HISTORY OF ISRAEL LIBRARY |
CONTENTS
Introduction
I. Isaac
Israeli
II. David
ben Merwan Al Mukammas
III. Saadia
ben Joseph Al-Fayyumi
IV. Joseph
Al-Basir and Jeshua ben Judah
V. Solomon
Ibn Gabirol
VI. Bahya
Ibn Pakuda
VII. Pseudo-Bahya
VIII. Abraham
Bar Hiyya
IX. Joseph
Ibn Zaddik
X. Judah
Halevi
XI. Moses
and Abraham Ibn Ezra
XII. Abraham
Ibn Daud
XIII. Moses
Maimonides
XIV. Hillel
ben Samuel
XV. Levi
ben Gerson
XVI. Aaron
ben Elijah of Nicomedia
XVII. Hasdai
ben Abraham Crescas
XVIII.
Joseph Albo
Conclusion
CHAPTER XIV.HILLEL BEN SAMUEL
In the
post-Maimonidean age all philosophical thinking is in the nature of a
commentary on Maimonides whether avowedly or not. The circle of speculation and
reflection is complete. It is fixed by the "Guide of the Perplexed,"
and the efforts of those who followed Maimonides are to elaborate in his spirit
certain special topics which are treated in his masterpiece in a summary way.
In the case of the more independent thinkers like Levi ben Gerson we find the
further attempt to carry out more boldly the implications of the philosophical
point of view, which, as the latter thought, Maimonides left implicit by reason
of his predisposition in favor of tradition. Hasdai Crescas went still farther
and entirely repudiated the authority of Aristotle, substituting will and
emotion for rationalism and logical inference. Not knowledge of God as
logically demonstrated is the highest aim of man, but love of God. But even in
his opposition Crescas leans on Maimonides's principles, which he takes up one
by one and refutes. Maimonides was thus the point of departure for his more
rigorous followers as well as for his opponents. In the matter of external
sources philosophical reflection after Maimonides was enriched in respect to
details by the works of Averroes on the Arabic side and those of the chief
Christian scholastics among the Latin writers. Albertus Magnus and Thomas
Aquinas furnished some material to men like Hillel of Verona in the thirteenth
century and Don Isaac Abarbanel in the fifteenth. Maimonides was limited to the
Aristotelian expositions of Alfarabi and Avicenna. The works of Averroes, his
contemporary, he did not read until toward the end of his life. After his death
Averroes gained in prestige and influence until he succeeded in putting into
the shade his Arabian predecessors and was regarded by Jew and Christian alike
as the Commentator of Aristotle par excellence. His works were rapidly
translated into Hebrew and Latin, and the Jewish writers learned their
Aristotle from Averroes. The knowledge of the Arabic language was gradually
disappearing among the Jews of Europe, and they were indebted for their
knowledge of science and philosophy to the works translated. Philosophy was
declining among the Arabs themselves owing to the disfavor of the powers that
be, and many of the scientific writings of the Arabs owe their survival to the
Hebrew translations or transcriptions in Hebrew characters which escaped the
proscription of the Mohammedan authorities.
The one
problem that came to the front as a result of Averroes's teaching, and which by
the solution he gave it formed an important subject of debate in the Parisian
schools of the thirteenth century, was that of the intellect in man, whether
every individual had his own immortal mind which would continue as an individual
entity after the death of the body, or whether a person's individuality lasted
only as long as he was alive, and with his death the one human intellect alone
survived. This was discussed in connection with the general theory of the
intellect and the three kinds of intellect that were distinguished by the
Arabian Aristotelians, the material, the acquired and the active. The problem
goes back to Aristotle's psychology, who distinguishes two intellects in man,
passive and active. But the treatment there is so fragmentary and vague that it
gave rise to widely varying interpretations by the Greek commentators of
Aristotle, Alexander of Aphrodisias and Themistius, as well as among the Arabs,
Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes. The latter insisted on the unity of the
intellect for the human race, thereby destroying individual immortality, and
this Averroistic doctrine, adopted by some Masters of Arts at the University of
Paris, was condemned among other heresies, and refuted in the writings of
Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas. Maimonides does not discuss these problems
in detail in his "Guide." He drops a remark incidentally here and
there, and it would appear that for him too, as for Averroes, the intellect
when in separation from the body is not subject to individual distinction, that
there cannot be several human intellects, since matter is the principle of
individuation and the immaterial cannot embrace a number of individuals of the
same species. The problem of immortality he does not treat ex professo in the
"Guide." Hence this was a matter taken up by his successors. Hillel
ben Samuel as well as Levi ben Gerson discuss this question in detail.
