MEDIEVAL HISTORY LIBRARY |
THE EMPEROR JULIAN THE APOSTATECHAPTER III.NEO-PLATONISM.
So far as concerns pagan religion and philosophy, the centuries
preceding Julian have been depicted in the Introduction to this Essay as a time
of exposure and disintegration. Along with the gradual extinction of patriotism
under the incubus of an enormous centralized despotism, they witnessed a decay
of morals, a despairing surrender of primitive faiths, and throughout the most
honored schools a trepidation, a nerveless depression, and an impotence that
presaged imminent extinction. The heartiest attempt at conservation was revived
Platonism; that acknowledged the great truth of the unity of God, and renounced
the balder fallacies of idol-worship: but it lacked sound basis and inherent
vitality; it clung to extinct myths, and to solemn forms, and to edifying
survivals of ritual, out of which all virtue and meaning had departed for
generations, and which had long since become 'rudimentary' appendages. In the
hour of distress Mystery-worship with mischievous and ill-directed sympathy had
tried to drown men's legitimate and reasonable cravings, and to intoxicate them
out of consciousness of their despair. Christianity meanwhile, had owed its
strength and achieved its progress by recognizing the misery, the helplessness,
the degradation of the world, and by supplying it with a solution of its
misery, and also with a hope of redemption from it.
There was one other system which recognized the same unsatisfied
aspirations and present discontent, and strove not altogether ineffectively to
prescribe an explanation and a remedy. This system was Neo-Platonism.
Historically it was collateral rather than antagonistic to Christianity. Its
genius was philosophical, not sectarian; it was the intellectual expression of
that revulsion against skepticism and materialism, which distinguishes third
century thought. Not only did Pyrrhonism and
Epicureanism die completely out, but the intellectual revolt against them took
a positive form. The craving after worship, after some sure ground of belief,
after communion with the deity, in a word the spiritual element in man's nature
reasserted itself, and evolved a philosophic system at once reverential,
dogmatic, and spiritual. To skepticism the new philosophy opposed dogmatism, to
materialism an ascetic idealism. The astounding boldness of the attempt is one
of its most striking features. Starting from no historical basis, and claiming
no direct revelation, on the sole strength of intuitive belief, it assumed its
fundamental truth, and thence passing from step to step, lost in excess of daring,
framed a spacious and elaborate theology, by which it strove to solve or
elucidate the inscrutable problems that on all sides confronted it. It reposed
upon complete subjectivity: “the soul turned inwards upon itself, and there
read the nature of God and the riddle of existence. Perfect abstraction from
all without, when the soul centres upon itself, beholds beauty past understanding is the realization of the
highest life and identification with the divine”. It remains, if nothing else,
a standing witness to the permanent strength, the irresistible determination
and the boundless daring of the spiritual instinct of man.
In its original and most worthy cast Neo-Platonism was a system of
philosophy. The satisfaction it offered was primarily intellectual, though it
did not neglect, but indeed gave a splendid primacy to the spiritual element in
man. In religious precision and definiteness of aim it towered above previous
tentative efforts. It threw its whole strength of abstract thought and
exposition into the fundamental questions concerning the being and attributes
of God, the 'origin and existence of evil, the constitution and government of
the phenomenal world, the nature and powers of the human soul, and the
relations connecting together matter, man and God. The foundation of the system
was laid in a reconstruction or interpretation of Platonic teaching; but it
claimed and not unsuccessfully, to absorb into itself all previous
philosophies, all at least that acknowledged any active or even potential communion
between God and man. It reconciled them not by arbitrary identification as
offshoots from a common Platonic or Socratic stock, but as varying expressions
of a single truth, which truth was declared to be perfectly enshrined and
secreted in Plato. It is this which gives to Neo-Platonism its markedly
eclectic character.
It assimilated mystic numerical formulae from Neo-Pythagoreanism;
it accepted all that was truest in the syncretic liberalism of revived Platonism: it endorsed the austere morality of the Stoic,
and by its emanation system appropriated his captivating Pantheism; so far as
mere reason was concerned it admitted the contention of the sceptic; it practically borrowed from Aristotle his
scientific methods and forms of thought; while its obligations to Plato require
no mention. It went further afield than Greek philosophy. Its new and hazardous
conception of God as above all quality and specification, and its metaphysical separation
of the Divine Mind from the absolute God is found in germ if anywhere in the Judaeo-Alexandrine doctrines of
Philo: its views of matter, its account of the communication of the Deity to
phenomenal things through intermediate agencies and gradations of being, its
transcendental conception of the Godhead itself exhibit striking analogies to
Gnostic teaching, and at least a superficial resemblance to the most original
results of Oriental speculation.
