HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CONCLUSION
Our task
is done. We have now reached the limit we have assigned ourselves. We have
traced objectively and with greater or less detail the rationalistic movement
in medieval Jewry from its beginnings in the ninth and tenth centuries in
Babylon among the Karaites and Rabbanites to its decline in Spain and south
France in the fifteenth century. We have followed its ascending curve from
Saadia through Gabirol, Bahya and Ibn Daud to its highest point in Maimonides,
and we likewise traced its descent through Gersonides, Crescas and Albo. We
took account of its essential nature as being a serious and conscientious
attempt to define a Jewish Weltanschauung in the midst of conflicting claims of
religions and philosophies. The Jewish sacred writings had to be studied and
made consistent with themselves in regard to certain ethical and metaphysical
questions which forced themselves upon the minds of thinking men. In this
endeavor it was necessary to have regard to the system of doctrine that was
growing up among their Mohammedan neighbors and masters itself inherited from
Greece and adjust its teachings to those of Judaism. The adjustment took
various forms according to the temperament of the adjuster. It embraced the
extremes of all but sacrificing one of the two systems of doctrine to the
other, and it counted among its votaries those who honestly endeavored to give
each claim its due. The system of Judaism was the same for all throughout the
period of our investigation, excepting only the difference between Karaites and
Rabbanites. This was not the case with the system of philosophic doctrine.
There we can see a development from Kalam through Neo-Platonism to
Aristotelianism, and we accordingly classified the Jewish thinkers as
Mutakallimun, Neo-Platonists or Aristotelians, or combinations in varying
proportions of any two of the three systems mentioned.
It was
not our province to treat of the mystic movement in medieval Jewry as it
developed in the Kabbalistic works and gained the ground yielded in the course
of time by the healthier rationalism. To com plete the picture it will suffice
to say that as the political and economic conditions of the Jews in the
fourteenth and fifteenth centuries deteriorated, and freedom and toleration
were succeeded by persecution and expulsion, the Jews became more zealous for
their own spiritual heritage as distinguished from foreign importations;
philosophy and rationalism began to be regarded askance, particularly as
experience showed that scientific training was not favorable to Jewish
steadfastness and loyalty. In suffering and persecution those who stuck to
their posts were as a rule not the so-called enlightened who played with
foreign learning, but the simple folk who believed in Torah and tradition in
the good old style. The philosophical and the scientific devotees were the
first to yield, and many of them abandoned Judaism. Thus it was that mysticism
and obscurantism took the place of enlightenment as a measure of self-defence.
The material walls of the Ghetto and the spiritual walls of the Talmud and the
Kabbala kept the remnant from being overwhelmed and absorbed by the hostile
environment of Christian and Mohammedan. The second half of the fourteenth, and
the fifteenth century were not favorable to philosophical studies among the
Jews, and the few here and there who still show an interest in science and
philosophy combine with it a belief in Kabbala and are not of any great
influence on the development of Judaism.
Shemtob
ben Joseph ibn Shemtob (ab. 1440) author of a work entitled "Emunot,"
is a strong opponent of Greek science and philosophy. He is not content with
attacking the lesser lights and extremists like Albalag or Gersonides or
Abraham ibn Ezra. He goes to the very fountain-head of Jewish Aristotelianism
and holds Maimonides responsible for the heresies which invaded the Jewish
camp. He takes up one doctrine after another of the great Jewish philosopher
and points out how dangerous it is to the true Jewish faith. Judah Halevi and
Nachmanides represent to him the true Jewish attitude. The mysteries of the
Jewish faith are revealed not in philosophy but in the Kabbala, which
Maimonides did not study, and which he would not have understood if he had
studied it, for he had no Kabbalistic tradition.
Unlike
Shemtob, his son Joseph ben Shemtob (d. 1480) shows great admiration for
Aristotle and Maimonides. But he is enabled to do so by lending credence to a
legend that Aristotle in his old age recanted his heretical doctrines, in
particular that of the eternity of the world. Joseph ben Shemtob made a special
study of Aristotle's Ethics, to which he wrote a commentary, and endeavored to
show that the Stagirite's ethical doctrines had been misunderstood; that the
highest good of man and his ultimate happiness are to be sought according to
Aristotle not in this world but in the next. It was likewise a
misunderstanding, he thinks, when Maimonides and others make Aristotle deny
special Providence. True science is not really opposed to Judaism. At the same
time he too like his father realizes the danger of too much scientific study,
and hence agrees with Solomon ben Adret that the study of philosophy should be
postponed to the age of maturity when the student is already imbued with Jewish
learning and religious faith.
