MEDIEVAL HISTORY LIBRARY |
THE EMPEROR JULIAN THE APOSTATE
CHAPTER IV.JULIAN'S THEOLOGY.
"In the silent mind of One all-pare
At first imagined lay
The sacred world, and by procession sure
From those still deeps, in form and color drest,
Seasons alternating and night and day,
The long-nursed thought to north, south, east, and west,
Took then its all-seen way."
The ground is now cleared for examining Julian's scheme of religious
revival. The first step in this will be to master its intellectual basis, in
other words Julian's theology.
Julian nowhere in his surviving works develops his doctrine concerning
the One with any fullness or precision. In the incidental allusions which
occur, he wavers as to the rightful title to be assigned; whether this highest
original principle is to be regarded as ineffable and to be described simply as
that which is beyond or transcending Nous,
or as the One, or in Platonic terminology as the Good, or lastly as the Idea of
all Existences, by which he explains himself to mean the Intelligible in its entirety.
So far as he goes, he agrees with Plotinus in either assigning to it
negative determinations only, or allowing it by courtesy the imperfect title of
the Good, or finally treating it positively through the medium of its effects
as absolute causality. On the exact relation of the One to Nous Julian is
silent: in the above there seems a tendency to confuse the highest Deity with
either the first or second members of the trinity of Plotinus. On the essential
being of the One Julian is sufficiently orthodox.
It transcends all human description or conception: it is from eternity
pre-subsistent; it includes within itself all Being; its very essence is unity. Itself incomprehensible it is the sole unique
in-Composite cause of the whole universe. Julian most frequently denominates it the Good. Itself the
crown and source of every existence, it enters into transcendental relations
with the subordinate orders of Being. These are three in number, and carefully
differentiated by Julian.
To distinguish them in English, recourse must be had to terms of formal
philosophy. The first and highest
order is styled the Intelligible; the second, the Intellectual; the third, the Cosmic. This strict trinitarian conception runs through the whole system: the
triad involves a pantheistic belief, since the lowest member of the trinity
includes the material world. It is with the first and most spiritual alone that
the Good has direct communication. In that order, in other words in the
Intelligible Gods, it becomes the author of the beauty, the essential being,
the perfectness and the unity which characterize them. Thus through them it is
said to originate in all existences
their beauty and perfection, their unity and power inexplicable. These
Intelligible Gods are not generally conceived to issue from the supreme One,
though such language is in loose usage admissible. More strictly they cluster
round the One, being as it were with all creation a part of his ever-emitted
radiance. He transcends all things, round him are all things, and for his sake
all things are. The One is not so much a creator, as an everlasting well of
existence: in the case of the Intelligible Gods, immediately, elsewhere mediately, by virtue of essence transmitted to the
Intelligible Gods. To such demiurgic functions committed to these last, and by
them in turn transmitted to the inferior grades of deities, all orders of being
are due, until contact is finally attained with mortal perishable forms of
matter.
The Gods, those at any rate of the two higher orders, the Intelligible
and the Intellectual, are unsubstantial and immaterial. Goodness, and that
which is good, is an inseparable part of their essence, and remains ever inherent in their very nature.
No duality of nature, corresponding to the spiritual and carnal elements in
man, is conceivable in the Gods. They are not to be regarded as non-natural
magnified men: for in truth the divine nature is radically different from the
human. It is indivisible, and does not admit the analysis or the modifications
to which man's nature is liable.
The kind of personality which they possessed in Julian's eyes is a
difficult matter to settle. They combined strangely the impersonal nature of
the Platonic Ideas with the personality attributed to the polytheistic deities. There is a confusion of their persons one with another,
and a necessitarianism attributed to their whole mode
of being and acting, that converts them into forces rather than living wills.
Both the limitations and the powers of strict personality seem not seldom
denied to them. But, on the other hand, they are habitually feared, addressed,
adored and propitiated as though gifted with personal will, and the power to
put it into effect. With the Gods, will, power, action, are one and the same
thing, a part of their essence and inseparable. “Whatsoever a God wills, that he is and can
and does: he neither wills what he is not, nor is thwarted in what he wills,
nor is of the mind to do what he cannot”. Good being a constant element of
their essence, or rather actually constituting their essence, they are in
action, whether towards one another or towards man, entirely and invariably
beneficent. This description, though vouchsafed primarily of the higher orders
of Gods, is applicable also to the lower Cosmic Gods—the visible and sensible
as contrasted with the invisible and spiritual Gods—whose functions will be considered in due course. For to depict
their true relations, it is essential to treat of the Gods according to their
proper grades.
The highest sphere is, as has been repeated, the Intelligible. The
Intelligible World is characterized by what Julian speaks of as an exuberant
superabundance of life-producing fecundity. As the superfluous energy of the
One produced the Intelligible World round about the One, so too does it in its
turn manifest a like exuberance. All
that belongs to it enjoys pure, uncontaminated immaterial being; nothing of
alien nature inheres in it, nor ever has or can approach it from without. In
attributes of beauty, eternity, absoluteness, spirituality, or, if the term be
allowed, intellectuality, it corresponds to the Platonic world of Ideas; it is full of its own proper untainted purity. It is peopled by the Intelligible
Gods, and by them alone.
Essentially the Intelligible Gods exist around the Good, by eternal
emanation from him. From the Good they inherit direct all their gifts and
powers; he supplies them ungrudgingly with beauty, with being, with perfection,
with unity, in Neo-Platonic language he contains them all, and illuminates them
with inherited element or faculty of the archetypal Good, in which their
majesty consists, and which they transmit in measure to subordinate orders of
being. Among these Intelligible Gods, and highest of them all, is ranked
Helios, King Sun.