But Neo-Platonism did not concoct an undigested conglomerate of rival
ideas, and call it a philosophy. It gave organic unity to the elements it
incorporated. If it assimilated the strength, it radically modified the
principle of Stoic Pantheism; it gave up the hard mechanical notion of the
literal transfusion of the Deity through all parts of the universe, for it
justly appeared a profane and illogical materializing of God to suppose him
actually present as fire or air-current or animating soul in all phenomenal
objects. It substituted for this the more elevated notion of a dynamic and not
a mechanical inherence, of an inward sustainment and impulse, an ever-present
effect of divine will constituting for each creature the law of its being and
the condition of existence. It recognized an indestructible duality, where
Stoics discerned an indissoluble unity.
To Chrysippus God was in all things; to
Plotinus all things were in God. Again, Neo-Platonism, we have said, conceded,
nay reaffirmed and emphasized the skeptic invalidation of reason; but it
escaped the Nihilism, which appeared its logical corollary, by revealing and
calling into play a new faculty transcending reason, superseding it both in
scope and efficacy. Even to the dicta of Plato it yielded no servile obedience:
it selected and developed at pleasure. Metaphysical hints from the Sophistes and Protagoras,
enigmatic allusions or metaphors from the Republic, speculative imagery from
the Timaeus equipped it with doctrines which so exceeded as almost to efface
much of Plato's most essential teaching. Convinced of the untrustworthiness of
phenomena and sense-knowledge, Plato had taken refuge in the Ideal theory. He
had claimed objective reality for Thought and Knowledge. They alone were real; their embodied forms peopled a suprasensual world of pure being. But the
Neo-Platonist improved upon this conception. To him the “Ideas”, the
“Intelligible Forms” as he called them, were not the highest and last grade. They retained indeed
their exaltation above the world of sense, but became intermediary agents
whereby the effects of the primal One, the First Principle of all things, were
conveyed to that world. In a word, the Platonic dualism between Thought and
Sense, Pure Being and Phenomena, was superseded and merged in a Unity
transcending both. So far from asserting the truth and absolute existence of
thought, this theory accomplished the reverse; for it represented the ground of
thought as uncognizable.
Some ninety years before the birth of Julian there had come to Rome a
stranger whose worn but philosophic garb, whose bright though sunken eye
denoted at once the genius and the ascetic. The wisdom of Zoroaster, and the
secret lore of India exercised it was said a strange spell over his
imagination, but his training had been in the Greek philosophy; he was an
adoring pupil of the Alexandrian, Ammonius Sakkas, who as an apostate
Christian, under color of the faith he had abjured, gave catechetical
instruction under a veil of Pythagorean secrecy in the new doctrine he
professed. Plotinus, such was the stranger's name, opened a school at Rome, and
became the Chrysippus of the Neo-Platonic
philosophy. Disciplined austerity of person combined with rare acuteness and
intensity of mind, and a philosophic fervor of conviction that bordered upon
inspiration attracted pupils of every grade and temperament: emperors and
titled dames mingled in his saloon with trained philosophers or threadbare
students. For many years his characteristic and esoteric doctrines remained a
secret, uncommitted to writing and but obscurely hinted in oral discourse. At
length the representations or feigned attacks of favourite pupils, Amelius and Porphyry, induced him to systematize
his philosophy. The result was the Enneads.
The central aim of Plotinus was to explain and establish the connection between God, man and the world. To this he pertinaciously adhered. He disregarded Physics; he meddled but little with Logic; even his Ethics were rigidly subordinated to his metaphysical inquiries. Only the roughest outline of his system can be here attempted; that is a necessary preface to any understanding of Julian's philosophical position. Spirit and Matter stand at opposite poles. Man in his twofold nature
implies the existence of both, testifies to the connection of the two, and craves after an explanation of that
connection. Its nature and its mode are the problems set before him. In the Spirit world, such is the answer of Plotinus, there exists a triad—the One, Intelligence, and Soul.
These are not three persons or substances of a co-equal Trinity, but denote
three descending orders of Spiritual
Being.
At the summit of all, absolute, unconditioned, ineffable and
incomprehensible stands the One. Unlike the One or the Good of Plato, the One
of Plotinus is not an Idea, but rather the principle of all Ideas, itself
raised above the sphere of the Ideas, and transcending all determinations of
existence, so that neither rest nor motion, not even Being or not-Being can be
predicated of it. It transcends thought, for thought implies a duality, still
less can it be the Good, for that admits of a multiplicity of determinations.
Its imperfect name, the One, is but an approximate description, correct only so
far as absolute Oneness excludes the attribution of any but negative
predicates.
