HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER XVIAARON BEN ELIJAH OF NICOMEDIA
The
chronological treatment of Jewish philosophy which we have followed makes it
necessary at this point to take up a Karaite work of the fourteenth century
that is closely modelled upon the "Guide of the Perplexed." In doing
this we necessarily take a step backward as far as the philosophical
development is concerned. For while it is true that the early Rabbanite
thinkers like Saadia, Bahya, Ibn Zaddik and others moved in the circle of ideas
of the Mohammedan Mutakallimun, that period had long since been passed. Judah
Halevi criticized the Kalam, Ibn Daud is a thorough Aristotelian, and
Maimonides gave the Kalam in Jewish literature its deathblow. No Rabbanite
after Maimonides would think of going back to the old arguments made popular by
the Mutakallimun—the theory of atoms, of substance and accident in the
Kalamistic sense of accident as a quality which needs continuous creation to
exist any length of time, the denial of law and natural causation, the
arguments in favor of creation and the existence of God based upon creation,
the doctrine of the divine will as eternal or created, residing in a subject or
existing without a subject, the world as due to God's will or to his wisdom,
the nature of right and wrong as determined by the character and purpose of the
act or solely by the arbitrary will of God—these and other topics, which formed
the main ground of discussion between the Muʿtazilites and the Ashariya,
and were taken over by the Karaites and to a less extent by the early
Rabbanites in the tenth and eleventh centuries, had long lost their
significance and their interest among the Rabbanite followers of Maimonides.
Aristotelianism, introduced by Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes among the Arabs,
and Ibn Daud and Maimonides among the Jews, dominated all speculative thought,
and the old Kalam was obsolete and forgotten. Gersonides no longer regards the Kalamistic
point of view as a living issue. He ignores it entirely. His problems as we
have seen are those raised by the Averroistic system. In this respect then a
reading of Aaron ben Elijah's "Ez Hayim" (Tree of Life) affects us
like a breath from a foreign clime, like the odor of a thing long buried. And
yet Aaron ben Elijah was a contemporary of Levi ben Gerson. He was born about
1300, and died in 1369. He lived in Nicomedia, Cairo, Constantinople. The
reason for the antiquated appearance of his work lies in the fact that he was a
Karaite, and the Karaites never got beyond the Mutazilite point of view.
Karaism was only a sect and never showed after the days of Saadia anything like
the life and enthusiastic activity of the great body of Rabbanite Judaism, which
formed the great majority of the Jewish people. The Karaites had their
important men in Halaka as well as in religious philosophy and Biblical
exegesis. Solomon ben Yeroham, Joseph Ha-Maor (Al-Kirkisani), Joseph Al Basir,
Jeshua ben Judah, Yefet Ha-Levi, Judah Hadassi, Aaron ben Joseph—all these were
prominent in Karaitic literature. But they cannot be compared to the great men
among the Rabbanites. There was no Maimonides among them. And Aaron ben Elijah
cherished the ambition of being to the Karaites what Maimonides was to the
Rabbanites. Accordingly he undertook to compose three works representing the
three great divisions of Karaitic Judaism—a book of Laws, a work on Biblical
exegesis and a treatise on religious philosophy. The last was written first,
having been composed in 1346. The "Sefer Ha-Mizvot," on the religious
commandments, was written in 1354, and his exegetical work, known as
"Keter Torah" (The Crown of the Law) was published in 1362. It is the
first that interests us, the "Ez Hayim." As was said before, this
book is closely modelled upon the "More Nebukim," though the
arrangement is different, being more logical than that of the
"Guide." Instead of beginning, as Maimonides does, with interpreting
the anthropomorphic expressions in the Bible, which is followed by a treatment
of the divine attributes, long before the existence of God has been proved or
even the fundamental principles laid down upon which are based the proofs of
the existence of God, Aaron ben Elijah more naturally begins with the basal
doctrines of physics and metaphysics, which he then utilizes in discussing the
existence of God. As Maimonides brought to a focus all the speculation on
philosophy and religion as it was handed down to him by Arab and Jew, and gave
it a harmonious and systematic form in his masterpiece; so did Aaron ben Elijah
endeavor to sum up all Karaitic discussion in his work, and in addition declare
his attitude to Maimonides. The success with which he carried out this plan is
not equal. As a source of information on schools and opinions of Arabs and
Karaites, the "Ez Hayim" is of great importance and interest. But it
cannot in the least compare with the "Guide" as a constructive work
of religious philosophy. It has not the same originality or any degree remotely
approaching it. The greater part of the Aristotelian material seems bodily
taken from Maimonides, and so is the part dealing with the anthropomorphic
expressions in the Bible. There is a different point of view in his exposition
of the Mutazilite physics, which he presents in a more systematic and favorable
light than Maimonides, defending it against the strictures of the latter. But
everywhere Aaron ben Elijah lacks the positiveness and commanding mastery of
Maimonides. He is not clear what side of a question to espouse. For the most
part he places side by side the opposed points of view and only barely
intimates his own attitude or preference. Under these circumstances it will not
be necessary for us to reproduce his ideas in
extenso. It will be sufficient if we indicate his relation to Maimonides in
the problems common to both, adding a brief statement of those topics which
Aaron ben Elijah owes to his Karaite predecessors, and which Maimonides omits.
