HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER XV.LEVI BEN GERSON
Among the
men who devoted themselves to philosophical investigation in the century and a
half after Maimonides's death, the greatest and most independent was without
doubt Levi ben Gerson or Gersonides, as he is also called. There were others
who were active as commentators, translators and original writers, and who
achieved a certain fame, but their work was too little original to merit more
than very brief notice in these pages. Isaac Albalag (second half of thirteenth
century) owes what reputation he enjoys to the boldness with which he
enunciated certain doctrines, such as the eternity of the world and
particularly the notion, well enough known among the Averroists of the
University of Paris at that time and condemned by the Church, but never before
announced or defended in Jewish philosophy—the so-called doctrine of the twofold
truth. This was an attitude assumed in self-defence, sincerely or not as the
case may be, by a number of scholastic writers, who advanced philosophic views
at variance with the dogma of the Church. They maintained that a given thesis
might be true and false at the same time, true for philosophy and false for
theology, or vice versa. Shem Tob Falaquera (1225-1290) is a more important man
than Albalag. He was a thorough student of the Aristotelian and other
philosophy that was accessible to him through his knowledge of Arabic. Munk’s
success in identifying Avicebron with Gabirol was made possible by Falaquera’s
translation into Hebrew of extracts from the "Fons Vitae." Of great
importance also is Falaquera’s commentary of Maimonides's "Guide,"
which, with that of Moses of Narbonne (d. after 1362), is based upon a
knowledge of Arabic and a thorough familiarity with the Aristotelian philosophy
of the Arabs, and is superior to the better known commentaries of Shemtob,
Ephodi, and Abarbanel. Falaquera also wrote original works of an ethical and
philosophical character.
Joseph
Ibn Caspi (1297-1340) is likewise a meritorious figure as a commentator of
Maimonides and as a philosophical exegete of Scripture. But none of these men
stands out as an independent thinker with a strong individuality, carrying
forward in any important and authoritative degree the work of the great
Maimonides. Great Talmudic knowledge, which was a necessary qualification for
national recognition, these men seem not to have had; and on the other hand
none of them felt called upon or able to make a systematic synthesis of philosophy
and Judaism in a large way.
Levi ben
Gerson (1288-1344) was the first after Maimonides who can at all be compared
with the great sage of Fostat. He was a great mathematician and astronomer; he
wrote supercommentaries on the Aristotelian commentaries of Averroes, who in
his day had become the source of philosophical knowledge for the Hebrew
student; he was thoroughly versed in the Talmud as his commentary on the Pentateuch
shows; and he is one of the recognized Biblical exegetes of the middle ages.
Finally in his philosophical masterpiece "Milhamot Adonai" (The Wars
of the Lord), he undertakes to solve in a thoroughly scholastic manner those
problems in philosophy and theology which Maimonides had either not treated
adequately or had not solved to Gersonides's satisfaction. That despite the
technical character and style of the "Milhamot," Gersonides achieved
such great reputation shows in what esteem his learning and critical power were
held by his contemporaries. His works were all written in Hebrew, and if he had
any knowledge of Arabic and Latin it was very limited, too limited to enable
him to make use of the important works written in those languages. His fame extended
beyond the limits of Jewish thought, as is shown by the fact that his
scientific treatise dealing with the astronomical instrument he had discovered
was translated into Latin in 1377 by order of Pope Clement VI, and his
supercommentaries on the early books of the Aristotelian logic were
incorporated, in Latin translation, in the Latin editions of Aristotle and
Averroes of the 16th century.
Levi ben
Gerson's general attitude to philosophical study and its relation to the
content of Scripture is the same as had become common property through
Maimonides and his predecessors. The happiness and perfection of man are the
purpose of religion and knowledge. This perfection of man, or which is the same
thing, the perfection of the human soul, is brought about through perfection in
morals and in theoretical speculation, as will appear more clearly when we
discuss the nature of the human intellect and its immortality. Hence the
purpose of the Bible is to lead man to perfect himself in these two
elements—morals and science. For this reason the Law consists of three parts.
The first is the legal portion of the Law containing the 613 commandments,
mandatory and prohibitive, concerning belief and practice. This is preparatory
to the second and third divisions of the Pentateuch, which deal respectively
with social and ethical conduct, and the science of existence. As far as ethics
is concerned it was not practicable to lay down definite commandments and
prohibitions because it is so extremely difficult to reach perfection in this
aspect of life. Thus if the Torah gave definite prescriptions for exercising
and controlling our anger, our joy, our courage, and so on, the results would
be very discouraging, for the majority of men would be constantly disobeying
them. And this would lead to the neglect of the other commandments likewise.
Hence the principles of social and ethical conduct are inculcated indirectly by
means of narratives exemplifying certain types of character in action and the
consequences flowing from their conduct. The third division, as was said
before, contains certain teachings of a metaphysical character respecting the
nature of existence. This is the most important of all, and hence forms the
beginning of the Pentateuch. The account of creation is a study in the principles
of philosophical physics.
As to the
relations of reason and belief or authority, Levi ben Gerson shares in the
optimism of the Maimonidean school and the philosophic middle age generally,
that there is no opposition between them. The priority should be given to
reason where its demands are unequivocal, for the meaning of the Scriptures is
not always clear and is subject to interpretation. On the other hand, after
having devoted an entire book of his "Milhamot" to a minute investigation
of the nature of the human intellect and the conditions of its immortality, he
disarms in advance all possible criticism of his position from the religious
point of view by saying that he is ready to abandon his doctrine if it is shown
that it is in disagreement with religious dogma. He developed his views, he
tells us, because he believes that they are in agreement with the words of the
Torah. This apparent contradiction is to be explained by making a distinction
between the abstract statement of the principle and the concrete application
thereof. In general Levi ben Gerson is so convinced of man's prerogative as a
rational being that he cannot believe the Bible meant to force upon him the
belief in things which are opposed to reason. Hence, since the Bible is subject
to interpretation, the demands of the reason are paramount where they do not
admit of doubt. On the other hand, where the traditional dogma of Judaism is
clear and outspoken, it is incumbent upon man to be modest and not to claim the
infallibility of direct revelation for the limited powers of logical inference
and deduction.
We must
now give a brief account of the questions discussed in the "Milhamot
Adonai." And first a word about Gersonides's style and method. One is
reminded, in reading the Milhamot, of Aristotle as well as Thomas Aquinas.
There is no rhetoric and there are no superfluous words. All is precise and
technical, and the vocabulary is small. One is surprised to see how in a brief
century or so the Hebrew language has become so flexible an instrument in the
expression of Aristotelian ideas. Levi ben Gerson does not labor in the
expression of his thought. His linguistic instrument is quite adequate and
yields naturally to the manipulation of the author. Gersonides, the minute
logician and analyst, has no use for rhetorical flourishes and figures of
speech. The subject, he says, is difficult enough as it is, without being made
more so by rhetorical obscuration, unless one intends to hide the confusion of
one's thought under the mask of fine writing. Like Aristotle and Thomas
Aquinas, he gives a history of the opinions of others in the topic under
discussion, and enumerates long lists of arguments pro and con with rigorous
logical precision. The effect upon the reader is monotonous and wearisome.
Aristotle escapes this by the fact that he is groping his way before us. He has
not all his ideas formulated in proper order and form ready to deliver. He is
primarily the investigator, not the pedagogue, and the brevity and obscurity of
his style pique the ambitious reader and spur him on to puzzle out the meaning.
