HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER XVIII.JOSEPH ALBO (1380-1444)
Of the
post-Maimonidean philosophers Crescas is the last who contributes original
views of philosophical value. Joseph Albo, of Monreal in Aragon, is of little
importance as a philosopher. He rehashes the problems which occupied a
Maimonides, a Gersonides and a Crescas, and sides now with one, now with the
other. He benefited by the writings of his predecessors, particularly
Maimonides, Crescas, and Simon Duran; and the philosophical discussions in the
last three sections of his "Book of Roots" ("Sefer
Ikkarim") give the impression of an eclectic compilation in the interest
of a moderate conservatism. The style is that of the popularizer and the
homilist; and to this he owes his popularity, which was denied his more
original teacher, Crescas.
But
philosophy as such was not Albo's forte, nor was it his chief interest. While
it is true that all the Jewish thinkers of the middle ages were for a great
part apologetes, this did not prevent a Maimonides or a Gersonides from making
a really thorough and disinterested study of science and philosophy; and often
their scientific and philosophic conviction was so strong that the apologia was pro philosophia sua rather than pro Judaismo. The central theme therefore
in the majority of Albo’s philosophical predecessors was the equally
metaphysical and theological, of God and his attributes. These were proved by
reason and confirmed by Scripture and tradition. Judaism had to be formulated
and defended with a view not so much to the dangers threatening from
Christianity and Mohammedanism as to those endangering all religions alike,
namely, the opinions of science and philosophy as taught especially by the
Aristotelians. Hence Maimonides treated for the most part of the same problems
as the Mohammedan Mutakallimun before him, and Thomas Aquinas the Christian had
no scruple in making the Jewish philosopher's method his own when he undertook
to defend the Catholic faith "contra Gentiles."
Different
were the circumstances as well as the attitude of Joseph Albo. The purely
philosophic interest was not strong in his day. He was not confronted by the
necessity of proving the existence and incorporeality of God by reason. No one
doubted these things and they had been abundantly written about in times gone
by. In the interest of completeness and for the benefit of those who were not
trained in technical philosophy, Albo found it desirable to restate the results
of previous discussions of these topics in a style more accessible to the readers
of his day. But the central interest in his age was shifted. It was a time of
religious disputations and forced conversions. Albo himself had taken part in
such a disputation held at Tortosa in 1413-14, and he had to defend Judaism
against Christianity. He had to show his own people that Judaism was the true
religion and Christianity spurious. Hence it was religion as such he had to
investigate, in order to find what marks distinguished a divine law from a
human, and a genuine divine law from one that pretended to be such. To make
this investigation logically complete he had to show that there must be such a
thing as a divine law, and that no such law can be conceived without assuming
certain basal beliefs or dogmas. A discussion of religious dogma was essential,
for upon the nature of these fundamental beliefs depended one's judgment of a
given law and its character as divine or human, genuine or spurious. Hence the
title of Albo’s treatise, "Book of [religious] Roots [dogmas]." And
while it is true that Maimonides, the systematizer and codifier, could not fail
to put down in his commentary on the Mishna a list of articles of the Jewish
creed, nothing is said of this in his philosophical work, the "Guide of
the Perplexed." With Albo the establishment of the fundamental dogmas is
the central theme.
At the
same time Albo was anticipated even in this, his more original contribution.
Crescas, his teacher, had written, beside the "Or Adonai," a work
against Christianity. And in the "Or Adonai" itself he devotes
considerable space to the question of the fundamental dogmas of Judaism, and
takes occasion to criticize Maimonides for his faulty method in the selection
of the thirteen articles, on the ground that he did not distinguish between
what was fundamental and what was derivative. This suggestion gave Albo his
cue, which he developed in his own way.
Human
happiness, Albo tells us, depends upon theory and practice, as Aristotle says.
But the human mind is inadequate to know by itself the truth touching these two.
Hence there is need of something superior to the human mind which will define
right practice and the true ideas. This can be only by divine guidance. Hence
everyone must be able to tell the divine legislation from those which are not
divine. For this it is necessary to know what are the principles without which
a divine law cannot exist. This is the purpose of the book, to explain the
essential principles of a divine law.
A
knowledge of the principles of religion would seem easy, for all people profess
some religion or other, and hence are presumed to know upon what their
religions are based. But this question has not been treated adequately before,
and there is no agreement among previous writers about the number of the
principles or their identity. Some say there are thirteen (Maimonides), some
say twenty-six, some six (Crescas), without investigating what are the
principles of divine religion generally. For we must distinguish between the
general principles which pertain to divine legislation as such and hence are
common to all religions, and special principles which are peculiar to a particular
religion.
Seeing
the importance of this subject, Albo continues, I undertook this investigation.
I came to the conclusion that there are three general principles of divine
religion, existence of God, Revelation, and Reward and Punishment after death.
Then there are special principles peculiar to a particular religion. From the
general principles ("Ikkarim") follow particular or derivative
principles ("Shorashim.")
