HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER XVIIHASDAI BEN ABRAHAM CRESCAS (1340-1410)
The
influence of Aristotle on Jewish thought, which began as early as Saadia and
grew in intensity as the Aristotelian writings became better known, reached its
high water mark in Ibn Daud, Maimonides and Gersonides. To Maimonides Aristotle
was the indisputable authority for all matters pertaining to sublunar
existence, but he reserved the right to differ with the Stagirite when the
question concerned the heavenly spheres and the influences derived from them.
Hence he denied the eternity of motion and the fundamental principle at the
basis of this Aristotelian idea, that necessity rules all natural phenomena. In
his doctrine of creation in time, Maimonides endeavored to defend God's
personality and voluntary and purposeful activity. For the same reason he
defended the institution of miracles. Gersonides went further in his
rationalistic attitude, carried the Aristotelian principles to their inevitable
conclusions, and did not shrink from adopting to all intents and purposes the
eternity of the world (strictly speaking the eternity of matter), and the
limitation of God's knowledge to universals. Aristotle's authority was now
supreme, and the Bible had to yield to Aristotelian interpretations, as we have
seen abundantly. Maimonides and Gersonides were the great peaks that stood out
above the rest; but there was any number of lesser lights, some who wrote books
and still more who did not write, taking the great men as their models and
looking at Jewish literature and belief through Aristotelian spectacles.
Intellectualism is the term that best describes this attitude. It had its basis
in psychology, and from there succeeded in establishing itself as the ruling
principle in ethics and metaphysics. As reason and intellect is the
distinguishing trait of man—the part of man which raises him above the
beast—and as the soul is the form of the living body, its essence and actuating
principle, it was argued that the most important part of man is his rational
soul or intellect, and immortality was made dependent upon theoretical ideas.
Speculative study made the soul; and an intellect thus constituted was
immortal, for it was immaterial. The heavenly world, consisting of the separate
Intelligences and culminating in God, was also in its essence reason and
intellect. Hence thought and knowledge formed the essence of the universe. By
thought is man saved, and through thought is he united with the Most High. All
else that is not pure thought acquires what value it has from the relation it
bears to thought. In this way were judged those divisions of Judaism that
concerned ceremony and ethical practice. Their value consisted in their function
of promoting the ends of the reason.
Judah
Halevi, influenced by Al Gazali, had already before Maimonides protested
against this intellectualistic attitude in the name of a truer though more
naive understanding of the Bible and Jewish history. But Judah Halevi's
nationalism and the expression of his poetical and religious feelings and ideas
could not vie with the dominating personality of Maimonides, whose
rationalistic and intellectualistic attitude swept everything before it and
became the dominant mode of thinking for his own and succeeding ages. It
remained for Hasdai Crescas (born in Barcelona, in 1340), who flourished in
Christian Spain two centuries after Maimonides and over a half century after
Gersonides, to take up the cudgels again in behalf of a truer Judaism, a
Judaism independent of Aristotle, and one that is based more upon the spiritual
and emotional sides of man and less upon the purely intellectual, theoretical
and speculative. Himself devoid of the literary power and poetic feeling of
Judah Halevi, Crescas had this in common with the medieval national poet that
he resented the domination of Jewish belief and thought by the alien Greek
speculation. In a style free from rhetoric, and characterized rather by a
severe brevity and precision, he undertakes to undermine the Aristotelian
position by using the Stagirite's own weapons, logical analysis and proof. His
chief work is the "Or Adonai," Light of the Lord.
Agreeing
with all other Jewish writers that the existence of God is the basis of
Judaism, he sees in this very fact a reason why this principle cannot be
regarded as one of the six hundred and thirteen commandments. For a commandment
implies the existence of one who commands. Hence to regard the belief in the
existence of God as a commandment implies the very thing which the commandment
expresses. The existence of God therefore as the basis of all commandments
cannot itself be a commandment. Besides only those things can form the objects
of a command which can be controlled by the will. But a matter of belief like
the existence of God is not subject to will, it is a matter of fact and of
proof.
