
belongs. And in the “Book of the Elements”, too, some of the episodic
discussions are of value for our purpose.
Philosophy,
Israeli tells us, is self-knowledge and keeping far from evil. When a man knows
himself truly—his spiritual as well as his corporeal aspects—he knows
everything. For in man are combined the corporeal and the spiritual. Spiritual
is the soul and the reason, corporeal is the body with its three dimensions. In
his qualities and attributes—“accidents” in the terminology of Israeli—we
similarly find the spiritual as well as the corporeal. Humility, wisdom and
other similar qualities borne by the soul are spiritual; complexion, stature,
and so on are corporeal. Seeing that man thus forms an epitome, as it were, of
the universe (for spiritual and corporeal substance and accident exhausts the
classes of existence in the world), a knowledge of self means a knowledge of
everything, and a man who knows all this is worthy of being called a
philosopher.
But
philosophy is more than knowledge; it involves also action. The formula which
reveals the nature and aim of philosophy is to become like unto God as far as
is possible for man. This means to imitate the activities of God in knowing the
realities of things and doing what the truth requires. To know the realities of
things one must study science so as to know the various causes and purposes
existing in the world. The most important of these is the purpose of the union
in man of body and soul. This is in order that man may know reality and truth,
and distinguish between good and evil, so as to do what is true and just and
upright, to sanctify and praise the Creator and to keep from impure deeds of
the animal nature. A man who does this will receive reward from the Creator,
which consists in cleaving to the upper soul, in receiving light from the light
of knowledge, and the beauty of splendor and wisdom. When a man reaches this
degree, he becomes spiritual by cleaving to the created light which comes
directly from God, and praising the Creator. This is his paradise and his
reward and perfection. Hence Plato said that philosophy is the strengthening
and the help of death. He meant by this that philosophy helps to deaden all
animal desires and pleasures. For by being thus delivered from them, a man will
reach excellence and the higher splendor, and will enter the house of truth.
But if he indulges his animal pleasures and desires and they become
strengthened, he will become subject to agencies which will lead him astray
from the duties he owes to God, from fear of him and from prayer at the
prescribed time.
We look
in vain in Israeli’s two treatises for a discussion of the existence and nature
of God. Concerning creation he tells us that when God wanted to show his wisdom
and bring everything from potentiality to actuality, he created the world out
of nothing, not after a model (this in opposition to Plato and Philo), nor for
the purpose of deriving any benefit from it or to obviate harm, but solely on
account of his goodness.
But how
did the creation proceed? A fragment from the treatise of Israeli entitled “The
Book of Spirit and Soul” will give us in summary fashion an idea of the manner
in which Israeli conceived of the order and connection of things in the world.
In the
name of the ancients he gives the following account. God created a splendor.
This having come to a standstill and real permanence, a spark of light
proceeded from it, from which arose the power of the rational soul. This is
less bright than the splendor of the Intelligence and is affected with shadow
and darkness by reason of its greater distance from its origin, and the
intervening Intelligence. The rational soul again becoming permanent and fixed,
there issued from it likewise a spark, giving rise to the animal soul. This
latter is endowed with a cogitative and imaginative faculty, but is not
permanent in its existence, because of the two intervening natures between it
and the pure light of God. From the animal soul there likewise issued a
splendor, which produced the vegetative soul. This soul, being so far removed
from the original light, and separated from it by the Intelligence and the
other two souls, has its splendor dimmed and made coarse, and is endowed only
with the motions of growth and nourishment, but is not capable of change of
place. From the vegetative soul proceeds again a splendor, from which is made
the sphere (the heaven). This becomes thickened and materialized so that it is
accessible to the sight. Motion being the nature of the sphere, one part of it
pushes the other, and from this motion results fire. From fire proceeds air;
from air, water; from water, earth. And from these elements arise minerals,
plants and animals.