Hillel
ben Samuel does not tower as a giant in medieval Jewish literature. His
importance is local, as being the first devotee of Jewish learning and
philosophy in Italy in the middle of the thirteenth century, at the close of a
period of comparative ignorance. The Italian Jews before his time contributed
little to knowledge and learning despite their external circumstances, which
were more favorable than in some other countries. Hillel ben Samuel (1220-1295)
was a strong admirer of Maimonides and undertook to comment on the "Guide
of the Perplexed." He defended Maimonides against the aspersions of his
opponents, and was so confident in the truth of his master's teachings that he
proposed a conference of the learned men of Jewry to judge the works and
doctrines of Maimonides and to decide whether the "Guide" should be
allowed to live or should be destroyed. Another interest attaching to Hillel
ben Samuel is that he was among the first, if not the first Jew who by his
knowledge of Latin had access to the writings of the scholastics, to whom he
refers in his "Tagmule ha-Nefesh" (The Rewards of the Soul) as the "wise
men of the nations." He was also active as a translator from the Latin.
His chief
work, which entitles him to brief notice here, is the "Tagmule
ha-Nefesh" just mentioned. He does not offer us a system of philosophy,
but only a treatment of certain questions relating to the nature of the soul,
its immortality and the manner of its existence after the death of the body,
questions which Maimonides passes over lightly. With the exception of the
discussion relating to the three kinds of intellect and the question of the
unity of the acquired intellect for all mankind, there is not much that is new
or remarkable in the discussion, and we can afford to pass it by with a brief
notice.
Men of
science know, he tells us in the introduction, that the valuable possession of man
is the soul, and the happiness thereof is the final purpose of man's existence.
And yet the number of those who take pains to investigate the nature of the
soul is very small, not even one in a hundred. And even the few who do
undertake to examine this subject are hindered by various circumstances from
arriving at the truth. The matter itself is difficult and requires long
preparation and preliminary knowledge. Then the vicissitudes of life and the
shortness of its duration, coupled with the natural indolence of man when it
comes to study, completely account for the lack of true knowledge on this most
important topic.
Induced
by these considerations Hillel ben Samuel undertook to collect the scattered
notices in the extensive works of the philosophers and arranged and expounded
them briefly so as not to discourage those who are in search of wisdom. His
purpose is the knowledge of truth, which is an end in itself. He desires to
explain the existence of the soul, its nature and reward. The soul is that which
makes man man, hence we should know the nature of that which makes us
intelligent creatures, else we do not deserve the name.
Another
reason for the importance of knowing the nature of the soul is that error in
this matter may lead to more serious mistakes in other departments of knowledge
and belief. Thus if a man who calls himself pious assumes that the soul after
parting from the body is subject to corporeal reward and punishment, as appears
from a literal rendering of passages in Bible and Talmud, he will be led to
think that the soul itself is corporeal. And since the soul, it is believed,
comes from on high, the upper world must have bodies and definite places, and
hence the angels too are bodies. But since the angels are emanations from the
divine splendor, God too is body! Thus you see how serious are the consequences
of a belief, in itself perhaps not so dangerous, as that of the corporeality of
the soul.
We must
first prove the existence of the soul. This can be shown in various ways. We
see that of natural bodies some take food, grow, propagate their like, while
others, like stones, do not do these things. This shows that the powers and
functions mentioned cannot be due to the corporeal part of the objects
performing them, else stones, too, would have those powers, as they are also
corporeal like the rest. There must therefore be a different principle, not
body, which is responsible for those activities. We call it soul.
As all
existents are divided into substance and accident, the soul must be either the
one or the other. Now an accident, according to Aristotle, is that which may be
or not be without causing the being or destruction of the object in which it
is. But the body cannot be a living body without the soul. Hence the soul is
not an accident; it is therefore a substance. Substance may be corporeal or
incorporeal. The soul cannot be a corporeal substance, for all body is
divisible, and sub ject to motion and change, whereas the soul, as will be
shown later, is not movable, not changeable and not divisible. It might seem
that the soul is subject to motion, since it descends into the body and rises
again when it leaves the body. But this is not so. Descent and ascent when thus
applied to the soul are metaphorical. The union of soul and body is not a
spatial relation. The upper world from which the soul comes is not corporeal,
hence there is no such thing as place there, nor anything limited by space.