Maimonides,
as we know, based his proofs of the existence, unity and incorporeality of God
upon twenty-six philosophical propositions taken from the works of Aristotle
and his Arabian interpreters. As he was not writing a book on general
philosophy, Maimonides simply enumerates twenty-five propositions, which he
accepts as proved by Aristotle and his followers. To these he adds
provisionally another proposition, number twenty-six, concerning the eternity
of motion, upon which he bases his proof of the existence of God in order to be
safe from all criticism. In the sequel he discusses this last proposition and
shows that unlike the other twenty-five, it is not susceptible of rigid
demonstration, and the arguments in favor of the origin of motion and the world
in time are more plausible.
Crescas
goes further than Maimonides, and controverts most of the other propositions as
well, maintaining in particular against Aristotle and Maimonides that an
infinite magnitude is possible and exists actually; that there is an infinite
fulness or void outside of this world, and hence there may be many worlds, and
it need not follow that the elements would pour in from one world into the
next, so that all earth should be together in the centre, all fire together in
the outer circumference, and the intermediate elements, air and water, between
these two. The elements may stay in their respective worlds in the places assigned
to them. It will not be worth our while to wade through all the technical and
hair-splitting discussions of these points. The results will be sufficient for
our purpose.
The proof
of the existence of an unmoved mover in Aristotle and Maimonides is based upon
the impossibility of a regress to infinity. If Hasdai Crescas admits the
infinite, the Aristotelian proof fails. Similarly God's unity in Maimonides is
among other things based upon the finiteness of the world and its unity. If
infinite space is possible outside of this world, and there may be many worlds,
this proof fails for God's unity. So Crescas takes up in detail all the
Maimonidean proofs of the existence, unity and incorporeality of God and points
out that they are not valid because in the first place they are based upon
premises which Crescas has refuted, and secondly were the premises granted
Maimonides's results do not follow from them. It remains then for Crescas to
give his own views on this problem which, he says, the philosophers are unable
to solve satisfactorily, and the Bible alone is to be relied upon. At the same
time he does give a logical proof which in reality is not different from one of
the proofs given by Maimonides himself. It is based upon the distinction
insisted upon by Alfarabi and Avicenna between the "possible
existent" and the "necessary existent." Whatever is an effect of
a cause is in itself merely possible, and owes the necessity of its existence
to its cause. Now, argues Crescas, whether the number of causes and effects is
finite or infinite, there must be one cause of all of them which is not itself
an effect. For if all things are effects they are "possible
existents" as regards their own nature, and require a cause which will
make them exist rather than not. This self-subsisting cause is God.
He then
endeavors to prove the unity of God in the two senses of the term; unity in the
sense of simplicity, and unity in the sense of uniqueness. Unity as opposed to
composition—the former sense of the term—is neither the same as the essence of
a thing, nor is it an accident added to the essence. It cannot be essence, for
in that case all things called one would have the same essence. Nor is it
accident, for that which defines and separates the existing thing is truly called
substance rather than accident; and this is what unity does. Accordingly
Crescas defines unity as something essential to everything actually existing,
denoting the absence of plurality. This being true, that existent which is
before all others is most truly called one. Also that being which is most
separated from other things is best called one.
Crescas
disagrees with Maimonides's opinion that no positive attributes can be applied
to God, such as indicate relation to his creatures, and so on. His arguments
are that we cannot avoid relation to creatures even in the term
"cause," which Maimonides admits; and in the attributes of action—the
only kind of positive attributes allowed by Maimonides—it is implied that
before a given time God did not do a particular thing, which he did later, a
condition in God which Maimonides will not admit. Besides, if there are no
positive attributes, what could be the meaning of the tetragrammaton, about
which Maimonides has so much to say? If it expressed a negative attribute, why
was its meaning kept so secret? Crescas's own view is that there are positive
attributes, and that there is a relation between God and his creatures, though
not a similarity, as they are far apart, the one being a necessary existent,
the other a possible existent; one being infinite, the other finite.
We must
now try to show that God is one in the sense that there are no other Gods
besides. We may proceed as follows: If there are two Gods, one of them controls
only part of the world or he does not control it at all. The first is
impossible because the unitary world must be due to one agent. But there may be
more than one world and hence more than one agent. This is, however, answered
by the thought that being infinite in power one could control them all. There
is still another alternative, viz., that one agent controls the whole world and
the other does nothing. Here speculation can go no further, and we must have
recourse to Scripture, which says, "Hear, O Israel, the Lord our God, the
Lord is One." We see here that Crescas is interested in discrediting the
logic chopping of the philosophers. No merely logical argument, is his idea,
can give us absolute certainty even in so fundamental a doctrine as the unity
of God. Like Judah Halevi, Crescas took his inspiration from Algazali, whose
point of view appealed to him more than that of Maimonides and Gersonides, who
may be classed with Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes.
