CHAPTER XXVII.
DESCARTES
AND CARTESIANISM.
The period of Continental history which extends from the beginning of the Thirty
Years’ War to the Peace of the Pyrenees is, from the point of view of
intellectual progress, chiefly noteworthy for the works of Descartes and for
the growing influence of the Cartesian Philosophy. Descartes was a Frenchman.
Now, he travelled over the whole of Europe; he lived for twenty years in
Holland; he was connected with numerous learned men of different countries ;
and among his pupils were a Princess Palatine and a Queen of Sweden. To some extent,
therefore, he represents the whole of Europe, which, moreover, even in his
lifetime displayed a fervent partisanship for or against his philosophy.
At the
beginning of the seventeenth century France, where Descartes passed his days of
studentship, presented, in the world of thought, a spectacle of disorder and
confusion. The instruction given in the colleges was still wholly scholastic;
but in the field of philosophy the yoke of authority had been cast off since
the time of Ramus and the Renaissance. The philosophy of Aristotle was being
rejected, and no substitute could be offered in its place except some other
system likewise borrowed from the ancients, such as Neo-Platonism, Platonism,
Epicureanism, or Stoicism. On the other hand, learning enlisted fewer
enthusiasts than in the sixteenth century, and philology was in its decadence.
The work of the Renaissance, so far as philosophy was concerned, seemed to be
chiefly negative, and drew a number of thinkers towards scepticism.
And, from
the religious standpoint, there was not less cause for anxiety in the
prevailing condition of mind. Side by side with the development of medieval
doctrine, from the fifteenth century onwards, a struggle had manifested itself
between faith and reason, which was wholly adverse to the scholastic point of
view. On the other hand, the Reformation had with incomparable force reawakened
the craving for a personal and living way of belief and thought, as opposed to
mere repetition of formulae and of comment upon them. And this movement had not
been confined to the Protestants. Towards the middle of the sixteenth century
the Catholic Church had also experienced its Renaissance of faith and religious
life. The celebrated Society of Jesus, which was afterwards so dangerously to
confound the policy of man with the service of God, had, in the words of its
founder, Ignatius de Loyola, been actually instituted with the object of
awakening in men’s souls, by means of appropriate exercises, the Christian
faith and Christian love. Now, even if an abstract philosophical treatise can
sustain side by side doctrines mutually opposed, without any interference of
the one with the other, the living human conscience cannot for long endure such
an antagonism. Thus all thoughtful men were perturbed by the struggle between
faith and reason which had caused the moral revolution of the sixteenth
century; whilst, on the other hand, the frivolous were provided with arguments
in favour of incredulity.
Moreover,
side by side with philosophy and theology a new power was developing which
would infallibly claim a share in the guidance of man’s mind. This was the
science of nature. Hitherto the earth had been regarded as the centre of the world; but Copernicus had recently assigned
this place of honour to the sun. About 1604 Galileo,
by the discovery of the laws of gravitation and of the pendulum, had proved it
possible to explain the phenomena of nature by comparing them with one another,
while stating natural laws, and avoiding any recourse to mysterious forces and
influences. What would be the effect of this scientific revolution when men
came to examine its bearings on philosophy?
In this
intellectual atmosphere, in which antagonistic elements were at variance with
one another, a class of men frivolous, sceptical,
impatient of all restraint, who claimed the right to think and live according
to their individual inspiration, was continually on the increase. These were
the free-thinkers. They took their inspiration from Montaigne, appropriating
in particular his critical and negative conclusions. They were represented by
some very prominent men: Cesare Vanini, a young
Neapolitan priest, who acknowledged no other God but Nature, Theophile de Viau, a worldly poet, “ head of the secret atheists,” and,
close to the throne, Gaston of Orleans, brother of Louis XIII, who wrote
lampoons on God and his sovereign in verse. Such in general was the chaotic
state of men’s minds.
However, a
very different age was at the same time announcing itself. While Richelieu was
re-establishing in society the principle of order and authority it was natural
that a similar change should take place in the world of thought. Now, ever
since the end of the sixteenth century, Malherbe had been subjecting the
poetry, versification, and overloaded style of the Renaissance to the laws of
clearness, purity, method, and good taste; and from 1620 onwards the Hotel de Rambouillet, where particular attention was paid to purity
of style, fostered the idea of the French Academy, which was actually
established in 1635. Soon, in 1636, there burst forth with the suddenness of a
thunderbolt a masterpiece in which were blended to perfection youthful
enthusiasm and scrupulous obedience to rule—the Cid of Pierre Corneille.
A desire
for order and stability was therefore beginning to make itself felt, and it is
to be noticed that men sought for the principles of such order, not in the
authority of any established law, but in the supreme right of common-sense,
truth, and reason. In 1540 Calvin, had published his Institution Chretienne in French, with a view to attracting the simple as well as the learned to the
individual religious life. In the hands of Montaigne (from 1580) the French
language had become more pliant, more capable of expressing in a simple and
picturesque way the subtle thoughts of philosophy. And thus men of the world
were enabled to examine questions formerly reserved for scholars.
All these
tendencies, both positive and negative, are united in Descartes, whose work,
suggestive and far-reaching, though severely methodical, was at the same time
the complete realisation of the thought of his epoch,
and the starting-point of future developments.
René Descartes
(1596-1650) was born at La Haye in Touraine on March 31, 1596. His family
belonged to the petite noblesse, and came originally from Poitou. From
1604 to 1612 he was a pupil at the Jesuit College of La Fleche. Then he spent
two years (1615-6) at the University of Poitiers, where he took his Bachelor’s,
and afterwards his Licentiate’s, degree in civil and canon law. In 1617 he
entered the service of Prince Mamice of Nassau in Holland as a volunteer.
About the same time he was studying the principles of music, algebra, and
science. He was justifying the nickname given him by his father, who, from his
childhood, had called him the “ little philosopher.” Then, in 1619, when war
threatened in Germany, he went to that country, was present at the coronation
of the Emperor Ferdinand II at Frankfort, and enlisted in the Duke of Bavaria’s
forces. He spent the winter in the duchy of Neuburg,
where he remained all day shut up in his little room, untroubled by cares and
passions, free to devote himself to meditation. It was then that he fell into a
sort of trance of enthusiasm, in the midst of which, so he tells us, he
discovered the principles of a wonderful science. And, in order to secure the
help of the Blessed Virgin in this undertaking, he vowed to make a pilgrimage
to Our Lady of Loretto.