Hence the coming of the soul from the spiritual world and its return thither
are not motions at all. The relation of the soul to the body is as that of form
to matter, as Aristotle says.
Granted
that the soul's union with and separation from the body are not motions, is not
the soul subject to motion while in the body? Hillel's answer is that it is
not, and he proves his point in the prescribed fashion by making use of
Aristotle's classification of motion into (1) genesis and (2) decay, (3)
increase and (4) diminution, (5) qualitative change and (6) motion proper, or
motion of translation. He then undertakes to show that the soul can have none
of the kinds of motion here enumerated. The arguments offer nothing striking or
interesting, and we can afford to omit them. It is worthwhile, however, to
refer to his interpretation of emotion. The passage of the soul from joy to
grief, from anger to favor, might seem to be a kind of motion. Hillel answers
this objection by saying that these emotions do not pertain to the soul as
such. Their primary cause is the state of mixture of the humors in the body,
which affects certain corporeal powers in certain ways; and the soul shares in
these affections only so far as it is united with the body. In its own nature
the soul has no emotions.
We can
also prove that the soul is not divisible. For a divisible thing must have
parts. Now if the soul is divided or divisible, this means either that every
part of the soul, no matter how small, has the same powers as the whole, or
that the powers of the soul are the resultant of the union of the parts. The
first alternative is impossible, for it leads us to the absurd conclusion that
instead of one soul every person has an infinite number of souls, or at least a
great number of souls. The second alternative implies that while the soul is
not actually divided, since its powers are the summation of the parts, which
form a unit, it is potentially divisible. But this signifies that at some time
this potential divisibility will be realized (or potentiality would be vain and
meaningless) and we are brought back to the absurdity of a multiplicity of
souls in the human body.
Having
shown that the soul is not movable, changeable or divisible, we are certain of
its incorporeality, and we are ready to give a definition of the soul. Hillel
accordingly defines the soul as "a stage of emanation, consisting of a
formal substance, which subsists through its own perfection, and occupies the
fourth place in the emanatory process, next to the Active Intellect. Its
ultimate source is God himself, who is the ultimate perfection and the Good,
and it emanates from him indirectly through the mediation of the separate
Powers standing above it in the scale of emanation. The soul constitutes the
first entelechy of a natural body."
The above
definition is interesting. It shows that Hillel did not clearly distinguish the
Aristotelian standpoint from the Neo-Platonic, for in the definition just
quoted, the two points of view are combined. That all medieval Aristotelianism
was tinged with Neo-Platonism, especially in the doctrine of the Active
Intellect, is well known. But in Hillel's definition of the soul we have an
extreme form of this peculiar combination, and it represents a step backward to
the standpoint of Pseudo-Bahya and Ibn Zaddik. The work of Ibn Daud and
Maimonides in the interest of a purer Aristotelianism seems not to have
enlightened Hillel. The Neo-Platonic emanation theory is clearly enunciated in
Hillel's definition. The soul stands fourth in the series. The order he has in
mind is probably (1) God, (2) Separate Intelligences, (3) Active Intellect, (4)
Soul. We know that Hillel was a student of the Neo-Platonic "Liber de
Causis" , having translated some of it into Hebrew, and he might have
imbibed his Neo-Platonism from that Proclean book.
Continuing
the description of the soul in man, he says that the noblest part of matter,
viz., the human body, is endowed with the rational soul, and becomes the
subject of the powers of the latter. Thereby it becomes a man, i.e., a rational animal, distinguished
from all other animals, and similar to the nature of the angels.
The
Active Intellect causes its light to emanate upon the rational soul, thus
bringing its powers out into actuality. The Active Intellect, which is one of
the ten degrees of angels, is related to the rational power in man as the sun
to the power of sight. The sun gives light, which changes the potentially
seeing power into actually seeing, and the potentially visible object into the
actually visible. Moreover, this same light enables the sight to see the sun
itself, which is the cause of the actualization in the sight. So the Active
Intellect gives something to the rational power which is related to it as light
to the sight; and by means of this something the rational soul can see or
understand the Active Intellect itself. Also the potentially intelligible
objects become through this influence actually intelligible, and the man who
was potentially intelligent becomes thereby actually intelligent.