Having
discussed the fundamental principles of all religion and philosophy, namely,
the existence and nature of God, Crescas next takes up the following six
fundamental dogmas of Judaism, God's knowledge of existing things, Providence,
Power, Prophecy, Freedom, Purpose.
There are
three things to be remembered in the matter of God's knowledge. He knows the
infinite, for he knows particulars. He knows the non-existent, as he knows the
future; and his knowledge of the contingent does not remove its contingent
character. Maimonides and Gersonides had difficulty with this problem and we
know their respective solutions. Gersonides, for reasons metaphysical as well
as ethical, does not scruple to limit God's knowledge to universals. Maimonides
endeavors to reconcile the dilemma by throwing the blame upon our limited
understanding. In God's knowledge which is toto cœlo different from ours, and
of which we have no conception, all oppositions and contradictions find their
ultimate harmony. Crescas, as we might naturally expect, agrees with Maimonides
in this matter rather than with Gersonides. To limit God's knowledge is opposed
to the Bible, and would involve us in greater difficulties than those we
endeavor to escape.
Related
to the question of God's knowledge is the problem of Providence. For God must
know the individual or thing for which he provides, and if God has no knowledge
of particulars, there can be no such thing as special providence. This latter
as we know is virtually the opinion of Gersonides. Crescas, we have seen,
defends God's knowledge of particulars, hence he sees no difficulty in special
providence on this score. He takes, however, the term in a broad sense. All
evidence of design in nature, all powers in plant and animal which guide their
growth, reproduction and conservation are due to God's providence. Providence,
he says, is sometimes exercised by God directly, without an intermediate
voluntary agent, sometimes with such mediation. God's relations to Moses and to
the Israelites in Egypt at the time of the tenth plague were without
intermediate agency. In all other cases there is mediation of angels, or
prophets, or wise men, or, according to some, the heavenly bodies, which are
living and intelligent beings.
Providence
itself is of different kinds. There is the most general and natural exhibited
in the equipment of the various species of plant and animal life for their
protection and growth and conservation. There are the more special powers found
in the human race. These forms of providence have little to do with the
person's deserts. They are purely dependent upon the constitution and influence
of the stars. Then there is the more special providence of the Jewish nation,
then of the male members of this nation, and of the priests and the levites.
Finally comes the special providence of the individual, who is rewarded and
punished according to his conduct. The reward and punishment of this world are
not strictly controlled by conduct, the reward and punishment of the next world
are. In this last remark Crescas cuts the knot which has been the cause of so
much discussion in religious philosophy. If the real reward and punishment are
in the next world, the prosperity of the wicked and the adversity of the
righteous in this world do not form so great a problem. At the same time an
explanation of this peculiar phenomenon is still wanting. For surely the
righteous man does not deserve to suffer for his righteousness, even though his
good deeds will not go unrewarded in the next world. In this discussion also
Crescas takes issue with the intellectualistic point of view of Maimonides and
particularly Gersonides. The solution of these men that evil does not come from
God directly but by accident and by reason of matter, and the corollary drawn
therefrom that God does not punish the wicked directly, that he merely neglects
them, leaving them to the accidents of nature and chance, Crescas does not
approve. Nor is he more favorably inclined to the theory that the good man is
provided for because the more he cultivates his mind, the more closely he comes
in contact with God, in whom are contained actually all the ideas of which man
has some potentially. His main criticism is that the theory is opposed to clear
statements in the Bible, which imply special and individual reward and
punishment in a miraculous and supernatural manner, which cannot be due to
intellectual perfection, nor to the order of the heavenly bodies. Besides, if a
man who is highly intellectual did much wrong, he should be punished in his
soul, but on the intellectualist theory such a soul is immortal and cannot be
destroyed.