At this point a digression becomes necessary. One of Julian's surviving
works is a kind of devotional rhapsody—addressed to Salustius—in honor of King Sun. The address is
manifestly an effort of rhetoric rather than a spontaneous effusion of
devotion. Hastily, often confusedly put together, and too pretentiously
embellished, it yet remains the most fruitful quarry from which to extract
Julian's dogmatic beliefs. No doubt it exaggerates the functions and
pre-eminence of Sun, or rather throws them out of just proportion as compared
with those of other deities. Sun, his position and his work, are in the
foreground; the rest are aside or in the background, jumbled, slurred, and out
of focus.
But from sources quite independent of this elogium, it is plain that Julian did elevate
King Sun, under one representation or another, to the first place among Gods.
Neo-Platonism hailed from the East, and most grew and flourished there; it
became deeply tinged with influences of the Mithras cult and various forms of
fire-worship, every one of which sprang from, while most still acknowledged,
Sun adoration as the groundwork of religion. Julian espoused the worship with
devotion: it appeared to him instinctive; it dovetailed with his philosophy, no
less than it charmed his imagination. King Sun was the supreme deity, whom
under many various names all peoples of the world combined to worship. He was
the most tangible link by which Neo-Platonism gave unity to Paganism, rendered
Polytheism philosophical, and by aid of which, minds like Julian's became
reconciled to the incongruous superstitions or bizarre confusions of popular
beliefs. Julian regarded him moreover as in a special sense his patron; and
delights to call himself his follower, his liegeman, or his devotee.
Exaggeration or displacement of relations it will be easy in the main to
rectify. More misleading than either is a lack of lucidity and inconsistency,
the inevitable result of a pervading mysticism of tone. If the writer himself
was mystified, it became his penalty, or perhaps duty, to mystify his reader.
The action of King Sun in the Intelligible and Intellectual spheres has to be
spiritually derived from the analogous action of the phenomenal Sun in the
world of sense. Julian is at great pains to work out these analogies, and
contributes both knowledge and ingenuity to the task: but he is forever
confounding metaphor with fact, and converting analogies into modes of action;
much in the same spirit as when to the Alexandrians he insists upon the
alternations of summer and winter, the blessings of sunlight and growth of
plants, as evidences of the existence of Serapis (the
Sun God), constituting in his behalf a claim to adoration. At times he seems
purposely to confuse phenomenal faction with its spiritual counterpart, and
throughout leaves a vast deal to be interpreted by the spiritual intuitions of
the reader. Happily, a large residuum of solid information is left.
King Sun himself, most frequently entitled “King of the Universe”, is
himself primarily one of the Intelligible Gods, and chiefest among them all. He is the immediate and
trueborn offspring of the Good, emanating by eternal procession from the One,
or as it is elsewhere phrased, around the fruitful essence of the Good. By virtue of its abiding and initiative
essence the Good produced from its own being and in all things like itself Sun
the most high God. This emanative
production must not be looked upon as an act of creation, or as realized in
time. To every Neo-Platonic deity, and to Sun if any, belongs eternal
procession: he subsisted from Eternity around the abiding essence of the Good,
and thus is legitimately spoken of more than once as self-subsistent.
Among the Intelligible Gods, or as they are sometimes styled,
Intelligible Ideas, he not only himself shines with pure uncontaminated
radiance, but primus inter pares, as
incapable of admixture or impurity as light in the sensible world, holds
predominance. He is the centre of the Intelligible
system; he almost usurps functions which are elsewhere attributed to
the One; at any rate, his action begins at the point where the direct activity
of the One ceases; to his centrality is imputed the emanative multiplication of
the divine Intelligible essence, which without thereby receiving diminution or
increase or any kind of affection gives rise to the Intellectual order of
existences.
It is not a little curious that in more than one passage Julian speaks
of Sun apparently as one of the Intellectual Gods. His language, taken alone,
hardly admits another interpretation. Yet that Sun's position is such as has
been just described is undeniable. The fact is, that Julian has three separate
Suns, or phases of Sun in his mind, and is not sufficiently precise in
distinguishing them. In the actual passage where he alludes to this tripleness, he makes it perfectly
clear that the third Sun is the phenomenal Sun: for the two others, he leaves
the reader in obscurity. Both from the immediate context however and from the
whole oration the obvious interpretation is, that the first Sun is King Sun
himself, the Intelligible Deity, whose harmonizing office in his own sphere
almost intrudes upon that of the Good itself; while the second Sun is the Sun
regarded in his action on the Intellectual sphere. This forms the subject of
whole pages of the treatise, and it is his sovereignty and most intimate action
among the Intellectual Gods of which Julian is thinking, when he loosely
classes Sun as one of them rather than one above them.
Each of the three orders, Intelligible, Intellectual and Cosmic enjoys
perfection after its own kind. In the Intelligible World there is a pervading
unity, the gift of the One, which contains, conjoins or confederates the whole
into a One or perfect harmony. This unifying principle in the Intelligible
World is analogous to that Quintessence or Fifth Substance, which, in constant
motion round and round the heaven, by virtue of such periphery contains and
welds together all the parts of the Cosmic order, and forbids separation or
dissolution. The corresponding harmony that rules the Intellectual World, is
the immediate work of Sun, whose energies in that sphere are as all-important
as those of the Good in the higher sphere, or of the visible Sun in the lower.
This is the place to examine these in detail.
First then the Intellectual Gods were derived from Sun essentially. To
Neo-Platonist thought the one mode of
origination was eternal emanation. But emanation was carried on by successive
stages. At the head of all being, the one original Demiurge, from whom every
entity and essence is primarily derived, stands the One or the Good. He becomes
immediately the principle or first cause of the whole intelligible order. From
that point his demiurgic work is carried on mediately.