Intellect
("sekel") in man is distinguished from wisdom ("hokmah").
By the former power is meant an immediate understanding of abstract principles.
The latter is mediate understanding. Wisdom denotes speculation about
universals through inference from particulars. Intellect applies directly to
the universals and to their influence upon the particulars.
Hillel
next discusses the live topic of the day, made popular by Averroes, namely,
whether there are in essence as many individual souls as there are human
bodies, or, as Averroes thought, there is only one universal soul, and that its
individualizations in different men are only passing incidents, due to the
association of the universal soul with the human body, and disappear when the
body dies. The "sages of the Gentiles," Hillel tells us, regard
Averroes's notion as heretical, and leading besides to the absurd conclusion
that the same soul is both rewarded and punished; a view which upsets all
religion. Averroes employs a number of arguments to prove his point, among them
being the following. If there are many souls, they are either all existing from
eternity or they are created with the body. The first is impossible, for since
the soul is a form of the body, we should have actually an infinite number of
forms, and this would necessitate the actual existence of an infinite number of
bodies also; else the existence of these souls for the purpose of joining the
bodies would be in vain. But it is absurd to suppose that there has been from
eternity an infinite number of bodies created like the number of souls, and yet
they have not become real bodies with souls until now.
The
second alternative is also impossible. For if there are many souls which came
into being with the bodies, they either came from nothing or from something.
From nothing is impossible, for nothing comes from nothing except by way of
creation, which is a miracle; and we do not believe in miracles unless we have
to. That they came from something is also impossible; for this something can be
neither matter nor form. It cannot be matter, for form, the actual and
superior, cannot come from the potential and inferior. It cannot be form, for
then form would proceed from form by way of genesis and dissolution, which is
not true. Matter is the cause of generation and dissolution, not form. We are
thus forced to the conclusion that the soul is one and eternal, one in
substance and number; and that it becomes many only per accidens, by virtue of the multiplicity of its receiving
subjects, comparable to the light of the one sun, which divides into many rays.
The Bible
cannot help us to decide this question, for its expressions can be interpreted
either way. Hillel then undertakes to adjudicate between the contending views
by striking a compromise. He feels that he is contributing to the solution of
an important problem by an original suggestion, which he says is to be found
nowhere else expressed with such clearness and brevity.
Here
again Hillel's Neo-Platonic tendencies are in evidence. For he assumes both a
universal soul and a great number of individual souls emanating from it in a
descending series. The objection that forms cannot come from other forms by way
of generation and dissolution, Hillel says, is not valid, for no such process
is here involved. Generation and dissolution is peculiar to the action of body
upon body, which is by contact. A spiritual form acts upon other forms not
through contact, because it is not limited by time or place. We know concerning
the Intelligences that each comes from the one previous to it by way of
emanation, and the same thing applies to the issue of many human souls from the
one universal soul. After death the rational part of every soul remains; that
part which every soul receives from the Active Intellect through the help of
the possible or material intellect, and which becomes identified with the
Active and separate Intellect. This is the part which receives reward and
punishment, whereas the one universal soul from which they all emanate is a
divine emanation, and is not rewarded or punished.
We must
now discuss further the nature of the three grades of intellect. For this it
will be necessary to lay down three preliminary propositions.
1. There
must be an intellect whose relation to the material intellect is the same as
that of the object of sense perception is to the sense. This means that just as
there must be a real and actual object to arouse the sense faculty to perceive,
so there must be an actual intelligible object to stir the rational power to
comprehend.
2. It
follows from 1 that as the material sense has the power of perceiving the
sensible object, so the material intellect has the power of perceiving this
other intellect.
3. If it
has this power, this must at some time be realized in actu. Therefore at some
time the material intellect is identified with the other intellect, which is
the Active Intellect.
We must
now prove 1. This is done as follows: We all know that we are potentially
intelligent, and it takes effort and pains and study to become actually
intelligent. In fact the process of intellection has to pass several stages
from sense perception through imagination. Now our intellect cannot make itself
pass from potentiality to actuality. Hence there must be something else as
agent producing this change; and this agent must be actually what it induces in
us. Hence it is an active intellect.