Accordingly
Crescas goes back to the religious doctrine of reward and punishment as
ordinarily understood. God rewards and punishes because man obeys or disobeys
his will and command. The complaint raised on account of the misery of the good
and the prosperity of the wicked he answers by saying that real reward and
punishment are in the next world. The goods and evils of this world are also to
be considered, and he gives the ordinary excuses for the apparent deviation
from what ought to be, such as that evil is sometimes a good in disguise and
vice versa; that one sometimes inherits evil and good from one's parents; that
the individual is sometimes involved in the destinies of the majority, and so
on, and so on. Evil in the sense of moral evil, i. e., wrong, does not come
from God, it is true, but punishment does come from God, and as its aim is
justice, it is a good, not an evil. The providence extended to Israel is
greatest. There is more Providence in Palestine than elsewhere, not because
there is any difference in the relation on God's side, but there is on the side
of the man enjoying this providence. His character and disposition change with
the place, and similarly with the time and the season. Hence certain seasons of
the year, like that about the time of the Day of Atonement, are more propitious
for receiving God's providence.
Another
fundamental doctrine of Judaism is God's omnipotence. Weakness would be a
defect. Hence God can do everything except the contradictory. His power is
infinite not merely in duration, but also in intensity. From Aristotle's proof
of the necessity of an immovable mover as based upon the eternity of motion, we
gather only that God's power is infinite in duration; whereas our doctrine of
creation ex nihilo shows that there is no relation at all between God's power
and the work he does; hence his power is infinite. This is shown also in the
miracles, some of which took place instantaneously, as the destruction of the
first born in Egypt at midnight precisely. Crescas insists that the ass of
Balaam did speak, and refers with disapproval to those who doubt it and say it
was in a vision (Gersonides).
In his
discussion of Prophecy the interest lies once more in his
anti-intellectualistic attitude. Maimonides agrees with the philosophers that the
prophetic power is a psychological process attainable by the man who in
addition to moral perfection possesses a highly developed intellect and power
of imagination. To anticipate the objection that if this be so, why are there
no prophets among the philosophers, Maimonides adds that divine grace is
necessary besides, and that if this is lacking, one may have all the
qualifications and yet not be a prophet. Crescas sees the forced nature of this
explanation, and once more frankly returns to the plain intent of Scripture and
Jewish tradition that the prophet is the man chosen by God because he is a
student of the Torah and follows its commandments, and because he cleaves to
God and loves him. The prophet receives his inspiration from God directly or
through an intermediate agent, and the information received may concern any
topic whatsoever. It is not to be limited to certain topics to the exclusion of
others, as Gersonides tries to make out; and its purpose is to give guidance to
the prophet himself or to others through him.
The most
original contribution of Crescas to philosophical theory is his treatment of
the ever living problem of freedom. So fundamental has it seemed for Judaism to
maintain the freedom of the will that no one hitherto had ventured to doubt it.
Maimonides no less than Judah Halevi, and with equal emphasis Gersonides,
insist that the individual is not determined in his conduct. This seemed to be
the only way to vindicate God's justice in reward and punishment. But the idea
of man's freedom clashed with the doctrine of God's omniscience. If nothing in
the past determines a man's will in a given case, then up to the moment of the
act it is undetermined, and no one can know whether a given act will take place
or its opposite. On the other hand, if God does know everything in the future
as well as in the past, man is no longer free to act in a manner contrary to
God's foreknowledge. This difficulty was recognized by Maimonides as well as by
Gersonides, and they solved it in different ways. Maimonides gives up neither
God's omniscience nor man's absolute freedom, and escapes the dilemma by taking
refuge in his idea of God's transcendence. Human knowledge is incompatible with
human freedom; God's knowledge is not like human knowledge, and we have no
conception what it is. But it is consistent with human freedom. Gersonides, who
objects to Maimonides's treatment of the divine attributes, and insists that
they must resemble in kind though not in degree the corresponding human
attributes, can avoid the difficulty only by a partial blunting of the sharp
points of either horn of the dilemma. Accordingly he maintains freedom in all
its rigor, and mitigates the conception of omniscience. God's omniscience
extends only to the universal and its consequences; the contingent particular
is by definition not subject to foreknowledge, and hence it argues no defect in
God's knowledge if it does not extend to the undetermined decisions of the
will.