Not so Thomas Aquinas and the scholastics generally. As the term scholastic
indicates, they developed their method in the schools. They were expositors of
what was ready made, rather than searchers for the new. Hence the question of
form was an important one and was determined by the purpose of presenting one's
ideas as clearly as may be to the student. Add to this that the logic of
Aristotle and the syllogism was the universal method of presentation and the
monotony and wearisomeness becomes evident. Levi ben Gerson is in this respect
like Aquinas rather than like Aristotle. And he is the first of his kind in
Jewish literature. Since the larger views and problems were already common property,
the efforts of Gersonides were directed to a more minute discussion of the more
technical details of such problems as the human intellect, prophecy,
Providence, creation, and so on. For this reason, too, it will not be necessary
for us to do more than give a brief résumé of the results of Gersonides's
lucubrations without entering into the really bewildering and hair-splitting
arguments and distinctions which make the book so hard on the reader.
We have
already had occasion in the Introduction to refer briefly to Aristotle's theory
of the intellect and the distinction between the passive and the active
intellects in man. The ideas of the Arabs were also referred to in our
treatment of Judah Halevi, Ibn Daud and Maimonides. Hillel ben Samuel, as we saw,
was the first among the Jews who undertook to discuss in greater detail the
essence of the three kinds of intellect, material, acquired and active, as
taught by the Mohammedan and Christian Scholastics, and devoted some space to
the question of the unity of the material intellect. Levi ben Gerson takes up
the same question of the nature of the material intellect and discusses the
various views with more rigor and minuteness than any of his Jewish
predecessors. His chief source was Averroes. The principal views concerning the
nature of the possible or material intellect in man were those attributed to
Alexander of Aphrodisias, the most important Greek commentator of Aristotle
(lived about 200 of the Christian Era), Themistius, another Aristotelian Greek
commentator who lived in the time of Emperor Julian, and Averroes, the famous
Arabian philosopher and contemporary of Maimonides. All these three writers
pretended to expound Aristotle's views of the passive intellect rather than
propound their own. And Levi ben Gerson discusses their ideas before giving his
own.
Alexander's
idea of the passive intellect in man is that it is simply a capacity residing
in the soul for receiving the universal forms of material things. It has no
substantiality of its own, and hence does not survive the lower functions of
the soul, namely, sensation and imagination, which die with the body. This
passive intellect is actualized through the Active Intellect, which is not a
part of man at all, but is identified by Alexander with God. The Active
Intellect is thus pure form and actuality, and enables the material or possible
intellect in man, originally a mere potentiality, to acquire general ideas, and
thus to become an intellect with a content. This is called the actual or
acquired intellect, which though at first dependent on the data of sense, may
succeed later in continuing its activity unaided by sense perception. And in so
far as the acquired intellect thinks of the purely immaterial ideas and things
which make up the content of the divine intellect (the Active Intellect), it
becomes identified with the latter and is immortal. The reason for supposing
that the material intellect in man is a mere capacity residing in the soul and
not an independent substance is because as having the capacity to receive all
kinds of forms it must itself not be of any form. Thus in order that the sense
of sight may receive all colors as they are, it must itself be free from color.
If the sight had a color of its own, this would prevent it from receiving other
colors. Applying this principle to the intellect we make the same inference
that it must in itself be neutral, not identified with any one idea or form,
else this would color all else knocking for admission, and the mind would not
know things as they are. Now a faculty which has no form of its own, but is a
mere mirror so to speak of all that may be reflected in it, cannot be a
substance, and must be simply a power inherent in a substance and subject to
the same fate as that in which it inheres. This explains the motive of
Alexander's view and is at the same time a criticism of the doctrine of
Themistius.
This
commentator is of the opinion that the passive intellect of which Aristotle
speaks is not a mere capacity inherent in something else, but a real spiritual
entity or substance independent of the lower parts of the soul, though
associated with them during the life of the body, and hence is not subject to
generation and destruction, but is eternal. In support of this view may be
urged that if the passive intellect were merely a capacity of the lower parts
of the soul, we should expect it to grow weaker as the person grows older and
his sensitive and imaginative powers are beginning to decline; whereas the
contrary is the case. The older the person the keener is his intellect. The
difficulty, however, remains that if the human intellect is a real substance
independent of the rest of the soul, why is it that at its first appearance in
the human being it is extremely poor in content, being all but empty, and grows
as the rest of the body and the soul is developed?
To
obviate these difficulties, Averroes in his commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle practically
identifies (according to Levi ben Gerson's view of Averroes) the material
intellect with the Active Intellect. The Active Intellect according to him is
neither identical with the divine, as Alexander maintains, nor is it a part of
man, as Themistius and others think, but is the last of the separate
Intelligences, next to the spiritual mover of the lunar sphere. It is a pure
actuality, absolutely free from matter, and hence eternal. This Active
Intellect in some mysterious manner becomes associated with man, and this
association results in a temporary phase represented by the material intellect.
As a result of the sense perceptions, images of the external objects remain in
the imagination, and the Active Intellect takes hold of these images, which are
potentially universal ideas, and by its illumination produces out of them
actual ideas and an intellect in which they reside, the material intellect. The
material intellect is therefore the result of the combination of the Active
Intellect with the memory images, known as phantasmata, in the human faculty of
imagination. So long as this association exists, the material intellect
receives the intelligible forms as derived from the phantasmata, and these
forms are represented by such ideas as "all animal is sensitive,"
"all man is rational," i. e., ideas concerning the objects of this
world. This phase of man's mind ceases when the body dies, and the Active
Intellect alone remains, whose content is free from material forms. The Active
Intellect contemplates itself, a pure intelligence. At the same time it is
possible for man to identify himself with the Active Intellect as he acquires
knowledge in the material intellect, for the Active Intellect is like light
which makes the eye see. In seeing, the eye not merely perceives the form of
the external object, but indirectly also receives the light which made the
object visible. In the same way the human soul in acquiring knowledge as
implicit in its phantasmata, at the same time gets a glimpse of the spiritual
light which converted the phantasma into an explicit idea. When the soul in man
perfects itself with all the knowledge of this world it becomes identified with
the Active Intellect, which may be likened to the intellect or soul of the
corporeal world.
In this
combination of the views of Alexander and Themistius Averroes succeeds in
obviating the criticisms levelled at the two former. That the power of the
material intellect grows keener with age though the corporeal organs are
weaker, supports Averroes's doctrine as against Alexander, to whom it is a mere
capacity dependent upon the mixture of the elements in the human body. But
neither is he subject to the objection applying to Themistius’s view, that a
real independent entity could scarcely be void of all forms and a mere
receptacle. For the material intellect as it really is in itself when not in
combination with the human body is not a mere receptacle or empty potentiality.
It is the Active Intellect, which combines in itself all immaterial forms and
thinks them as it thinks itself. It is only in its individualized aspect that
it becomes a potential intellect ready to receive all material forms.
But what
Averroes gains here he loses elsewhere. There are certain considerations which
are fatal to his doctrine. Thus it would follow that theoretical studies which
have no practical aim are useless. But this is impossible. Nature has put in us
the ability as well as the desire to speculate without reference to practical
results. The pleasure we derive from theoretical studies is much greater than
that afforded by the practical arts and trades. And nature does nothing in
vain. Theoretical studies must therefore have some value. But in Averroes's
theory of the material intellect they have none. For all values may be divided
into those which promote the life of the body and those which lead to the final
happiness of man. The former is clearly not served by those theoretical
speculations which have no practical aim. On the contrary, they hinder it. Deep
students of the theoretical sciences forego all bodily pleasures, and often do
without necessities. But neither can there be any advantage in theoretical
speculation for ultimate human happiness. For human happiness according to
Averroes (and he is in a sense right, as we shall see later) consists in union
with the Active Intellect. But this union takes place as a matter of course
according to his theory at the time of death, whether a man be wise or a fool.
For the Active Intellect then absorbs the material.
Another
objection to Averroes's theory is the following. If the material intellect is
in essence the same as the Active Intellect, it is a separate, immaterial
substance, and hence is, like the Active Intellect, one. For only that which
has matter as its substratum can be quantitatively differentiated. Thus A is
numerically different from B, though A and B are both men (i. e., qualitatively
the same), because they are corporeal beings. Forms as such can be
differentiated qualitatively only. Horse is different from ass in quality.