Later refinements of Neo-Platonic theology subtilised the demiurgic succession into a series of
triads, each issuing from a monad. Phanes was selected in the Intelligible triad as the term from which emanated the Intellectual triad, Kronos, Rhea and Zeus. From Zeus issues the supramundane triad: at the extremity of which comes Apollo,
who produces a triad of so-called liberated gods. Their extreme becomes the
generative monad of a triad of mundane gods. Julian nowhere endorses in detail
these refinements; he retails, by his own confession, but few out of many of
the inventions of the divine Iamblichus: in his classification of Gods there
are marked divergencies; but the general principle
is strongly asseverated.
King Sun, the arch-demiurge in the Intelligible World, Sun and plays
towards the Intellectual the same part that in the higher sphere is played by
the Good, who there causes
and directs all things aright in accordance with presiding intelligence or Nous. Thus, though metaphysically the
Intellectual Gods share original co-procession and co-subsistence with Sun,
they are yet said to owe their being to him. This. means that without his
agency their being would never be realized. He supplies them, and in constant unfailing measure, with what to the
Intellectual God is the very condition of being. Without this active and apprehended intelligence, their
existence is but potential; they are as eye-sight without light. Nor does his
task end here with this creation, or more strictly actualization of their
essential being and attributes. Having received from the Good dominion among
the Intellectual Gods, he actively and incessantly exercises it: they are as
subordinate and inferior to him as the stars are to the natural sun; their
whole being is directed by his providing guidance. It is Sun that imparts its
unity to all Intellectual being throughout the universe. In technical
phraseology he contains them intellectually in himself, fills all heaven with
them, and himself becomes a unifying centre about
which their action is harmonized. He may be called a harmonic mean or centre; not (Julian is careful to explain) as a mean
between extremes, but as a central principle everywhere infusing unity of action, perfecting and
harmonizing diverse energies, and combining otherwise conflicting extremes into a single identity. Like
the phenomenal Sun he controls, adjusts and regulates the centrifugal forces of
the system.
In addition to his originative and regulative functions, he exercises
distributive powers on a royal scale. He is directly commissioned to dispense
to all Intellectual forms of being the rich endowments of perfectness and beauty which the Good originates and
imparts among the Intelligible Gods. Being, unity, illimitable beauty, productive fecundity, perfected intelligence, all the divine attributes
Analogy to proceed from great Sun. His counterpart or image in the visible
world acts imitatively as a revealing medium whereby men may adore and
understand the analogous work of sovereign Sun in the Intellectual order. Just as the phenomenal Sun imprints harmony
upon the visible universe, of which he forms the centre,
as he regulates the concentric motions of the spheres, guides the circling
orbits of the planets at measured distances, and no less the changeful phases
of the moon, as with creative energy he ministers to earth her unbroken power
of being, as he gives the beauty of day for work, and in turn the terror of
night wherein men rest from their labors, as he brings to pass storm and wind
and cloud and all atmospheric changes, so does the royal Sun act in the
Intellectual world. The sincere uncontaminated radiance of light, which Sun ever sheds abroad in this
world, which gives sight to the eyes as the artist gives form to the marble, is
but the counterpart of that undefiled illuminating Truth in which he bathes the
Intellectual forms of being. Light is to the visible as Truth to the
Intelligible.
Thus King Sun originates, impels and harmoniously adjusts, endows and
equips with appropriate excellences and energies. He continues too to exorcise
a providing control. But he is often mythologically represented as performing this by deputy. Thus he is said, having controlled
the gods to a single unity, to hand them over as a mighty army to Athene Pronoia to do at her bidding their appointed work. She acts
as his subordinate consort. Elsewhere
his guiding control finds a different personification as Prometheia, identified with the Mother of the Gods,
and constantly in concert with the higher deity assuming preservative direction
of the Intellectual Gods.
Sun's influence does not end with the Intellectual sphere, and pass from
thence by transmitted emanation only into the Cosmic order. He exercises a
direct palpable influence over the Cosmos. His demiurgic power is active there.
He is said to have called the Cosmos into being, reserving for his
representative the central place, so as to secure ready and equal distribution
of goods and ordering of the heavenly bodies, the subordinate co-proceeding
Gods. His demiurgic action in the Cosmos occupies a central place between that
of the primal demiurge and the numerous lower demiurgic deities: but no
delimitation is attempted of the provinces in which each acts. Relatively to
the Cosmos these inferior creative agencies exhibit themselves in diverse and
multiplied activities; relatively to Sun they are uniform, crowning the
uncontaminated essence of the deity. In regard to the origination of the Cosmos
one warning deserves repetition. Its creation is not a chronological event. It
might appear such in the bold representations of Plato and Iamblichus. It is
convenient to describe it so; indeed hardly possible to do otherwise. But the
strict theological conception is that things proceeded or rather were produced
from eternity. Sun procreated things visible from the invisible in the infinite
present, by the ineffable celerity and unsurpassed power of the divine will.
Beyond this point it is hard to push with precision any account of the
functions of King Sun. They mingle inextricably with those of his mundane
representative. Julian is so busy with tracing affinities, with extorting
spiritual correspondences from scientific analyses of the nature and uses of
light, with wresting astronomical arrangements and speculations into
allegorical representations of higher truth, and so often veils the transition
from the sign to the thing signified under an ambiguous 'Sun', that it is
impossible without arbitrariness to decide whether the agency of the higher or
the lower deity is intended. Sun, for instance, is described as being with man
the joint and universal begetter of men: he gathers souls from himself and from
other Gods, and sows them on earth: in life he ministers to them every good, he
judges, he directs, he purges them; finally, he liberates them from their
bodily tenement, reunites them to the kindred and divine essences, converting
the ethereal activity of his divine rays into a vehicle for their conveyance.