The
investigation of the principles of religion is a delicate matter because one is
in danger of being reckoned an infidel if he denies what is considered by
others a fundamental dogma. Thus according to Maimonides the belief in the
Messiah is fundamental, and he who denies it is a heretic and has no share in
the world to come. And yet Rabbi Hillel in the Talmud (Sanhedrin, 99a) said,
"Israel need expect no Messiah, for they had the benefit of one in the
days of Hezekiah, King of Judah." On the other hand, Maimonides does not
regard creation ex nihilo as fundamental, whereas others do; and to their mind
Maimonides is open to the charge of unbelief.
The truth
is that only he is an unbeliever who deliberately and knowingly contradicts the
Bible. A person who believes in the Bible but is led mistakenly to misinterpret
it, and denies real principles because he thinks the Bible does not require us
to believe them as principles, or does not require us to believe them at all,
is guilty of error and in need of forgiveness, but is not a heretic.
Having
thus defined his attitude and purpose, Albo proceeds to criticize the list of
dogmas laid down by Maimonides and modified by Crescas, and then defends his
own view. A fundamental principle ("Ikkar," lit. root) is one upon
which something else depends and without which this latter cannot exist.
Maimonides counts thirteen principles of Judaism as follows: (1) Existence of
God, (2) Unity, (3) Incorporeality, (4) Eternity, (5) He alone must be
worshipped, (6) Prophecy, (7) Superiority of the prophecy of Moses, (8)
Revelation, (9) Immutability of the Law, (10) God's Omniscience, (11) Reward
and Punishment, (12) Messiah, (13) Resurrection. This list is open to
criticism. If Maimonides intended to admit strict principles only without which
Judaism cannot exist, we understand why he named (1), (6), (8), (10), (11),
which are general principles of any divine religion, and (7) and (9) as special
principles of Judaism. But we cannot see why he included (2) and (3). For while
they are true, and every Jew should believe them, Judaism can be conceived as
existing without them. It is still more strange that (5) should be counted as a
principle. To be sure, it is one of the ten commandments, "Thou shalt have
no other Gods before me.... Thou shalt not bow thyself down to them, nor serve
them" ... (Exod. 20, 35), but Judaism can be conceived to exist even with
the belief in a mediator. Similarly it is not clear why (13) should be
considered as a fundamental dogma. On the other hand, he omitted Tradition and
Free Will as beliefs essential to any divine religion.
If, in
defence of Maimonides, we say that he intended to name not only fundamental
principles, but also true beliefs, whether fundamental or derivative, then
there are many others he might have mentioned, such as creation ex nihilo,
belief in miracles, that God rests in Israel through the Torah, and so on.
Another
writer counts twenty-six principles, including everything that occurred to his
mind, such as the attributes of eternity, wisdom, life, power, will and others,
counting paradise and hell as two, and other absurd ideas. Others again,
criticizing Maimonides's principles, reduce them to six, viz. (1) God’s
knowledge, (2) Providence, (3) Power, (4) Prophecy, (5) Free Will, (6) Purpose,
adding thereto the three proved by Maimonides, God's existence, unity and
incorporeality. The objection to this list is that it does not contain the
special dogmas of Judaism, and does not give us a principle by which we can
distinguish between the genuine and spurious divine religion. For the dogmas
named in the above list give us the necessary requirements for a divine law,
but not the sufficient. We may have all these principles and yet not have a
divine religion. As to Free Will and Purpose, they are essential to divine
legislation to be sure, but not qua divine; they are also essential to a
conventional human law. Divine religion has a special purpose peculiar to it.
Having
laid bare the defects in the attempts at a list of fundamental dogmas of Judaism
made by his predecessors, Albo categorically lays down the following three
principles as fundamental to divine religion: (1) Existence of God, (2)
Providence, and reward and punishment, (3) Revelation.
To
justify this statement Albo finds it necessary to make clear what is meant by
divine law or religion, and what relation it bears to other laws, not divine.
This necessitates an explanation of existing laws and their motives and causes.
Animal
life, we are told, may be divided into three classes according to the mode of
living adopted by each. Beasts of prey live separately and not in groups.
Mankind must live in communities, as one individual is dependent upon the work
of another, and social life is essential to their existence. Intermediate
between beast of prey and man are the gregarious animals, which keep together
not as a matter of necessity, as is the case in man, but for convenience, for
the sake of being together. Man is social by nature; and in order to make
communal life possible, there must be some order in the community which
prohibits violence, robbery, and so on. This is known as "natural
law." In addition to this there are in many places "conventional
laws," made by kings and emperors, regulating more carefully and with
greater detail than the natural law the affairs of the members of the
community.
But this
is not all. There is still another kind of law due directly to God's
providence. The providence of God is seen even in the lower animals, in the
constitution of their bodies, not merely in matters essential to the
preservation of the animal, but also in the interest of comfort and
convenience, as for example the duplication of the sense organs. It stands to
reason therefore that there is a divine influence which provides for man even to
a greater degree. This providence may extend only to one individual, but this
person brings about the perfection of the race; just as in the individual man
the heart is instrumental in giving life to all the other limbs. The law which
is promulgated through this person is a "divine law."