Horse as such and horse as such are the same. It follows from this that the
material intellect, being like the Active Intellect an immaterial form, cannot
be numerically multiplied, and therefore is one only. But if so, no end of absurdities
follows. For it means that all men have the same intellect, hence the latter is
wise and ignorant at the same time in reference to the same thing, in so far as
A knows a given thing and B does not know it. It would also follow that A can
make use of B's sense experience and build his knowledge upon it. All these
inferences are absurd, and they all follow from the assumption that the
material intellect is in essence the same as the Active Intellect. Hence Averroes's
position is untenable.
Gersonides
then gives his own view of the material intellect, which is similar to that of
Alexander. The material intellect is a capacity, and the prime matter is the
ultimate subject in which it inheres. But there are other powers or forms
inhering in matter prior to the material intellect. Prime matter as such is not
endowed with intellect, or all things would have human reason. Prime matter
when it reaches the stage of development of the imaginative faculty is then
ready to receive the material intellect. We may say then that the sensitive
soul, of which the imaginative faculty is a part, is the subject in which the
material intellect inheres. The criticism directed against Alexander, which
applies here also, may be answered as follows. The material intellect is dependent
upon its subject, the sensitive soul, for its existence only, not for the
manner of receiving its knowledge. Hence the weakening or strengthening of its
subject cannot affect it directly at all. Indirectly there is a relation
between the two, and it works in the reverse direction. When the sensitive
powers are weakened and their activities diminish, there is more opportunity
for the intellect to monopolize the one soul for itself and increase its own
activity, which the other powers have a tendency to hinder, since the soul is
one for all these contending powers. It follows of course that the material
intellect in man is not immortal. As a capacity of the sensitive soul, it dies
with the latter. What part of the human soul it is that enjoys immortality and
on what conditions we shall see later. But before we do this, we must try to
understand the nature of the Active Intellect.
We know
now that the function of the Active Intellect is to actualize the material
intellect, i. e., to develop the capacity which the latter has of extracting
general ideas from the particular memory images (phantasmata) in the faculty of
imagination, so that this capacity, originally empty of any content, receives
the ideas thus produced, and is thus constituted into an actual intellect. From
this it follows that the Active Intellect, which enables the material intellect
to form ideas, must itself have the ideas it induces in the latter, though not
necessarily in the same form. Thus an artisan, who imposes the form of chair upon
a piece of wood, must have the form of chair in his mind, though not the same
sort as he realizes in the wood. Now as all the ideas acquired by the material
intellect constitute one single activity so far as the end and purpose is
concerned (for it all leads to the perfection of the person), the agent which
is the cause of it all must also be one. Hence there are not many Active
Intellects, each responsible for certain ideas, but one Intellect is the cause
of all the ideas realized in the material intellect. Moreover, as this Active
Intellect gives the material intellect not merely a knowledge of separate
ideas, but also an understanding of their relations to each other, in other
words of the systematic unity connecting all ideas into one whole, it follows
that the Active Intellect has a knowledge of the ideas from their unitary
aspect. In other words, the unity of purpose and aim which is evident in the
development of nature from the prime matter through the forms of the elements,
the plant soul, the animal soul and up to the human reason, where the lower is
for the sake of the higher, must reside as a unitary conception in the Active
Intellect.
For the
Active Intellect has another function besides developing the rational capacity
in man. We can arrive at this insight by a consideration undertaken from a
different point of view. If we consider the wonderful and mysterious
development of a seed, which is only a piece of matter, in a purposive manner,
passing through various stages and producing a highly complicated organism with
psychic powers, we must come to the conclusion, as Aristotle does, that there
is an intellect operating in this development. As all sublunar nature shows a
unity of purpose, this intellect must be one. And as it cannot be like one of its
products, it must be eternal and not subject to generation and decay. But these
are the attributes which, on grounds taken from the consideration of the
intellectual activity in man, we ascribed to the Active Intellect. Hence it is
the Active Intellect. And we have thus shown that it has two functions. One is
to endow sublunar nature with the intelligence and purpose visible in its
processes and evolutions; the other is to enable the rational power in man to
rise from a tabula rasa to an actual intellect with a content. From both these
activities it is evident that the Active Intellect has a knowledge of sublunar
creation as a systematic unity.
This
conception of the Active Intellect, Levi ben Gerson says, will also answer all
the difficulties by which other philosophers are troubled concerning the
possibility of knowledge and the nature of definition. The problems are briefly
these. Knowledge concerns itself with the permanent and universal. There can be
no real knowledge of the particular, for the particular is never the same, it
is constantly changing and in the end disappears altogether. On the other hand,
the universal has no real existence outside of the mind, for the objectively
real is the particular thing. The only really existing man is A or B or C; man
in general, man that is not a particular individual man, has no objective
extra-mental existence. Here is a dilemma. The only thing we can really know is
the thing that is not real, and the only real thing is that which we cannot
know. The Platonists solve this difficulty by boldly declaring that the
universal ideas or forms are the real existents and the models of the things of
sense. This is absurd. Aristotle's solution in the Metaphysics is likewise
unsatisfactory. Our conception, however, of the Active Intellect enables us to
solve this problem satisfactorily. The object of knowledge is not the
particular thing which is constantly changing; nor yet the logical abstraction
which is only in the mind. It is the real unity of sublunar nature as it exists
in the Active Intellect.
The
problem of the definition is closely related to that of knowledge. The
definition denotes the essence of every individual of a given species. As the
individuals of a given species have all the same definition, and hence the same
essence, they are all one. For what is not in the definition is not real. Our
answer is that the definition represents that unitary aspect of the sublunar
individuals which is in the Active Intellect. This aspect is also in a certain
sense present in every one of the individual objects of nature, but not in the
same manner as in the Active Intellect.
We are
now ready to take up the question of human immortality. The material intellect
as a capacity for acquiring knowledge is not immortal. Being inherent in the
sensitive soul and dependent for its acquisition of knowledge upon the memory
images (phantasmata) which appear in the imagination, the power to acquire
knowledge ceases with the cessation of sense and imagination. But the knowledge
already acquired, which, we have shown above, is identical with the conceptions
of sublunar nature in the Active Intellect, is indestructible. For these
conceptions are absolutely immaterial; they are really the Active Intellect in
a sense, and only the material is subject to destruction. The sum of
acquisition of immaterial ideas constitutes the acquired or actual intellect,
and this is the immortal part of man.
Further
than this man cannot go. The idea adopted by some that the human intellect may
become identified completely with the Active Intellect, Levi ben Gerson
rejects. In order to accomplish this, he says, it would be necessary to have a
complete and perfect knowledge of all nature, and that too a completely unified
and wholly immaterial knowledge just as it is in the Active Intellect. This is
clearly impossible. But it is true that a man's happiness after death is
dependent upon the amount and perfection of his knowledge. For even in this
life the pleasure we derive from intellectual contemplation is greater the more
nearly we succeed in completely concentrating our mind on the subject of study.
Now after death there will be no disturbing factors such as are supplied in
this world by the sensitive and emotional powers. To be sure this lack will
also prevent the acquisition of new knowledge, as was said before, but the
amount acquired will be there in the soul’s power all at once and all the time.
The more knowledge one has succeeded in obtaining during life, the more nearly
he will resemble the Active Intellect and the greater will be his happiness.
The next
topic Levi ben Gerson takes up is that of prognostication. There are three ways
in which certain persons come to know the future, dreams, divination and
prophecy. What we wish to do is to determine the kind of future events that may
be thus known beforehand, the agency which produces in us this power, and the
bearing this phenomenon has on the nature of events generally, and particularly
as concerns the question of chance and free will.