In 1620 he
was with the army in Bohemia, and in 1621 in Hungary. Then he abandoned the
profession of arms, which he had regarded mainly as a means towards the study
of his fellow-men, and came back to France by way of northern Germany and
Holland. From 1622 to 1625 he travelled again, in France, in Switzerland, and
in Italy. From 1625 to 1629 he stayed for the last time in Paris; then, having
been entreated by his friends to publish some portion of his works, he withdrew
to Holland, hoping, in the healthy climate of that well-governed State, to meet
with conditions of life more favourable to meditation
than he had found in France. He remained in Holland until September 5, 1649;
but while here, in order to escape from interference, he frequently changed his
place of abode; and during this period he made several journeys, one of which
is said to have been to England (1631). In Holland he composed his great works
: Meditationes de prima philosophia, which
was not published till 1641, twelve years after it had been written; Le
Monde, ou Traité de la Lumière, which he decided not to publish on account of the condemnation pronounced on
Galileo (1633), whose opinion as to the motion of the earth coincided with
Descartes’ own; Le Discours de la Méthode, with La Dioptrique,
les Mét´rores et la Géométrie (attempts to exemplify his method) in 1637; Principia Philosophiae in 1644; and Le Traité des passions de
l'ame in 1649.
At the
same time he was in correspondence with several learned men; with his friend
Father Mersenne, who formed a centre of scientific
correspondence; with Fermat and Roberval; and, as his philosophy had spread
rapidly throughout the Dutch Universities and had excited much opposition among
the Aristotelians, he defended himself and his doctrines against his
antagonists and enemies. Among his pupils were Princess Elizabeth, daughter of
the Elector Palatine Frederick V and of the English Princess Elizabeth, and,
afterwards, Queen Christina of Sweden. The latter entreated him to come to her
Court, and sent a ship to Amsterdam in order to convey him. After some
hesitation Descartes yielded, largely in the hope that he might serve the cause
of the Princess Elizabeth in Stockholm. But the winter climate of Sweden proved
too severe for him, and he died at Stockholm, February 11, 1650. He was only in
his fifty-fifth year.
In
addition to his published works he left several manuscripts, which were
gradually brought to light. These included, in the first place, a voluminous
correspondence; then, a Traité de l’homme et de la formation du foetus (1664), Le Monde, ou Traité de la Lumière (1664); with the Regulae ad directionem ingenii (1701), a work probably composed between 1619
and 1629.
The most
salient characteristic of the author of the Discours de la Méthode is his restless and independent
disposition. This philosopher is an aristocrat of an adventurous disposition, a
worthy contemporary of the heroes of the Thirty Years’ War. One day Gassendi apostrophised him with
the taunt, “ O mens! ” But as a matter of fact
few men have seen so many countries, or have so ardently longed to come in contact
with reality. At the same time, he is impatient of any kind of restraint,
whether material or intellectual. Throughout all his struggles and adventures
he endeavours to retain his serenity of thought; he
would like his motto to be, bene qui latuit, bene vixit. Descartes is the very reverse of a philosopher
of the Schools. Nothing seems alien to him; philosophy is a part of his daily
life, no less on the battlefield than when he is solving a problem of geometry.
And his philosophy has practical purposes which are constantly before his eyes.
He considers that those who do not work for the good of their fellow-men are
essentially worthless.
Hence it
follows naturally that he is dissatisfied with ready-made doctrines, which can
be proved or rejected by means of an abstract system of dialectics. He is in
quest of living certainties, of doctrines which will satisfy his spiritual
needs; the only truth which he is prepared to acknowledge, is that which he
has, to some extent, reconstituted by the activity of his own reason. And his
diction, so wonderfully clear, correct, and logical, merely translates into
words the inner working of his mind. In Descartes life, philosophy, science,
and the art of writing, which hitherto had usually been isolated, are reunited
and form an indissoluble whole. Hence the original force and the significance
of his personality. To define his point of view with regard to life and its
phenomena, means to trace the history of his mind.
Among the
scientific subjects studied by him at the College of La Fleche, there was one
to which he felt especially attracted, and which made him unduly critical of
the rest, viz. mathematics. This science brought logical reasons to support
what it affirmed, and therefore afforded him intellectual certainty. Compared
with mathematics, all other sciences, such as language, history, jurisprudence,
medicine, philosophy, ethics, were mere exercises of memory or of abstract
dialectics, and incapable of supplying irrefutable conclusions. To Descartes it
seemed that information which brought with it no certainty had no claim to the
title of science.
He
therefore first came forward with mathematical researches. Herein he succeeded
so well that he formed the highest idea of the power and capability of this
science, and, realising that hitherto it had merely
been made serviceable to the mechanical arts, he asked himself why, seeing
that its foundations were so firm and solid, no more important structure had
been raised upon them. Thus, he conceived the idea of treating according to the
mathematical method not merely numbers and figures, but concrete realities—in
other words, of applying the mathematical method to philosophy. But this
application could not be legitimately made unless the method were rendered more
general by divesting it of the peculiarities which belong to the special
purpose of mathematics. In order to enable himself to effect this, Descartes determined
to develop in himself the sense of truth, the critical faculty, and the power
of solid argument. With this end in view he devoted long years to the solution
of mathematical problems and to reflexion on the
operations of the mind involved in this work.
Thus was
very gradually brought out the point of view which is characteristic of his
line of speculation, and which places him so high in the study of human
thought. In every branch of knowledge, in all the sciences, however exact they
might be, he marked out in an ultimate analysis the human understanding, as
their common support, their source, and their final criterion. And he placed
the mainspring of all knowledge, not in a given dogma, fact, or proposition,
but in the mind of man, trained by a suitable education to discern the truth. “Bona mens, sive universalissima sapientia” we
read at the beginning of the Regulae. And
at the end of the Discours de la Méthode Descartes explains that he has written in
French rather than in Latin, trusting that those who depend on their
unsophisticated natural reasoning faculty will be better qualified to criticise his opinions than those who only place their
faith in ancient books.
The
evidence acknowledged by honest reason is in all cases the supreme criterion of
truth. This reason, moreover, can never become for man a complete and finite
thing, replaceable by a formula. We must unceasingly exercise, strengthen, and
extend it by supplying it with truths; for activity is its being. This is the
principle which regulated the intellectual occupations and the doctrines of
Descartes.
As a born
mathematician he could not fail to apply himself with zeal to a science then so
flourishing. As is known, analytical geometry, that is, algebra applied to
geometry, dates from the Essai de géométrie, published by him in 1637, immediately after
his Discours de la Méthode. It must, however, be admitted that this discovery would in any case have,
sooner or later, followed on those in analysis due to Viète. What is wholly
original in the mathematical work of Descartes is his complete recasting of the
theory of equations, and the general solution given by him to the problem of
tangents for algebraical curves.
Descartes
was not only a mathematician, but also a physicist. The discoveries of Galileo
determined him to seek to improve the telescope. With this end in view, he
investigated the mathematical law of refraction, and in order to decide on the
shapes of the lenses he studied the problem of tangents. Soon afterwards he
applied himself to the general subject of light, and applied his principles to
the explanation of the phenomenon of the rainbow. And he thus arrived at the
conception of a complete revolution in the whole science of physics, in the
widest sense of the word. This consisted in substituting everywhere purely
mathematical explanations for the scholastic formulae assuming occult influences.
But this
step could not be taken simply by the application of principles proper to
mathematical science. How could it be asserted that the nature of bodies could
be fully expressed in mathematical terms? In order to solve this problem
Descartes plunged into metaphysical speculation. He sought, by the light of
reasonable evidence, some truth which would enable him to prove the principles,
not only of mathematics, or the science of what may be, but of philosophy, or
the science of what is. He finds this principle in the proposition, Cogito,
ergo sum, inasmuch as it implies such an association of an essence with an
existence as appears to the reason indissoluble in fact, if not by right.