The term
"law" ("Dat") applies to any system of directions embracing
a large aggregate of men, whether it contains many commands or one. There are
thus three kinds of law, natural, conventional and divine. Natural law is the
same for all persons, times and places. Conventional law is ordered by a wise
man or men in conformity with the necessity of the persons, times and places,
as the reason dictates, without special divine suggestion. Divine law is
ordered by God through a prophet. The purpose of natural law is to remove wrong
and promote right, keeping men from robbery and theft so that society may be
able to exist. Conventional law goes further and tends to remove the unseemly
and to promote the becoming. Divine law has for its purpose to guide men to
true happiness, which is the happiness of the soul and its eternal life. It
points out the way to follow to reach this end, showing what is the true good
for man to pursue, and what is the real evil which one must shun; though it
also lays down the law of right and wrong like the other two.
The
conventional law is inferior to the divine in a number of ways.
The
conventional law only orders human conduct for the purpose of improving social
life, but does not concern itself with perfection in theoretical speculation
and knowledge, which leads the soul to eternal life. The divine law embraces
both the parts upon which human perfection depends, conduct and theory. It
embraces the becoming and unbecoming (practice), and the true and untrue
(theory). As the Psalmist has it, "The Law of the Lord is perfect,
restoring the soul" (Psal. 19, 8).
The
conventional law, being human, cannot always decide with certainty what is
becoming and what unbecoming. It is liable to error. This is particularly the
case in matters of theory, such as the creation or eternity of the world. The
divine law gives us certainty in all things, "The testimony of the Lord is
sure, making wise the simple" (ib.).
The
person guided by the conventional law is not sure that he is always guided
aright; hence he cannot feel the satisfaction and the joy of the man whose
guide is the divine law, making him certain of being right—"The precepts
of the Lord are upright, rejoicing the heart" (ib. 9).
The
conventional law can give general rules only, but is unable to advise in a
particular case. So Aristotle in the Ethics points out that virtue is a mean,
but he cannot determine exactly the proper measure at a given time. This is the
function of the divine law—"The commandment of the Lord is clear,
enlightening the eyes" (ib.).
The
conventional law is subject to change in the course of time. Witness the
marriage of sisters in the early period of Adam and Abel. The divine law alone
does not change—"The fear of the Lord is pure, enduring for ever"
(ib. 10).
The
conventional law cannot estimate exactly the merited amount and kind of reward
and punishment; whereas, "The ordinances of the Lord are the truth; they
are just altogether" (ib.).
Freedom
and Purpose are principles of conventional law. Without freedom there is no
sense in giving orders. For this reason Freedom and Purpose are not correctly
given as fundamental dogmas of divine law, for while the latter cannot get
along without them, they are not peculiar to divine law as such, but are common
also to conventional law. This is why Maimonides omitted Freedom in his creed.
The same is true of Purpose in general. The divine law, however, has a special
purpose, perfection and eternal life, hence Maimonides did include it in his list.
The
fundamental dogmas of divine law are, as we said before, Existence of God,
Revelation, Reward and Punishment. It is evident that there cannot be a divine
law without the first two. The third is also necessary; for the purpose of
divine law must be a perfection greater than the conventional law can
accomplish. This is eternal life, and is signified by Reward and Punishment.
As all
agree that the Law of Moses is divine, it is proper to use it as a standard in
order to discover what a divine law must have. Accordingly if we examine the
first four chapters of Genesis, we find the principle of the existence of God
in chapter one, describing creation. The second and third chapters give
evidence of revelation, or communication of God with man for the purpose of
directing his conduct. Finally in the Cain incident in chapter four is
illustrated the third dogma of Reward and Punishment.
Creation
ex nihilo is a true belief but not a fundamental principle. For though the
Aristotelian view of eternity is heretical, as it takes away the possibility of
miracles, nay even the possibility of Moses and the Messiah (for these could
exist only after the lapse of an infinite number of individuals), one who
believes like Plato in a primitive matter is not necessarily in contradiction
with the Biblical miracles, for they were not ex nihilo.
It is not
sufficient to believe in the three principles mentioned to be considered a
believer and to be entitled to a share in the world to come. One must believe
also in the derivative principles following from them. Thus from the existence
of God follow his unity and incorporeality. And if a man does not believe in
incorporeality, he disbelieves in the real nature of God, and it is as if he
denied the original principle.
The
derivative principles ("Shorashim" = roots) are as follows. From
existence of God are derived four: (1) Unity, (2) Incorporeality, (3) Independence
of time, (4) Freedom from defects. From Revelation are derived three: (1) God's
knowledge, (2) Prophecy, (3) Authenticity of God's messenger. From Reward and
Punishment is derived one—Providence in the sense of special Providence. In all
there are eleven dogmas.
A
particular commandment of the Law is not reckoned either as a fundamental
principle or as a derivative. He who trangresses it is a sinner and is punished
for his misdeed, but is not a heretic who loses his share in the world to come,
unless he denies that the commandment in question is from God. In that case he
comes in the category of those who deny revelation. Similarly the belief in
tradition is not a principle because it is a particular commandment. Unity of
God is a principle though it is apparently a special commandment, because the
term unity contains two concepts; first, that God is one and there is not
another like him; second, that being one and free from any multiplicity or
composition, he is the cause of all the multiplicity in the world. The latter
is not a particular commandment, but a principle derived from the existence of
God. The former is a particular commandment. If particular commandments were
regarded as principles, we should have as many principles as there are commandments
in the Bible.