His
general attitude on the relation of religion or revelation to reason and
philosophy is somewhat inconsistent. For while he endeavors to rationalize
Jewish dogma and Scriptural teaching like Maimonides, and in doing so utilizes
Aristotelian terminology in matters physical, metaphysical, psychological,
ethical and logical, he nevertheless in the beginning of his work condemns
philosophy as well as philosophers, meaning of course the Aristotelians. He
nowhere expressly indicates the manner of reconciling this apparent
contradiction. But it would seem as if he intended to distinguish between the
philosophical method and the actual teachings of the Aristotelians. Their
method he approves, their results he condemns. The Aristotelians taught the
eternity of the world, the immutability of natural law, God's ignorance of
particulars and the absence of special Providence. These doctrines must be
condemned. Maimonides too rejects these extreme teachings while praising
Aristotle and maintaining that philosophy was originally a possession of the
Israelitish people, which they lost in the exile. Aaron ben Elijah is not
willing to follow the philosophers as far as Maimonides. He admits positive
attributes in God, which Maimonides rejects; he admits an absolute will in God
and not merely a relative like Maimonides; he extends God's providence to all
individuals including irrational creatures, whereas Maimonides limits special
providence to the individuals of the human species, and so on. And so he
condemns the philosophers, though he cannot help using their method and even
their fundamental doctrines, so far as they are purely theoretical and
scientific. He is willing to go the full length of the Aristotelians only in
the unity and incorporeality of God, though here too he vindicates sense
perception to God, i. e., the knowledge of that which we get through our sense
organs. He too like the philosophers insists on the importance of the reason as
the instrument of truth and knowledge. Abraham was the first, he tells us, who
proved the existence of God with his intellect. Then came the law of Moses,
which strengthened the same idea. The Gentiles hated and envied Israel for
their superiority and their true opinions; hence they endeavored to refute
their ideas and establish others in their stead. This was the work of the
ancient Greek philosophers, who are called enemies in the Bible (Psalms 139,
21). At the time of the second Temple, seeing that the Jewish religion and its
teachings were true, they took advantage of the advent of Jesus to adopt his
false teachings, thus showing their hatred and envy of Israel. At the same
time, however, they were obliged to borrow some views and methods of proof from
Israel, for religion as such is opposed to philosophy. Still the true nature of
God was unknown to them. Then came the Arabs, who imitated the Christians in
adopting a belief different from Judaism, at the same time borrowing views from
the Bible. These are the Mutazila and the Ashariya. Later when on account of
the exile differences arose among the Jews, there were formed the two parties
of the Karaites and the Rabbanites. The Karaites followed the Mutazila, and so
did some of the Rabbanites, because their views coincided with those of the
Bible, from which they were borrowed. The views of the philosophers as being
opposed to the Bible they naturally rejected. Nevertheless some Rabbanites
adopted the views of the philosophers, though believing in the Bible. This is a
mistake, for even the Christians rejected the views of the philosophers.
Here we
see clearly the difference in general attitude between Aaron ben Elijah and
Maimonides. The latter has no use whatsoever for the Mutazila. He realizes the
immeasurable superiority of the Aristotelians (this is the meaning of the word
philosophers in medieval Jewish and Arabic literature). His task is therefore
to harmonize the Bible with Aristotelian doctrine wherever possible. Aaron ben
Elijah is still, in the fourteenth century, a follower of the Kalam, and
believes the Mutazila are closer to Scripture than Aristotle. He is two
centuries behind Maimonides philosophically, and yet he has the truer insight
because less debauched by Aristotelian learning.
As was
said before, Aaron ben Elijah follows a more logical arrangement in the
disposition of his work than Maimonides. In reality it is the old arrangement
of the Kalamistic works. The purpose of all Jewish investigators, he says, is
the same, namely, to prove the existence and nature of God, but there is a
difference among them in the method of proving God's existence. Some base their
proofs on the assumption of the creation of the world, others on that of the
world's eternity. The Mutakallimun follow the former method, the philosophers,
the latter. Their respective views of the origin of the world are determined by
their opinions concerning the principles of existence and the existent, that
is, the fundamental principles of physics and metaphysics. Accordingly Aaron
ben Elijah finds it necessary to give a preliminary account of the Kalamistic
as well as the philosophic theories, as Maimonides did before him . It is not
necessary for us to reproduce here his sketch of the philosophical views, as we
know them sufficiently from our studies of Ibn Daud and Maimonides. But it will
be of value to refer to his account of the Kalamistic principles, though we
have already discussed them in the introduction and in our study of Maimonides
. This is due principally to the fact that Aaron ben Elijah endeavors to defend
the Mutakallimun against Maimonides's charge that they were influenced by
preconceived notions and allowed their religious views to dictate to them their
interpretation of nature, instead of letting the latter speak for itself. Thus
Maimonides specifically accuses them of having adopted the atomic theory of the
pre-Aristotelian philosophers not because they were really and independently
convinced of its scientific truth—how could that be since Aristotle proved it
impossible?—but because on this theory they could prove the creation of the
world, which they must at all hazards maintain as a religious dogma fundamental
in its nature, since upon it is based the proof of the existence of God.
Aaron ben
Elijah denies this charge, maintaining the philosophical honesty of the
Mutakallimun. Epicurus too, he says, believed in the atomic theory, though he
regarded the world as eternal. Hence there is no necessary connection between
atoms and creation. The atomic theory is defensible on its own merits, and the
motives of the Mutakallimun in adopting it are purely scientific, as follows:
According to the Mutakallimun there are only body or substance and its
accidents or qualities. This is the constitution of material objects. There
are, however, two kinds of qualities or attributes, viz.,
"characters," and accidents. Characters are such attributes as are
essential to body and without which it cannot exist. Accidents may disappear,
while body continues. Since, then, body may exist with or without accidents,
there must be a cause which is responsible for the attachment of accidents to
body when they are so attached. This cause we call "union." When a
body is "united" with accidents it owes this to the existence of a
certain something, a certain property, let us say, in it which we have called "union."
Hence when the body is "separated" from accidents, when it is without
accidents, it is because there is no "union." Further, every body
possessed of magnitude or extension is divisible, hence it must have
"union" to hold its parts together. But this "union" is not
essential to all existents; for we have seen that its function is to unite
accidents with body. And as accidents are separable while body may continue to
exist without them, "union" disappears together with the accidents.
Bodies without "union" are therefore possible and real. But we have
just seen that all bodies possessing magnitude have "union." It
follows therefore that if there are "union"-less bodies, they are
without magnitude, and hence atoms. This is the proof of the atomic theory and
it has nothing to do with the matter of the origin of the world. As a matter of
fact the Mutakallimun believe that the atoms were created ex nihilo. But the
creation of the world can be proved whichever view we adopt concerning the
nature of the existent, whether it be the atomic theory of the Mutakallimun or
the principles of matter and form of the Aristotelians. The important principle
at the basis of this proof is the well-known Kalamistic one that if an object
cannot do without an attribute originating in time, the object itself has its
origin in time. Now on either view of the constitution of the existent, body
must have form or accidents respectively, and as the latter are constantly
changing, body or matter has its origin in time, hence the world is not
eternal.