Here we
recognize the Neo-Platonic scheme of emanation as we saw it in Plotinus, a
gradual and successive emanation of the lower from the higher in the manner of
a ray of light radiating from a luminous body, the successive radiations
diminishing in brightness and spirituality until when we reach the Sphere the
process of obscuration has gone so far as to make the product material and
visible to the physical sense. The Intelligence and the three Souls proceeding
from it in order are clearly not individual but cosmic, just as in Plotinus.
The relation between these cosmic hypostases, to use a Neo-Platonic term, and
the rational and psychic faculties in man Israeli nowhere explains, but we must
no doubt conceive of the latter as somehow contained in the former and
temporarily individualized, returning again to their source after the
dissolution of the body.
Let us
follow Israeli further in his account of the nature of these substances. The
Intelligence is that which proceeds immediately from the divine light without
any immediate agency. It represents the permanent ideas and principles—species
in Israeli’s terminology—which are not subject to change or dissolution. The
Intelligence contains them all in herself eternally and immediately, and
requires no searching or reflection to reach them. When the Intelligence wishes
to know anything she returns into herself and finds it there without requiring
thought or reflection. We can illustrate this, he continues, in the case of a
skilful artisan who, when he wishes to make anything, retires into himself and
finds it there. There is a difference, however, in the two cases, because
Intelligence always knows its ideas without thought or reflection, for it
exists always and its ideas are not subject to change or addition or
diminution; whereas in the smith a difficulty may arise, and then his soul is
divided and he requires searching and thinking and discrimination before he can
realize what he desires.
What has
been said so far applies very well to the cosmic Intelligence, the νοῦς of the
Neo-Platonists. It represents thought as embracing the highest and most
fundamental principles of existence, upon which all mediate and discursive and
inferential thinking depends. Its content corresponds to the Ideas of Plato.
But the further account of the Intelligence must at least in a part of it refer
to the individual human faculty of that name, though Israeli gives us no
indication where the one stops and where the other begins.
He
appeals to the authority of Aristotle for his division of Intelligence into
three kinds. First, the Intelligence which is always actual. This is what has
just been described. Second, the Intelligence which is in the soul potentially
before it becomes actual, like the knowledge of the child which is at first
potential, and when the child grows up and learns and acquires knowledge,
becomes actual. Third, that which is described as the second Intelligence. It
represents that state of the soul in which it receives things from the senses.
The senses impress the forms of objects upon the imagination (φαντασία) which
is in the front part of the head. The imagination, or phantasy, takes them to
the rational soul. When the latter knows them, she becomes identical with them
spiritually and not corporeally.
We have
seen above the Aristotelian distinction between the active intellect and the
passive. The account just given is evidently based upon it, though it modifies
Aristotle's analysis, or rather it enlarges upon it. The first and second
divisions in Israeli's account correspond to Aristotle's active and passive
intellects respectively. The third class in Israeli represents the process of
realization of the potential or passive intellect through the sense stimuli on
the one hand and the influence of the active intellect on the other. Aristotle
seems to have left this intermediate state between the potential and the
eternally actual unnamed. We shall see, however, in our further study of this
very difficult and complicated subject how the classification of the various
intellects becomes more and more involved from Aristotle through Alexander and
Themistius down to Averroes and Levi ben Gerson. It is sufficient for us to see
here how Israeli combines Aristotelian psychology, as later Aristotelian logic
and physics, with Neo-Platonic metaphysics and the theistic doctrine of creation.
But more of this hereafter.
From the
Intelligence, as we have seen, proceeds the rational soul. In his discussion of
the general nature of the three-fold soul (rational, animal and vegetative)
Israeli makes the unhistoric but thoroughly medieval attempt to reconcile
Aristotle’s definition of the soul, which we discussed above, with that of
Plato. The two conceptions are in reality diametrically opposed. Plato's is an
anthropological dualism, Aristotle's, a monism. For Plato the soul is in its
origin not of this world and not in essential unity with the body, which it
controls as a sailor his boat. Aristotle conceives of the relation between soul
and body as one of form and matter; and there is no union more perfect than
that of these two constituent elements of all natural substances. Decomposition
is impossible. A given form may disappear, but another form immediately takes
its place. The combination of matter and form is the essential condition of
sublunar existence, hence there can be no question of the soul entering or
leaving the body, or of its activity apart from the body.