The above
distinction between the two senses of the term unity, one of which is
rationally derived from the existence of God, whereas the other not being so
derivable is not a principle, and is given in the Bible as a special
commandment, is clearly due to Crescas, who after a few attempts at proving the
unity of God in the sense of excluding dualism, gives it up as incapable of
proof logically, and falls back upon the testimony of Scripture, "Hear, O
Israel, the Lord our God, the Lord is One." The other sense of the word
unity Crescas proves by reason. Hence Albo counts it among the derivative
principles.
If a
particular commandment is not a principle, which means that a fundamental or
derivative dogma cannot itself be a commandment, but must lie at the basis of
all commandments, the question arises whence come these principles, and who is
to warrant their truth. In the sciences we know that the basal principles of a
given science are not proved in that science itself, but are borrowed from
another science in which they are proved. Thus physics takes the concepts of
substance and accident from metaphysics. In turn the latter takes the idea of a
first mover from physics. Among the laws, too, the conventional law takes its
principles, freedom and purpose, from political philosophy. Whence does divine
law take its principles? The existence of God can be demonstrated
philosophically from premises going back to axioms and first principles. But
this is not true of Prophecy and Providence.
The answer
Albo gives to this question is that of Judah Halevi and Crescas. The principles
of the divine law are known empirically, i.
e., by experience. Adam knew of the existence of God, of prophecy and
reward and punishment from personal experience. Similarly Noah and Abraham.
Nowadays we know the law by tradition, but the majority of the principles thus
known are so certain that there is neither difference of opinion nor doubt
entertained by anyone concerning them. Such is the status for example of the
principle of Revelation. Other principles again, like the existence of God,
are, as was said before, known by theoretical speculation.
To find
out whether a religion professing to be of divine origin is really so or not,
it must be examined first with reference to the three fundamental, and the
other derivative principles. If it opposes them, it is spurious and not
genuine. If it is not opposed to the principles in question, it must be further
examined with a view to determining whether the promulgator is a genuine messenger
of God or not. And the test here must be a direct one. Miracles and signs are
no conclusive proof of prophecy, and still less do they prove that the person
performing them is a messenger sent by God to announce a law. They merely show
that the person is considered worthy of having miracles performed through him,
provided the miracles are genuine and not performed through magic. The test of
the prophet and the messenger of God must be as direct as it was in the case of
Moses, where the people actually saw that he was addressed by God and
commissioned with a message for them.
This
opinion of Albo is clearly intended as a defence of Judaism against
Christianity's claim that Jesus performed miracles, a claim which the Rabbis of
the middle ages were inclined to recognize.
In
addition to the three fundamental and eight derivative principles of divine
legislation, there are six dogmas, which every follower of the Mosaic law must
believe. They are (1) Creation ex nihilo, (2) Superiority of Moses to other prophets,
(3) Immutability of the Law, (4) That human perfection can be attained by any
one of the commandments of the Law, (5) Resurrection, (6) Messiah.
Creation
ex nihilo is neither a fundamental nor a derivative principle of religion
generally or of Judaism specially because, as we saw before, they can exist
without this dogma. At the same time it is a truth which it behooves every
religionist and particularly every Jew to believe. It follows from the
principle of the existence of God. If God cannot create ex nihilo, there is a
defect in him. For creation ex nihilo is admitted in a certain sense even by those who hold that the world is
eternal. They admit that God is the cause of everything else; hence matter is
his effect through the mediation of the separate Intellect. But how can a
separate Intellect be the cause of matter if there is no creation ex nihilo.
This is ex nihilo as much as anything can be. To say that we can find no reason
why he should create at a particular time rather than at another, and hence the
world must be eternal, is no argument; for this reasoning can apply only to
action from necessity. Voluntary action is just of this kind, that it takes
place at a particular time.
In the
above argument for creation the reader will not fail to see reminiscences of
Maimonides as well as Crescas.
The
superiority of Moses to other prophets is not essential to Judaism,
nevertheless it behooves every Jew to believe it, as it is included in the
principle of Revelation, and the Bible tells us, "And there arose not a
prophet since then in Israel like unto Moses" (Deut. 34, 10).
The
Immutability of the Law will be treated in detail later. Here it will suffice
to say that while it is not a sine qua
non of Judaism, every Jew should believe it, as it is included in the
derivative principle of the Authenticity of God's messenger.
It stands
to reason that human perfection can be attained by the performance of any one
of the commandments of the Law. For if it requires the performance of all the
commandments for this purpose, then the Law of Moses makes it more difficult to
reach perfection than the previous laws, which is not in consonance with the
statement of the Rabbis that "God gave Israel so many laws and
commandments because he wished to make them meritorious" (Tal. Bab.
Makkot, 23 b).