Crescas
embraces the other horn of the dilemma. God's omniscience must be maintained in
all its rigor. It is absurd to suppose that the first universal and absolute
cause should be ignorant of anything pertaining to its effects. Is man then not
free? Has he no choice at all, no freedom in the determination of his conduct?
If so how justify God's reward and punishment, if reward and punishment are
relative to conduct and imply responsibility? Crescas's answer is a compromise.
Determinism is not fatalism. It does not mean that a given person is
preordained from eternity to act in a given way, no matter what the
circumstances are. It does not mean that command and advice and warning and
education and effort and endeavor are useless and without effect. This is
contradicted by experience as well as by the testimony of Scripture. But
neither is it true on the other hand that a person's will and its conduct are
causeless and undetermined until the moment of action. This idea is equally
untrue to reason and experience. We know that every effect has a cause and the
cause has a cause, and this second cause has again a cause, until we reach the
first necessary cause. Two individuals similar in every respect would have the
same will unless there is a cause which makes them different. We have already
intimated that God's foreknowledge, which we cannot deny, is incompatible with
absolute freedom, and in the Bible we have instances of God's knowing future
events which are the results of individual choice, as in the case of Pharaoh.
The only solution then is that the act of will is in a sense contingent, in a sense
determined. It is contingent in respect to itself, it is determined by its
cause, i. e., the act is not fated to take place, cause or no cause. If it were
possible to remove the cause, the act would not be; but given the cause, the
effect is necessary. Effort is not in vain, for effort is itself a cause and
determines an effect. Commandments and prohibitions are not useless, for the
same reason. Reward and punishment are not unjust, even though antecedent
causes over which man has no control determine his acts, any more than it is
unjust that fire burns the one who comes near it, though he did so without
intention. Reward and punishment are a necessary consequence of obedience and
disobedience.
This is a
bold statement on the part of Crescas, and the analogy between a man's
voluntary act in ethical and religious conduct and the tendency of fire to burn
irrespective of the person's responsibility in the matter can be valid only if
we reduce the ethical and religious world to an impersonal force on a plane
with the mechanism of the physical world order. This seems a risky thing to do
for a religionist. And Crescas feels it, saying that to make this view public
would be dangerous, as the people would find in it an apology for evil doers,
not understanding that punishment is a natural consequence of evil. This latter
statement Crescas does not wish to be taken in its literal strictness, nor
should the analogy with the burning fire be pressed too far. For it would then
follow even if a person is physically compelled to do evil that he would be
punished, just as the fire would not refrain from burning a person who was
thrown into it by force. The determination of the will, he says, must not be
felt by the agent as a constraint and compulsion, else the act is not free and
no punishment should follow; for command and prohibition can have no effect on
a will constrained. Reward and punishment have a pedagogical value generally,
even if in a given case they are not deserved. Even though in reality every act
is determined, still where there is no external compulsion the person is so
identified with the deed that it is in a real sense the product of his own
soul, bringing about a union with, or separation from God; and hence reward and
punishment are necessarily connected with it. Where there is external
compulsion, on the other hand, the act is not in reality his own and hence no
reward or punishment.
The
question arises, however, why should there be punishment for erroneous belief
and opinion? These have nothing to do with the will, and are determined if
anything is, i. e., the person having them is constrained to believe as he does
by the arguments, over which he has no control. This matter offers no
difficulty to those who, like Maimonides and Gersonides, regard intelligence as
the essence of the soul, and make immortality dependent upon intellectual
ideas. A soul acquiring true ideas, they say, becomes ipso facto immortal. It
is not a question of right and wrong or of reward and punishment. But this is
not the Biblical view, and if it were true, there would be no need of the many
ceremonial regulations. Geometry would play a greater rôle in immortality than
the Torah. Crescas’s answer is that reward and punishment in this case are not
for the belief itself, but rather for the pleasure one finds in it and the
pains one takes to examine it carefully. Even in conduct one is not rewarded or
punished for deeds directly, but for the intention and desire. Deed without
intention is not punished. Intention without deed is; though the two together
call for the greatest punishment or reward. "A burnt offering," say
the Rabbis, "atones for sinful thoughts; sin committed through compulsion
is not punished."