These might seem duties worthily
ascribed to the sovereign Sun; yet are almost unmistakably transferred to his
lower representative. Can any other interpretation be placed on these words:
“Just as Sun is author of day and night, and of winter or summer by his
approach or retrocession, so is the most venerable of
the Gods; to him are all things and of him are all things; he appoints us rulers during life, and after death
apportions us governors”. Julian is either enhancing the dignity of the cosmic
Sun, or purposely giving him the advantage of his name and confounding him with
his better.
It would be tedious to rehearse all Julian's praises of the Sun
apparent. He is leader and lord in the sensible world. He is the originative
cause of heaven and the stars, and upholds them with sustaining force. His vast
productive fertilizing power is dwelt upon persistently. He supplies a
never-ceasing stimulus of life to the earth by alternate approach and
retirement. He enriches men with equable unceasing distribution of blessings,
material and spiritual. The simplicity of his motion betokens the excellence
and superiority of his power beyond that of all planets and stars and heavenly
bodies. His appearance, his position, his work, his action upon natural
phenomena proclaim his majesty.
This is the barest outline of Sun's specific work: but it will be more
instructive to view the Cosmos as a whole, and range its different parts
according to their proper dignity. “The divine and all lovely universe from the
highest arc heaven to the utmost ends of earth is from everlasting to
everlasting. It is a single animate whole, everywhere instinct with Soul and
Intellect, perfect and of perfect parts”. It is not the immediate work of the
great First Cause, but of those Intelligible Gods to whom he has committed his
Demiurgic Functions. Its origin is emanative, and it subsists around the supreme
God Helios or Sun. It is ruled directly by the so-called visible or apparent
Gods, of whom phenomenal Sun is the chief. Moon, planets, stars are all such
apparent Gods, emanating from primal Sun, and counterparts in the Cosmic
sphere of the Intelligible Gods corresponding to them in the higher order.
Between the supramundane and mundane Gods Julian draws no plain line of demarcation.
Immediately beneath the Gods come the so-called divine kinds of being. These ubiquitous spirits exercise superhuman
agencies, and are distributed in various classes, Angels, Daemons, Heroes and
Separate Souls. The precise differentia of daemons, heroes and souls
respectively had been one of Porphyry's perplexities, and Julian does not
emulate the extravagances of Iamblichus by any scientific analysis. He teaches
in general terms that all alike owe their innate energy to Sun. Of Angels there
are various classes; the highest are Solar Angels, who are the first creation
of Sun about the Cosmos: there are also Lunar Angels. One at least of their
functions is to act as guardian spirits. The Daemons too are active agents of
the Gods.
Porphyry had assigned to them superintendence over distinct animal or
vegetable or meteorological departments of nature; had honored them as patrons
of particular arts, and commissioned ambassadors between Gods and men. But they
are of uncertain character: exceptional daemons may be altogether beneficent,
but as a rule the daemon is not absolutely pure or perfectly good, like the
Gods, but participates in some alloy of evil: some are no better than imps or
bogies. Daemons of distinct characters preside over nations, acting under the
superintendence of the patron God, and helping to mould and perpetuate their national characteristics. Conversely there is an appointed
tribe of malicious daemons who, guarding the honor of the eternal and saving
Gods, delude the apostate Christians with dreams of heaven after death, or
drive them out as anchorites into the wildernesses far from their fellow-men.
The Separate Souls are products or effects of the great central Soul, which
pervades the All. Though in contact with matter temporarily individualized,
they are yet one and the same, just as Knowledge or Light though divisible into
parts remain nevertheless essentially wholes. So the Soul of the Universe
remains indivisible, though each individual soul derives from it its proper
complement, when it accepts the self-imposed limitations of time, space, and
quasi-personality involved in the combination with matter.
At this stage the world of matter is reached. Matter, in Julian's belief, is eternal, subsisting
beside the procreative essence of the Gods, and generated by eternal
co-procession with the Gods, by virtue of that superfluous energy of
procreative and constructive powers, with which the Gods, no less than the
First Cause himself, are endowed. Matter in its raw form consists only of
negations ; it is the substratum void of all attributes and incomprehensible to
sense: it is utterly lifeless and sterile, the filth, the refuse, the dregs of
existence; no language can be too strong
to express its demerits. Potential determination of being is the sole attribute
allowed to what is in itself “the absolutely non-existent”. It requires to be
animated by divine essence before it is raised to that degree of passible being, in which we apprehend it by sense. It then
becomes materialized form. Thus the material world consists of so many
junctions of matter with immaterial cause, which confers on it sensible being.
Matter and spirit alike are primary and necessary assumptions; the union of the
two is inexplicable; neither the mode nor agent of the combination is
discoverable: we only see the result. Some cause of the union there must of
course have been. That it was not blind chance we may rest satisfied. Any
Epicurean theory of fortuitousness may be dismissed at the bare mention.
Peripatetics attribute the conjunction to the action of the Quintum Genus or Fifth element. But
this merely pushes the difficulty a step back, not solving it. The earth is
supported on the elephant, the elephant on the tortoise, and the tortoise—on
what? It remains a final fact that soul is united with various forms of
material being. The mode or cause of union transcends reason. It is best
regarded not as an act of free-will on the part of animating soul, but as
necessarily arising from the natural constitution of things. Soul in a figure
lying on the outskirts of the suprasensual world could not but illuminate the darkness on which it bordered, formless
matter, and thereby brought into being before all time the phenomenal world.