Starting with this positive but contingent existence he, by examining that idea
of the Perfect Being which he finds in the mind of man, arrives at the
existence of God; and he shows that the fact of this existence is laid down by
reason, no longer as hypothetical but as a logical necessity. And from the
existence of God he proceeds by argument to that of material things; but at the
same time he shows that the only sense in which this can be held to be proved
is that which regards all material bodies as in themselves mere modifications
of geometrical extension. Physics, therefore, can and must be treated
altogether from a geometrical standpoint; and this was precisely quod erat demonstrandum.
In
accordance with a practical rule which he had made for himself, and which
consisted in devoting the greater part of his time to the recreation of the
senses, and a very small portion of it to the exercise of the pure
understanding, within a few months Descartes succeeded in establishing the
principles of his metaphysics. In order to make sure of the strength of the
work, he thought it necessary and sufficient that this work should have been
the genuine product of free reason, disentangled from sense and imagination.
In fact, though the Meditations is but small in bulk, its doctrinal
matter is large, and the book is great by its originality and by its
importance. First, it demonstrates the method known as that of methodic doubt,
which consists in the provisional rejection of all that knowledge which, when
examined from the standpoint of pure reason, appears uncertain. In the second
place, by means of the proposition of Cogito, ergo sum, it defines that
knowledge which by its own action the mind has established as primary and fundamental
knowledge, inasmuch as no knowledge has any value for us unless it rationally
connects itself with the knowledge which we have of our own existence. But if
we admit that rational evidence is the sole criterion of certainty, the
important consequence necessarily follows that those kinds of knowledge which,
depend upon the evidence of such witnesses as history or positive theology can
never become sciences in the exact meaning of the word.
The soul is defined by thought, the body by extension; since these two
attributes are the only ones of which we can form a clear idea. Hence all the
other properties of being, such as sentiment and will, which are produced in
the mind, or concrete qualities and passions which manifest themselves in the
body, have to be regarded merely as moods, either of thought or extension. And
the actual fact of the union of soul and body is, so far as science is
concerned, solely a confused medley of essences which cannot be simplified, but
must be dissociated from each other.
The
existence of God can no longer be demonstrated by considering the nature of the
world. On the contrary, it must be recognised before
we have the right to speak of the existence of material things. Descartes
attempts to find the starting-point for the demonstration of the existence of
God in our own existence and in the content of our reason. The latter, according
to him, contains innate germs, which by force of meditation grow and are
evolved into clear and distinct ideas. One of these ideas is that of God, or of
the Perfect Being. A careful consideration of this idea enables the
understanding to perceive clearly that, differing from all others, it involves
the existence of its object. From our reason is likewise derived the idea of
extension, by the help of which we can conceive of the existence of something
external to ourselves. Now, the senses for their part represent to us objects
which, among other qualities, possess that of extension. The knowledge of a
perfect God, the author of reason and senses alike, transforms into a rational
belief our natural tendency to believe that our sensations proceed from corporeal
things which actually exist; consequently, it permits us to reduce all the
qualities of bodies to extension, which alone can clearly be conceived, and
which is therefore alone, in the eyes of reason, capable of existence.
From these
metaphysical principles proceed the celebrated physical theories of Descartes.
No explanation by final causes is received in the science of nature; for mathematics
admit only the mechanical relations between component and composed. The world
has been evolved mechanically from chaos, matter having, in the course of
time, automatically taken all possible forms, only those being retained which,
according to the general laws of motion, offered adequate conditions of
equilibrium and stability. In order to account in this way for the formation of
the world, Descartes lays down as a principle the permanency of the same
quantity of motion in the universe; and he holds that all motion is transmitted
by impact. Moreover he invents the celebrated hypothesis of vortices, according to which each body is surrounded by numerous particles of matter,
arranged in spherical layers, which revolve continually about it as round a common centre. This mechanical theory of the formation of
the solar system formed the prelude to that which Kant and Laplace were
afterwards to enunciate with so much success. All the properties of bodies, in
so far as they belong to the things themselves, and are not merely the illusory
projections of our inner feelings, are nothing but extension and motion in
space. Thought, or reason, alone, which are the necessary conditions of the
knowledge of extension of bodies, are of a different character. Beings devoid
of reason, however much their actions may seem to be to the purpose, are to
scientific insight mere machines. An animal is but a very complicated clock.
In man,
however, we see that thought and extension are substantially united. This union
manifests itself by means of the influence upon each other of soul and body. In
certain conditions the soul can affect the direction, though not the quantity,
of motion. The influence of the body on the soul is illustrated by the
passions, which can only be studied from a scientific point of view when
referred to their bodily cause.
From these
metaphysical and physical principles Descartes by no means concludes that any
object whatever can become known a priori without the aid of experience.
In explaining the creation of the world out of initial chaos he had merely
presented his conclusions in the light of a hypothesis, the total value of
which consisted in its conformity with observable phenomena. In proportion as
he treats of more complicated phenomena he assigns a greater and more necessary
part to experiment and to Baconian induction. And the celebrated Discours de la Méthode ends
with an appeal to the generosity of the friends of science, soliciting their
aid for the author in the costly experiments which he is obliged to undertake
in order to work, as his ambition impels him to work, for the progress of
physiology and of medicine.
The
mathematics, physics, and biology of Descartes have one important feature in
common. They are as profound as it seemed possible to the philosopher to make
them, but they are restricted to the study of a few fundamental problems, and
have no pretensions to be complete. The mind of Descartes was, in fact, firmly
fixed upon what was to him the very principle and object of philosophy, namely
reason as the standard of truth, and at the same time a power which it is our
duty to develop by culture. And the sciences are the instruments of this
culture. According to Descartes, it is through them only that either man will
acquire a control over nature, on which the liberty of reason is conditional,
or the formation of reason itself will be achieved; but he only asks of the
sciences that which is necessary and sufficient for reaching this twofold end.
Thus in
the end his philosophy leads to the practical applications which, by
means of the theoretical sciences, teach men to realise the work of reason. These applications are, in the first place, mechanics, or
the appropriation by man of the forces of nature; next, medicine, or the care
for the health of the body, on which that of the soul is so largely dependent;
and finally ethics, or the determination by reason of the objects; to be
selected by the will of man, and the choice of means suitable for calming or
subduing the passions, and for creating a virtuous disposition in the soul.
According to Descartes, the will has for its ends the love of God and the interest
of the whole of which the individual is a part. And the surest way to reach
these ends is to attain to a clear and exact knowledge of things, because a
luminous understanding generates a strong desire in the will.
Such is
the philosophy of Descartes, which may be said to have re-established order and
certainty in the human mind. As viewed by Descartes, science, experience of
life, the principles of religious faith, and the good-sense of a well-bred man,
do not merely exist side by side, they cooperate in forming a harmonious whole.