The One is not all things, but before all things. Unapproachable by thought, it is known
only in its effects. In what way all things, the Many, were evolved from the
One, transcends human treason to conceive. It is the overflowing source of
essential Being, but as such even in emitting energy experiences no change, nor
is its pre-existent Oneness affected or impaired.
From this excess of radiated energy, related to the One, as the image to
the original, the sun to light,
proceeded Nous or Intelligence. Classed next to the One, towards which it
constantly turns, it represents the smallest degree of departure from absolute
Oneness and perfection. Thought and Being, the latter being the posterior of
the two and definable as Thought made stationary, are regarded as its
fundamental determinations. It is pure spirit still, hampered by none of the
limitations or imperfections that attend on matter, independent of space or
time, enjoying a repose which consists in equable and unchanging motion, so
that its whole being is absolute activity. Emanating from the One, this Nous
becomes in its turn the basis of all existence, for it includes as immanent
parts of itself all the Ideas. In fact the whole sum of Ideas, regarded as a
unity, constitutes the N0us, which thus becomes the determining source of all
being and all thought. The spiritual order which it contains and pervades is
called the Intelligible World. From
this every element of phenomenal finiteness is absent, and it combines in
itself the apparent contradictories of absolute plurality, as containing
perfectly all forms of being, and yet of perfect unity, with which it is imbued
by the primal One. Harmony with this Now is the highest goal to which the
spiritual part of man can attain.
The third factor in the Trinity, Soul, stands in the same relation to
Nous, as Nous to the One. It is the image or reflection of Nous, as the moon's
light to the sun's. It too belongs still to the order of Spirit, but is as it
were on the outer fringe of the circle illumined by the central One. Nous may
be represented by an inner immovable sphere described about the great centre of all Being, Soul as an outer movable sphere
turning about the interior Nous. Spirit has now by a series of acts of
self-estrangement from its creative centre reached
the lowest gradation of which it is capable. Light has reached the confines of
darkness, and potential connection with matter has been secured: by another
metaphor Soul is spoken of as extended Nous, which, just as the point extended
becomes a line, is now brought within touch of matter. Thus Soul is made the
link between the Many and the One, Best and Motion, Eternity and Time. Into the
subtler minutiae of the double World-Soul, Earth-Soul, and Separate Souls, it
is needless to enter. The final contact with Matter is established by emanative
action analogous to that by which the One passed into Nous and Nous into Soul.
On the nature of this so-called emanation it behoves to speak shortly.
Emanation is only a clumsy mode, imposed by the limitations of human
thought and expression, of representing a transcendental act or series of acts.
It should be called rather eternal procession, for it must not be regarded as
occurring in time at all. The divisions of the triad as just described are all
alike co-eternal; so too is matter, and the interdependence and relations of
all these to each other. Further in Neo-Platonic emanation there is no
communication of being, passing into or calling into existence lower
intermediary orders: herein it is quite distinct from the emanation of Oriental
philosophies. The First Cause is in essence incommunicable: there is a
communication of force or effect only, not of being. The One, Nous and Soul are
in themselves absolutely unaffected by any emanation to which they give rise:
it does not take place at their expense: they are occupied solely with that
from which they emanated. Emanation is not even produced by any act of volition, still less of self-impartition: it takes place by an internal land
natural necessity, which is a part of the nature of Spirit, no more consciously
exercised than gravity by a particle. Lastly, each act of emanation represents
a degradation: Nous is lower than the One, and the Soul than Nous, though in
its proper sphere each is perfect. By such progressive stages of imperfection
is it alone possible to bridge the illimitable gulf between Spirit and Matter.
With regard to Matter, some substratum appeared to Plotinus a necessary
assumption involved by the existence of the phenomenal world. This substratum
he regards as the absolute privation of all being or quality. As such it is
wholly unthinkable, and can be described by negatives only, as formless,
indeterminate, unqualified and the like. One positive attribute it does appear
at first sight to possess. It is the cause and origin of all Evil, which cannot
by possibility be derived from the spiritual nature of the emanative Soul. This
is explained however by representing Evil as a negative quantity, a certain
absence or deprivation of Good which belongs properly to Matter. Into Matter so
conceived Soul entering by voluntary emanation produces the phenomenal world,
almost every degree of intermixture or rather proportionate prevalence of the
elements being provided for by gradations descending from angels, daemons and
heroes through men to animals and inanimate matter.