That
there is such knowledge of future events is a fact and not a theory. Experience
testifies to the fact that there are certain people who are able to foretell
the future, not as a matter of accident or through a chance coincidence, but as
a regular thing. Diviners these are called, or fortune tellers. This power is
even better authenticated in prophecy, which no one denies. We can also cite
many instances of dreams, in which a person sees a future event with all its
particulars, and the dream comes true. All these cases are too common to be
credited to chance. Now what does this show as to the nature of the events thus
foreseen? Clearly it indicates that they cannot be chance happenings, for what
is by chance cannot be foreseen. The only conclusion then to be drawn is that these
events are determined by the order of nature. But there is another implication
in man's ability to foretell the future, namely, that what is thus known to man
is first known to a higher intellect which communicates it to us.
The first
of these two consequences leads us into difficulties. For if we examine the
data of prognostication, whether it be of dream, divination or prophecy, we
find that they concern almost exclusively such particular human events as would
be classed in the category of the contingent rather than in that of the
necessary. Fortune tellers regularly tell people about the kind of children
they will have, the sort of things they will do, and so on. In prophecy
similarly Sarah was told she would have a son (Gen. 18, 10). We also have examples
of prognostication respecting the outcome of a battle, announcement of coming
rain,—events due to definite causes—as well as the prediction of events which
are the result of free choice or pure accident, as when Samuel tells Elisha
that he will meet three men on the way, who will give him two loaves of bread,
which he will accept; or when the prophet in Samariah tells the prophet in
Bethel that he will be killed by a lion. The question now is, if these
contingent things can be known in advance, they are not contingent; and if
these are not, none are. For the uniform events in nature are surely not
contingent. If then those events usually classed as contingent and voluntary
are not such, there is no such thing as chance and free will at all, which is
impossible.
Our
answer is that as a matter of fact those contingent happenings we call luck and
ill luck do often come frequently to certain persons, whom we call lucky or
unlucky, which shows that they are not the result of pure chance, and that
there is some sort of order determining them. Moreover, we know that the higher
in the scale of being a thing is, the more nature takes care to guard it. Hence
as man is the highest being here below, it stands to reason that the heavenly
bodies order his existence and his fortune. And so the science of astrology,
with all its mistakes on account of the imperfect state of our knowledge, does
say a great many things which are true. This, however, does not destroy freedom
and chance. For the horoscope represents only one side of the question. Man was
also endowed with reason and purpose, which enable him whenever he chooses to
counteract the order of the heavenly bodies. In the main the heavenly bodies by
their positions and motions and the consequent predominance of certain
elemental qualities in the sublunar world over others affect the temperaments
of man in a manner tending to his welfare. The social order with its
differentiation of labor and occupation is worked out wonderfully well—better
than the system of Plato's Republic—by the positions and motions of the
heavenly bodies. If not for this, all men would choose the more honorable
trades and professions, there would be no one to do the menial work, and
society would be impossible. At the same time there are certain incidental
evils inherent in the rigid system which would tend to destroy certain
individuals. To counteract these unintended defects, God endowed man with
reason and choice enabling him to avoid the dangers threatening him in the
world of nature.
The solution
of our problem then is this. These human events have a twofold aspect. They are
determined so far as they follow from the order of the heavenly bodies; and in
so far they can be foretold. They are undetermined so far as they are the
result of individual choice, and in so far they cannot be known beforehand.
There are also pure chance events in inanimate nature, bearing no relation to
human fortune. These cannot be foretold.
We said
above that there must be an intellect which knows these contingent events
predicted in dreams, divination and prophecy and imparts a knowledge of them to
these men. This can be no other than the Active Intellect, whose nature we
discussed above. For the Active Intellect knows the order of sublunar things,
and gives us a knowledge of them in the ideas of the material intellect.
Moreover, he is the agent producing them through the instrumentality of the
heavenly bodies. Hence the heavenly bodies are also his instrument in ordering
those contingent events which are predicted in dreams and prophetic visions.
The
purpose of this information is to protect man against the evil destined for him
in the order of the heavenly bodies, or in order that he may avail himself of
the good in store for him if he knows of it.
There is
a difference in kind between prophecy on the one hand and divination and dream
on the other. Prophecy comes from the Active Intellect directly acting on the
material intellect. Hence only intelligent men can be prophets. Divination and
dream come from the Active Intellect indirectly. They are caused by the
heavenly bodies, and the action is on the imagination. The imagination is more
easily isolated from the other parts of the soul in young people and
simpletons. Hence we find examples of dreams and divination among them.
In
discussing the problem of God’s knowledge, Gersonides takes direct issue with
Maimonides. The reader will recall that the question turns upon the knowledge
of particulars. Some philosophers go so far as to deny to God any knowledge of
things other than his own essence; for the known is in a sense identified with
the knower, and to bring in a multiplicity of ideas in God's knowledge would
endanger his unity. Others, however, fell short of this extreme opinion and
admitted God's knowledge of things other than himself, but maintained that God
cannot know particulars for various reasons. The particular is perceived by
sense, a material faculty, whereas God is immaterial. Particulars are infinite
and cannot be measured or embraced, whereas knowledge is a kind of measuring or
embracing. The particulars are not always existing, and are subject to change.
Hence God's knowledge would be subject to change and disappearance, which is
impossible. If God knows particulars how is it that there is often a violation of
right and justice in the destinies of individual men? This would argue in God
either inability or indifference, both of which are impossible.
Maimonides
insists on God's knowledge of all things of which he is the creator, including
particulars. And he answers the arguments of the philosophers by saying that
their objections are valid only if we assume that God's knowledge is similar to
ours, and since with us it is impossible to know the material except through a
material organ, it is not possible in God. As we cannot comprehend the
infinite; as we cannot know the non-existent, nor the changing without a change
in our knowledge, God cannot do so. But it is wrong to assume this. God's
knowledge is identical with his essence, which these same philosophers insist
is unlike anything else, and unknowable. Surely it follows that his knowledge
is also without the least resemblance to our knowledge and the name alone is
what they have in common. Hence all the objections of the philosophers fall
away at one stroke. We cannot in one act of knowing embrace a number of things
differing in species; God can, because his knowledge is one. We cannot know the
non-existent, for our knowledge depends upon the thing known. God can. We
cannot know the infinite, for the infinite cannot be embraced; God can. We
cannot know the outcome of a future event unless the event is necessary and
determined. If the event is contingent and undetermined we can only have
opinion concerning it, which may or may not be true; we are uncertain and may
be mistaken. God can know the outcome of a contingent event, and yet the event
is not determined, and may happen one way or the other. Our knowledge of a
given thing changes as the thing itself undergoes a change, for if our
knowledge should remain the same while the object changes, it would not be
knowledge but error. In God the two are compatible. He knows in advance how a
given thing will change, and his knowledge never changes, even though that
which was at one moment potential and implicit becomes later actual and
explicit.
At this
point Gersonides steps in in defence of human logic and sanity. He accuses
Maimonides of not being quite honest with himself. Maimonides, he intimates,
did not choose this position of his own free will—a position scientifically
quite untenable—he was forced to it by theological exigencies. He felt that he
must vindicate, by fair means or foul, God's knowledge of particulars. And so
Gersonides proceeds to demolish Maimonides's position by reducing it ad absurdum.
What does
Maimonides mean by saying that God knows the contingent? If he means that God
knows that the contingent may as contingent happen otherwise than as he knows
it will happen, we do not call this in us knowledge, but opinion. If he means
that God knows it will happen in a certain way, and yet it may turn out that
the reverse will actually take place, then we call this in our case error, not
knowledge. And if he means that God merely knows that it may happen one way or
the other without knowing definitely which will happen, then we call this in
our experience uncertainty and perplexity, not knowledge. By insisting that all
this is in God knowledge because, forsooth, God's knowledge is not like our
knowledge, is tantamount to saying that what is in us opinion, uncertainty,
error, is in God knowledge—a solution far from complimentary to God's
knowledge.