Taken by themselves,. apart from the mind which sustains them, and considered
from an abstract point of view, science, religion, and life may seem in opposition,
or even in contradiction to each other. With Descartes, however, they find a
common basis in philosophy, which in itself is but the free activity of reason,
just as the most widely divergent branches of the same tree are nourished by
the same roots. Reason is no longer the empty form to which the dialecticians
of the school had confined it, but contains positive and innate principles; if
these be developed by culture and meditation, reason draws from them the
elementary ideas of science, together with the essential truths of religion.
And these principles, which are at the same time universal, inspiring, and
productive, are nothing but good-sense, freed from prejudices and deepened in
the process. By means of this doctrine philosophy grew to be of great
importance; it was the necessary mediating power between religion, science, and
life, and was to accomplish this important function, not by surpassing the
other sciences in obscurity and pedantry, but, on the contrary, by assuming the
standpoint of the well-bred man towards scholastic subtleties, and by speaking
simply and clearly in the common tongue. In short, as understood to consist in
the culture of reason, in Descartes’ conception of this word, philosophy had
become the basis of every branch of knowledge, and had been secularised once for all.
As is the
case with all works that are essentially original, the meaning and importance
of Descartes’ philosophy were but inadequately appreciated by his
contemporaries. However, such vigorous and productive thought could not fail to
excite immediate attention on every side. Unlike the learned criticism of the
Renaissance scholars, it did not content itself with destroying or with
exhuming the past, but built afresh on new foundations. Pierre Borel, a contemporary of Descartes, tells us that, at the
actual time of the master’s death, his disciples were as numerous as the stars
in the firmament or the grains of sand by the sea.
Some of
the most celebrated of these were his personal pupils. Among the most
distinguished we must place the Princess Palatine Elizabeth. In 1640 she was
living at the Hague with her mother, who had taken refuge there. She was a
beautiful and haughty Princess, a worthy daughter of the House of Stewart,
eager to prove herself heroic and magnanimous. When twenty years of age, she
had refused the Crown of Poland, so as not to abjure the Protestant faith, in
which she had been brought up. Meditation was for her the highest happiness.
She wished to see the man of whom all Holland was then talking—such had been
the interest excited by his Essais on their
appearance in 1637—and whose works she had read with admiration. At that time Descartes
was living in the small castle of Endegeest, near
Leyden, and only two leagues distant from the Hague. He caused himself to be
presented to the Queen of Bohemia, whose salon he found to be wholly
Cartesian. Elizabeth received him not only as a master, but as a friend. She
had attached herself to the new doctrine, and henceforward adopted its method
of seeking to know things clearly and distinctly. Descartes was surprised to
find that the mind of this young Princess was capable of the most arduous research,
and of grasping the most sublime truths. In 1644, having already opened a
correspondence with her which was to last six years (1643-9), he dedicated to
her his Principes.
For her
part, Elizabeth could not remain satisfied with the abstract theory of the
system of the world which formed the conclusion of Descartes’ work. She was in
great trouble, and her sufferings threatened to undermine her health. She was
tried hard by the calamities of her kith and kin; for the cause of the Stewarts
seemed to be lost, and in 1649 the head of Charles I was to fall on the
scaffold. The sufferings of the Princess Palatine were the more acute in that
she was gifted with an especially keen intelligence, and with an exceptionally
refined sense of morality. She tells Descartes that she realised the inconvenience of being somewhat reasonable. She asked of philosophy a
remedy for her misfortunes. She helped to draw the attention of Descartes towards
practical questions, to make him consider the passions, and to study medicine
and ethics, by which they may be combated. She conscientiously made trial of
the remedies which Descartes proposed to her. But the teaching of the
philosopher was essentially optimistic, and the very real sorrows of the
Princess, her passionate nature, and her melancholy temperament, prevented her
from finding in this teaching the relief which she sought. At least, however,
the Cartesian philosophy in itself continued to arouse her enthusiasm; and
when, in 1648, she was obliged to leave the Hague, owing to a murder committed
by her brother, she devoted herself to propagating the principles of the
Cartesian philosophy in Berlin and Heidelberg. She died in 1680, having been, since
1667, Abbess of the Lutheran abbey of Herford, in Westphalia. This rich foundation
had been converted by the pupil of Descartes into a free academy, a retreat
open to men irrespective of nationality, religion, and opinions, provided only
that they were students of philosophy.
Another
pupil of Descartes was Queen Christina of Sweden, the daughter of Gustavus
Adolphus; and the relation between them furnishes a striking illustration of
the place which science and scientific men then held in the world. Queen
Christina was undoubtedly capable and intelligent, but also whimsical, excessively
passionate, and addicted to dissipation and licence.
In 1657 she caused her lover, Monaldeschi, to be
assassinated. She was a keen student of languages and science, and drew to her
Court the learned men of every country. In the interval between presiding at a
Council of her Ministers and riding for ten consecutive hours in a reckless
hunt, she despatched to Descartes, through Chanut,
the French ambassador at Stockholm, such queries as the following:What is love?” Does the light of nature alone teach us to love
God?” Which is the worse disorder, that of love, or that of
hatred?” And Descartes replied by a formal dissertation on each of these three
heads. Then she sends word to him that she doubts whether the hypothesis of an
infinite universe can be admitted without damage to the Christian faith. Or
again, having heard, at Upsala, an oration on the Supreme Good, pronounced by
Professor Freinsheim, she sends to ask Descartes’
opinion on the subject. More and more transported by his replies, she wishes
to study his Principes, desires to see
the author, and to receive from him lessons in philosophy. Descartes made up
his mind to proceed to Stockholm, where he saw the Queen four or five times in
her library, at a very early hour in the morning. But the Court had at that
time little thought for anything but its rejoicings on the conclusion of the
Peace of Munster; and, as the Queen could not induce Descartes to dance in the
ballets, she prevailed upon him to at least write some French verses in honour of the ball. Descartes’ ballet was called La
Naissance de la Paix. He also wrote a comedy. His
sudden death aroused a short-lived sorrow in the Queen. She afterwards pretended
that he had played an important part in her glorious conversion—that transition
to Catholicism by which she astonished the Pope himself, who was disillusioned
at finding in his neophyte a strange freedom of conduct, and no sign whatever
of a vocation for holiness.
Not only
Elizabeth and Christina, but also all those who came into contact with
Descartes, or who read his works, were filled with admiration for his genius,
and became eager students of his philosophy. Throughout all Europe the advent
of his system caused a revolution in the world of thought, exceptional in its
force, its extent, and its duration. It would be no easy task to give an
account of this revolution of thought, and to follow it in all its
manifestations and results. Here it is only possible to add a few instances and
indications.
Holland
was the first battlefield of the Cartesian philosophy. In this land of wealth
and freedom intense intellectual activity prevailed. Descartes was surrounded
by friends who interested themselves in his doctrines. Among them were
Constantine Huyghens, lord of Zuitlichem,
father of the great Huyghens, and himself a person of
no small importance —a Councillor of the
Prince of Orange, a statesman, a soldier, and withal a scholar and a man of
letters. On the death of Descartes Huyghens apostrophised Nature and bade her lead the way in mourning
for the great Descartes, the loss of whose life was the loss of her light; for
it was by means only of that shed on her by him that men had been able to
behold her. Another was van Hoogland, the physician, who, following the
footsteps of Descartes, sought to solve the problems of medicine through
chemistry and mechanics.