Besides,
not to speak of the inconclusive character of the philosophical arguments in
favor of eternity and the positive arguments for creation (all or most of which
we have already met in our previous studies, and need not therefore reproduce
Aaron ben Elijah's version of them), the philosophers themselves without
knowing it are led to contradict themselves in their very arguments from the
assumption of eternity. The doctrine of creation follows as a consequence from
their own presuppositions. Thus on the basis of eternity of motion they prove
that the heavenly spheres are endowed with soul and intellect, and their
motions are voluntary and due to conceptions which they endeavor to realize.
This makes the sphere a composite object, containing the elements, sphericity,
soul, intellect. Everything composite is a possible existent, because its
existence depends upon the existence of its parts. What is a possible existent
may also not exist. Moreover, that which is possible must at some time become
actual. Hence the sphere must at some time have been non-existent, and it
required an agent to bring it into being. We are thus led to contradict our
hypothesis of eternity from which we started.
Creation
is thus established, and this is the best way to prove the existence, unity and
incorporeality of God. Maimonides attempts to prove creation from the
peculiarities of the heavenly motions, which cannot be well accounted for on
the theory of natural causes. Adopting the latter in the main, he makes an
exception in the case of the spherical motions because the philosophers cannot
adequately explain them, and jumps to the conclusion that here the
philosophical appeal to mechanical causation breaks down and we are dealing
with teleology, with intelligent design and purpose on the part of an intelligent
agent. This leads to belief in creation. But this argument of Maimonides is
very weak and inconclusive. Ignorance of causes in a special case, due to the
limitations of our reason, proves nothing. Mechanical causes may be the sole determinants
of the heavenly motions even though the philosophers have not yet discovered
what they are.
Nor is
Maimonides to be imitated, who bases his proof of the existence of God on the
theory of eternity. The Bible is opposed to it. The Bible begins with creation
as an indication that this is the basis of our knowledge of God's existence,
revelation and providence. This is the method Abraham followed and this is what
he meant when he swore by the "most high God, the creator of heaven and
earth" (Gen. 14, 22). Abraham arrived at this belief through ratiocination
and endeavored to convince others. The same thing is evident in the words of
Isaiah (40, 26), "Lift up your eyes on high and see who created
these." He was arguing with the people who believed in eternity, and
proved to them the existence of God by showing that the world is created. All
these indications in the Bible show that the doctrine of creation is capable of
apodeictic proof.
The
reader will see that all this is directed against Maimonides, though he is not
mentioned by name. Maimonides claimed against the Mutakallimun that it is not
safe to base the existence of God upon the theory of creation, because the
latter cannot be strictly demonstrated. And while he believed in it himself and
gave reasons to show why it is more plausible than eternity, he admitted that
others might think differently; and hence based his proofs of God's existence
on the Aristotelian theory of eternity in order to be on the safe side. It is
never too late to prove God's existence if the world is created. We must be
sure of his existence, no matter what the fate of our cosmological theories
might be. This did not appeal to the Karaite and Mutakallim, Aaron ben Elijah.
His idea is that we must never for a moment doubt the creation of the world. To
follow the procedure of Maimonides would have the tendency of making people
believe that the world may be eternal after all, as happened in fact in the
case of Gersonides. Aaron ben Elijah will not leave a way open to such a heresy.
In the
doctrine of attributes Aaron ben Elijah likewise maintains the views of the Mutazilite
Karaites against the philosophers, and especially against Maimonides. The
general problem is sufficiently familiar to us by this time, and we need only
present the salient points in the controversy. The question is whether there
are any positive attributes which may be applied to God as actually denoting
his essence—hence positive essential attributes. Maimonides denied it, the
Karaites affirmed it. The arguments for Maimonides's denial we saw before. And
his conclusion is that the only attributes that may be applied to God are the
negative, and those positive ones which do not denote any definite thing
corresponding to them in God's essence, but are derived from the effects of
God's unitary and simple being on the life of man and nature. He is the author
of these effects, and we characterize him in the way in which we would
characterize a human being who would do similar things; but this must not be
done.
Aaron ben
Elijah insists that there are positive essential attributes, which are the
following five: Omnipotent, Omniscient, Acting with Will, Living, Existent. He
agrees with Maimonides that these essential attributes must be understood in a
manner not to interfere with God's simplicity and unity, but is satisfied that
this can be done. For we must not conceive of them as additions to God's
essence, nor as so many distinct elements composing God's essence, but as
representing the multiplicity of powers issuing from him without detriment to
his unity. We call them essential attributes, meaning that they are the essence
of God, but not that they are different from each other and each makes up part
of God's essence. We do not know God's essence, and these terms are simply
transferred from our human experience, and do not indicate that God's activity
can be compared to ours in any sense.
The five
attributes above named are all identical with God's simple essence.
"Living" denotes ability to perceive, hence is identical with
"Omniscient." "Acting with will" likewise denotes just and
proper action, which in turn involves true insight. Hence identity of will and
knowledge. "Omnipotent" also in the case of an intellectual being
denotes the act of the intellect par excellence, which is knowledge. And surely
God's existence is not distinct from his essence, else his existence would be
caused, and he would not be the necessary existent all agree him to be. It
follows then that God is one, and his essence is nevertheless all these five
attributes.
There are
all the reasons in the world why we should apply attributes to God. The same
reason as we have for applying names to anything else exists for giving names
to God. In fact it would be correct to say that we should have more names for
God than for anything else, since in other things we can avoid naming them by
pointing to them, as they can be perceived by the senses. Not so God. We are
forced to use words in talking about him. God has given himself names in the
Bible, hence we may do the same.