Besides,
the entire principle of Maimonides that there is no relation of resemblance
between God's attributes and ours, that the terms wise, just, and so on, are pure
homonyms, is fundamentally wrong. We attribute knowledge to God because we know
in our own case that an intellect is perfected by knowledge. And since we have
come to the conclusion on other grounds that God is a perfect intellect, we say
he must have knowledge. Now if this knowledge that we ascribe to God has no
resemblance whatsoever to what we understand by knowledge in our own case, the
ground is removed from our feet. We might as well argue that man is rational
because solid is continuous. If the word knowledge means a totally different
thing in God from what it means in us, how do we know that it is to be found in
God? If we have absolutely no idea what the term means when applied to God,
what reason have we for preferring knowledge as a divine attribute to its
opposite or negative? If knowledge does not mean knowledge, ignorance does not
mean ignorance, and it is just the same whether we ascribe to God the one or
the other.
The truth
is that the attributes we ascribe to God do have a resemblance to the same
attributes in ourselves; only they are primary in God, secondary in ourselves, i.e., they exist in God in a more
perfect manner than in us. Hence it is absurd to say that what would be in us
error or uncertainty is in God knowledge. Our problem must be solved more
candidly and differently. There are arguments in favor of God's knowing particulars
(Maimonides gives some), and there are the arguments of the philosophers
against the thesis. The truth must be between the two, that God knows them from
one aspect and does not know them from another. Having shown above that human
events are in part ordered and determined by the heavenly bodies, and in part
undetermined and dependent upon the individual's choice, we can now make use of
this distinction for the solution of our problem. God knows particulars in so
far as they are ordered, he does not know them in so far as they are
contingent. He knows that they are contingent, and hence it follows that he
does not know which of the two possibilities will happen, else they would not
be contingent. This is no defect in God's nature, for to know a thing as it is
is no imperfection. In general God does not know particulars as particulars but
as ordered by the universal laws of nature. He knows the universal order, and
he knows the particulars in so far as they are united in the universal order.
This
theory meets all objections, and moreover it is in agreement with the views of
the Bible. It is the only one by which we can harmonize the apparent
contradictions in the Scriptures. Thus on the one hand we are told that God
sends Prophets and commands people to do and forbear. This implies that a
person has freedom to choose, and that the contingent is a real category. On
the other hand, we find that God foretells the coming of future events
respecting human destiny, which signifies determination. And yet again we find
that God repents, and that he does not repent. All these apparent
contradictions can be harmonized on our theory. God foretells the coming of
events in so far as they are determined in the universal order of nature. But
man's freedom may succeed in counteracting this order, and the events predicted
may not come. This is signified by the expression that God repents.
Levi ben
Gerson's solution, whatever we may think of its scientific or philosophic
value, is surely very bold as theology, we might almost say it is a theological
monstrosity. It practically removes from God the definite knowledge of the
outcome of a given event so far as that outcome is contingent. Gersonides will
not give up the contingent, for that would destroy freedom. He therefore accepts
free will with its consequences, at the risk of limiting God's knowledge to
events which are determined by the laws of nature. Maimonides was less
consistent, but had the truer theological sense, namely, he kept to both horns
of the dilemma. God is omniscient and man is free. He gave up the solution by
seeking refuge in the mysteriousness of God's knowledge. This is the true
religious attitude.
The
question of Providence is closely related to that of God's knowledge. For it is
clear that one cannot provide for those things of which he does not know.
Gersonides's view in this problem is very similar to that of Maimonides, and
like him he sees in the discussions between Job and his friends the
representative opinions held by philosophers in this important problem.
There are
three views, he says, concerning the nature of Providence. One is that God's
providence extends only to species and not to individuals. The second opinion
is that God provides for every individual of the human race. The third view is that
some individuals are specially provided for, but not all. Job held the first
view, which is that of Aristotle. The arguments in favor of this opinion are
that God does not know particulars, hence cannot provide for them. Besides,
there would be more justice in the distribution of goods and evils in the world
if God concerned himself about every individual. Then again man is too insignificant
for God's special care.
The
second view is that of the majority of our people. They argue that as God is
the author of all, he surely provides for them. And as a matter of fact
experience shows it; else there would be much more violence and bloodshed than
there is. The wicked are actually punished and the good rewarded. This class is
divided into two parts. Some think that while God provides for all men, not all
that happens to a man is due to God; there are also other causes. The others
think that every happening is due to God. This second class may again be
divided according to the manner in which they account for those facts in
experience which seem to militate against their view. Maintaining that every
incident is due to God, they have to explain the apparent deviation from
justice in the prosperity of the wicked and the adversity of the righteous. One
party explains the phenomenon by saying that the prosperity and the adversity
in these cases are only seeming and not real; that they in fact are the
opposite of what they seem, or at least lead to the opposite. The second party
answers the objection on the ground that those we think good may not really be
such, and similarly those we think bad may not really be bad. For the way to
judge a person's character is not merely by his deeds alone, but by his deeds
as related to his temperament and disposition, which God alone knows. Eliphaz
the Temanite belonged to those who think that not all which happens is due to
God; that folly is responsible for a man's misfortune. Bildad the Shuchite
believed that all things are from God, but not all that seems good and evil is
really so. Zophar the Naamathite thought we do not always judge character
correctly; that temperament and disposition must be taken into account.
Of these
various opinions the first one, that of Aristotle, cannot be true. Dreams,
divination, and especially prophecy contradict it flatly. All these are given
to the individual for his protection. The second opinion, namely, that God's
providence extends to every individual, is likewise disproved by reason, by
experience and by the Bible. We have already proved that God's knowledge does
not extend to particulars as such. He only knows things as ordered by the
heavenly bodies; and knows at the same time that they may fail to happen
because of man's free will. Now if God punishes and rewards every man according
to his deeds, one of two things necessarily follows. Either he rewards and
punishes according to those deeds which the individual is determined to do by
the order of the heavenly bodies, or according to the deeds the individual
actually does. In the first case there would be often injustice, for the person
might not have acted as the order of the heavenly bodies indicated he would
act, for he is free to act as he will. The second case is impossible, for it
would mean that God knows particulars as particulars—a thesis we have already
disproved. Besides, evil does not come from God directly, since he is pure form
and evil comes only from matter. Hence it cannot be said that he punishes the
evil doer for his sin.
Experience
also testifies against this view, for we see the just suffer and the wicked
prosper. The manner in which Eliphaz, Bildad and Zophar wish to defend God's
justice will not hold water. Man's own folly will account perhaps for some
evils befalling the righteous and some good coming to the wicked. But it will
not account for the failure of the good man to get the reward he deserves, and
of the wicked to receive the punishment which is his due. The righteous man
often has troubles all his life no matter how careful he is to avoid them, and
correspondingly the same is true of the wicked, that he is prosperous, despite
his lack of caution and good sense. To avoid these objections as Eliphaz does
by saying that if the wicked man himself is not punished, his children will be,
is to go from the frying pan into the fire. For it is not just either to omit
to punish the one deserving it, or to punish another innocent man for him. Nor
is Zophar's defence any better. For the same man, with the same temperament and
disposition, often suffers more when he is inclined to do good, and is
prosperous when he is not so scrupulous. Bildad is no more successful than the
other two. The evils coming to the righteous are often real and permanent. But
neither does the Bible compel us to believe that God looks out for all individuals.
This is especially true in reference to punishment, as can be gathered from
such expressions as "I will hide my face from them, and they shall be
given to be devoured" (Deut. 31, 17), or "As thou hast forgotten the
law of thy God, so will I myself also forget thy children" (Hosea 4, 6).
These expressions indicate that God does not punish the individuals directly,
but that he leaves them to the fate that is destined for them by the order of
the heavenly bodies. True there are other passages in Scripture speaking of
direct punishment, but they may be interpreted so as not to conflict with our
conclusions.