The
influence of Descartes was soon to exceed the narrow limits of coteries and to
make itself felt outside, in the tumultuous sphere of the Universities. The
first professors to be converted to the Cartesian philosophy in Holland were
Henry Reneri and Henry de Roy, otherwise Regius, of
the University of Utrecht. The latter became famous on account of his private
lectures in medicine and philosophy, based on Cartesian principles. He aroused
such enthusiasm that in 1638 his pupils united in compelling the University to
establish in his favour a second chair of medicine.
This was but one year after the publication of the Discours de la Méthode. On the death of Reneri, Regius became chief representative of the new
philosophy, and vehemently defended it against scholasticism. Thus, in 1641 he
caused de Raey, one of his pupils, to sustain a
public thesis in which the philosophy and the science of Aristotle were turned
to ridicule. Hereupon war broke out in the University. Each time that a thesis
was sustained it was met by blast and counterblast of applause and hisses.
Foremost among the professors of the Peripatetic School was the Calvinist
minister, Gisbert de Voet,
Rector of the University, and a bigoted opponent of all new movements. This
guardian of orthodoxy had already discountenanced the teaching of the theory of
the circulation of the blood. He determined to ruin Descartes. On the one
hand, by means of insinuation, he accused him of atheism; on the other he
denounced him as a pupil and spy of the Jesuits. And he declared that his whole
method of philosophy was heretical and opposed to the scholastic system of instruction.
At his instigation the magistrates ordered Regius to confine himself to his
lectures on medicine, and the majority of the professors, in the General
Assembly of the University, condemned the new philosophy, on the grounds that
it was opposed to the ancient and the true philosophy, that it deterred young
men from the study of scholastic terms, and that it was conducive to scepticism and irreligion.
Next, Voetius caused one of his pupils, Martin Schoockius, a professor at Groningen, to write a libellous pamphlet against Descartes, entitled, Philosophia cartesiana, sive admiranda methodus Cartesii. Descartes addressed his reply to Voetius himself, who thereupon caused this reply to be
condemned by the magistrates as libellous. And,
according to Baillet, the biographer of Descartes, Voetius lost no time in making a bargain with the
executioner to the effect that no fuel should be spared in burning the books of
the philosopher, so that the flames might be seen from afar. But Descartes, who
at that time was not living in the Province of Utrecht, but at Egmont in North
Holland, succeeded in putting an end to all these proceedings, thanks to the
protection of the French ambassador and of the Prince of Orange. Then the
accused turned accuser and obtained a decree from the Senate of the University
of Groningen, which in effect condemned his two enemies, Voetius and Schoockius, as libellers.
The
University of Leyden, in its turn, was divided on the subject of the teaching
of the Cartesian philosophy. The great opponent of Descartes in this city was
Jacques de Reves, or Revius,
who wrote a pamphlet against methodic doubt, entitled Furiosum nugamentum,. In 1676, after the teaching of the
Cartesian philosophy had been formally forbidden, Heidanus,
a Cartesian, made a public protest against this prohibition, and was dismissed
from office; while Voider, another Cartesian, who was more skilful,
continued his teaching under disguises which he was gradually able to discard.
Besides
the University of Groningen, that of Breda welcomed the Cartesian philosophy.
In the Catholic University of Louvain in Belgium it met with violent
opposition. In 1652 the physician Plempius persuaded
his colleagues, each individually, to condemn the Cartesian philosophy, as a
system which had sprung from Democritus and was opposed to the doctrine of the
Eucharist. In 1662, by order of the Nuncio, it was formally condemned by the
theological faculty. This was the prelude to its being, in the following year,
placed on the Index at Rome. But all these efforts proved fruitless. In 1667
five Franciscan friars came forward to defend Cartesian theses at Louvain, and
dedicated them to the same Nuncio, Geronimo Vecchio.
The
Cartesian philosophy was not merely an object of strife and a means of
instruction in the Low Countries, it was the source of a new movement in philosophy.
From the University of Groningen there came the Cartesian philosopher Clauberg, born at Solingen in Westphalia, who became a
professor in the German University of Herborn in
1649, and in 1651 in that of Duisburg. Clauberg was
active in spreading the Cartesian philosophy in western Germany, laying
especial stress on the problems of the relation of the Deity to the world, and
on that of the soul to the body. Geulincx of Antwerp,
a doctor of the University of Louvain, became professor there in 1646. In 1658,
having been dismissed for his attacks upon the scholastic philosophy and the
clergy, he withdrew to Leyden, and in 1665 was made a professor of that
University. He was more than a mere disciple of Descartes. He refused to admit
the union of soul and body which had been accepted by Descartes, and advanced
the Cartesian metaphysics in the direction of occasionalism afterwards
developed by Malebranche. About the same time, in the vicinity of Amsterdam,
Spinoza was learning from Descartes the geometrical and rational method which
he was to apply so forcibly to the demonstration of his half-scientific,
half-religious pantheism (1661-77).
In France
the Cartesian philosophy was opposed by the Jesuits, who, perceiving its
audacity, hastened to make war upon it with the same fervour with which they had combated the doctrines of Luther and Calvin. On the other
hand it was welcomed by the Congregation of the Oratory, on the grounds that it
was akin to Platonism and to Augustinianism. The Oratorian Malebranche was
awakened to philo; sophical reflexion by the perusal
of Descartes’ Traité de l’hommeafterwards (1665-1712) he put together his brilliant system by attributing,
through the inspiration of Plato and Saint Augustine, to God Himself the ideas
designated as “clear” by the author of the Meditations. At Port-Royal,
in the Church, in literature, in the Universities, and in the law-courts the
influence of Descartes gradually grew to be considerable, and even dominant.
Thus it was the Cartesian philosophy which inspired the celebrated Logique de Port-Royal, in which the art of
reasoning, which was the very end and object of scholastic logic, is
subordinated to the art of thought or judgment—that is, to the art of
distinguishing between truth and falsehood by means of reason or good-sense,
shared by all men. According to Pascal, it is not by “barbara and baralipton” that the faculty of
reasoning can be trained and formed; “ you must not hoist the mind up by a
crane.” It is mainly owing to the influence of Descartes that, in the latter
half of the seventeenth century, religion and philosophy were reconciled, and
came to form a harmonious whole. A Malebranche, a Bossuet, a Fenelon, far from
distrusting reason, sound the praises of its power and authority. Did not
Descartes show with mathematical precision that reason itself contains the
principles of belief in God and of the spirituality of the soul, which are the
foundations of religion? Reason, perfect and eternal, said Fenelon, is common
to all men, and, withal, superior to man. “What is this supreme reason? Is it
not the God whom I seek?”