But
Israeli does not seem to have grasped Aristotle’s meaning, and ascribes to him
the notion that the soul is a separate substance perfecting the natural body,
which has life potentially, meaning by this that bodies have life potentially
before the soul apprehends them; and when the soul does apprehend them, it
makes them perfect and living actually. To be sure, he adds in the immediate
sequel that he does not mean temporal before and after, for things are always
just as they were created; and that his mode of expression is due to the impossibility
of conveying spiritual ideas in corporeal terms in any other way. This merely
signifies that the human body and its soul come into being simultaneously. But
he still regards them as distinct substances forming only a passing
combination. And with this pretended Aristotelian notion he seeks to harmonize
that of Plato, which he understands to mean not that the soul enters the body,
being clothed with it as with a garment, and then leaves it, but that the soul
apprehends bodies by clothing them with its light and splendor, and thus makes
them living and moving, as the sun clothes the world with its light and
illuminates it so that sight can perceive it. The difference is that the light
of the sun is corporeal, and sight perceives it in the air by which it is
borne; whereas the light of the soul is spiritual, and intelligence alone can
perceive it, not the physical sense.
Among the
conceptual terms in the Aristotelian logic few play a more important part than
those of substance and accident. Substance is that which does not reside in
anything else but is its own subject. It is an independent existence and is the
subject of accidents. The latter have no existence independent of the substance
in which they inhere. Thus of the ten categories, in which Aristotle embraces
all existing things, the first includes all substances, as for example, man,
city, stone. The other nine come under the genus accident. Quantity, quality,
relation, time, place, position, possession, action, passion—all these
represent attributes which must have a substantial being to reside in. There is
no length or breadth, or color, or before or after, or here or there, and so on
except in a real object or thing. This then is the meaning of accident as a
logical or ontological term, and in this signification it has nothing to do
with the idea of chance. Clearly substance represents the higher category, and
accident is inferior, because dependent and variable. Thus it becomes important
to know in reference to any object of investigation what is its status in this
respect, whether it is substance or accident.
The
nature of the soul has been a puzzle to thinkers and philosophers from time
immemorial. Some thought it was a material substance, some regarded it as
spiritual. It was identified with the essence of number by the Pythagoreans.
And there have not been wanting those who, arguing from its dependence upon
body, said it was an accident and not a substance. Strange to say the
Mutakallimun, defenders of religion and faith, held to this very opinion. But
it is really no stranger than the maintenance of the soul's materiality equally
defended by other religionists, like Tertullian for example, and the opposition
to Maimonides’s spiritualism on the part of Abraham ben David of Posquières.
The Mutakallimun were led to their idea by the atomic theory, which they found
it politic to adopt as more amenable to theological treatment than Aristotle's
Matter and Form. It followed then according to some of them that the
fundamental unit was the material atom which is without quality, and any power
or activity in any atom or group of atoms is a direct creation of God, which
must be recreated every moment in order to exist. This is the nature of
accident, and it makes more manifest the ever present activity of God in the
world. Thus the “substantial” or “accidental” character of the soul is one that
is touched on by most Jewish writers on the subject. And Israeli also refers to
the matter incidentally in the “Book of the Elements”. Like the other Jewish philosophers
he defends its substantiality.
The fact
of its separability from the body, he says, is no proof of its being an
accident. For it is not the separability of an accident from its substance that
makes it an accident, but its destruction, when separated. Thus when a white
substance turns green, the white color is not merely separated from its
substance but ceases to exist. The soul is not destroyed when it leaves the
body.
Another
argument to prove the soul a substance is this. If the soul were an accident it
should be possible for it to pass from the animal body to something else, as
blackness is found in the Ethiopian's skin, in ebony wood and in pitch. But the
soul exists only in living beings.