The material
intellect has certain aspects in common with the sense faculty, and in certain
aspects it differs. It is similar to it in being receptive and not active. But
the mode of receptivity is different in the two. As the intellect understands
all forms, it cannot be a power residing in a body in the sense of extending
through it and being divided with the division of the body, as we see in some
of the powers of sense. This we can prove as follows:
1. If the
intellect were receptive in the same manner as the senses, it would receive
only a definite kind of form, as for example the sense of sight does not
receive taste.
2. If the
intellect were a power in body and had a special form, it could not receive
that form, just as for example if the eye were colored, it could not perceive
colors.
3. If the
intellect were a corporeal power, it would be affected by its object and
injured by a powerful stimulus, as is the case in the senses of sight and
hearing. A dazzling light injures the eye, a deafening noise injures the ear,
so that thereafter neither sense can perform its normal function properly. This
is not true with the intellect. An unusually difficult subject of thought does
not injure the intellect.
4. If the
intellect were similar in its activity to sense perception, it would not be
self-conscious, as the sense faculties cannot perceive themselves.
5. The
intellect, if it were like sense, would not be able to comprehend a thing and
its opposite at the same time, or it would do so in a confused manner, as is the
case in the powers of sense.
6. The
intellect perceives universals; the sense, particulars.
This
being the case, there is a difference of opinion as to the nature of the
material intellect. Some say that it has no definite nature in itself except
that of possibility and capacity, though it is different from other
possibilities in this respect that it is not resident in, and dependent upon a
material subject like the others. That is why Aristotle says that the material
intellect is not anything before it intellects; that it is in its essence
potential with reference to the intelligibilia,
and becomes actual when it understands them actually.
Themistius
says it is not any of the existents actually, but a potential essence receiving
material forms. Its nature is analogous to that of prime matter; hence it is
called material intellect. It is best to call it possible intellect. Being a
potential existent it is not subject to generation and dissolution any more
than prime matter.
Alexander
of Aphrodisias thinks the material intellect is only a capacity, i. e., a power
in the soul, and appears when the soul enters the body, hence is not eternal a
parte ante.
Averroes
holds that the possible intellect is a separate substance, and that the
capacity is something it has by virtue of its being connected with the body as
its subject. Hence this capacity is neither entirely distinct from it nor is it
identical with it. According to him the possible intellect is not a part of the
soul.
Which of
these views is correct, says Hillel, requires discussion, but it is clear that
whichever of these we adopt there is no reason opposing the conjunction of the
possible intellect with the Active. For if it is an eternal substance,
potential in its nature, like primary matter, then it becomes actual when it
understands the intelligible objects. The same is true if it is a capacity
residing in the soul.
Hillel is
thus of the opinion in this other question debated in those days, whether the
intellect of man is capable of conjunction during life with the angelic Active
Intellect, that it is. The Active Intellect, he says, in actualizing the
material intellect influences it not in the manner of one body acting upon
another, i. e., in the manner of an efficient or material cause, but rather as
its formal or final cause, leading it to perfection. It is like the influence
which the separate Intelligences receive from one another, the influence of
emanation, and not a material influence comparable to generation. This
reception of influence from the Active Intellect on the part of the potential
is itself conjunction. It means that the agent and the thing acted upon become
one, and the same substance and species. The material intellect becomes a
separate substance when it can understand itself.
Before
taking up the more theological problem of reward and punishment, he devotes the
last section of the theoretical part of his book to a discussion of the
relation of the possible or material intellect to the rest of the human soul.
This problem also arose from Averroes's interpretation of the Aristotelian
psychology, and is closely related to the other one of the unity of the human
intellect. It is needless for us to enter into the technical details which are
a weariness to the flesh of the modern student, but it is worthwhile to state
briefly the motives underlying the opposing views. Averroes, who had no
theological scruples, interpreted Aristotle to mean that the part of the soul
which was intimately associated with the body as its form, constituting an
indissoluble organism in conjunction with it, embraced its lower faculties of
sense, imagination and the more concrete types of judgment. These are so
intimately bound up with the life of the body that they die with its death. The
reason on the other hand, which has to do with immaterial ideas, or
intelligibles as they called them, is eternal and is not the form of the body.
It is a unitary immaterial substance and is not affected by the life or death
of the body. To be sure it comes in contact with the human soul during the life
of the body, thus bringing into existence an individualized human reason as a
passing episode. But this individualized phase of the intellect's life is
dependent upon the body and ceases when the body dies, or is reabsorbed in the
universal intellect.