Resurrection
will be treated more at length later. It must be believed because it has been
accepted by Israel and has come down to us by tradition. The same thing applies
to the belief in the Messiah. This is also a traditional belief and is related
to the principle of Reward and Punishment, though it is not like the latter
indispensable either to religion in general or to Judaism in particular.
The
difference, it will be seen, between Albo and Maimonides in the question of Jewish
dogmas is simply one of classification and grading. Albo includes in his
enumeration all the thirteen dogmas of Maimonides with the exception of the
fifth, namely, that God alone be worshipped, but instead of placing them all on
the same level of importance as equally essential to the structure of Judaism,
as Maimonides apparently intended, Albo divides them into three categories of
descending rank as follows: fundamental principles, derived principles, true
beliefs. Of Maimonides's list the last two, Messiah and Resurrection, belong to
the last category. None the less Albo believed strictly in both and held it
incumbent upon every Jew to believe in them. It was only a question of the
status of a person who mistakenly denies these true beliefs. According to
Maimonides, it would seem, he would be called a heretic and be excluded from a
share in the world to come equally with one who denied the existence of God;
whereas according to Albo a person so guilty is a sinner and needs forgiveness,
but is not a heretic. Of the other eleven dogmas of Maimonides, (1), (8) and
(11) are placed by Albo in his first class, (2), (3), (4), (6) and (10) belong
to the second class, while (7) and (9) come under true beliefs along with
Messiah and Resurrection. The difference between the first and the second class
is purely logical and not practical. As we saw before, one who denies
incorporeality (a principle of the second class) disbelieves in the true nature
of God, which is tantamount to denying the principle of the existence of God.
Before
concluding this general discussion of the fundamental dogmas of religion and
Judaism, Albo undertakes to answer two questions which must have been near his
heart, and which were on the tongues no doubt of a great many honest people in
those days of religious challenge and debate. The first question is, Is it
proper, or perhaps obligatory, to analyze the fundamental principles of one's
religion, to see if they are true; and if one finds another religion which
seems to him better, is one permitted to adopt it in place of his own? Albo
sees arguments against both sides of the dilemma. If a man is allowed to
analyze his religion and to choose the one that seems best to him, it will
follow that a person is never stable in his belief, since he is doubting it, as
is shown by his examination. And if so, he does not deserve reward for belief,
since belief, as Albo defines it elsewhere (Pt. I, ch. 19), means that one
cannot conceive of the opposite being true. Again, if he finds another religion
which he thinks better and is allowed to exchange his own religion for the new
one, he will never be sure of any religion; for he may find a third still
better, and a fourth, and so on, and as he cannot examine all the possible
religions, he will remain without any religious convictions.
On the
other hand, if he is not allowed to investigate the foundations of his belief,
it follows either that all religions alike bring their believer happiness, no
matter how contradictory they are, which is absurd; or God would seem unfair if
only one religion leads its devotees to happiness and no one is allowed to
change his religion for one that seems to him the true one.
The
answer of Albo to this interesting question is characteristic. It shows that he
armored himself in advance, before he risked such a delicate question. He makes
it clear that it really does not expose to any danger the religion of Judaism,
the mother of the other two, which they came to supersede. If all religions in
the world, Albo tells us, were opposed to one another, and regarded each other
as untrue, the above difficulty would be real. But it is not so. All religions
agree in respect to one of them that it is divine; but they say that it is
superseded. Hence every religionist who is not a Jew must investigate his
religion to see if it is justified in opposing the religion which is
acknowledged to be divine. Similarly the professor of the admittedly divine
religion should investigate to see if his religion is temporary or eternal. In
this investigation he must first see if the religion conforms to the principles
of divine religion above mentioned. If it does this and in addition endeavors
to order human affairs in accordance with justice, and leads its devotees to
human perfection, it is divine. It is still, however, possible that it is the
work of a wise man of good character. It is therefore necessary to investigate
the character of the promulgator, to find out whether he is a genuine divine
messenger or not. This test, as was said above, must be a direct test and not
an indirect.
The other
question is whether there can be more than one divine religion. Apparently
there can be only one, since the giver is one, and the recipients are of one
species. But in reality the receivers vary in temperament according to
difference in inheritance and environment. Hence there may be a difference in
the law according to the character of the people for whom it is intended.
Since, however, the difference is due to the receiver and not to the giver, it
must reside in those elements which are dependent upon the receiver, i.e., in particulars and details, not in
the principles, fundamental or derived. So the Noachite and the Mosaic laws
differ only in details, not in fundamental principles.
We have
now completed the exposition of the part of Albo's teaching that may be called
distinctly his own. And it seems he was aware that he had nothing further to
teach that was new, and would have been content to end his book with the first
part, of which we have just given an account. But his friends, he tells us in
the concluding remarks to the first part of the "Ikkarim," urged him
to proceed further and discuss in detail the principles, fundamental and
derived, the true beliefs and the so-called "branches," which he
barely enumerated in the first part. He was persuaded by their advice and added
the other three sections, each devoted to one of the three fundamental dogmas
and the corollaries following from it. Here Albo has nothing new to teach. He
follows the beaten track, reviews the classic views of Maimonides, takes
advantage of the criticisms of Gersonides and Crescas, and settles the problems
sometimes one way sometimes another, without ever suggesting anything new.