Maimonides
and his school endeavor to obviate the criticisms of the philosophers, who are
opposed to all attributes, by excluding all but negative terms. But this does
not help the matter in the least. A negative attribute is in reality no
different from a positive, and in the end leads to a positive. Thus if we say
"not mineral," "not plant," we clearly say
"animal." The advocates of negative attributes answer this criticism
by saying that they understand pure negation without any positive implications,
just as when we say a stone is "not seeing," we do not imply that it
is blind. But this cannot be, for when they say God is "not
ignorant," they do not mean that he is not "knowing" either, for
they insist that he is power and knowledge and life, and so on. This being the
case, it is much more proper to use positive attributes, seeing that the
Prophets do so. When they say that the Prophets meant only to exclude the
negative; that by saying, "Able," "Knowing," they meant to
exclude "weak" "ignorant," they ipso facto admit that by
excluding the latter we posit the former.
The
arguments against positive essential attributes we can easily answer. By saying
that certain attributes are essential we do not claim to know God's essence.
All we know is God's existence, which we learn from his effects, and according
to these same effects we characterize God's existence by means of attributes of
which also we know only the existence, not the essence. For we do not mean to
indicate that these terms denote the same thing in God as they denote in us.
They are homonyms, since in God they denote essence, whereas in us they are
accidents. The plurality of attributes does not argue plurality in God, for one
essence may perform a great many acts, and hence we may characterize the
essence in accordance with those acts. The error of composition arises only if
we suppose that the various acts point to various elements in their author. Of
the various kinds of terms those only are applicable to God which denote pure essence
or substance like knowledge, power; and those denoting activity like creating,
doing, and so on.
In
reference to the will of God Aaron ben Elijah refuses to agree with the
peculiar view of the Mutakallimun; but unlike Maimonides, who can afford to ignore
their discussions entirely and dismiss their fanciful notion with a word
("Guide," I. 75, proof 3), Aaron ben Elijah takes up the discussion
seriously. The Mutakallimun (or the Ashariya, according to Aaron ben Elijah)
were in dread of anything that might lend some semblance to eternity of the
world. Hence they argued, If the will of God is identical with his essence like
the other essential attributes, it follows that as his essence is eternal and
unchangeable so is his will. And if we grant this, then the objects of his will
too must be eternal and unchangeable, and we have the much abhorred doctrine of
the eternity of the world. To avoid this objectionable conclusion they
conceived of God's voluntary acts as due to an external will. But this external
will also offered difficulties. It cannot be a power or quality residing in God
as its subject, for God is not a material substance bearing accidents. It
cannot be a quality inherent in another subject, for then it would not be God's
will at all; it would be the will of this other being, and God's acts would be
determined by someone else. They were thus forced to assume a subject-less will
newly created with every act of God. This notion Aaron ben Elijah rejects on
the ground that a subject-less will is an impossibility. An accident must have
a subject, and will implies life as its subject. Besides, the relation between
God and this subject-less accident, will, would be the cause of much logical
difficulty. Aaron ben Elijah therefore accepts the ordinary sane view that the
will of God is identical with his essence; that God wills through his own
essence. And he does not fear that this will lead to eternity of the world. He
identifies God's will with his wisdom, and God's wisdom with right action. As
we do not know the essence of God's wisdom, so we do not know how it is that it
prompts him to realize his will at one time and not at another, though his will
is always the same.
Aaron ben
Elijah also follows his party in attributing to God sense perception, not, to
be sure, the same kind of perception as we have, acquired by means of corporeal
organs; for this is impossible in God for many reasons. God is not corporeal,
and he cannot be affected or changed by a corporeal stimulus. But it is clear
beyond a doubt that nothing can be more absurd than to suppose that the creator
of the sense organs does not understand the purpose which they serve and the
objects which they perceive. What we mean then is that the objects which we
perceive with our senses God also perceives, though in an incorporeal manner.
Hence it does not follow that there is any change in God due to the external
object he perceives, nor that the multiplicity of objects involves plurality in
God; for even our power of perception is one, though it perceives many things
and opposite. We conclude then that God has perception as well as intelligence,
but they are not two distinct powers in him. It is the object perceived that
determines the power percipient. Hence one and the same power may be called
perception when we are dealing with a sensible object, and intelligence when it
has an intelligible as its object.
In his
discussion of the nature of evil we once more are brought in contact with
Kalamistic views recalling the old Karaite works of the eleventh century. Thus
the notion that good and bad are adjectives applied to acts not in view of
their inherent character, which is per se neither good nor bad, but solely to
indicate that they have been commanded or forbidden; the idea that only the
dependent subject can do wrong, but not the master, since his will is the
source of all right and wrong—these views are frequently discussed in the Mutazilite
works of Arabs and Karaites. The Rabbanites scarcely ever mention them. Aaron
ben Elijah enumerates six views on the nature of evil, with all of which except
the last he disagrees. The opinion named above that an act is made good or bad
by being commanded or prohibited, he refutes as follows: Such a view removes
the very foundation of good and bad. For if the person in authority chooses to
reverse his order, the good becomes bad, and the bad good, and the same thing
is then good and bad, which is absurd. Besides, if there are two authorities
giving opposite orders, the same act is good and bad at the same time. To say
that God's command alone determines the character of an act is incorrect,
because as long as commanding and prohibiting as such determine the goodness or
bad ness of an act, the person issuing the command is immaterial. We do say
quite generally that an act which God commands is good, and one which he
prohibits is bad; but we mean by this merely that the command or prohibition is
an indication to us, who are ignorant of the true nature of acts.
Again, on
this theory of the value of acts, what will you do with such an act as the
investigation of the existence and nature of God? Surely such an important
matter cannot be indifferent. It must be good or bad. And yet we cannot apply
to it the above test of command and prohibition, for this test implies the
existence of God, which the act endeavors to prove. It follows therefore that
the value of an act is inherent in it and not determined and created by command
and prohibition.
Aaron ben
Elijah is similarly dissatisfied with another view, which regards evil as a
negation. We have heard this opinion before and we know that Maimonides adopted
it . Its motive as we know is to remove from God the responsibility for evil.