It is of
interest here to know that Spinoza, as has been shown by Joel, owed his idea of
man's freedom to Crescas. He also like Crescas denies the absolute
indeterminism of a person's conduct that is insisted upon by the majority of
the medieval Jewish philosophers. And Joel shows moreover that Spinoza's final
attitude to this question as found in his Ethics was the outcome of a gradual
development, and the result of reading Crescas. In some of his earlier writings
he insists that anything short of absolute omniscience in God is unthinkable.
He sees the difficulty of reconciling this with man's freedom, but is not ready
to sacrifice either, and like Maimonides decides that we must not deny it
simply because we cannot understand it. Later, however, he maintains that God's
omniscience and man's freedom are absolutely incompatible, and solves the
difficulty in a manner similar to that of Crescas by curtailing freedom as
formerly understood.
The next
topic of which it is necessary to have a clear idea for a complete
understanding of Judaism, is the purpose of the Law, and in general the purpose
of man. Here also appears clearly the anti-intellectualism of Crescas and his
disagreement with Maimonides and Gersonides. The final purpose of the Law is of
course, he says, a good. The Bible teaches us to perfect our morals; it
inculcates true beliefs and opinions; and it promises by means of these
happiness of body and happiness of soul. Which of these four is the ultimate
end? Clearly it must be the best and most worthy. And it seems as if this
quality pertains to the eternal happiness of the soul, to which as an end the
other three tend. Corporeal happiness is a means to the perfection of the soul
since the latter acts through the means of bodily organs. Similarly moral
perfection assists in purifying the soul. As for perfection in ideas, some think
that it alone makes the soul immortal by creating the acquired intellect, which
is immaterial and separate, and enjoys happiness in the next world incomparably
greater than the joy we feel here below in the acquisition of knowledge. There
is a difference of opinion as to the subject-matter which bestows immortality.
According to some it is all knowledge, whether of sublunar things or of the
separate substances. According to others it is only the knowledge of God and
the angels that confers immortality. All these views are wrong from the
Scriptural as well as the philosophical point of view.
The Bible
makes it clear repeatedly that eternal life is obtained by performance of the
commandments; whereas according to the others practical observance is only a
means and a preparation to theory, without which practice alone is inadequate.
According to Scripture and tradition certain offences are punished with
exclusion from eternal life, and certain observances confer immortality, which
have nothing to do with theoretical truths.
But
philosophically too their views are untenable. For it would follow from their
opinions that the purpose of the Law is for something other than man, for the
acquired intellect is "separate," and hence cannot be the form of
man. It is different in kind from man, for unlike him it is eternal as an
individual. Besides it is not true that the acquired intellect is made as a
substance by its ideas, while being separate from the material intellect; for
as immaterial it has no matter as its subject from which it could come into
being. It must therefore come into being ex nihilo, which is absurd.
And there
are other reasons against their view. For if all knowledge confers immortality,
one may acquire it by studying geometry, which is absurd. And if this privilege
can be gained only by a knowledge of God and the separate substances, the
objection is still greater; for, as Maimonides has shown, the only knowledge
that may be had of these is negative; and it is not likely that such imperfect
knowledge should make an eternal intellect.
If then
theoretical knowledge does not lead to immortality as they thought, and the
other perfections are preparatory to theoretical, it follows that the ultimate
purpose of the Law and of man is attained primarily neither by theory alone nor
by practice alone, but by something else, which is neither quite the one nor
the other. It is the love and fear of God. This is demanded alike by Scripture,
tradition and philosophy. That it is the view of religion is clear enough from
the many passages in the Bible urging love of God. But it is also demanded by
philosophy. For the soul is a spiritual substance, hence it is capable of
separation from the body and of existing by itself forever, whether it has
theoretical knowledge or not; since it is not subject to decay, not being
material. Further, the perfect loves the good and the perfect; and the greater
the good and the perfection the greater the love and the desire in the perfect
being. Hence the perfect soul loves God with the greatest love of which it is
capable. Similarly God's love for the perfect soul, though the object as
compared with him is low indeed, is great, because his essence and perfection
are great. Now as love is the cause of unity even in natural things, the love
of God in the soul brings about a unity between them; and unity with God surely
leads to happiness and immortality. As love is different from intellectual
apprehension, the essence of the soul is love rather than intelligence.