Accordingly it will not be worth our while to reproduce his discussions here.
It will suffice briefly to indicate his position on the more important
problems.
The
second section deals with the existence of God and the derived principles and
branches growing out from this root. In proving the existence of God he refers
to Maimonides's four proofs, and selects the third and fourth as really valid
and beyond dispute. The first and second are not conclusive; the one because it
is based upon the eternity of motion, which no Jew accepts; the other because
the major premise is not true. It does not follow if one of the two elements a,
b, of a composite a + b is found separately, that the other must be found
existing separately likewise.
We have
seen that from the principle of the existence of God follow four derivative
dogmas, unity, incorporeality, independence of time, freedom from defects. We
are now told that from these secondary roots issue a number of branches. From
Unity it follows that no attributes either essential or accidental can be applied
to God, such as wisdom, strength, generosity, and so on, for they would cause
multiplicity. From incorporeality we infer that God is not subject to corporeal
affections like fear, sorrow, joy, grudge, and so on. Independence of time
implies infinite power and want of resemblance to other things. Freedom from
defect implies absence of such qualities as ignorance, weakness, and so on.
In the
discussion of the divine attributes Albo has nothing new to offer, but instead
he argues forward and backward, now with Maimonides, now against him,
reproducing a good deal of Maimonides's classification, embodying some material
of Bahya on unity, and after this rambling and not very consistent discussion,
he comes to the conclusion that none but active and negative attributes are
applicable to God; and yet some essential attributes too must be his, but these
must be understood as implying only the aspect of perfection, and not that
other aspect of attribute which is responsible for multiplicity.
He asks
the question so often asked before, How can multiplicity come from unity? And
after giving Ibn Sina's scheme of the emanation of the Intelligences one after
the other, and criticizing it in the manner of Gazali and Maimonides, he gives
his own solution that the variety and multiplicity of the world tends to one
end, which is the order of the world. And thus are reconciled plurality and
unity.
He
discusses the question of angels or Intellects, gives the views of the
philosophers concerning their nature and number, each being the effect of the
superior and the cause of the inferior, and objects to their idea on the ground
that these cannot be the same as the Biblical angels, who are messengers of God
to mankind. He then gives his own view that the number of angels is infinite,
not as the philosophers say ten or fifty, and that they are not related to each
other as cause and effect, but that though they are immaterial Intellects they
are individuated and differentiated according to the degree of understanding
they have of God.
In
discussing the second fundamental principle, Revelation, Albo argues in the
good old fashion that man is the noblest creature of the sublunar world, and
the most distinctive and noblest part of man—his form and essence—is the
theoretical reason. Hence the purpose of man must be the realization of the
theoretical intellect. At the same time, and with little consistency, Albo
takes the part of Judah Halevi and Crescas, employing their arguments, without
naming them, that the philosophers and the philosophizing theologians are wrong
who make human immortality, perfection and happiness depend solely upon
intellectual activity. He comes to the conclusion, therefore, that spiritual
understanding, which gives perfection of soul when in combination with practice,
is not acquisition of ideas but the intention of doing the will of God in the
performance of good deeds, and not that of pleasure or reward.
This
being so, it becomes an important question what are the practices which tend to
human perfection, and what are those which tend the other way. In general we
may conclude, as like desires and rejoices in like, that those deeds which give
the soul pleasure before and after performance are good and helpful, while
those which cause subsequent pain, regret and sorrow are bad, and tend away
from the soul's perfection.
But the
criterion of pleasure and pain just suggested is not sufficient as a guide in
conduct, for a great deal depends upon a man's temperament. What a hot-blooded
man may commend and find pleasure in, the phlegmatic temperament will object
to, and will feel discomfort in doing. Besides, as the good deed is always a
mean between two extremes, which it is hard to measure precisely; and as the
good deed is that which pleases God, and beyond generalities we cannot tell
what does, and what does not please God, since we do not know his essence, it
was necessary for man's sake that God should reveal his will to mankind through
a prophet. Thus Revelation is proved by reason.
This
leads to the problem of prophecy, one of the derivative principles of
Revelation. The divine influence from which man gets a knowledge of the things
pleasing and displeasing to God, he cannot obtain without the divine will.
Instead of magic, divination, and communication with evil spirits and the dead,
which the ancient heathen employed in order to learn the future, God sent
prophets to Israel, to tell the people of the will of God. Foretelling the
future was only secondary with them. Prophecy is a supernatural gift, whether
it takes place with the help of the imagination or not. If it were a natural
phenomenon dependent upon the intellectual power of the individual and his
faculty of imagination, as the philosophers and some Jewish theologians think,
there should have been prophets among the philosophers.