The only reasonable explanation of the final dualism that everywhere meets the
philosopher is offered by the Neo-Platonic scheme of eternally existent spirit
and eternally existent matter connected by emanative processes! The union is
brought about solely for the improvement and elevation of matter. Much as it
may have to endure in the union, soul the superior nature, akin to God, can
take no hurt or hindrance from contact with its baser companion.
But a nearer insight into the stage, so to speak, at which the
connection was divinely consummated is granted to us in the myth of Attis. Therein it is recounted how Attis exposed beside the eddies of the Gallus grew to the perfect flower of beauty;
how the mother of the Gods conceived a passion for him, loaded him with gifts
and crowned him with stars; how afterwards false to that love he went down into
the cave and had intercourse with the nymph; whereupon followed his mutilation,
and the visitation with madness. In this pregnant myth the initiated will
discern the true account of the union between spirit and matter, and the
origination of the material world.
The Mother of the Gods is the faithful handmaid of King Helios. She
personifies his providing control. As such she directs and preserves the lower
orders of Gods. She dispenses to them Sun's gifts, among others the prime gift
of demiurgic power, which she at once stimulates and guides. Of this there are
various grades corresponding to the grades of Gods. Attis represents the lowest stage of demiurgic
productiveness, that namely at which the divine comes in contact with the
material. He is the last link in the chain which unites earth with the
superabundant fertility of the productive principle. The Gallus beside which Attis lay blooming is the Milky Way, which is confessedly
the junction of passible substance with the
impassible Quintessence. The Mother's love, her gifts, the crown of stars show
her at her proper work, elevating, stimulating, etherealizing the demiurgic
force and desire of the lower God, so as to win it and wean it from its
perilous inclination towards matter. Spite of that preserving love Attis goes down into the cave, forsaking heaven for earth,
and impregnates the nymph, who typifies the immaterial cause which converts
matter into material being. Such declension from divine continence might argue Attis less than divine. He has been called a demigod. But
in reality it was a gracious, generous condescension, a sacrifice for the sake
of outcast matter. His end achieved he returns to heaven. His emasculation has
a most real meaning. It signifies the restraint of his infinite productive
power, in other words the fact that in the material world generation is limited
by the demiurgic Providence to definite forms. So too has his ensuing madness.
The generative cause at the last stage, where the divine is brought into
contact with matter, loses self-control: that is to say, the material world is
not self-subsistent, but subject to never-ceasing change and decay.
Such, temporally depicted, is the origination of the material world. The
combination remains ever active: otherwise every organism, matter that is to
say informed with spirit, being neither uncreate nor
self-subsistent, would revert to abstract indeterminate. Its whole Being is but
Becoming; in other words life depends on constant change of conditions, the
means towards which is supplied from without. There is need of constant,
outward sustainment, or as the Neo-Platonists prefer to say containment, by
divine power. Primarily this must be conferred by the action of the sovereign
One, secondarily by the Intelligible order, but immediately the world is
preserved or contained by nothing else than that “fifth substance” or Quintessence,
of which the principal component is the sun's ray. This pericosmic Quintessence, not seldom spoken of as the
cyclic substance, is incessantly busy at the borders of the universe coercing
and welding together all the naturally dispersive elements. It belongs to the
divine impassible portion of being, being that part of it which comes in
contact with lower passible existences. The Milky Way
marks the border line, where the creative reign of the higher Gods ends, and
that of Attis commences.
The Quintessence conserves being: it is not said to originate it. This
function is constantly attributed to Sun. The necessary influx and efflux of Being, which is essential to an
active existence, is provided by his ordered approach and retirement. To take a
specific instance man is, as Aristotle says, the offspring of man and of Sun,
the former transmitting the mortal material element, the latter providing for
the indwelling presence of Soul.
The procreative Gods produced man, having from the beginning received
souls from the prime Demiurge. As to the act of creation, while admitting as an
alternative the Scripture account, he prefers to believe that numerous couples
and not one merely were created. It would have been as easy to create many as
one, and the distinctive characteristics of race, features, laws, customs, and
the like, no less than the vast numbers existing, point decidedly to the former
as the true hypothesis. And not the nobler parts of the Universe alone, not man
or the celestial bodies only, but every stick or stone is animate with its
proper complement of soul, without which it would be mere formless undetermined matter. At the same time the
nature of the soul animating man, living creatures, plants and inanimate matter
differs with the respective differences of the body animated. Inanimate
objects possess qualities only, plants a
living organism, animals soul, man a reasonable soul: though it is a grave
question whether the superiority is not one of energy rather than of essential
kind.
As a brief summary of what may be called Julian’s doctrinal theology,
the grand ascription of praise which closes his Hymn to the Sun deserves
quotation. There he addresses him as before all Gods Sun himself, monarch of
the universe:
“Who proceedeth from
everlasting around the procreative essence of The Good, midmost and in the midst of the
Intellectual Gods,
Who before time was fulfilleth them with cohesion and infinite beauty and
procreative abundance and perfect intellect and all good gifts together,
Who in time present radiateth light from everlasting into His visible and proper seat that hath its course in
the midst of the whole heaven,
Who imparteth of the
intelligible beauty to all the universe,
Who fulfilleth the
whole heaven with all those Gods whom He Himself intellectually containeth within Himself,
multiplying around Him in indivisible fellowship and joined to Him in single
unity,
Who not less containeth also the sublunar space by perpetual generation and
the good gifts ministered from His cyclic frame,
Who careth for the
whole common race of men and for Rome our city in peculiar wise, even as He
hath supplied the substance of my soul that is from everlasting, and hath made
me His own devotee”.