There are
many Talmudical passages confirming this view logically derived. We are told
that the souls of the righteous enjoy the splendor of the Shekinah, and the
wicked suffer correspondingly. This agrees with our conception of immortality
and not with theirs. For enjoyment is impossible on their showing, though they
try to make it plausible. Pleasure is different from apprehension; and as the
essence of the acquired intellect is apprehension, there is no room for the
pleasure, the intellect being simple. According to our view love is rewarded
with pleasure. The pleasure we feel here below in intellectual work proves
nothing, for it is due to the effort and the passing from potential knowledge
to actual knowledge, i. e., to the process of learning. Proof of this is that
we find no pleasure in axioms and first principles, which we know without
effort. But the acquired intellect after the death of the body does not learn
any new truths, hence can have no pleasure.
The
Rabbis also speak of definite places of reward and punishment, which cannot
apply to the acquired intellect, since it is a "separate" substance
and can have no place. The soul as we understand it can have a place, just as
it is connected with the body during life.
The
Rabbis often speak of the great reward destined for school children. But surely
the acquired intellect cannot amount to much in children. The truth is that the
soul becomes mature and complete as soon as it acquires the rational faculty in
the shape of the first principles or axioms. Then it is prepared for
immortality as a natural thing without regard to reward.
The
purpose of the soul as we showed is to love God. This object the Bible attains
by the commandments, which may be classified with reference to their
significance in seven groups. They exalt God; they show his great kindness to
us; they give us true ideas concerning the nature of God; they call our
attention to his providence; they give us promises of corporeal and spiritual
reward; they call our attention to God's miracles in order to keep our attention
from flagging; and finally they command love of God and union with him as the
final aim of man.
In
addition to the six fundamental doctrines of Judaism mentioned above, there are
true beliefs which are essential to Judaism, and the denial of which
constitutes heresy; though they are not as fundamental as the other six, in the
sense that the Law would continue to exist without them. They are (1) Creation,
(2) Immortality, (3) Reward and Punishment, (4) Resurrection, (5) Eternity of
the Law, (6) The superiority of Moses to the other prophets, (7) The priest's
learning the future through the Urim and Tumim, (8) Belief in the Messiah. The
list of thirteen articles of the creed given by Maimonides is open to
criticism. If he meant fundamental dogmas, there are not as many as thirteen;
there are no more than seven or eight—the six mentioned before, and, if one
chooses, the existence of God, making seven, and revelation as the eighth. On
the other hand, if Maimonides meant to include "true beliefs," there
are more than fifteen, the six enumerated above, existence of God and
revelation, and the eight "true beliefs" named at the head of this
section, not counting a great many specific commandments.
Having
made this criticism of Maimonides's thirteen articles, Crescas proceeds to
discuss every one of the eight true beliefs named at the beginning of the last
paragraph. For our purpose it will not be necessary to reproduce the minute
arguments here. We will select a few of the more important topics and state
briefly Crescas's attitude.
The
doctrine of creation formed the central theme in Maimonides and Gersonides. It
was here, as we have seen, that Maimonides stopped short in his devotion to
Aristotle and took pains to show that the arguments of the latter in favor of
eternity are not valid, and that Aristotle knew it. He endeavored to show,
moreover, that the doctrine of creation can be made more plausible than its
opposite, and hence since creation is essential to Judaism, it must be regarded
as a fundamental dogma. Gersonides could not see his way clear to accepting
creation ex nihilo, among other things because as matter cannot come from form,
the material world cannot come from God. Accordingly he compromised by saying
that while the present world as it is is not eternal, it came from a primitive
"hyle" or matter, which was eternal. Thus our world is dependent for
its forms upon God, for its matter upon the prime and eternal "hyle."