Having
seen that neither of the two extreme views is correct, it remains to adopt the
middle course, namely, that some individuals are provided for specially, and
others not. The nearer a person is to the Active Intellect, the more he
receives divine providence and care. Those people who do not improve their
capabilities, which they possess as members of the species, are provided for
only as members of the species. The matter may be put in another way also. God
knows all ideas. Man is potentially capable of receiving them in a certain
manner. God, who is actual, leads man from his potentiality to actuality. When
a man's potentialities are thus realized, he becomes similar to God, because
when ideas are actualized the agent and the thing acted upon are one. Hence the
person enjoys divine providence at that time. The way in which God provides for
such men is by giving them knowledge through dream, divination or prophecy or
intuition or in some other unconscious manner on the individual's part, which
knowledge protects him from harm. This view is not in conflict with the truth
that God does not know particulars as such. For it is not to the individual
person as such that providence extends as a conscious act of God. The
individualization is due to the recipient and not to the dispenser. One may
object that after all since it is possible that bad men may have goods as
ordered by the heavenly bodies, and good men may have misfortune as thus
ordered, when their attachment to God is loosened somewhat, there is injustice
in God if he could have arranged the heavenly spheres differently and did not,
or incapacity if he could not. The answer is briefly that the order of the
spheres does a great deal of good in maintaining the existence of things. And
if some little evil comes also incidentally, this does not condemn the whole
arrangement. In fact the evils come from the very agencies which are the
authors of good. The view of providence here adopted is that of Elihu the son
of Barachel the Buzite in the book of Job (ch. 32), and it agrees also with the
opinion of Maimonides in the "Guide of the Perplexed".
Instead
of placing his cosmology at the beginning of his system and proceeding from
that as a basis to the other parts of his work, the psychology and the ethics,
Levi ben Gerson, whose "Milhamot Hashem" is not so much a systematic
work as an aggregation of discussions, reversed the process. He begins as we have
seen with a purely psychological analysis concerning the nature of the human
reason and its relation to the Active Intellect. He follows up this discussion
with a treatment of prognostication as exhibiting some of the effects of the
Active Intellect upon the reason and imagination of man. This is again followed
by a discussion of God's knowledge and providence. And not until all these
psychological (and in part ethical) questions have been decided, does Levi ben
Gerson undertake to give us his views of the constitution of the universe and
the nature and attributes of God. In this discussion he takes occasion to
express his dissatisfaction with Aristotle's proofs of the existence of the
spheral movers and of the unmoved mover or God, as inadequate to bear the
structure which it is intended to erect upon them. It will be remembered that
the innovation of Abraham Ibn Daud and Maimonides in making Jewish philosophy
more strictly Aristotelian than it had been consisted in a great measure in
just this introduction of the Aristotelian proof of the existence of God as
derived from the motions of the heavenly bodies. Levi ben Gerson's proofs are
teleological rather than mechanical. Aristotle said a moving body must have a
mover outside of it, which if it is again a body is itself in motion and must
have a mover in turn. And as this process cannot go on ad infinitum, there must
be at the end of the series an unmoved mover. As unmoved this mover cannot be
body; and as producing motion eternally, it cannot be a power residing in a body,
a physical or material power, for no such power can be infinite. Gersonides is
not satisfied with this proof. He argues that so far as the motions of the
heavenly bodies are concerned there is no reason why a physical power cannot
keep on moving them eternally. The reason that motions caused by finite forces
in our world come to a stop is because the thing moved is subject to change,
which alters its relation to its mover; and secondly because the force
endeavors to move the object in opposition to its own tendency, in opposition
to gravity. In the case of the heavenly bodies neither of these conditions is
present. The relation of the mover to the moved is always the same, since the
heavenly bodies are not subject to change; and as they are not made of the four
terrestrial elements they have no inherent tendency to move in any direction,
hence they offer no opposition to the force exerted upon them by the mover. A
finite power might therefore quite conceivably cause eternal motion. Similarly
an unmoved mover cannot be body, to be sure, but it may be a physical power
like a soul, which in moving the body is not itself moved by that motion.
Aristotle's proofs therefore are not sufficient to produce the conviction that
the movers of the spheres and God himself are separate Intelligences.
Gersonides
accordingly follows a different method. He argues that if a system of things
and events exhibits perfection not here and there and at rare intervals but
regularly, the inference is justified that there is an intelligent agent who
had a definite purpose and design in establishing the system. The world below
is such a system. Hence it has an intelligent agent as its author. This agent
may be a separate and immaterial intelligence, or a corporeal power like a
soul. He then shows that it cannot be a corporeal power, for it would have to
reside in the animal sperm which exhibits such wonderful and purposive
development, or in the parent animal from which the sperm came, both of which,
he argues, are impossible. It remains then that the cause of the teleological
life of the sublunar world is an immaterial power, a separate intellect. This
intellect, he argues further, acts upon matter and endows it with forms, the
only mediating power being the natural heat which is found in the seed and
sperm of plants and animals. Moreover, it is aware of the order of what it
produces. It is the Active Intellect of which we spoke above . The forms of
terrestrial things come from it directly, the heat residing in the seed comes
from the motions of the spheres. This shows that the permanent motions of the
heavenly bodies are also intelligent motions, for they tend to produce
perfection in the terrestrial world and never come to a standstill, which would
be the case if the motions were "natural" like those of the elements,
or induced against their nature like that of a stone moving upward. We are
justified in saying then that the heavenly bodies are endowed with intellects
and have no material soul. Hence their movers are pure Intelligences, and there
are as many of them as there are spheres, i. e., forty-eight, or fifty-eight or
sixty-four according to one's opinion on the astronomical question of the
number of spheres.
Now as
the Active Intellect knows the order of sublunar existence in its unity, and
the movers of the respective spheres know the order of their effects through
the motions of the heavenly bodies, it follows that as all things in heaven
above and on the earth beneath are related in a unitary system, there is a
highest agent who is the cause of all existence absolutely and has a knowledge
of all existence as a unitary system.
The
divine attributes are derived by us from his actions, and hence they are not
pure homonyms . God has a knowledge of the complete order of sublunar things,
of which the several movers have only a part. He knows it as one, and knows it
eternally without change. His joy and gladness are beyond conception, for our
joy also is very great in understanding. His is also the perfect Life, for
understanding is life. He is the most real Substance and Existent, and he is
One. God is also the most real Agent, as making the other movers do their work,
and producing a complete and perfect whole out of their parts. He is also
properly called Bestower, Beneficent, Gracious, Strong, Mighty, Upright, Just,
Eternal, Permanent. All these attributes, however, do not denote multiplicity.
From God
we now pass again to his creation, and take up the problem which caused
Maimonides so much trouble, namely, the question of the origin of the world. It
will be remembered that dissatisfied with the proofs for the existence of God
advanced by the Mutakallimun, Maimonides, in order to have a firm foundation
for the central idea of religion, tentatively adopted the Aristotelian notion
of the eternity of motion and the world. But no sooner does Maimonides
establish his proof of the existence, unity and incorporeality of God than he
returns to the attack of the Aristotelian view and points out that the problem
is insoluble in a strictly scientific manner; that Aristotle himself never
intended his arguments in favor of eternity to be regarded as philosophically
demonstrated, and that they all labor under the fatal fallacy that because
certain laws hold of the world's phenomena once it is in existence, these same
laws must have governed the establishment of the world itself in its origin.
Besides, the assumption of the world's eternity with its corollary of the
necessity and immutability of its phenomena saps the foundation of all
religion, makes miracles impossible, and reduces the world to a machine.