If evil is nothing positive it is not caused by the activity of an agent. All
essential activity is good, and all the acts of God are good. Evil consists in
the absence of good; it is due to matter, and does not come from God. Aaron ben
Elijah objects properly that as good is a positive act, a doing of something
positive, so is evil, even on the theory of its negative character, a removal
of something positive, hence a positive act. Besides, granting all that the
opponent claims, the argument should work both ways, and if God is not held
responsible for the evil in the world because it is mere privation, why should
man be held responsible for doing evil,
i.e., for removing the positive? He clinches his argument by quoting Isaiah
(5, 20), "Woe unto those who say of evil it is good, and of good it is
evil ... that put bitter for sweet, and sweet for bitter." Good and evil
are placed parallel with sweet and bitter, which are both positive. Hence the
Bible is opposed to the negative conception of evil.
His own
view is that good and evil are qualities pertaining to an act by reason of its
own nature, but these are not absolute conceptions like true and false. The
good and the bad are conventional constructs, and the value of an act is
relative to the end or purpose it serves. The purpose of human convention in
regarding certain acts as good and others as bad is the protection of the human
race. An act which conduces to human welfare is good, one that militates against
it is bad. Still there are instances in which an act generally regarded as bad
may assume a different character when in the given instance it serves a good
purpose, as for example when pain is inflicted to obviate more serious danger.
The surgeon, who amputates a leg to save the patient's life, does good, not
evil. The judge, who punishes the criminal with imprisonment or death for the
protection of society and to realize justice, does good, not evil. In this way
we must explain the evil which God brings upon man. God cannot be the cause of
evil. For evil in man is due to want or ignorance. Neither is found in God,
hence he has no motive to do wrong. All the evil of which we complain is only
apparent. In reality it is good, because it is either brought upon us to
prevent still greater evils, or it is in the nature of just punishment for
wrongdoing. In either case it is a good.
Aaron ben
Elijah's discussion of Providence follows closely the plan of the corresponding
arguments in Maimonides. The problem is treated by both in connection with
God's knowledge, and both maintain that the real motive of those who denied
God's knowledge of particulars is their observation of apparent injustice in
the happenings of this world. Both again preface their own views of the
question of Providence by a preliminary statement of the various opinions held
by other sects. Here too the two accounts are in the main similar, except that
Aaron ben Elijah is somewhat more detailed and names a few sects not mentioned
by Maimonides, among them being the Manicheans and the followers of the Syrian
Gnostic Bardesanes. In their own views, however, Aaron ben Elijah and
Maimonides differ; the latter approaching the view of Aristotle, the former
that of the Mutazila.
Maimonides
as we know denies special providence for the individuals of the sublunar world
with the exception of man. In the case of the lower animals, the species alone
are protected by divine providence, hence they will continue forever, whereas
the individual animals are subject to chance. Man, as a rational animal, is an
exception. He is a free and responsible agent, hence he is under divine
guidance and is rewarded and punished for his conduct. The extent of the divine
care depends upon the degree to which the individual develops his reason,
actualizing his potential intellect.
Aaron ben
Elijah argues that this view is erroneous, for it is not proper to make a
distinction between God's knowledge and his providence. If it would argue
imperfection in God not to know certain things, the same objection applies to
limiting his providence, and the two should be coextensive. To say that God's
providence extends to superior and important things and ignores the inferior is
to make God guilty of injustice. Aaron ben Elijah believes therefore that
Providence extends to all individuals, including animals. And he quotes the
Bible in his support, "The Lord is good to all, and his mercies are over
all his works," (Ps. 145, 9), and, "Thou shalt not plough with an ox
and an ass together" (Deut. 22, 10). Maimonides, he says, was led to his
opinion by his idea that death and suffering always involve sin; and not being
able to apply this dictum to the suffering of animals that are slaughtered, he
removed Providence from their individuals entirely. When the Bible orders us to
consider the feelings of the animal, he says the object is to train our own
faculties in mercy, and prevent the formation of habits of cruelty, not for the
sake of the animal. But he cannot remove all difficulties in this way. What
will he do with the case of a person born crippled, and the sufferings of
little children? The idea that death and suffering in all cases involve sin
must be given up. Maimonides is also wrong when he says that reward is purely
intellectual and is dependent upon the development of the "acquired
intellect." It would follow from this that right conduct as such is not
rewarded; that it serves merely as a help to realizing the acquired intellect.
All this is opposed to Biblical teaching.
The
prosperity of the wicked and the adversity of the righteous Aaron ben Elijah
endeavors to explain as follows. The prosperity of the wicked may be due to
former good deeds; or by way of punishment, that he may continue in his evil
deeds and be punished more severely. It may be in order that he may use the
good fortune he has in whatever way he pleases, for good or ill. Finally his
good fortune may be given him as a matter of grace, like his creation.
Correspondingly we may explain the adversity of the righteous in a similar
manner. It may be due to former sins. If he has no sins, his sufferings may be
intended to test him in order to add to his reward. If he dies without having
enjoyed life, he will be rewarded in the next world. The pleasures of this
world must not be considered. For since they are given as a matter of grace,
they may come or not without involving any injustice. When a man has both good
deeds and sins, he may be rewarded for his good deeds and punished for his bad,
or he may be paid according to the element which predominates. Those who are
born crippled and the sufferings of children will be rewarded later. In
reference to the slaughter of animals, Aaron ben Elijah does not agree with the
Mutazila that the animals will be recompensed for their undeserved sufferings.
There is no immortal part in animals, hence no reward after death. He can
assign no reason for their sufferings except that men need them for food, but
he sees nothing wrong in taking an animal's life for food, for as the life of
animals was given to them as a matter of grace, there is no wrong in taking it
away. However, to inflict pain in a way different from the manner permitted by
God is wrong.
Aaron ben
Elijah lays great stress upon what he considers an important difference of
opinion between the Rabbanites and the Karaites concerning the nature and
purpose of divine punishment. The Rabbanites according to him insist that
"there is no death without sin, nor suffering without guilt," whereas
the Karaites admit that some of the sufferings of the righteous are not in the
nature of punishment at all, but are what are known as "chastisements of
love." Their purpose is to increase the man's reward later in the future
world, and at the same time they have a pedagogical value in themselves in
strengthening the person spiritually. Accordingly Aaron ben Elijah, who in the
main follows the opinions of the Karaites, differs with the Rabbanites and
particularly Maimonides in the interpretation of the "trials" of
Adam, Abraham, Job.