Here
Crescas takes up the problem and points out that whether we accept or not an
eternal "hyle," everything that exists must be dependent upon God as
the only necessary existent. Everything outside of him, be it eternal matter or
not, is only a possible existent and owes its existence to God. Creation ex
nihilo means no more. To be sure, if we assume that the existence of the world
and its emanation from God is eternal, because his relation to his product is
the same at all times, it will follow that the emanation of the world from God
is a necessary process. But necessity in this case does not exclude will, nay
it implies it. For the only way in which anything can come from a rational
cause is by way of conception. The rational cause forms a conception of the
world order and of himself as giving existence to this world order as a whole
and in its parts. Will means no more than this. This will also solve the old
philosophic difficulty, how can the many come from the One. Our answer is that
the good God created a good world. The goodness of the world is its unity, i.e., the parts contribute to making a
whole which is good. On the other hand, an agent is perfectly good when he acts
with will. God's will also makes miracles possible. Moreover, eternal creation
is not inconsistent with continued creation, and we have creation ex nihilo every moment. Maimonides is
wrong therefore when he thinks that eternity would upset Judaism and make
miracles impossible. Creation in time is therefore not a fundamental dogma with
which Judaism stands and falls. At the same time it is a true belief as taught
in the first verse of Genesis.
Another
of the true beliefs is reward and punishment. This consists of two kinds,
corporeal and spiritual. Corporeal is spoken of in the Bible and is not opposed
to reason. For as the purpose of creation is to do man good and enable him to
achieve perfection, it stands to reason that God would remove any obstacles in
the way of man's perfecting himself, and this is the kind of reward mentioned
first, "All the diseases which I put upon the Egyptians I shall not put
upon thee, for I the Lord am thy healer" (Exod. 15, 26). Punishment is
primarily for the same purpose.
As for
spiritual reward and punishment, they are not mentioned specifically in the
Bible, but the Talmud is full of it. Rationally they can be explained as
follows. As the soul is spiritual and intellectual, it enjoys great pleasure
from being in contact with the world of spirit and apprehending of the nature
of God what it could not apprehend while in the body. On the other hand, being
restrained from the world of spirit and kept in darkness gives it pain; and
this may lead to its ultimate destruction. The essence of the soul, as was said
above, is not intellectuality, but love and desire; hence pain may destroy it.
The
reason spiritual reward and punishment, which is the more important of the two,
is not mentioned in the Bible, is because it was taken as a matter of fact.
Corporeal reward and punishment was not so regarded, hence the need of
specifying it.
A
difficulty that presents itself is, How is it consistent with justice to punish
the soul by itself, when it was the composite of body and soul that sinned?
This may be answered by saying that the soul is the form of the body and does
not change when separated. Hence, being the more important of the two elements
composing man, it receives the more important punishment, namely, spiritual.
Besides,
it is true that the composite also receives compensation. And this is the
purpose of resurrection.
Resurrection
of the body is not universal, but is reserved only for some, as is clear from
the passage in Daniel (12, 2), "And many of those that sleep in the dust
of the earth shall awake, some to everlasting life, and some to disgrace and
everlasting abhorrence." At the same time it is difficult to know who these
some are. It cannot be the perfect and the good only, since some of those
rising will go "to disgrace and everlasting abhorrence." We can
decide this better later, when we have learned more of resurrection.
The
variety of opinions concerning the time of the resurrection Crescas endeavors
to reconcile by supposing that all agreed it would take place as soon as the
Temple was built, but that the Messiah would precede the building of the Temple
by some length of time.
The
purpose of the resurrection is to strengthen belief in those who have it and to
impress it upon those who have it not. At the time of the resurrection those
who come back to life will tell the living how they fared when their souls left
their bodies. Another purpose of resurrection is, as mentioned above, in order
to reward and punish the composite of body and soul which acted during life.
The dogma
of resurrection is regarded so seriously by the Rabbis, who exclude the
unbeliever in it from a portion in the world to come, because in this act is
completed the form of man; and because thereby is realized the justice of God,
and the faith is strengthened in the minds of the believers.
It seems
at first sight impossible that the elements of the body, which were dispersed
at the time of the body's death and formed part of other substances, can be
gathered together again. But it is not really so strange, for in the first
place God may so arrange matters that these elements may be in a position to
return. Besides, this is not really necessary. It is quite sufficient that God
create a body exactly like the first in temperament and form, and endow it with
the old soul, which will then behave like the old person; and being endowed
with memory besides, the identity of personality will be complete.
For the
purpose of showing God's justice and strengthening man's faith it is sufficient
to resurrect the perfectly good and the completely bad. The intermediate
classes do not deserve this extraordinary miracle, and their spiritual reward
will be sufficient.
CHAPTER XVIIIJOSEPH ALBO (1380-1444)
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|