We find,
besides, that the activity of the soul extends far beyond the body, and acts
upon distant things without being destroyed. Hence it follows that the soul
itself, the agent of the activity, keeps on existing without the body, and is a
substance.
Having
made clear the conception of soul generally and its relation to the body, he
next proceeds to treat of the three kinds of soul. The highest of these is the
rational soul, which is in the horizon of the Intelligence and arises from its
shadow. It is in virtue of this soul that man is a rational being, discriminating,
receptive of wisdom, distinguishing between good and evil, between things
desirable and undesirable, approaching the meritorious and departing from
wrong. For this he receives reward and punishment, because he knows what he is
doing and that retribution follows upon his conduct.
Next to
the rational soul is the animal soul, which arises from the shadow of the
former. Being far removed from the light of Intelligence, the animal soul is
dark and obscure. She has no knowledge or discrimination, but only a dim notion
of truth, and judges by appearance only and not according to reality. Of its
properties are sense perception, motion and change in place. For this reason
the animals are fierce and violent, endeavoring to rule, but without clear
knowledge and discrimination, like the lion who wants to rule over the other
beasts, without having a clear consciousness of what he is doing. A proof that
the animals have only dim notions of things is that a thirsty ass coming to the
river will fly from his own shadow in the water, though he needs the latter for
preserving his life, whereas he will not hesitate to approach a lion, who will
devour him. Therefore the animals receive no reward or punishment (this in
opposition to the Mutakallimun) because they do not know what to do so as to be
rewarded, or what to avoid, in order not to be punished.
The
vegetative soul proceeds from the shadow of the animal soul. She is still
further removed from the light of Intelligence, and still more weighed down
with shadow. She has no sense perception or motion. She is next to earth and is
characterized by the powers of reproduction, growth, nutrition, and the
production of buds and flowers, odors and tastes.
Next to
the soul comes the Sphere (the heaven), which arises in the horizon and shadow
of the vegetative soul. The Sphere is superior to corporeal substances, being
itself not body, but the matter of body. Unlike the material elements, which
suffer change and diminution through the things which arise out of them as well
as through the return of the bodies of plants and animals back to them as their
elements, the spiritual substances (and also the sphere) do not suffer any
increase or diminution through the production of things out of them. For plants
and animals are produced from the elements through a celestial power which God
placed in nature effecting generation and decay in order that this world of
genesis and dissolution should exist. But the splendor of the higher
substances, viz., the three souls, suffers no change on account of the things
coming from them because that which is produced by them issues from the shadow
of their splendor and not from the essence of the splendor itself. And it is
clear that the splendor of a thing in its essence is brighter than the splendor
of its shadow, viz., that which comes from it. Hence the splendor of the
vegetative soul is undoubtedly brighter than that of the sphere, which comes
from its shadow. The latter becomes rigid and assumes a covering, thickness and
corporeality so that it can be perceived by sight. But no other of the senses
can perceive it because, although corporeal, it is near to the higher
substances in form and nobility, and is moved by a perfect and complete motion,
motion in a circle, which is more perfect than other motions and not subject to
influence and change. Hence there is no increase or diminution in it, no
beginning or end, and this on account of the simplicity, spirituality and
permanence of that which moves it. The Intelligence pours of her splendor upon
it, and of the light of her knowledge, and the sphere becomes intelligent and
rational, and knows, without investigation or reflection, the lordship of its
Creator, and that he should be praised and glorified without intermission. For
this reason the Creator assigned to the Sphere a high degree from which it
cannot be removed, and gave it charge of the production of time and the four
seasons of the year, and the month and the day and the hour, and made it ruler
of the production of perishable things in this world of generation and
dissolution, so that the upper souls may find bodies to apprehend, to clothe
with their light, and to make visible in them their activities according to the
determination of God.
The
Sphere by its motion produces the four elements, fire, air, water, earth; and
the combinations of these in various proportions give rise to the minerals,
plants and animals of this world, the highest of whom is man.