So far as
Job is concerned, we know the opinions of Maimonides on the subject. In his
"Guide of the Perplexed" he interprets the book of Job in connection
with his discussion of Providence. In the general nature of suffering the idea
of "chastisement of love" is quite familiar to the Rabbis, though
Maimonides does not care to insist on it, claiming that there is no support for
it in the Bible. The idea of "trial" according to him is neither that
God may know what he did not know before; nor is it to make a man suffer that
he may be rewarded later. The purpose of trial is that mankind may know
whatever it is desired to teach them in a given case. In the trial of Abraham
when he was told to sacrifice Isaac, there was a two-fold reason; first, that
all may know to what extent the love of God may go in a pious man; and second
to show that a prophet is convinced of the reality of his visions as an
ordinary person is of the data of his senses.
The book
of Job is to Maimonides a treatise on Providence, and the five characters in
the drama represent the various opinions on the nature of Providence as they
were held by different schools of philosophy and theology in Maimonides's day.
Job has the Aristotelian view that God cares nothing for man. Eliphaz
represents the correct Jewish view that everything is reward or punishment for
merit and demerit. Bildad maintains the Mutazilite opinion that many
misfortunes are for the purpose of increasing reward in the world to come.
Zophar stands for the view of the Ashariya that all is to be explained by reference
to the will of God, and no questions should be asked. Elihu finally insists
that the individual man is the object of the divine care, but that we must not
compare God's providence with our own interest in, and care for things; that
there is no relation at all between them except in name. The Rabbis, who do not
make of Job a philosopher, naturally do not understand the matter as Maimonides
does, but they nevertheless agree with him that Job deserved the punishment he
received. The Karaites on the other hand classed Job's sufferings with
"chastisements of love," which would mean that Job was a perfect man
and did not deserve any punishment. The sole motive for inflicting pain and
tribulation upon him was to reward him the more later.
Aaron ben
Elijah agrees in the main with his Karaite predecessors that Job was not
punished for any fault he had committed. He does not see in the arguments of
Job's friends any difference of opinion on the general question of Providence,
and Job was not an Aristotelian. Unlike Aristotle, he did believe in God's care
for man, as is evident from such statements as (Job 10, 10), "Behold like
milk didst thou pour me out, and like cheese didst thou curdle me." The
Karaites, he holds, are correct in their main contention that Job's sufferings
were not in the nature of punishment for previous guilt and wrongdoing, but
they are mistaken in supposing that Job was altogether right in his conception
of the meaning and reason of his sufferings; that they had no other purpose except
to increase his reward in the future. Aaron ben Elijah then explains his own
view of "trial."
Man, he
says, is composed of body and soul, and must therefore endeavor to gain this
world and the next. If he is punished for guilt or offence, the punishment
corresponds to the offence. Corporeal guilt is followed by corporeal
punishment, spiritual guilt by spiritual punishment. Adam offended spiritually
and was punished spiritually by being driven from the Garden of Eden as will be
explained later. Abraham endeavored to do justice to both the constituent parts
of his being; and hence God in his kindness, wishing to strengthen Abraham
spiritually, gave him the opportunity in the trial of Isaac. At the same time
the physical suffering was compensated by the promise to Abraham of the
continuity of Isaac's descendants. Job's sufferings were of the same kind,
except that they came to him without his knowledge and without his being told
their purpose. And at first he thought they were in order to give him future reward,
but without any use in themselves. Later he discovered that they benefited him
directly by increasing his spiritual strength.
Aaron ben
Elijah differs also from Maimonides in reference to the purpose of the world.
Maimonides maintains that while there is sense in inquiring for the purpose of
the parts of the world, the question of the ultimate purpose of the world as a
whole is meaningless. The purpose of a given event or law of nature lies in its
relation to the other events and laws, hence there is a relative purpose in
particular things; thus, given the existence of animals they must have food,
sense perception, and so on. But if we ask why the universe as a whole, the
only answer that can be given is God's wisdom, which we do not understand. In particular
Maimonides will not admit that the world is for the sake of man, as this view
clashes with experience and makes it impossible to explain a great many
phenomena in nature, which are distinctly of no benefit to man and take no
cognizance of his interests. Aaron ben Elijah agrees with Maimonides that God's
wisdom rather than his arbitrary will, as the Ashariya maintain, must be
appealed to in answering the question of the purpose of the world. But he is
inclined to regard man as the purpose of the lower world, admitting that we
cannot know the purpose of the higher worlds of the spheres and Intelligences,
as they transcend the powers of our comprehension.
We can
pass over Aaron ben Elijah's discussion of prophecy very briefly because there
is no new attitude or contribution in his views. Without saying it, he
reluctantly perhaps, leans upon Maimonides, and with apparent variations in
form really adopts the classification of the "Guide". He gives no
psychological explanation of prophecy because he disagrees with the
philosophers, to whom prophecy is a purely natural gift which cannot fail to
manifest itself when the requisite conditions are there, namely, perfection in
intellect and imagination. In fact when he gives the different views on the
nature of prophecy, he refuses to identify what seems to stand in his book for
the view of Maimonides (the fourth view) with that of the followers of the
Mosaic law. Whereas Maimonides following the philosophers insists on the two
important elements in prophecy, namely, intellect and imagination, adding
thereto also moral perfection, Aaron ben Elijah in giving the opinion of those
who follow the law of Moses, says nothing of the imagination. He insists only
on perfection in intellect and in ethical character. This difference is,
however, only apparent; and further on he refers to the imagination as an
important element, which determines, in its relation to the reason, the
character of a man as a prophet or a mere statesman or philosopher—all in the
manner of Maimonides.
His idea
of the purpose of prophecy he develops, as it seems, with an eye to the
criticism of the Brahmins of India, whom he quotes as denying prophecy, though
admitting Providence, on the ground that it can serve no purpose. The reason
alone, they say, is sufficient to decide what is right and what is wrong.