It will now become plain at once that Julian did not decompose the
Hellenic mythology into representations of nature worship, detecting in its
tales so many transformed and fossilized solar myths. For this he had not the
materials with which Sanskrit and Zend mythology have
supplied moderns. An extract from Cyril's work will furnish the most compact summary of Julian’s
doctrine concerning the popular divinities. “The Demiurge is common father and
king of all, but he hath moreover assigned all peoples to Gods presiding over
peoples and caring for commonwealths, each of whom governs his allotment
conformably to his own nature. For seeing that in the Father all things are
perfect and all one, while in the separate deities one or another quality
predominates, therefore is it that Ares presides over the bellicose, Athene
over them that combine wisdom with war, Hermes over them that are shrewd rather
than adventurous, and the nations over which they preside follow each the
several natures of their proper Gods”. The
language here is plain; a fuller personality than usual is accorded, and in
itself the passage seems clear of ambiguities. But I one question remains. Into
what part of this theology were the current Pagan Gods fitted?
How far the Gods themselves, like the stories of Homer concerning them,
are mythical, and do but adumbrate the Divine essences with which popular
theology confounds them, it is difficult to determine. The question indeed at
this point becomes one of terms: in short are the names assigned true names or
misnomers? The answer is that the names are of human invention, the beings
denoted are real. With very few exceptions they take rank among the
Intellectual Gods as subordinate helpers of King Sun. But it would be a vain
hope to search Julian's pages for a consistent account of their respective
relations, functions and priority. He is too enamored of arbitrary allegorizing
from Homeric genealogies, of subtle inferences from oracular verses, and of
mystic interpretations of popular myths, to adhere to any plain uniform
classification of deities. Their relations to King Sun are as determinate as
anything, and offer the best standard of comparison.
Zeus is the highest God. In order to accommodate Hellenic beliefs and
revelations to the Neo-Platonic theology, he is placed usually on an exact
equality with Sun, though here and there slight traces of inferiority are
permitted appear. It is only in casual adjuration that great Sun is allowed to
stand second. Most commonly the two are identified as sharing single coequal
sovereignty over the whole tribe of Intellectual Gods. The identification is actually justified by a Homeric genealogy. To both alike is given the
title 'Father of the Gods.'
Incidentally Serapis is identified with Zeus
or Sun, mainly on the strength of an oracular verse; he is elsewhere spoken of
as the brother of Zeus. The only other God elevated to such rank is Hades. He
too must thank the oracle for his representation as the gentle propitious deity
whose kindly hand dissolves that union between soul and matter, which it is the
reciprocal work of Sun to bring to pass.
The Muses follow him as the leader of their choir, while Dionysus is the
son and consort to whom Sun appoints his proper work. Horus and Mithras are
other names for Sun rather than coequal deities. None other can claim a place
among Intelligible Gods unless it be Apollo. His identification with Sun can be
only of a popular character, but as consort with him he takes unsurpassed rank, partaking of the same
simplicity of intelligence, the same stability of being, the same immutability
of energy as Sun himself. It is he who in joint ascendancy instructs men by
oracles, inspires them with wisdom, and adorns societies with religions,
constitutions, laws and civilization.
The other Gods are definitely inferior to Sun, and assist in special
departments of his wide range of activities, personifying as it were those
activities. None transcend in dignity Athene and the Mother of the Gods,
between whom there is a clear affinity. Each represents Sun's controlling Providence:
each may be spoken of as his consort, and acts in full communion with the
Intelligible Gods. The Athene myth stereotypes anthropomorphically the direct
emanation of Athene from Sun or Zeus, and does not conceal her inferiority.
Justice has been already done to their controlling, preservative custodianship
of forces imparted to the Intellectual Gods. Athene is moreover the wisest of
goddesses, and virtue and wisdom and contrivance and statesmanship are among
her bounties to men. Aphrodite too
consorts with Sun, as a busy handmaid in his service. Among the heavenly Gods
she acts as a combining principle; she is the concord and unity of their
harmony, and goes everywhere with Sun tempering his creative work. On earth she
sheds forth rays of purest loveliness, brighter than very gold, melting men' s
souls with delight, and becoming to all living things the principle of
generation and the source of self-renewing life.
Dionysus represents and shares the disseminative productive power of
Sun, and is a loyal fellow-worker and ruler, whom Sun regards with paternal
love. Asclepius is begotten of Sun in the Cosmos, to
preserve the life and harmony of which he is the author and sustainer. Though
enjoying with Sun a premundane existence, he was made incarnate on
earth by the vivifying power of Sun, and endowed with human form to heal both
bodies and souls of men, with which beneficent purpose he wandered—whether
allegorically or no it is hard to decide—through all the great towns of earth.
The Muses and the Graces are the offspring of Sun and serve him as their lord. The lower demigods, such as Korybantes,
or Satyrs, Fauns, Bacchants take rank as daemons.
These shadowy identities are gleaned submissively from the preserves of
Iamblichus. Both in spirit and form Plotinus' identifications had been more
philosophic and rational, though open to a charge of tameness from the
monotonous recurrence of personifications of the soul as manifested in higher
or lower spheres. The obvious vagueness of this survey, which minimizes not
exaggerates Julian's own lack of precision, shows how shadowy and unreal his
assumed personifications are. They are of a random, kaleidoscopic character.