That the
elements are those mentioned above and nothing else is proved by the definition
of element and its distinction from “principle”. A principle is something
which, while being the cause of change, and even possibly at the basis of
change, is not itself subject to change. Thus God is undoubtedly the cause of
everything that happens in the world. He may therefore be called a principle of
the world, but he does not enter with his essence the changing things. Hence it
is absurd to speak of God as an element of the sublunar world. Matter, i. e., primary formless matter, does
enter all changing things and is at the basis of all change; but it does not
itself change. Hence matter also is a principle but not an element. An element
is something which is itself a composite of matter and form, and changes its
form to become something else in which, however, it is contained potentially,
not actually. The product ultimately goes back to the element or elements from
which it was made. When we follow this resolution of a given composite into its
elements back as far as we can until we reach a first which is no longer
produced out of anything in the same way as things were produced from it, we
have the element. Such is the nature of fire, air, water, earth. All things are
made from them in the manner above indicated. But there is nothing prior to
them which changes its form to become fire, continues to reside potentially in
fire and returns to its original state by the resolution of fire. The same
applies to the other three.
The
matter is now clear. The elements stand at the head of physical change and take
part in it. Prior to the elements are indeed matter and form, but as logical
principles, not as physical and independent entities. Hence it would seem,
according to Israeli, that matter and form are side-tracked in the gradual
evolution of the lower from the higher. For the elements, he tells us, come from
the motion of the Sphere, the Sphere from the shadow of the Soul, the Soul from
the shadow of the Intelligence, the Intelligence is created by God. To be sure
he tells us that the Sphere is not body, but the matter of body. Yet the Sphere
cannot take the place of prime matter surely, for it is undoubtedly endowed
with form, nay is rational and intelligent, as we have seen.
When
Israeli says that prior to the four elements there is nothing but the
Omnipotence of God, he means that the sublunar process of change and becoming
stops with the elements as its upper limit. What is above the elements belongs
to the intelligible world; and the manner of their production one from the
other is a spiritual one, emanation. The Sphere stands on the border line between
the corporeal and the intelligible, itself a product of emanation, though
producing the elements by its motion—a process apparently neither like
emanation nor like sublunar becoming and change.
Creation
in Israeli seems to be the same as emanation, for on the one hand he tells us
that souls are created, that nothing precedes the four elements except the
Omnipotence of God, and on the other that the elements come from the motion of
the Sphere, and the souls issue from the shadow of the Intelligence. For matter
and form there seems to be no room at all except as logical principles. This is
evidently due to the fact that Israeli is unwittingly combining Aristotelian
physics with Neo-Platonic emanationism. For Aristotle matter and form stand at
the head of sublunar change and are ultimate. There is no derivation of matter
or form from anything. The celestial world has a matter of its own, and is not
the cause of the being of this one except as influencing its changes. God is
the mover of the Spheres, but not their Creator, hence he stands outside of the
world. This is Theism. In Israeli there is a continuity of God, the
intelligible world and the corporeal, all being ultimately the same thing,
though the processes in the two worlds are different. And yet he obviates
Pantheism by declaring that God is a principle not an element.
We said
before that Israeli takes no avowed attitude to Jewish dogma or the Bible. He
never quotes any Jewish works, and there is nothing in his writings to indicate
that he is a Jew and is making an effort to harmonize Judaism with philosophy
and science. In words he refers to creation ex nihilo, which is not necessarily
Jewish, it might be just as well Mohammedan or Christian. But in reality, as we
have seen, his ideas of the cosmic process are far enough removed from the
orthodox doctrine of creation as it appears in Bible and Talmud.