Of Neo-Platonic anthropology or ethics no analysis need be given, but
its most original and characteristic tenet demands an allusion. Intelligence
the highest rational faculty of man might, as in the Platonic scheme, be
trained more and more to harmony with the supreme Nous. Yet by no conceivable
perfection of mere reason could the finite attain to communion with the
incomprehensible infinite. The nature of the two things forbade it. Reduced by
rigorous metaphysical reasoning to this result, and yet intuitively assured
that knowledge of the infinite was within the range of man, Plotinus fell back
on the doctrine of Ecstasy. Above reason and above intelligence man, so he
taught, possesses an energy kindred to the One whereby he may attain to direct
communion with it.
Leaving thought and spirit behind, divesting itself of personality and
individual consciousness, the soul by an ecstatic elevation of being might
enter into actual unification or contact with God, and become absorbed in the
Infinite Intelligence from which it emanated. For that rapturous space
reminiscence might be changed into intuition. Weaned altogether from the flesh,
disenthralled of desire and lust, trained to the sincere unalloyed
contemplation of the divine Ideas, four times in a lifetime was Plotinus caught
up to the seventh heaven and admitted to this transcending and ineffable
communion: and once, when he was an old man of near seventy, the same exalted
privilege was vouchsafed to Porphyry. For this supreme end, this final term of
knowledge, the Neo-Platonist was invited to mortify the flesh, to pursue after
virtue and to purify the soul. Such was
his incentive and his reward.
As regards all forms of religion Plotinus himself had the Popular
intellectual strength to take a singularly independent attitude. The spirit of
his system was doubtless antagonistic to Christianity: that reposed on
objective historical facts by which it declared God was brought down to man;
while Neo-Platonism from a purely subjective basis claimed to enable men to
rise to God. The analogies that appear between the two are more verbal than
real. On the other hand, Neo-Platonism lent itself readily to current Pagan
beliefs: its final monotheism left abundant room for any amount of subordinate
polytheism. This Plotinus admitted without turning aside to corroborate or
refute details. To him Paganism was an amplified and not always trustworthy commentary,
which fell short of deserving a place in his text.
Such is a rough outline of Plotinus' solution of the great
world-problem. It attained its purest and most masculine successors development
in his hands. His successor Porphyrius did indeed add details and advance
individual arguments a step or two further, but was little more than a skilful and trusty expositor: such real modification as he
did introduce was in the direction of coordination of Pagan beliefs with
Neo-Platonic philosophy, and the abandonment of the free position taken by
Plotinus towards all extant forms of religion.
But under Iamblichus the school entered upon what is justly regarded as
a new stage. Though overflowing with intellectual pretentiousness he added
nothing of metaphysical or ethical value. To him the religious attitude of the
philosophy became all in all. He caught at numerical formula of the
Pythagoreans, and though in that department he discovered nothing new and
misunderstood much that was old, proclaimed that there lay deep secrets of
religion and philosophy. He multiplied Gods ad nauseam: he accumulated insipid
divisions and subdivisions of spiritual genera. In fact, he and the Syrian
School used to fatal effect the mysticism which Plotinus' own intellect had not
always kept in bounds.
They employed Neo-Platonism as an engine against Christianity, as the
new and last stronghold of Polytheism. They converted a school of inquirers
into a church of believers. In order to this they recklessly degraded their
philosophy. In attempting to popularize they also irremediably vulgarized: they
depreciated the intellectual side, to expand the mystical or theurgic. They exalted Pythagoras and deposed Aristotle.
Iamblichus, foiled in a dialectical discussion, coolly replied that the
intuitions of virtue were above logic. Julian fell into the hands of this
school when he was referred by his first teachers to one who “for the grandeur
and power of his natural intellect could discard philosophical demonstration”.
In spite of the protests of the aged Porphyry, magic or theurgy was made the
highest branch of philosophy. “The philosopher” while admitting a true art of
augury and divination, in a series of skeptical questions and doubts partly
practical and partly metaphysical, criticized many current manifestations of
the art as interposing material obstacles between man and God, with whom the
heart was the one true organ of communion and revealer of oracles, and did not
conceal his perplexity concerning the modes, and causes, and tests of
divination depending on the strange material mediums or adjuncts which were
coming into vogue.
Thus in his Epistle to Anebon,
the cygneus cantus of the dying sage, he enters his
final protest against the new-fangled hocus-pocus of priestcraft.
But in vain: cabbalistic fatuity, fantastic ceremonies, bloody initiative
rites, miracles, evocation of spirits, theophanies,
sorceries, with their accompanying abominations came crowding in. Superstition
and philosophy signed an adulterous compact, and were made one flesh. The
intellectual ingenuity with which
Iamblichus made necromancy and thaumaturgy the
handmaids of philosophy only wakens a regret that his talents were not better
employed than in stultifying the learned and imposing on the incredulous.
With the third stage of Neo-Platonism, the acute but sterile scholastic period of Proclus, an essay on Julian
has no concern.
|