Accordingly Aaron ben Elijah meets their objection as follows: It is true that
man might have gotten along without prophecy through the laws which his own
reason established for right and wrong, good and evil. Those who followed these
rational laws would have attained long life, and the others would have
perished. But a good man living in a bad environment would have been involved
in the downfall of the majority, which would not be just. Hence it was necessary
that God should warn the man, that he might save himself. This is the first
beginning of prophecy. Witness Noah and Lot. Abraham was a great advance on his
predecessors. He endeavored to follow God's will in respect to both body and
soul. Hence God saved him from the danger to which he was exposed in Ur of the
Chaldees, and wanted to benefit his descendants also that they should perfect
their bodies and their souls. This is impossible for a whole nation without
special laws to guide them. This is particularly true of the
"traditional" laws (ceremonial), which are not in themselves good or
bad, but are disciplinary in their nature.
A prophet
must have both intellectual and ethical perfection. For he must understand the
nature of God in order to communicate his will; and this cannot be had without
previous ethical perfection. Hence the twofold requirement. This is the reason,
he says, why we do not believe in the religions of Jesus and Mohammed, because
they were not possessed of intellectual perfection. And besides they tend to
the extinction of the human species by reason of their monastic and celibate
ideal. They were misled by the asceticism of the prophets, who meant it merely
as a protest against the material self-indulgence of the time, and called
attention to the higher life. But those people in their endeavor to imitate the
prophets mistook the means for the end, with the result that they missed both,
perfection of soul as well as of body, and merely mortified the flesh, thinking
it the will of God. Hence, Aaron ben Elijah continues, we shall never accept a
religion which does not preach the maintenance of this world as well as of the
next. Not even miracles can authenticate a religion which preaches monasticism
and celibacy.
Moses was
superior to the other prophets. All the others received their messages in a
vision or a dream, Moses had his inspiration while awake. The others were
inspired through the medium of an angel, i.e.,
through the imagination, hence their language abounds in allegories and
parables. Moses did not use the imagination, hence the plain character of his
speech. The others were overcome by the vision and physically exhausted, as we
read in Daniel (10, 17), "There remained no strength in me, and no breath
was left in me." Moses was free from this weakness—"And the Lord
spoke unto Moses face to face, as a man speaketh unto his neighbor" (Exod.
33, 11). The others required preparation, Moses did not. Moses's testimony,
too, was stronger than that of all the rest. His authority in the end was made
plain to all the people directly and openly, so that there remained not a shred
of a doubt. This is why we accept his law and no other, because none is so well
authenticated. The Law cannot change without implying that the standard of
perfection has changed, or the world has changed, or God's knowledge has
changed. All this is impossible. The Law says besides, "Thou shalt not add
thereto, and thou shalt not diminish therefrom" (Deut. 13, 1). Therefore,
concludes Aaron ben Elijah the Karaite, we do not believe in the oral or
traditional law because of the additions to, and subtractions from, the written
law which it contains.
Aaron ben
Elijah agrees with Maimonides that all the commandments of the Bible, including
the ceremonial laws, have a purpose and are not due to the arbitrary will of
God. The ceremonial laws are for the sake of the rational, serving a
pedagogical and disciplinary purpose, and the Law as a whole is for the purpose
of teaching the truth and inculcating the good. He goes further than Maimonides
in vindicating the rational and ethical purpose of all the details of the
various laws, and not merely of the several commandments as a whole.
A problem
that occupied the minds of the Mutakallimun, Arabs as well as Karaites, but
which Maimonides does not discuss, is the purpose of God's giving commandments
to those who he knew would remain unbelievers, and refuse to obey. That God's
knowledge and man's freedom co-exist and neither destroys the other, has
already been shown. If then God knows, as we must assume, that a given person
will refuse to obey the commandments, what is the use of giving them to him?
And granting that for some reason unknown to us they have been given, is it
just to punish him for disobedience when the latter might have been spared by
not giving the man in question any commandments?
Aaron ben
Elijah answers these questions by citing the following parallel. A man prepares
a meal for two guests and one does not come. The absence of the guest does not
make the preparation improper, for the character of the act does not depend
upon the choice of the guest to do or not to do the desire of the host. The
invitation was proper because the host meant the guest's benefit. To be sure,
the case is not quite parallel, and to make it so we must assume that the host
expects that the guest will not come. His intention being good, the invitation
is proper. In our problem knowledge takes the place of expectation. God does
not merely expect, he knows that the man will not obey. But as God's desire is
to benefit mankind and arouse them to higher things, the command is proper, no
matter what the person chooses to do.
To punish
the man for disobedience is not unjust because God intended to benefit him by
the command. If he disobeyed, that is his lookout. If the benefit could have
been had without the command, then the punishment would be unjust, but not
otherwise.
If only
good men were commanded and the rest ignored, the danger would be that the
former being thereby assured of reward, might be tempted to do wrong; and the
others in despair might be worse than they would be under ordinary
circumstances. God saw that man has evil tendencies, and needs warning and
guidance from without. And just as he gave men understanding and ability to
believe though he knew that a given person would not avail himself thereof, so
he gave all men commandments, though he knew that some would not obey.
The rest
of the book is devoted to such questions as reward and punishment after death,
immortality of the soul, the problem of the soul's pre-existence, the nature of
the future life, repentance—questions which Maimonides left untouched in the
"Guide" on the ground that whatever religion and tradition may say
about them, they are not strictly speaking scientific questions, and are not
susceptible to philosophical demonstration.
Aaron ben
Elijah proves that there must be reward and punishment after death. For as man
is composed of body and soul, there must be reward for each according as man
endeavors to maintain and perfect them. Thus if a man cares for his body alone,
he will be rewarded in his body, i.e., in this world. The other man who looks out for both body and soul must have the
same reward in this world as the other, since their physical efforts were
similar. At the same time he must have something over and above the other in
the nature of compensation for his soul, and this must be in the next world.
The
prosperity of the wicked and the misery of the righteous are also to be
explained in part, as we have seen, by reference to their respective destinies
in the next world, where the inequalities of this world will be adjusted.