Incidentally
we learn also something of Israeli's ideas of God's relation to mankind, of his
commandments, and of prophecy. God created the world, he tells us, because of
his goodness. He wanted to benefit his creatures. This could not be without
their knowing the will of God and performing it. The will of God could not be
revealed directly to everybody because the divine wisdom can speak only to
those in whom the rational soul is mistress and is enlightened by the
Intelligence. But people are not all of this kind; for some have the animal
soul predominating in them, being on that account ignorant, confused, forward,
bold, murderous, vengeful, unchaste like animals; others are mastered by the
vegetative soul, i. e., the appetitive, and are thus stupid and dull, and given
over to their appetites like plants. In others again their souls are variously
combined, giving to their life and conduct a composite character. On this
account it was necessary for God to select a person in whom the rational soul
is separated, and illumined by the Intelligence—a man who is spiritual in his
nature and eager to imitate the angels as far as it is possible for a man to do
this. This man he made a messenger to mankind. He gave him his book which
contains two kinds of teaching. One kind is spiritual in its nature, and needs
no further commentary or interpretation. This is meant for the intellectual and
discriminating. The other kind is corporeal, and requires spiritual
interpretation. This is intended for the various grades of those who cannot
understand directly the spiritual meaning, but who can grasp the corporeal
teaching, by which they are gradually trained and prepared for the reception of
higher truths. These people therefore need instructors and guides because a
book alone is not sufficient for the purposes of those who cannot understand.
Dreams
and prophecy are closely related, hence an explanation of the former will also
throw light on the latter. A dream is caused by the influence of the
Intelligence on the soul in sleep. The Intelligence receives its knowledge
directly from God, and serves as a mediator between him and the soul, like a
prophet who mediates between God and his creatures. In communicating to the
soul the spiritual forms which it received from God, the Intelligence
translates them into forms intermediate between corporeality and spirituality
in order that they may be quickly impressed upon the common sense, which is the
first to receive them. The common sense stands midway between the corporeal
sense of sight and the imagination, which is in the anterior chamber of the
brain, and is known as phantasy (Aristotelian φαντασία).
That the
forms thus impressed on the common sense in sleep are intermediate between
corporeal and spiritual is proved by the fact that they are different from the
corporeal forms of things seen in the waking state. The latter are obscure and
covered up, whereas those seen in sleep are finer, more spiritual and brighter.
Proof of this is that a person sees himself in sleep endowed with wings and
flying between heaven and earth. He sees the heavens opening and someone
speaking to him out of the heaven, and so on. There would be no sense in all this
if these phenomena had no spiritual meaning, for they are contrary to nature.
But we know that they have real significance if interpreted by a really
thoughtful person. The prophets also in wishing to separate themselves from
mankind and impress the latter with their qualities, showed them spiritual
forms of similar kind, which were preternatural. Hence all who believe in
prophecy admit that dreams are a part of prophecy.
Now these
intermediate forms which are impressed upon the common sense in sleep are
turned over by it to the phantasy and by the latter to the memory. When the
person awakes, he recovers the forms from the memory just as they were
deposited there by the phantasy. He then consults his thinking power; and if
this is spiritual and pure, the Intelligence endows him with its light and
splendor and reveals to him the spiritual forms signified by the visions seen
in sleep. He is then able to interpret the dream correctly. But if his powers
of thought are not so good and are obscured by coverings, he cannot properly
remove the husk from the kernel in the forms seen in sleep, is not able to
penetrate to the true spirituality beneath, and his interpretation is
erroneous.
This
explanation does not really explain, but it is noteworthy as the first Jewish
attempt to reduce prophecy to a psychological phenomenon, which was carried
further by subsequent writers until it received its definitive form for the
middle ages in Maimonides and Levi ben Gerson.
To sum
up, Israeli is an eclectic. There is no system of Jewish philosophy to be found
in his writings. He had no such ambitions. He combines Aristotelian logic,
physics and psychology with Neo-Platonic metaphysics, and puts on the surface a
veneer of theistic creationism. His merit is chiefly that of a pioneer in
directing the attention of Jews to the science and philosophy of the Greeks,
albeit in Arab dress. There is no trace yet of the Kalam in his writings except
in his allusions to the atomic theory and the denial of reward and punishment
of animals.
CHAPTER II
DAVID BEN MERWAN AL MUKAMMAS
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|