Here
again we see Albo adopt the view of Halevi and Crescas against the
intellectualism of Maimonides and Gersonides. His further classification of the
grades of prophecy is based upon Maimonides, though Albo simplifies it. Instead
of eleven Albo recognizes four grades in all, including that of Moses. The
great majority of mankind, he says, stop with the ability to analyze, such as
is exhibited in the analysis of things into matter and form, and so on, though
not all of them go so far. But there are some few who go farther and are
enabled to speak words of wisdom and to sing praises to God without being able
to account for the power. This is the holy spirit ("Ruah ha-Kodesh").
Some go still farther, and through the strength of their reason and imagination
they dream true dreams and receive prophecies; though, the imagination having
the upper hand, they struggle very hard and tremble and faint, almost losing their
soul. This is the first stage of prophecy. The second stage is when the
imagination and reason are equal. In that case there is no struggle or
fainting. Visions come to the prophet at night in dreams, or in a revery at
daytime. The forms that appear are not real, but the meanings they convey are.
Such are the figures of women, horses, basket of summer fruit, and so on, in
the visions of Zechariah and Amos. The third stage is when the reason gets the
better of the imagination and there are no forms or images, but real essences
and ideas, like the visions of Ezekiel, which represent real things in the
secrets of nature and divinity. The prophet in this stage also hears an angel
speaking to him and giving him information of importance to himself or others.
In all these cases the will of God is essential. No preparation can replace it.
Finally the fourth stage is reached when the imagination does not come into
play at all. In this stage there is no angel or form, and the message comes to
the prophet at daytime while he is awake. He hears a voice telling him what he
desires to know; and whenever he chooses he can summon this power. Moses alone
attained to this final stage. Outside of the prophets, the righteous and the
pious have various degrees of power according to the degree of their union with
God. Some can in this way influence the powers of nature to obey them, as a
person can, by thinking of food, make his mouth water. So they can by taking
thought cause rain and storm. Others can bring down fire from above and revive
the dead.
Through
the influence of a prophet the gift of prophecy may sometimes rest upon
individuals who are themselves unprepared and unworthy. Witness the revelation
on Sinai where the entire people, six hundred thousand in number, were endowed with
the spirit of prophecy, and that too of the highest degree, like Moses himself.
The prophetic medium reflects the spirit of prophecy on others as a smooth
surface reflects the light of the sun upon dark bodies. This is why prophecy is
found only in Israel and in Palestine, because the ark and the Tables of Stone,
upon which the Shekinah rests, reflect the divine spirit upon those who are
worthy and have in them something resembling the contents of the ark, namely,
the Torah and the commandments.
Among the
true beliefs we have seen that Immutability of the Law is related to the
principle of Revelation. Hence this is the place to discuss this question. Can
a divine religion change with time or not? It would seem at first sight that it
cannot. For the giver expresses his will in the Law, and his will never
changes. The receivers are the same, i. e., the same nation, and a nation does
not change. Finally the purpose of the Law or religion is to give people true
opinions, and these never change.
And yet
on further reflection there seems no reason why religion should not change with
the change of the recipient, as the physician changes his prescription with the
progress of the patient, and as a matter of fact we find that the commandments
given to Adam were different from those given to Noah and to Abraham and to
Moses. Adam was not allowed to eat meat, Noah was. Abraham was commanded
circumcision. High places were at first permitted and later forbidden.
Maimonides makes the immutability of the Law a fundamental dogma, relying upon
the commandment, "Thou shalt not add thereto, and thou shalt not diminish
therefrom" (Deut. 13, 1). But in the first place the verse refers to
changes in the mode of observing the laws; and besides, it says nothing about God
himself changing the Law.
The
phrases "an eternal statute," "throughout your
generations," "it is a sign for ever," are no proof of the
eternity of the Law; for not all commandments have these expressions attached,
and this shows rather that the others are subject to change. Besides, the
expressions, "for eternity," and so on, are not to be taken
absolutely. They are often used to express finite periods of time.
After the
Babylonian Exile two changes were made. They changed the characters in which
the Bible was written, and the order and names of the months, beginning with
Tishri instead of Nisan. There is no reason, therefore, why other laws might
not change, too. We need not, then, regard Immutability of the Law as a
fundamental dogma with Maimonides. Hasdai Crescas also classes it with true
beliefs and not with fundamental principles.
Albo
resolves the problem as follows: A matter that is revealed by God himself
cannot be changed by a prophet unless it is changed by God himself. The first
two commandments, "I am the Lord thy God,& c.," and "Thou
shalt not have other gods, &c.," were heard by the people directly
from God without the intervention of Moses, hence they cannot be changed by any
prophet. It follows therefore that the three fundamental dogmas, existence of
God, Revelation and Reward and Punishment can never be changed by a prophet,
for they are implied in the first two commandments, which were heard from God
himself. The rest of the commandments, as they were heard from God through the
interpretation of Moses, can be changed by a prophet as a temporary measure.
The other laws which were given by Moses may be changed by a later prophet even
permanently. But the prophet must be greater than Moses, and he must show this
by the greatness, number, publicity and permanence of his miracles, which must
excel those of Moses. He must likewise show that he was sent by God to change
the Law, as clearly as Moses proved that he was sent to give it. But it is
unlikely that any such prophet will come, for the Torah says that there never
was or will be any prophet like Moses.