The picturesque stir and life of the old Hellenic Olympus is all gone. It has
nothing in common with the new-fangled mysticism but some borrowed names and
metaphors. The Gods are no longer living, breathing men and women, active in
love and in hate, girded with poetry, ravishing to the sense. All individuality
is lost. There is no form and no color left. The vivid lines and outlines are
smeared into a neutral expressionless smudge. Personal Gods have been
metamorphosed into scientific and theological conceptions or mathematical
ideas; mythology has become a philosopho-cosmical
and physico-astronomical
system. One effect of this is to invest the entire religion with a frigid and
labored artificiality that must have chilled piety and lamed all devout
enthusiasm, even if it did not suggest a self-conscious insincerity. It showed
the very opposite of the free Hellenic spirit; it was forced instead of
natural, exaggerated instead of true, constrained instead of free. Amid this
misty confounding of deities one positive idea of some interest is discernible.
For the old republican constitution of the Homeric Olympus with its independent
and often mutually antagonistic powers, with its jealousies and favoritisms and
animosities, there has been substituted a strict and ordered hierarchy of
graded deities, centering their aspirations and even merging their personality
in the supreme divinity, whose sway represented in ideal perfection that
absolute dominion to which the Emperor of Rome only in theory attained.
To discover hard and fast identities, or even principles of theology,
arrangement in this cloudland, is impossible. But it is easy to define the
general position taken up towards the popular theology. This was contained
primarily in Homer, Hesiod, and various collections of Hymns of the Gods. These
the new religion accepted as of divine authority, and written by direct
inspiration. Homer is habitually quoted in Julian's works with the weight of an
inspired authority.
How keenly the defectiveness of these as Sacred Books was felt by the
Neo-Platonists is shown by Porphyrius' endeavor to supply the lacuna by a
collection of the utterances of the Oracles. Such as they were, however, Julian
and his confederates accepted them, and adapted them to their purpose by an
elastic system of allegorical interpretation. It was in the myths more than
anywhere else that the popular religious conceptions were really enshrined.
Julian's treatment of these is bold and instructive: so bold that at times he
seems almost to stand on his defense against a charge of irreverence. He freely
admits that many of the ancient myths were as they stood grossly immoral and
impious.
But this very fact goes to prove that they cannot be actually and nakedly true. Venerable with the
dust of antiquity, but stamped with the brand of inspiration, they are handed
down to us as apocalyptic glimpses into those truths which the flagging
intellect of man can neither accurately grasp nor formulate. They are
sign-posts, not termini; their function is to excite the intellectual powers,
not satisfy. Myths then, such is his theory, stand to the intellectual sense
much in the same relation as images to the spiritual. They are but emblematic
representations of the truth, not literal statements of fact. Wrongly regarded
they infallibly obscure and misrepresent the inner truth they allegorize. They
are so to say concrete mental projections into time and place of that which
happened out all temporary or local relations.
The very contradictions or incongruities with which they abound are
meant expressly to stimulate men to look behind the veil and decipher the
hidden mystery. From the necessity of the case they are in every particular
anthropomorphic in conception, whereas the truths and processes they adumbrate
are wholly spiritual. The mythical birth of Helios from Hyperion and Theia is not meant as an account of marriage and processes
of generation among the Gods, ideas which are wholly incongruous with their
very nature: its real signification is that Helios, first among the
Intelligible Gods, sprang by emanation from a Cause yet higher still, that
Cause to wit which is of all most divine, and which wholly transcends all
comprehension, for Whom and round Whom are all things create or uncreate. So again the procession of Athene from the head
of Zeus, which materially conceived becomes meaningless blasphemy, sets forth
in a figure the spiritual truth that she came forth entire by immediate
emanation from the highest God. The interpretation of the myth of Cybele and Attis, which runs through so much of Julian's Fifth
Oration, is a more elaborate and ambitious effort in the same direction. Under
Julian's handling it becomes in part a solar myth but primarily a more
transcendental revelation.
Myths thus regarded are a testimony to something of a progressive
revelation of God to man. As birds fly and fish swim by instinct, with none to
teach or guide the way, so man too has his nobler instinct, that will not be
denied its satisfaction. The Gods have given him a soul, and that soul, even in
man's infancy, could not but flutter and try its wings. Imbued with godlike
affinities it tugged at the chain that held it, soaring toward truth. Shadowy
images, visions of unknown glories floated before it. As the feathers sprouted
upon the infant soul, a strange tingling, half of pleasure half of pain,
thrilled it through and through. The soul itching with intolerable desire found
relief in myths. They were like nurses rubbing the infant's gums at
teeth-cutting, relieving the irritation and quickening the growth. The itching
was but the herald of growing powers, myths but the foreshadowing of coming
revelations. The full-grown philosopher, while recognizing that they may serve
the infant still, knows that they were presages of more solid supervening
abilities. They are of use still maybe to spice moral teaching distasteful in
its severe simplicity, and so to sweeten nauseous truths. But the perfect man
has no need of sweets.
He seeks rather the strong meat and medicine, which the sweet but
obscured or rendered ineffective. Popular Such was Julian's abstract dogmatic
theology. It is no disparagement of his creed to say that it was impossible to
Platonic present its loftier truths to the capacities of popular intelligence.
If theology is a science at all, it follows at once that its deeper mysteries
will be accessible to those only who are versed in the science. The popular
creed will remain a rough and imperfect representation of the truths it but
dimly perceives. By what modifications then or adaptations were these religious
conceptions commended to the public?
In the first place, the purely intellectual side was perforce left in
the background. The doctrine of a trinity, the relation of emanating Deities to
the incomprehensible First Cause, the interdependence of Intelligible and
Intellectual Gods on each other and on the primal One were left to the
philosophers. But a far more vital modification than this was adopted.