In the
seventeenth century it was chiefly the metaphysics of Descartes of which the
authority was acknowledged. Towards the close of the seventeenth and in the
eighteenth century his physics, and his method in general, were supreme.
Fontenelle (1657-1757) extolled Descartes not as a metaphysician, who had
attacked unanswerable questions, but as the thinker who had effected a
revolution in mathematics and physics, as the promoter of the true method of
reasoning. And Montesquieu, in his Esprit des Lois (1748) undoubtedly
makes use of the Cartesian method itself, applying it to political matters.
The
influence of the Cartesian philosophy continued more and more to prevail in
France until 1765, when the French Academy proposed the eulogy of Descartes as
the subject of competition for the prize of rhetoric. After this date the
system of innate ideas and of vortices was succeeded by English empiricism and
by the philosophy of Newton. But Cartesianism will
never die out in the land where the love of clearness and of the logical connexion of ideas is a part of the national temperament.
Cartesianism was not as much at home in Germany as it was in France. However, it spread in
Germany also and, to a great extent, contributed to the philosophical movement
in that country. Not only at Herborn in Nassau, and
at Duisburg near Dusseldorf, where Clauberg lectured
with so much success, but also at Frankfort-on-the-Oder, at Bremen, and at
Halle we find Cartesian professors. At Frankfort taught John Placentius, Professor of Mathematics and author of Renatus Cartesius triumphans; at
Bremen, Daniel Lipstorpius, author of Spedmina philosophiae Cartesianae (1653), and Eberhard Scheveling,
Professor of Law; at Halle, John Sperlette. At
Leipzig the Cartesian philosophy was supported with brilliant success by
Andreas Petermann, Michael Rhegenius,
and Gabriel Wagner. But the chief title to fame of the Cartesian philosophy in
its relation to German thought was the important part which it played in the
development of the philosophical genius of Leibniz. The system of this great
man, in several of its essential parts, may be regarded as an endeavour to penetrate still deeper into the principles
from which the Cartesian philosophy was built up.
In Switzerland
the Cartesian Robert Chouet was made Professor at
Geneva in 1669. Among his pupils in that city was Pierre Bayle.
The Cartesian
philosophy was introduced into England mainly by Antoine Legrand, of the
Brotherhood of St Francis of Douai, who published in London two works
expounding the philosophy in a scholastic form. Samuel Parker, of Oxford,
having simultaneously confuted Hobbes and Descartes, as alike supporters of the
mechanical theory, in 1659 Legrand indited an Apologia pro R. Descartes
contra S. Parkerum, in which he showed with what
power Descartes had proved the existence of God against the materialistic
supporters of the mechanical theory. Though expelled from Oxford, the Cartesian
philosophy played an important part at Cambridge. The opponent of Descartes in
this University, the celebrated Platonist Cudworth, a colleague of Henry More
of Christ’s College, accepted the Cartesian mechanism with regard to dead
matter, but pronounced it false and fatal to religion to extend this mechanism
to living organisms. Between thought and extension he introduced a universal
plastic nature, by means of which God controls the motion of things. The
Cartesian ideas concerning physics were introduced into the University of
Cambridge by English and Latin translations of the physics of Rohault, one of the first to spread the Cartesian
philosophy in France. Up to the time of Newton, this work was considered as a
classic at Cambridge. The fecundity of Cartesianism manifested itself in England chiefly through the part played by it in the
formation of the intellectual system of Locke, which was in its turn to
exercise so considerable an influence on the entire later development of
philosophy.
In Italy
the Cartesian philosophy, especially as a scientific doctrine, established
itself in the territory of Naples, the birthplace of Giordano Bruno and of
Campanella. It was introduced here by Tommaso Cornelio, and powerfully
supported by Fardella. On the other hand Vico (16881744), on behalf of concrete, historical, and
social studies, opposed the philosophy of pure reason as disregarding the
phenomena relative to time and space.
Cartesian
thought is the most original, and the most productive of all intellectual
systems that existed on the Continent in the period of the Thirty Years’ War.
Its essential characteristics were its conception of reason, which it regarded
as the common centre of knowledge, life, science,
morality, and religion. It signified the re-establishment of order and reason
in the intellects and in the souls of men, by means of those very sciences and
of those modern ideas which writers without ballast were ready to place in
opposition to philosophical certainty and to the religious faith of mankind.
Powerful,
however, as was the influence exercised by the genius of Descartes, it was not
the only important intellectual movement noticeable during this period. In
France itself two further names, unequal to each other in importance, call for
mention as representing tendencies distinct from his, but endowed like it with
permanent vitality.
Descartes
had sought to confute the free-thinkers, the sceptics, and the naturalists, and,
as a matter of fact, his philosophy had in course of time to a great extent
overshadowed them. But just at first they refused to disarm, the more so
because they hoped to find a fitting formula and a satisfactory defence of their theories, especially in the teaching of a
man of learning, who, during his lifetime, enjoyed a reputation similar to that
of Descartes. This was Gassend, or Gassendi.
Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655), the Christian Epicurean, is chiefly
famous for his antagonism to Descartes, and for the point of view maintained by
him in opposition to that of the great rationalist. He was born in Provence,
near Digne. He took Orders early in life and became
an irreproachable priest; he conscientiously said mass, drank nothing but
water, and was a vegetarian. He died from fasting with undue rigour during Lent, having received the holy viaticum and the extreme unction three times more majorum.
His chief
characteristic is that he lived two lives: the one devoted to religion, the
other to philosophy. No doubt, Descartes virtually seems to have done the same.
But with him, philosophy and religion were finally reunited in reason, the
universal source of all our thoughts, the necessary principle and guide of all
our knowledge. Now Gassendi rejected all idea of connexion or comparison between religious faith and
philosophical doctrine. It mattered little to him whether the two were in
harmony or opposition. As a Christian, he submitted his opinions wholly to the
judgment of the Catholic, Apostolic and Roman Church. As a philosopher, he held
that the truth is contained in the system of Epicurus. The substance of the
world to him consisted of purely material atoms; a mind which could think
without the organs of thought, innate ideas which existed before all
experience, truths which could be other than the expression of external reality
penetrating the experience of the senses, were to him mere idle philosophical
inventions. Moreover, being of a moderate frame of mind, he did not consider
himself bound to abide by all the consequences flowing from Epicurean
principles. But the modified Epicureanism of Gassendi owes its strength and its importance to the fact that he found a link between
it and modem experimental science. In contradiction to Descartes, who held that
the mind more readily admits of being understood than the body, Gassendi believed that the nature of our being is revealed
to us more especially by means of anatomy and chemistry. What he sees and
appreciates in Bacon is not an abstract theory, a merely philosophical
doctrine, but rather the positive modern idea of science and nature, such as it
presented itself to a Kepler or a Galileo. Gassendi himself was a zealous student of mathematics, physics, medicine, and astronomy.
He believed in the absolute worth of science as such, and declared that, when
reason and experiment appear to be in contradiction, it is to the evidence of
experience that we must appeal.