The
theological implications of this view were that if there is any reward and
punishment after death, it would either have to be administered to the lower
faculties of the soul, which would have to be made immortal for the purpose, or
if the rational soul is the subject of retribution, this cannot affect the
individual, as there is no individual rational soul. Hence the Christian
opponents of Averroes, like Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas (Hillel speaks
of them here as the "Religionists," or the "Sages who believe in
religion"), endeavored to vindicate for the Aristotelian definition of the
soul as the form of the body, also the rational part, thus maintaining the view
that the reason too has an individual existence both during life and after
death. Thomas Aquinas, as a truer interpreter of Aristotle, goes so far as to
maintain that the Active Intellect itself is also a part of the human soul, and
not one of the angelic separate Intelligences. Neither Maimonides nor Hillel
ben Samuel, nor any other Jewish philosopher was able to depart so widely from
their Arabian masters or to undertake an independent study of Aristotle's text,
as to come to a similar conclusion. Hence the Active Intellect in Jewish
Philosophy is unanimously held to be the last of the Angelic substances, and
the proximate inspirer of the prophet. The discussion therefore in Hillel's
work concerns the possible intellect, and here he ventures to disagree with
Averroes and decides in favor of the possible intellect as a part of the soul
and the subject of reward and punishment.
Concerning
the nature of reward and punishment after death opinions are divided. Some
think that both reward and punishment are corporeal. Some say reward is spiritual,
punishment is corporeal; while a small number are of the opinion that both are
spiritual. Hillel naturally agrees with the latter and gives reasons for his
opinion. If the soul, as was shown before, is incorporeal, immaterial and a
formal substance, it cannot be influenced by corporeal treatment. For corporeal
influence implies motion on the part of agent and patient, and the pervasion of
the influence of the former through the parts of the latter; whereas a
spiritual substance has no parts. Besides, if reward and punishment are
corporeal, and Paradise is to be taken literally, then why separate the soul
from the body, why not reward the living person with eternal life and give him
the enjoyment of paradise while on earth? The effect would be much greater upon
the rest of mankind, who would see how the righteous fare and the wicked. The
objection that this would make people mercenary does not hold, for they are
mercenary in any case, since they expect reward; whether in this life or in the
next makes no difference. Reward must therefore be spiritual, and so must
punishment, since the two go together.
When God
in his kindness favored the human race by giving them a soul, which he united
with the body, he also gave them the possibility of attaining eternal
happiness. For this purpose he arranged three grades of ascent, viz., the three
intellects spoken of above, the material or possible intellect, the acquired
intellect (this is the actual functioning of the possible intellect and the
result thereof) and the active intellect. The second intellect is partly
speculative or theoretical and partly practical. The theoretical intellect
studies and contemplates all intelligible existents which are separate from
matter. There is nothing practical in this contemplation, it is just the
knowledge of existents and their causes. This is called the science of truth,
and is the most important part of philosophy.
The
practical intellect is again divided into the cogitative and the technological.
The former decides whether a thing should be done or not, and discriminates
between the proper and the improper in human actions and qualities. It is
important as a guide to the happiness of the soul because it instructs the
appetitive power in reference to those things which are subject to the will,
and directs it to aim at the good and to reject the evil.
The
technological intellect is that by which man learns arts and trades. The
practical intellect is also theoretical in the sense that it has to think in
order to discriminate between the proper and the improper, and between the
beneficial and injurious in all things pertaining to practice. The difference
between the speculative and practical intellects is in the respective objects
of their comprehension, and hence is accidental and not essential. The objects
of the theoretical intellect are the true and the false; of the practical, the
good and the bad. The acquired intellect gives these intelligibles to the soul
through the possible intellect, and is intermediate between the latter and the
Active Intellect, which is one of the separate Intelligences above soul. The
Active Intellect watches over the rational animal that he may attain to the
happiness which his nature permits.
Men
differ according to their temperamental composition and their human conduct.
This leads to differences in the power of understanding and in the amount of
influence received from the Active Intellect. Hillel quotes Maimonides in
support of his view that the prophetic stage is an emanation of glory from God
through the medium of the Active Intellect, which exerts its influence upon the
rational power and upon the imagination, so that the prophet sees his vision
objectified extra animam. The three
conditions requisite for prophecy are perfection in theory, perfection in
imagination and perfection in morals. The first without the second and third
produces a philosopher; the second without the first and third gives rise to a
statesman or magician.