Finally,
material reward cannot be the consequence of intellectual and spiritual merit;
it would mean doing the greater for the sake of the smaller. And besides the
soul is not benefited by physical goods and pleasures, and would remain without
reward. Hence there must be another kind of reward after death. In order to
deserve such reward the soul must become wise. At the same time the common
people, who observe the ceremonial commandments, are not excluded from a share
in the world to come, because the purpose of these laws is also intellectual
and spiritual, as we said before, and hence their observance makes the soul
wise, and gives it immortality. This last comment is clearly directed against
the extreme intellectualism of Maimonides and Gersonides, according to whom
rational activity alone confers immortality.
The
considerations just adduced imply the immortality of the soul, to which they
lend indirect proof. But Aaron ben Elijah endeavors besides to furnish direct
proof of the soul's continuance after the death of the body. And the first
thing he does is to disarm the criticism of the philosophers, who deny
immortality on the ground that the soul being the form of the body, it must
like other material forms cease with the dissolution of the things of which
they are the forms. He answers this by showing that the soul as the cause of
knowledge and wisdom—immaterial faculties—is itself immaterial. Being also the
cause of the body's motion, it is not itself subject to motion, hence not to
time, and therefore not destructible like a natural form. Besides the composition
of body and soul is different from that of matter and form in the ordinary
sense. For in the former case each of the constituent parts is already a
composite of matter and form. The body has both matter and form, and the soul
has likewise. For the acquired intellect is the form of the soul, which is the
matter. Other proofs are as follows: The rational soul performs its functions
without help from the body, hence it is independent in its existence. The proof
of the last statement is that the power of the rational soul is not limited,
and does not become weary, as a corporeal power does. Hence it can exist
without the body. Again, as the corporeal powers grow stronger, the
intellectual powers grow weaker, and vice versa as the corporeal powers grow
weaker in old age, the intellect grows stronger. Hence the soul is independent
of the body, and when the physical powers cease entirely in death, the
intellect is at its height.
The
question of the soul’s pre-existence before coming in contact with the body,
Aaron ben Elijah answers in the affirmative, though his arguments in favor of
the opposite view are stronger. His sole argument in favor of its pre-existence
is that the soul, being a self-subsisting substance and not an accident, is not
dependent upon the body, and must have existed before the body. The consequence
which some have drawn from this supposition combined with the soul's
immortality, namely, that the soul is eternal, he refuses to adopt. The soul
existed before the body, but like all things which are not God it was created
in time.
Though we
have thus seen that the soul existed before the body, it is mistaken to suppose
that it was completely developed. For though the gradual progress in knowledge
and understanding as the individual matures proves nothing for the soul's
original imperfection, as we may account for this progress by the gradual
adaptation of the physical elements to the functions of the soul, there is a
more valid objection. If the soul was perfectly developed before entering the
body, all souls should be alike when they leave it, which is not the case. We
come to the conclusion therefore that the soul does acquire knowledge while in
contact with the body. The human soul is a unit, and from its connection with
the body arise the various powers, such as growth, life, reason. When the soul
is separated from the body, those powers which functioned with the aid of the body
perish; the others remain.
In the
matter of eschatology Aaron ben Elijah gives a number of views without
declaring himself definitely for any of them. The main difference among the
three points of view quoted concerns the possibility of the resurrection of the
body, and the meaning of the terms "revival of the dead"
("Tehiyat ha-metim") and "the world to come" ("Olam
ha-ba"). Aaron ben Elijah seems to incline to the first, in favor of
resurrection.
We must
endeavor, he says, to get some notion of final reward and punishment. For
without any idea of its nature a man's hope or fear is taken away from him, and
he has no motive for right conduct. To be sure it is not possible to get a
clear understanding of the matter, but some idea we must have. The first view
which he seems to favor is that revival of the dead and world to come are the
same thing; that the end of man is the resurrection of the body and its reunion
with the soul. This is the future life, and this is meant by reward and
punishment. There is Biblical support for this view in such expressions as,
"Thy dead shall live, thy dead bodies shall arise" (Isa. 26, 19).
"The Lord killeth, and maketh alive; he bringeth down to the grave and
bringeth up" (1 Sam. 2, 6). There is nothing to object in this, he says,
for the same God who made man of the dust can revive him after death. Besides,
there seems to be a logical propriety in bringing soul and body together for
reward and punishment just as they were during conduct in life. When the soul
is once reunited with the body in the resurrection, it is never separated
again. The expression "garden of Eden" for paradise is a figure of
speech for eternal life free from pain.
The
second opinion is expressed by those who do not believe in bodily resurrection.
The end of man according to these is the return of the soul to the world of
souls. This is the meaning of "world to come"; and "revival of
the dead" means the same thing. For it is not possible that the soul
should be reunited with the body, which is temporary in its nature and subject
to dissolution. Besides, the body has organs, such as those of food and
reproduction, which would be useless in the future life. The advocates of this
theory also believe in transmigration of souls as a punishment. Aaron ben
Elijah rejects metempsychosis on the ground that there is some relation between
a soul and its body, and not every body can receive every soul.
Aaron ben
Elijah also quotes without comment the classification, already familiar to us ,
of human souls into (1) dead, (2) alive, (3) healthy, and (4) sick. Death
denotes evil deeds; life, good deeds; health, intellectual knowledge; disease,
ignorance. This classification is applied in determining the destiny of the
soul after death. If one is alive and healthy, i. e., has knowledge and good
deeds, he has a share in the world to come. If he is healthy and dead
(knowledge + evil deeds), the soul is kept in an intermediate world forever. If
he is alive and sick (good deeds + ignorance), the soul rises to the upper air,
whence it returns again and again to the body until it acquires wisdom to be
able to rise to the world of angels. If he is dead and sick (evil deeds +
ignorance), the soul dies like an animal.
Finally,
the third opinion is a combination of resurrection and "future
world." Seeing that some of the functions of the soul are performed with
the help of the body, while others are not, the advocates of this view maintain
that the soul will be rewarded in both conditions—with the body, in
resurrection, without the body, in the world to come.
If a man
has merits and demerits, his good and evil deeds are balanced against each
other, and the surplus determines his reward or punishment according to its
nature.
CHAPTER XVII .HASDAI BEN ABRAHAM CRESCAS (1340-1410)
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|