Henceforward
his controversy with Descartes was something more than a quarrel between two
metaphysicians. When Gassendi apostrophised Descartes as “ O mens”and the latter retorted “O caro!” many of their
contemporaries concluded that the author of the Principes valued the ideas of his own mind more than the realities of experience; while
the learning and somewhat confused eclectic teaching of the author of the Syntagma philosophiae Epicuri (1649) represented the advance of modem science towards the complete subordination
of our conceptions to facts, to data, and to experiments.
Henceforward
it mattered little that Gassendi had always been a
docile Christian and a staunch supporter of Providence. His religious faith was
not only without root in his philosophy, but appeared to be in contradiction
with it. This faith could only be maintained by means of a radical dualism; and
the state of dualism is one of instability for the mind of man, which sooner or
later begins to compare different assertions with one another. Now, given the
enormous progress which awaited experimental science, a belief at variance with
the philosophical conception entertained of this science was fated to suffer
from so close a contact with it, and to seem less justifiable and less
important in proportion as the authority of science increased and its province
was extended. And hence Gassendi, because of the
exclusively empirical and naturalistic point of view which he assumed in the
domain of philosophy, because of his identification of ancient atomism with modern experimental science, represents, as opposed to the broad
rationalism of Descartes, the tendency of which, a hundred years later, the Encyclopedic was the outcome. In other words, he anticipated the apotheosis of natural
science as having put to flight the phantom of the
supernatural, and as being able in itself to satisfy every actual need of
the mind of man, whether practical or theoretical.
Notwithstanding
the considerable reputation which he enjoyed amongst his contemporaries, the
chief importance of Gassendi, who as a thinker was
inconsistent and lacked originality, lies in the interpretation which the
free-thinkers gave to his doctrines.
Of a very
different stamp was the great adversary of the Cartesian philosophy, who is the
chief glory of the Abbey of Port-Royal des Champs—Blaise Pascal. The most marvellous scientific capacity, a religious faith of
extraordinary depth and intensity, and the choicest gifts of the thinker and
the writer were united in this rare genius, which burst forth in childhood, and
which death gathered in at the early age of thirty-nine (1623-62).
Blaise
Pascal was born at Clermont-Ferrand in Auvergne; he came of a family belonging
to the legal noblesse. The father, President of the Cour des Aides at Clermont, was conversant with mathematics and physics, and associated
with the most intelligent men of the time. He gave his son an excellent
education, especially from a scientific point of view. The child, however, had
not been taught a word of mathematics, when one day—he was then not yet twelve
years of age—his father, taking him by surprise, found him employed in proving
the thirty-second proposition of Euclid, which demonstrates the sum of the
angles of a triangle to be equal to two right angles.
In the
intellectual atmosphere in which he grew up the precocious genius of Pascal
rapidly became productive. Before he was sixteen he had formed the first
conception of his Essai pour les Coniques, a work which afterwards filled Leibniz with
admiration. Pascal made important contributions to mathematical and physical
science. Following in the footsteps of Gerard Desargues (1593-1662), a
geometrician who was almost unknown in his lifetime, but whose works were of
great utility, Pascal established the entire theory of conic sections on a
general basis. He prepared the way for the infinitesimal calculus by his work
on calculating machines, entitled Lettres de Dettonville, from which Leibniz declared
himself to have derived the ideas that led him to his own discovery. D’Alembert
said that this work formed the connecting link between Archimedes and Newton.
Finally, together with the clever geometrician Fermat, of Toulouse (1595-1665),
and Huyghens, the great astronomical mathematician of
the Hague (1629-95), Pascal was one of the originators of the theory of
probabilities.
In connexion with Torricelli’s experiments on the possibility
of a vacuum, which were then attracting the attention of all Europe, Pascal (in
1647) conceived the idea of the celebrated experiment of the Puy-de-Dome, which
proved the hypothesis of the atmospheric pressure being the cause of the
suspension of the liquid column in the barometer. And by his generalisations from this result he completed the experimental theory of hydrostatics, the
principles of which had been demonstrated theoretically at the end of the
sixteenth century by Stevin, the Flemish geometrician.
While
making these discoveries, he examined the method which he employed in the
process, and boasted of being in opposition to Descartes, who, he maintained,
sought for hypotheses as to the nature of things and took pleasure in theoretic
points of view, while he, Pascal, put faith only in experiments. He declined to
ask himself in what light consisted, or on what subtle grounds visible
phenomena might be explained; but only examined physical laws, that is to say,
the permanent relations between facts such as are deducible from experiments.
Accurate
and profound in scholarship, Pascal was also full of spiritual ardour. Early in life he happened to read some Jansenist
works, and reflected on the true character of the Christian life. His
impassioned nature, eager to excel in all things, caused him to welcome with
enthusiasm a conception of religion which did away with the strange parallel
readily accepted by the insight of ordinary men between our love of God and our
love of things, and which, by acknowledging the emptiness of a world without
God, bade him devote to God all his thoughts, all his love, and all his life.
Meanwhile the state of his health compelled him to seek relaxation in society,
and for several years (1649-53) the world again took possession of him. But a
spiritual crisis of exceptional force caused him definitely to abandon the
world and self, and to concentrate all his efforts on the single point of
living for Jesus Christ. He withdrew to the Abbey of Port-Royal des Champs, a
place which breathed this very spirit of detachment from the world. There he
became intimate with the recluses and priests of that house, such as Arnauld, Nicole, and “ M. de Saci,”
and devoted all his strength to the service of God.
In this
strain he wrote the Petites Lettres called the Provinciales, in order to confute,
first the subtle theology, secondly the loose morals of the Jesuits. This work,
by reason of its vigour, its high moral tone, its
wit, its intensity, its dialectic force, its oratorical and dramatic power, is
a masterpiece of the French language, and of the mind of man, and withal one of
the most forcible attacks which the Society of Jesus has at any time sustained.
According
to Pascal the vice inherent in the teaching and practice of the Jesuits was
that of lowering the ideal of the Christian religion, in order to bring it to
the level, of the natural man. To entice men, and to get them into their power,
the Jesuits declare that God only requires of us human virtues. They degrade
our duty to the level of our capability, of our weakness, and of our cowardice.
They relax their rules in order to adjust them to the weakness of our will;
they corrupt the law to render it conformable to our corruption. Consequently
they detract from the necessity and the importance of Divine Grace, and go so
far as to resemble Pelagius and the pagans rather than disciples of Christ. In
opposition to the doctrine of the Jesuits, Pascal maintained, with the utmost
force, on the one hand, that we are commanded to love God, and to live for God;
and on the other, that Divine Grace is needed to accomplish a perfection which
surpasses the power of the natural man. His argument may be summed up in two
statements: first, God is our end; and, again, God cannot be our end unless He
is at the same time our inspiring principle. Hence, it is impossible to agree
with the Jesuits in admitting that the end justifies the means. He who uses
means condemned by God is not of Him, and does not work towards His Glory.