Monotheism, which was in a sense the creed of the Neo-Platonist, and the
language of which Julian constantly employs in intercourse with his philosophic
friends, was in its popular representation wholly abandoned. It is
metamorphosed into polytheism, pure and simple. Nor does Julian attempt to
conceal it. In temple-worship, lustrations, sacrifices, indeed in everything,
he says, the Jews are in exact accord with the Pagans, except in the
peculiarity of a monotheistic belief. “Their sole error is in doing a
displeasure to the other Gods by reserving their worship for the God whom they
with barbarian pride and stupidity regard as their special property, relegating
the rest to the Gentiles alone”. Monotheism is positively denounced as “a
calumniation of the Deity”. The transformation was as simple as it was
necessary to win the popular ear. It merely involved a certain ignoring or
rather reticence concerning higher
esoteric mysteries, which is not even chargeable with insincerity.
Philosophers themselves believed in the Gods as emanating agents of the One God: nay more believed that
through them alone contact with the One was possible for anything short of the
highest philosophic intuition.
The whole genius of Neo-Platonism was essentially polytheistic. The
Monotheistic element was subsidiary, a satisfaction and a secret for the
philosopher, but for the multitude at most a tenet never a belief, a theory not
a motive power. The One was incomprehensible, incommunicable, unapproachable by
man; the Gods who governed the universe about him, who ruled him and his
destiny, who heard his petitions, who shielded him from evil, were subordinate,
many in number, diverse in form and desires and powers. This conception had
firmly embedded itself in the religion of mankind. “Throughout the whole world
you find one single concurrent law and testimony, that there is one God, king
and father of all, and Gods many, sons of God and joint rulers with God. This Greek
declares and this Barbarian, this the dweller on the mainland and the dweller
by the sea, this the wise man and the fool”. In Julian's own language, “The
Demiurge of the universe is one; the demiurgic deities, the denizens of heaven,
are many”. It was a belief requiring the concentrated forces of Christianity to
extirpate it: within the Church, in its last subtle phase of Arianism, it only
not prevailed; without, it was seized by Neo-Platonism, coordinated with the
highest reason and conscience of mankind, systematized, sanctioned, and wielded
in all its versatile applications.
From this standpoint Julian was able to exhibit a ready and generous
sympathy with whatever form of cult had commended itself to the people with
whom he might be concerned. He assiduously emphasizes the value he attaches to the preservation of local rites
or beliefs. Each is in itself a revelation: to surrender an ancestral rite is
to fling away a fragment of revealed truth. Hence a scrupulous reverence for
all traditional sanctities. Nations by a curious inversion of facts are
regarded as representing, or as molded by, the character of their tutelar Gods.
To Heliopolis must be given back its Aphrodite-worship, to the Jews their temple, to the shrine of Serapis the cubit of the Nile. “In things holy we do well to preserve whatsoever
ancestral custom prescribes: we must neither add thereto nor diminish a whit therefrom; for that which is of the Gods is everlasting”.
High priests were directed to follow the same rule in their visitations, never
to extemporize new rites or improve upon old, but to shun innovation above all
things. In precisely the same spirit Julian systematically endeavors appropriately to localize his references to
the Gods. If he writes to the Romans, he dwells on the special connection of
Helios with Rome, reminding them how the great God by his connection with Venus
and Mars becomes through Aeneas and
Romulus respectively the immediate patron of Rome: how further the tale of the
miraculous assumption of Quirinus, and not less Numa’s ordinance concerning the
sacred fire recognizes him still as tutelar divinity
of their favored town; and how they are even reminded of the fact by the
measurement of months and the season of the opening of the new year. If it is
to the Athenians he addresses himself, it is to Athene, the most wise Goddess,
that he appeals. If he takes up his pen
to the Alexandrians, he exhorts them to a better mind by the reverence that
they owe their patron-saint and founder Alexander, or adjures them by the name
of Serapis their city-holding King and his
maiden-consort Isis. To the Jews, to take a yet more interesting sample of the
same spirit, he adopts their own monotheistic language. Their God, he says, is
the same all-powerful and beneficent ruler of the universe whom we Greeks
worship, though under a varying names. After commending their faith and
sympathizing with the maltreatment they had endured, he entreats them to offer
up prayers for him and for the Empire, “to the most high God and Creator, who
has deigned to crown me with his undefiled right hand”; in his treatise against
the Christians he says in so many words, “I adore always the God of Abraham,
Isaac and Jacob”.
It is droll to watch with what scrupulous consistency Julian carries
out the same principle even in playful
and familiar correspondence. If he writes to a philosopher, Hermes of
reason, or the Muses will be the Deity
selected; unless indeed he be in poor health, when wishes for his convalescence
will be fortified by the name of Asklepius:
while in a letter to an Egyptian official the name of Serapis naturally becomes the appropriate vehicle for indignation. The changes in adjuration that are rung
remind the reader of Acres' device for adding point and relevance to the formulas
of oath.
In his exoteric teaching Julian is perfectly content to put forward the
lower and more popular motive or explanation, where he does not think an appeal
to the higher will wake a responsive echo. The appeal he thought must be
accommodated to the audience. In the Caesars he gently censures the stern
uncompromising Probus for not thus adapting himself
to the people. Wise doctors mix bitter draughts with honey to suit the
unaccustomed palate: like cows or horses, men are easiest led by what they
like. A good instance of this occurs in one of his letters to the Alexandrians:
there in exhorting them to the worship of Helios, he says no word of the
theological position or relations of that divinity, but appeals simply to the
natural power of the visible sun, and bids them as they look on the changing
seasons, on the processes of birth and growth, and on the ordered phases of the
Moon, fall down and worship the manifested and all-powerful Deity.
His popular as contra-distinguished from his philosophical teaching on
the nature and attributes of these Gods, and the manner in which he desired
they should be regarded, leads naturally to a consideration of Julian's idea of
personal religion.
VJULIAN’S IDEA OF RELIGION.
|