Gersonides is on the whole agreed with Maimonides. He admits that Aristotle's
arguments are the best yet advanced in the problem, but that they are not
convincing. He also agrees with Maimonides in his general stricture on
Aristotle's method, only modifying and restricting its generality and sweeping
nature. With all this, however, he finds it necessary to take up the entire
question anew and treats it in his characteristic manner, with detail and
rigor, and finally comes to a conclusion different from that of Maimonides,
namely, that the world had an origin in time, to be sure, but that it came not
ex nihilo in the absolute sense of the word nihil, but developed from an
eternal formless matter, which God endowed with form. This is the so-called
Platonic view.
We cannot
enter into all his details which are technical and fatiguing in the extreme,
but we must give a general idea of his procedure in the investigation of this
important topic.
The
problem of the origin of the world, he says, is very difficult. First, because
in order to learn from the nature of existing things whether they were created
out of a state of non-existence or not, we must know the essence of existing
things, which is not easy. Secondly, we must know the nature of God in order to
determine whether he could have existed first without the world and then have
created it, or whether he had to have the world with him from eternity. The
fact of the great difference of opinion on this question among thinkers, and
the testimony of Maimonides that Aristotle himself had no valid proof in this
matter are additional indications of the great difficulty of the subject.
Some
think the world was made and destroyed an infinite number of times. Others say
it was made once. Of these some maintain it was made out of something (Plato);
others, that it was made out of absolute nothing (Philoponus, the Mutakallimun,
Maimonides and many of our Jewish writers). Some on the other hand, namely,
Aristotle and his followers, hold the world to be eternal. They all have their
defenders, and there is no need to refute the others since Aristotle has
already done this. His arguments are the best so far, and deserve
investigation. The fundamental fallacy in all his proofs is that he argues from
the laws of genesis and decay in the parts of the world to the laws of these
processes in the world as a whole. This might seem to be the same criticism
which Maimonides advances, but it is not really quite the same, Maimonides's
assertion being more general and sweeping. Maimonides says that the origin of
the world as a whole need not be in any respect like the processes going on
within its parts; whereas Gersonides bases his argument on the observed
difference in the world between wholes and parts, admitting that the two may be
alike in many respects.
In order
to determine whether the world is created or not, it is best to investigate
first those things in the world which have the appearance of being eternal,
such as the heavenly bodies, time, motion, the form of the earth, and so on. If
these are proven to be eternal, the world is eternal; if not, it is not. A
general principle to help us distinguish a thing having an origin from one that
has not is the following: A thing which came into being in time has a purpose.
An eternal thing has no purpose. Applying this principle to the heavens we find
that all about them is with a purpose to ordering the sublunar world in the
best way possible. Their motions, their distances, their positions, their
numbers, and so on are all for this purpose. Hence they had a beginning.
Aristotle's attempts to explain these conditions from the nature of the heavens
themselves are not successful, and he knew it. Again, as the heavenly bodies
are all made of the same fifth element (the Aristotelian ether), the many
varieties in their forms and motions require special explanation. The only
satisfactory explanation is that the origin of the heavenly bodies is not due
to nature and necessity, which would favor eternity, but to will and freedom,
and the many varieties are for a definite purpose. Hence they are not eternal.
Gersonides
then analyzes time and motion and proves that Aristotle to the contrary
notwithstanding, they are both finite and not infinite. Time belongs to the
category of quantity, and there is no infinite quantity. As time is dependent
on motion, motion too is finite, hence neither is eternal. Another argument for
creation in time is that if the world is eternal and governed altogether by
necessity, the earth should be surrounded on all sides by water according to
the nature of the lighter element to be above the heavier. Hence the appearance
of parts of the earth's surface above the water is an indication of a break of
natural law for a special purpose, namely, in order to produce the various
mineral, plant and animal species. Hence once more purpose argues design and
origin in time.
Finally
if the world were eternal, the state of the sciences would be more advanced
than it is. A similar argument may be drawn from language. Language is
conventional; which means that the people existed before the language they
agreed to speak. But man being a social animal they could not have existed an
infinite time without language. Hence mankind is not eternal.
We have
just proved that the world came into being, but it does not necessarily follow
that it will be destroyed. Nay, there are reasons to show that it will not be
destroyed. For there is no destruction except through matter and the
predominance of the passive powers over the active. Hence the being that is
subject to destruction must consist of opposites. But the heavenly bodies have
no opposites, not being composite; hence they cannot be destroyed. And if so,
neither can the sublunar order be destroyed, which is the work of the heavenly
bodies. There is of course the abstract possibility of their being destroyed by
their maker, not naturally, but by his will, as they were made; but we can find
no reason in God for wishing to destroy them, all reasons existing in man for
destroying things being inapplicable to God.
That the
world began in time is now established. The question still remains, was the
world made out of something or out of nothing? Both are impossible. The first
is impossible, for that something out of which the world was made must have had
some form, for matter never is without form, and if so, it must have had some
motion, and we have a kind of world already, albeit an imperfect one. The
second supposition is also impossible; for while form may come out of nothing,
body cannot come from not-body. We never see the matter of any object arise out
of nothing, though the form may. Nature as well as art produces one corporeal
thing out of another. Hence the generally accepted principle, "ex nihilo
nihil fit." Besides it would follow on this supposition that before the
world came into existence there was a vacuum in its place, whereas it is proved
in the Physics that a vacuum is impossible. The only thing remaining therefore
is to say that the world was made partly out of something, partly out of
nothing, i. e., out of an absolutely formless matter.
It may be
objected that to assume the existence of a second eternal thing beside God is
equivalent to a belief in dualism, in two gods. But this objection may be
easily answered. Eternity as such does not constitute divinity. If all the
world were eternal, God would still be God because he controls everything and
is the author of the order obtaining in the world. In general it is the
qualitative essence that makes the divine character of God, his wisdom and
power as the source of goodness and right order in nature. The eternal matter
of which we are speaking is the opposite of all this. As God is the extreme of
perfection so is matter the extreme of imperfection and defect. As God is the
source of good, so is matter the source of evil. How then can anyone suppose
for a moment that an eternal formless matter can in any way be identified with
a divine being?
Another
objection that may be offered to our theory is that it is an established fact
that matter cannot exist at all without any form, whereas our view assumes that
an absolutely formless matter existed an infinite length of time before the
world was made from it. This may be answered by saying that the impossibility
of matter existing without form applies only to the actual objects of nature.
God put in sublunar matter the nature and capacity of receiving all forms in a
certain order. The primary qualities, the hot and the cold and the wet and the
dry, as the forms of the elements, enable this matter to receive other higher
forms. The very capacity of receiving a given form argues a certain form on the
part of the matter having this capacity; for if it had no form there would be
no reason why it should receive one form rather than another; whereas we find
that the reception of forms is not at random, but that a given form comes from
a definite other form. Man comes only from man. But this does not apply to the
prime matter of which we are speaking. It may have been without form. Nay, it
is reasonable to suppose that as we find matter and form combined, and we also
find pure forms without matter, viz., in the separate Intelligences,—it is
reasonable to suppose that there is also matter without form.
Finally
one may ask if the world has not existed from eternity, what determined the
author to will its existence at the time he did and not at another? We cannot
say that he acquired new knowledge which he had not before, or that he needed
the world then and not before, or that there was some obstacle which was
removed. The answer to this would be that the sole cause of the creation was
the will of God to benefit his creatures. Their existence is therefore due to
the divine causality, which never changes. Their origin in time is due to the
nature of a material object as such. A material object as being caused by an
external agent is incompatible with eternity. It must have a beginning, and
there is no sense in asking why at this time and not before or after, for the
same question would apply to any other time. Gersonides cites other objections
which he answers, and then he takes up one by one the Aristotelian arguments in
favor of eternity and refutes them in detail. We cannot afford to reproduce
them here as the discussions are technical, lengthy and intricate.