The
casuistry of the Jesuits, was, according to Pascal, the enemy of the Church
from within. Without, she had an enemy no less terrible in the scepticism of the free-thinkers or philosophers. He
determined to crush the latter as he had crushed the former, and, inspired by a
miracle which he believed to have taken place in favour of Port-Royal, from about the year 1656 onwards he devoted all the energies
spared him by his serious ill-health to an important work directed against
atheism. In 1662 he died suddenly, before he had been able to complete it. He
had only made a few notes, fragmentary sketches, and suggestions. These, which
were reverently collected, and published with ever-increasing care, constitute
what we call the Pensées of Pascal. They are the disconnected thoughts
of a genius in whom the mathematical mind is blended, in an almost unique way,
with the most ardent passion, and with the most facile and most original gift
of style.
Like
Descartes, Pascal wishes to confute the sceptics and to convert them. But, in
order to accomplish this, Descartes thought it sufficient to compel them to
acknowledge the existence and authority of reason, which, according to him,
contains the principles which attest the truth of religion, as of science. But
it seemed to Pascal that to remain content with proving the supremacy of reason
left the point at issue still undecided. For reason of itself has no fixed
principles, and can serve in the cause of error as successfully as in that of
truth. The haughty Stoic and the complacent disciple of Pyrrho invoke the name of reason—and both lead man to his ruin. Pascal, therefore,
passing beyond the boundary which limits the province of philosophy, undertook
to demonstrate directly the truth of religion itself. And religion to him
signified Christianity.
The method
which he employed for this demonstration was, at the same time, most vivid and
most subtle. Indeed, faith, according to him, comes from Divine Grace, and no
demonstration could take its place. But it behoves man to strive, with the help of this very grace, to remove the barriers set up
by the soul’s corruption between itself and God. Pascal had in mind the
free-thinkers of his time, those superficial scholars, who, impressed with the
power and progress of science, professed to find it all-sufficing, and employed
its results as weapons against religion. Himself a scholar, with more than an
amateur knowledge of science, and one who had given some thought to the
scientific method, he determined to turn against the sceptics their own arguments,
by showing how the truth of religion is to be deduced from those very sciences
which they had placed in opposition to it. Pascal, who was not only a
mathematician, but also a student of physics, refused to admit that, in order
to attain to the knowledge of reality, one should proceed otherwise than by the
observation of facts, and by arguments based on this observation. Now, the
free-thinkers prided themselves on having supplanted God by natural man, who,
according to them, possessed within himself all the elements of his science and
of his happiness. Man suffices for himself, they said; he needs not to bow down
before something higher than himself. The scientific method, Pascal replied,
requires that before attributing such perfection to human nature we should
first observe it from an unprejudiced point of view.
What then
is man, taken in his actual and natural form? A mass of contradictory
elements, a chaotic medley, an enigma. Each of his faculties, in fact, aims at
an end which it is incapable of accomplishing. Happiness is our goal, and all
our actions merely procure for us deception and disquietude. We demand justice
which is not based on force, and in reality we can but decorate force with the
name of justice. In our sciences we seek for complete demonstrations, and in
our arguments we only succeed in avoiding progression towards infinity by
falling back on hypotheses based on sentiment and (since demonstration here
becomes impossible) admitted by us without demonstration. In a word, human
nature, lofty and noble on the one hand, is low and petty on the other. It is
an irreconcilable medley of all that is great and of all that is base. This is
an undeniable truth. A scientific mind should start from this and attempt to
explain it, just as the student of physics attempts to explain the strange
phenomenon of the suspension of a liquid column in the barometrical tube.
Now reason
cannot itself explain the presence of two contradictory attributes in the same
subject. But it so happens that the Christian faith supplies us with an
explanation, according to which the subject, which appears to us as being one,
is in reality twofold, containing on the one hand Divine Grace and on the other
fallen nature. As a hypothesis this explanation is convenient and possible; its
truth remains to be proved. In dealing with this latter point Pascal appeals to
the documents of history. He attempts to show how, in the face of innumerable
obstacles, the Christian faith has established itself in the world with a power
and with results which attest its Divine origin. But he also invokes an
argument of a different character, which, according to him, is as capable of
demonstration as the assertion of a phenomenon in physics. This consists in
the individual experience of the working of God in ourselves, the realisation—which comes to us in moments of inspiration—of
the tie which, even in this life, unites man to Jesus Christ, and, through Him,
to the Father and Creator.
Hence the
work which Pascal intended to accomplish was a demonstration of the truth of
Christianity on scientific principles. Not that he meant to substitute human
means for the action of Grace. On the contrary, he constantly declares that
Love and Faith can only come from God Himself. But he thought that Divine Grace,
instead of acting as a substitute for human effort, is its incentive and its
guide, and that it makes itself felt by actions wholly conformable with the
fundamental needs of our nature and of our reason.
The
originality of this demonstration lay in its starting, not from the examination
of religious matters, or of the idea of God, but in its taking up the actual
standpoint of the opposite side, the standpoint of nature, claimed by the
free-thinkers as a substitute for God. Pascal contended that nature herself,
and science, which is but the rational interpretation of nature, can only be
conceived by a thoughtful and reasoning man, by presupposing the existence of
God, the very God of the Christian Faith.
The Pensées of Pascal, which were published posthumously by his Port-Royal friends in 1670,
at once attracted a widespread attention. They showed that it was possible to
combine the humblest faith with a most vigorous scientific insight. And this
striking example did not fail to influence that large number of minds who never
dare to think in any particular way unless they are sure of being in excellent
company. But . the work of Pascal chiefly consisted in the
exact and clear expression of a certain attitude of the human mind when
confronted with the problem of the relations between religion and science. He
does not regard religion as a domain apart, wholly unconnected with our natural
life. Religion is the explanation and the principle of the true realisation of our very nature, the key and the goal of all
the sciences. Thought, action, and feeling are really consistent and salutary
only if they start from God, and end in Him. Religion is the light and the
force of science and of life.
The
several tendencies of which Descartes, Gassendi, and
Pascal were the representatives were not merely notable phenomena,
characteristic of the atmosphere and of the epoch in which these philosophers
had their being. The very brilliancy with which these tendencies were expressed
by such men as Descartes and Pascal led to their dissemination among all
nations and throughout the ages and ensured to them a great historical
importance. But this is not all. More profound than the phenomena, which are
but the expression of the genius of a particular period or of a given phase of
society, these tendencies seem to comprise in themselves the various ways in
which the modern spirit, taken as a whole, reacts when confronted with the problem
of the connexion between science and religion.
With
Descartes philosophy properly so-called finds in human reason the common source
of our knowledge of nature and of our beliefs concerning the supernatural. With Gassendi, or rather with the class of thinkers whom
he came to represent, science tends to be selfsufficient,
and to banish religion to the obscure retreat of individual feeling, till the
time comes for altogether expelling it. With Pascal the supreme guidance of
reason, science and nature is claimed by religion, on proving that it alone can
solve the problems inherent in nature, science, and reason. Religion, science,
reason—are not these the three teachers of humanity, the three powers which
even today struggle for the control of the moral world? And even today are we
not asking ourselves which of the three is to overcome and subjugate the
others—or whether they may be brought together in a lasting and beneficent
harmony?