Before
discussing the third fundamental dogma, Albo finds it desirable to dispose
first of a few other problems implied by this dogma, one of which, God's
knowledge, was postponed to this place, though it is connected with Revelation,
because it cannot well be separated in discussion from the problem of Freedom.
Providence is the other related problem, which is derived from the dogma of
Reward and Punishment.
There is
nothing that is new in Albo’s treatment of knowledge and Freedom. He insists
like Maimonides that God must be omniscient, and on the other hand the
contingent cannot be denied, and neither can freedom. He gives the stock
arguments, which it is not necessary to reproduce at this late hour. And his
solution is that of Maimonides that in God human freedom and divine Omniscience
are reconcilable because God's knowledge is not our knowledge.
Nor is
there anything original in Albo's discussion of the problem of Providence. He
recognizes with Maimonides and others that a strong argument against special
Providence is the observed inequality between the destinies of men and their
apparent merits. And he endeavors in the well-worn method to give reasons and
explanations for this inequality which will not touch unfavorably God's justice
or his special Providence. The reasons are such as we met before and we shall
not repeat them. Albo also gives a few positive arguments to prove the reality
of special Providence for man. He sees in various natural and human phenomena
evidence of deviation from the merely "natural" as demanded by the
principles of Aristotle's Physics or the laws of uniformity. This shows special
Providence. Thus the existence of dry earth, the heaviest element, above water,
cannot be accounted for by the laws of Physics. The phenomenon of rain cannot
be reduced to law, hence it argues will and purpose and Providence. Admonition
in dreams is direct evidence of special Providence, and it is scarcely likely
that man, who has special equipment above the other animals in his reason,
should not also receive special care above that which the lower animals have.
Now they are protected in the species, hence man is provided for as an
individual.
Having
disposed of the auxiliary dogmas, Albo takes up the fundamental principle of
Reward and Punishment. He cites various opinions on the subject, which are
dependent upon the idea one entertains concerning the nature of the soul. Thus
if one holds that the human soul is not different in kind from the animal soul,
it follows that as there is no reward and punishment for the animal, there is
none for man. And if one regards the human soul as merely a capacity or
possibility of intelligence he must necessarily conclude that the soul perishes
with the body and there is no spiritual reward and punishment after death. The
only reward there is must therefore be corporeal, during life. On the other
hand, our general experience, which brings before us many cases of good men
suffering and bad men enjoying prosperity, would seem to argue against
corporeal reward and punishment in this world. This taken together with the
philosophical opinion that the soul is an immaterial and indestructible
substance gives rise to the third view that the only recompense is spiritual
after death. None of these views is satisfactory to Albo. The first two because
they are based upon an erroneous notion of the soul. All agree, philosophers as
well as theologians, that the human soul is different in kind from the soul of
the animal; and it is likewise admitted that the human soul is immortal. His
criticism of the third view so far as it is based upon the intellectualist idea
that the thing of highest value is intellectual effort, and the only reward is
immortality which intellectual activity engenders, is similar to that of Halevi
and Crescas in its endeavor to refute this notion and to substitute for it the
religious view that the soul is an independent substance having a capacity for
intelligence in God's service. The degree in which a person realizes this
service determines his reward and punishment. The argument from experience Albo
does not answer here, but we may suppose he regards it as answered by what he
said in his discussion of Providence, where he tries to account for the
prosperity of the wicked and the adversity of the righteous.
Albo's
own view accordingly is that which he also attributes to the Bible that there
is a twofold reward, in this world and in the next. There is still a difference
of opinion concerning the nature of the true and ultimate reward, whether it is
given to the soul alone, or to body and soul combined in resurrection. He
quotes Maimonides's opinion, with whom he agrees, that the real reward is
purely spiritual enjoyed by the soul alone. To be sure, after the coming of the
Messiah the bodies of the righteous will be resurrected to make known abroad
God's wonders, or to give these people bodily pleasure for the pain they
suffered during life, or to give them additional opportunity to acquire
perfection so that they may have a greater reward later. But this state of
resurrected life will last only for a time, and then all will die again, and
the souls will enjoy spiritual life forever.
The other
opinion, held by Nachmanides, is that the real and ultimate reward is that of
body and soul united to everlasting life. Albo is not satisfied with this view,
his objections being among others that if only the perfect are resurrected, the
rest will remain without any reward at all, not to mention the difficulty that
it is not likely that the human body—a perishable thing—will change into a
matter that will last forever.
As to the
nature of reward and punishment after death, Albo tells us that reward will
consist in the soul's realization that its endeavors in this world were correct,
and in the next world it will be prepared to join the spiritual beings, which
will give it great joy. The erring soul will find itself in a position where it
will still desire the corporeal pleasures of this world, but will not be able
to have them for want of corporeal organs. At the same time it will also
entertain the other more natural desire of a spiritual substance to join the
other spiritual beings in the other world. This feeling too it will not be able
to satisfy because of its want of perfection. This division of desires
unsatisfied will cause the soul excruciating torture, and this is its
punishment.
CONCLUSION
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|