It is
important to know, he tells us, that the cultivation of the reason and
imagination alone is not sufficient. Practice of the commandments is very
important. Hence a man must guide properly the two powers of sense perception
and desire, which are instruments of the rational power. For, as Maimonides says
in his commentary on Aboth, all observance and violation of the commandments,
good and bad qualities depend upon those two powers. Without a proper training
of these the influence of the active intellect upon the reason and imagination
may lead to evil.
Beginning
with sense perception a man must train all his five senses to attend only to
what is good and to turn away from evil. When he satisfies his sensuous
desires, he must do this in order to preserve his body that he may be enabled
to serve God in the best possible way.
The same
applies to the power of desire. This is the power which directs one to pursue
the agreeable and shun the disagreeable. From it proceed also courage,
confidence, anger, good will, joy, sorrow, humility, pride. All these qualities
must be used in the service of God. If a man do this, he will attain the grade
of an angelic being even during life, and will be able to perform miracles like
the prophets and the sages of the Talmud.
After
death the souls of such men reach even a higher degree than they had before
entering the body, as a reward for not allowing themselves to be degraded by
their corporeal desires, but on the contrary directing these to higher aims.
As for
the nature of reward and punishment more particularly, we may say that the soul
of the wicked loses all the glory promised to her and descends to a position
lower than was hers originally. She is expelled from the land of life and
remains in darkness forever, without returning to her original station. Knowing
what she has lost, she will feel continuous distress, sorrow and fear, for the
power of imagination remains with the soul after death. But there is no
physical burning with fire. On the other hand, the soul of the righteous will
return to God.
The
doctrine of the resurrection and the explanation for it are a further proof
that the soul after death is not punished corporeally. The motive of the
resurrection is that the soul and body may receive their compensation together
as in life. If then the retribution of the soul is corporeal, there is no need
of resurrection.
Hillel
then proceeds to show that the words of the Rabbis which seem to speak for
corporeal retribution are not to be taken literally. In this connection it is worthwhile
to reproduce his classification of the contents of the Talmud and his attitude
toward them. He enumerates six classes.
1.
Passages in the Talmudic and Midrashic literature which must be taken
literally. These are the discussions of the Halaka (the legal and ceremonial
portions). To pervert these from their literal meaning, or to maintain that the
intention of the law is the important thing and not the practice of the
ceremony, is heresy and infidelity; though it is meritorious to seek for an
explanation of every law, as the Rabbis themselves do in many instances.
2.
Passages which should be understood as parables and allegories with a deeper
meaning. These are the peculiar Haggadahs, or the strange interpretations of
Biblical verses where no ceremonial precept is involved.
3.
Statements similar to those of the Prophetical books of the Bible, which were
the result of the influence of the Active Intellect and came to the sages in a
dream or in the waking state, speaking of the future in an allegorical manner.
These are the extraordinary tales found in the Talmud, which cannot be
understood literally, as they involve a violation of the order of nature; and
no miracle must be believed unless for a very important reason.
4. The
homilies addressed to the people on the occasion of holidays for the purpose of
exhorting them to divine worship and observance of the Law. Many of these are
hyperbolical in their expression, especially in the promises concerning the
future blessings in store for the people. These were in the nature of
encouragement to the people to make their burdens easier to bear. Here belong
also unusual interpretations of Biblical verses, explanations which do not give
the original meaning of the verse in question, but are suggested in order to
interest the people. We must add, too, stories of the good things that came to
pious people in return for their piety. These must be taken for the most part
literally, unless they are clearly improbable.
5. Jokes
and jests by way of relief from the strain of study. Hyperboles belong here.
6.
Narratives of miracles done for pious people, such as reviving the dead,
punishing with death by means of a word, bringing down rain, and so on. All
these must be taken literally. To disbelieve is heresy. This is true only where
the alleged miracles were done for a high purpose, otherwise we need not
believe them.
The
reason the Bible and the Talmud express themselves in corporeal terms
concerning reward and punishment is in order to frighten the people and to
impress them with the terrible punishment consequent upon wrongdoing. The
people do not understand any reward and punishment unless it is physical and
corporeal. In reality spiritual existence is more real than physical.
CHAPTER XV .- LEVI BEN GERSON
|
HISTORY OF THE JEWS
|