Having
given his philosophical cosmology, Gersonides then undertakes to show in detail
that the Biblical story of creation teaches the same doctrine. Nay, he goes so
far as to say that it was the Biblical account that suggested to him his
philosophical theory. It would be truer to say that having approached the Bible
with Aristotelian spectacles, and having no suspicion that the two attitudes
are as far apart as the poles, he did not scruple to twist the expressions in
Genesis out of all semblance to their natural meaning. The Biblical text had
been twisted and turned ever since the days of Philo, and of the Mishna and
Talmud and Midrash, in the interest of various schools and sects. Motives
speculative, religious, theological, legal and ethical were at the basis of
Biblical interpretation throughout its long history of two millennia and
more—the end is not yet—and Gersonides was swimming with the current. The Bible
is not a law, he says, which forces us to believe absurdities and to practice
useless things, as some people think. On the contrary it is a law which leads
us to our perfection. Hence what is proved by reason must be found in the Law,
by interpretation if necessary. This is why Maimonides took pains to interpret
all Biblical passages in which God is spoken of as if he were corporeal. Hence
also his statement that if the eternity of the world were strictly
demonstrated, it would not be difficult to interpret the Bible so as to agree.
But in the matter of the origin of the world, Gersonides continues, it was not
necessary for me to force the Biblical account. Quite the contrary, the
expressions in the Bible guided me to my view.
Accordingly
he finds support for his doctrine that the world was not created ex nihilo, in
the fact that there is not one miracle in the Bible in which anything comes out
of nothing. They are all instances of something out of a pre-existent
something. The miracle of the oil in the case of Elisha is no exception. The
air changed into oil as it entered the partly depleted vessel. The six days of
creation must not be taken literally. God's creation is timeless, and the six
days indicate the natural order and rank in existing things proceeding from the
cause to the effect and from the lower to the higher. Thus the movers of the
heavenly bodies come before the spheres which they move as their causes. The
spheres come before the terrestrial elements for the same reason. The elements
are followed by the things composed of them. And among these too there is a
certain order. Plants come before animals, aquatic animals before aerial,
aerial before terrestrial, and the last of all is man, as the most perfect of
sublunar creatures. All this he reads into the account of creation in Genesis.
Thus the light spoken of in the first day represents the angels or separate
Intelligences or movers of the spheres, and they are distinguished from the
darkness there, which stands for the heavenly bodies as the matters of their
movers, though at the same time they are grouped together as one day, because
the form and its matter constitute a unit. The water, which was divided by the
firmament, denotes the prime formless matter, part of which was changed into
the matter of the heavenly bodies, and part into the four terrestrial elements.
Form and matter are also designated by the terms "Tohu" and
"Bohu" in the second verse in Genesis, rendered in the Revised
Version by "without form" and "void." And so Gersonides
continues throughout the story of creation, into the details of which we need
not follow him.
The
concluding discussion in the Milhamot is devoted to the problem of miracles and
its relation to prophecy. Maimonides had said that one reason for opposing the
Aristotelian theory of the eternity of the world is that miracles would be an
impossibility on that assumption. Hence Maimonides insists on creation ex
nihilo, though he admits that the Platonic view of a pre-existent matter may be
reconciled with the Torah. Gersonides, who adopted the doctrine of an eternal
matter, finds it necessary to say by way of introduction to his treatment of
miracles that they do not prove creation ex nihilo. For as was said before all
miracles exhibit a production of something out of something and not out of
nothing.
To
explain the nature of miracles, he says, and their authors, it is necessary to
know what miracles are. For this we must take the Biblical records as our data,
just as we take the data of our senses in determining other matters. On
examining the miracles of the Bible we find that they may be classified into
those which involve a change of substance and those in which the substance remains
the same and the change is one of quality or quantity. An example of the former
is the change of Moses's rod into a serpent and of the water of Egypt into
blood; of the latter, Moses's hand becoming leprous, and the withering of the
hand of Jeroboam. We may further divide the miracles into those in which the
prophet was told in advance, as Moses was of the ten plagues, and those in
which he was not, as for example the reviving of the dead by Elijah and many
other cases. Our examination also shows us that all miracles are performed by
prophets or in relation to them. Also that they are done with some good and
useful purpose, namely, to inculcate belief or to save from evil.
These
data will help us to decide who is the author of miracles. Miracles cannot be
accidental, as they are performed with a purpose; and as they involve a
knowledge of the sublunar order, they must have as their author one who has
this knowledge, hence either God or the Active Intellect or man, i. e., the
prophet himself. Now it is not reasonable to suppose that God is the author of
miracles, for miracles come only rarely and are of no value in themselves but
only as a means to a special end, as we said before. The laws of nature,
however, which control all regular events all the time, are essentially good
and permanent. Hence it is not reasonable to suppose that the Active Intellect
who, as we know, orders the sublunar world, has more important work to do than
God. Besides if God were the author of miracles, the prophet would not know
about them, for prophetic inspiration, as we know , is due to the Active Intellect
and not directly to God.
Nor do we
need waste words in proving that man cannot be the author of miracles, for in
that case the knowledge of them would not come to him through prophetic
inspiration, since they are due to his own will. Besides man, as we have seen,
cannot have a complete knowledge of the sublunar order, and hence it is not
likely that he can control its laws to the extent of changing them.
There is
therefore only one alternative left, namely, that the author of miracles is the
same as the inspirer of the prophets, the controlling spirit of the sublunar
world, whose intellect has as its content the unified system of sublunar
creation as an immaterial idea, namely, the Active Intellect, of whom we have
spoken so often. The prophet knows of the miracles because the Active
Intellect, who is the author of them, is also the cause of the prophetic
inspiration. This will account too for the fact that all miracles have to do
with events in the sublunar world and are not found in the relations and
motions of the heavenly bodies. The case of Joshua causing the sun and moon to
stand still is no exception. There was no standing still of the sun and moon in
that case. What is meant by the expressions in Joshua 10 is that the Israelites
conquered the enemy in the short time that the sun occupied the zenith, while
its motion was not noticeable for about an hour, as is usually the case about
noon. In the case of Isaiah moving the sun ten degrees back for Hezekiah (Isai.
38, 8), there was likewise no change in the motion of the sun, but only in that
of the cloud causing the shadow.
Miracles
cannot be of regular occurrence, for if natural phenomena and laws were changed
by miracle as a regular thing, it would signify a defect in the original order.
Miracles cannot take place to violate the principle of contradiction, hence
there can be no miracles in reference to mathematical truths, nor in matters
relating to the past. Thus a miracle cannot make a thing black and white at the
same time; nor a plane triangle whose angles are less than two right angles;
nor is it possible by miracle now to make it not to have rained in Jerusalem
yesterday, when as a matter of fact it did rain. For all these involve a denial
of the logical law of contradiction that a thing cannot be and not be at the
same time.
A prophet
is tested (1) by being able to foretell miracles before they come, and (2) by
the realization of his prophetic messages. The question is raised concerning
the statement of Jeremiah that one may be a true prophet and yet an evil
prophecy may remain unfulfilled if the people repent. Does this mean that a
good prophecy must always come true? In that case a good deal of what comes
within the category of the possible and contingent becomes determined and
necessary! The answer is that a good prophecy too sometimes fails of
realization, as is illustrated in Jacob's fear of Esau after he was promised
protection by God. But this happens more rarely on account of the fact that a
man endeavors naturally to see a good prophecy realized, whereas he does his
best to counteract an evil prophecy.
Gersonides's
entire discussion of miracles shows a deep seated motive to minimize their
extent and influence. The study of science and philosophy had the effect of
planting in the minds of the medieval philosophers a great respect for reason
on the one hand and natural law on the other. A study of history, archeology
and literary criticism has developed in modern times a spirit of scepticism
regarding written records of antiquity. This was foreign to medieval
theologians generally. No one doubted for a moment the accuracy of the Biblical
records as well as their inspiration in every detail. Hence prophecy and miracles
had to be explained or explained away. Interpretation held the place of
criticism.
CHAPTER XVI .- AARON BEN ELIJAH OF NICOMEDIA
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|