The son
of Joseph, bearing the name of his grandfather, Shemtob ben Joseph (fl. ab.
1461-89), followed in his father's footsteps, and wrote a commentary on the
"Guide of the Perplexed" of Maimonides, whom he defends against the
attacks of Crescas.
Isaac ben
Moses Arama (1420-1494) is the author of a philosophico-homiletical commentary
on the Pentateuch entitled, "Akedat Yizhak," and a small treatise on
the relations of philosophy and theology. He was also interested in Kabbala and
placed Jewish revelation above philosophy.
Don Isaac
Abarbanel (1437-1508), the distinguished Jewish statesman who went with his
brethren into exile at the time of the expulsion of the Jews from Spain in
1492, was a prolific writer on Biblical exegesis and religious philosophy. Though
a great admirer of Maimonides, on whose "Guide" he wrote a
commentary, and whose thirteen articles of the creed he defended against the
strictures of Crescas and Albo, he was nevertheless an outspoken opponent of
the rationalistic attitude and has no phrases strong enough for such men as
Albalag, Gersonides, Moses of Narbonne and others, whom he denounces as
heretics and teachers of dangerous doctrines. He does not even spare Maimonides
himself when the latter attempts to identify the traditional "Maase
Bereshit" and "Maase Merkaba" with the Aristotelian Physics and
Metaphysics, and adopts Kabbalistic views along with philosophic doctrines. He
is neither original nor thoroughly consistent.
His son
Judah Leo Abarbanel (1470-1530) is the author of a philosophical work in
Italian, "Dialoghi di Amore," (Dialogues of Love), which breathes the
spirit of the Renaissance of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries in Italy. It
is under the influence of Plato and Plotinus and identifies God with love, which
is regarded as the essential principle of all life and activity in the world,
including even the inorganic natural processes. There is no attempt made to
construct a Jewish philosophy, and though all evidence is against it, some have
made it out that Judah Abarbanel was a convert to Christianity.
In the
same country, in Italy, Judah ben Yechiel Messer Leon of Mantua (1450-1490)
made a name for himself as a student of Cicero and of medieval Latin
scholasticism. He wrote a rhetoric in Hebrew based upon Cicero and Lactantius,
and composed logical works based upon Aristotle's Latin text and Averroes. As
an original student of philosophy he is of no importance.
Two
members of the Delmedigo family of Crete, Elijah (1460-1498) and Joseph
Solomon, are well known as students of philosophy and writers on philosophical
and scientific subjects.
Thus the stream of philosophical thought which rose among the Jews in Babylonia and flowed on through the ages, ever widening and deepening its channel, passing into Spain and reaching its high water mark in the latter half of the twelfth century in Maimonides, began to narrow and thin out while spreading into France and Italy, until at last it dried up entirely in that very land which opened up a new world of thought, beauty and feeling in the fifteenth century, the land of the Renaissance. Jewish philosophy never passed beyond the scholastic stage, and the freedom and light which came to the rest of the world in the revival of ancient learning and the inventions and discoveries of the modern era found the Jews incapable of benefiting by the blessings they afforded. Oppression and gloom caused the Jews to retire within their shell and they sought consolation for the freedom denied them without in concentrating their interests, ideals and hopes upon the Rabbinic writings, legal as well as mystical. There have appeared philosophers among the Jews in succeeding centuries, but they either philosophized without regard to Judaism and in opposition to its fundamental dogmas, thus incurring the wrath and exclusion of the synagogue, or they sought to dissociate Judaism from theoretical speculation on the ground that the Jewish religion is not a philosophy but a rule of conduct. In more recent times Jewry has divided itself into sects and under the influence of modern individualism has lost its central authority making every group the arbiter of its own belief and practice and narrowing the religious influence to matters of ceremony and communal activity of a practical character. There are Jews now and there are philosophers, but there are no Jewish philosophers and there is no Jewish philosophy.
THE END.
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|