THE CLOSE OF THE MIDDLE AGES
EPILOGUE
The
close of the Middle Ages has been placed by the general consent of historians at
the end of the fifteenth century after Christ, with which the narrative portion
of this concluding volume mainly deals. Although this date is arbitrary and conventional,
and suggests a sudden transformation remote from reality, it is yet the fittest
at which to make one of the artificial divisions between the great periods of
history, for it was the eve of the religious disruption, the conscious rivalry
of national States, the complete supremacy of the State within its boundaries,
the enfranchisement of capitalism, the enlargement of the known world, the accompanying
translation of commerce into its “oceanic” stage, the diffusion and
amplification of learning, the awakening of critical induction and scientific
investigation—those potent forces which were to be the mainsprings of the modern
age. That the date, however, with all its importance, is artificial is shewn on
the one hand by the slowness with which medieval conditions, ideas, and preoccupations
faded from Europe after it, and on the other by the long period of preparation
for change before it, in which the fifteenth century, perhaps, holds the most
significant place.
With
but few exceptions, indeed, and those mainly in Italy, the men of the fifteenth
century by no means appeared to themselves the harbingers of revolution. They were
so, not so much because they invented new things, as because they failed in
maintaining and revivifying the old and resigned themselves discontentedly to
their failure. They hardly recognised that, beside the ideals they accepted and
betrayed, other instincts and motives were leading them towards fresh modes of
thought, a fresh outlook on life, and a fresh direction of society. In reality,
in the very attempt at defence and conservation the fifteenth century was full
of marked changes, which undermined the social structure and the dominant ideas
inherited from earlier times and fostered the development of younger
conceptions which were to replace them.
First
among the older ideals we may take that of the unity of Christendom derived
from classical times, made for a moment a physical reality by Charlemagne, and
brought to some degree of permanence and organisation by the spiritual autocracy
of the Papacy. But the unity of Western Christendom had not only always been a
shell for incessant feudal and local anarchy, it was rent more and more by the
swelling force of national union and national aversions within it, and, more
than all, had been weakened and deprived of its spiritual appeal by the
cumbrous, unhealthy functioning and frequent corruption, both increasing with
the years, of the ecclesiastical hierarchy on which it depended. The Great
Schism made apparent to all men that the government and system of the Church
were out of gear. The Councils were the conscientious endeavour of the piety of
Europe to restore that system of unity, to reform and lead back to efficient
working Papacy and hierarchy together. But the Councils strove to restore more
than had ever existed, to give the unity achieved by papal autocracy what was
in fact a new basis in a representative synod, and they forgot, as reformers
forget, that the vices they attacked were due in large measure to natural human
tendencies which were ingrained in the Church’s system. The champions of unity
at Constance and Basle entered on a duel with centralisation; those foes of autocracy
attempted to stereotype thought and institutions in a partly bygone, partly
imaginary mould. Themselves both conservative and revolutionary, they dreaded
revolution.
Thus
the Conciliar Movement hoped to keep the Pope, a permanent monarch, subject to
an intermittent assembly of shifting, jarring individuals, to keep a
bureaucracy while abolishing taxation, to prevent the diversion of uncoordinated
local endowments from local needs to that maintenance of learning, eminence,
and favouritism to which each single member owed his livelihood. The task was formidable
from its inherent contradictions, and to them were added the incalculable influence
of personality and the steady current of nationalism. The Council of Constance
ended in separate national Concordats. Pope Martin V, strong in the prestige,
the authority, and the organisation of his office, embedded in law and habit,
naturally yielded no foot of defensible ground, and was also determined to
fortify the Papacy, threatened in revenue and independence, by the secular rule
of the Papal States which in law belonged to him. He bequeathed to his
successors the stubborn retention of profitable abuses and the purely worldly policy
of an Italian prince denuded of scruples. The Popes were aided not only by the
inevitable dissensions of moderates and extremists, doctrinaires and
self-seekers, in the Council of Basle, but also by the facts that the Conciliar
Fathers were drawn from different nations, unsympathetic and often hostile to
one another, and that national and State governments were at the same time playing
for their own ends not for those of the universal Church. France and England were
at grips in the Hundred Years’ War; the German princes and the Spanish monarchs
were all engrossed by problems of their lands. The mastery over the Church in
their own dominions was their only real aim in matters ecclesiastical. That it
was then impossible to segregate effective Church Reform from national
self-assertion and policy was shewn by the extraordinary strength and theological
innovation of the Hussite movement which broke the unity of the Church
throughout the fifteenth century. In Hussitism the vivid national consciousness
of the Czechs and their hatred of their German neighbours found their outlet
and expression in religious revolution which practically broke with the idea of
the Universal Church. It was a true transition, hybrid because transitional,
from the medieval towards the modern age. Religion in this isolated territory
of Bohemia behind the rampart of its mountains and its language became the
badge of a nation; and in the shelter of the alliance novelty of thought, once
the singularity of stray thinkers and scanty, surreptitious communities, could take
firm root and grow.
To
sum up, the fathers of Constance and Basle typify the failure to maintain and reinspire
older conceptions which is one mark of the fifteenth century. Throughout they
strove for fixity of doctrine, for ecumenic Christendom, and for co-operative
government by discussion. Yet these things were then incompatibles. Only the
papal autocracy had held the Catholic Church in some sort together. It was
still a living force allied to the contemporary trend towards despotism.
Conciliar government was growing steadily obsolete in secular life, and in the
Church gave a field for the separatist, national impulse. Allied with monarchs,
rigid against heresy, the Councils provided a stage for national dissidence,
and yet— for they represented Western Christendom—naturally shunned the separatist
thought of individuals which found its home in nationalism. They cut themselves
off from the growing life their efforts nourished. Their failure to produce
conservative reform was the prelude to later revolution. Small bands of fiery innovators
were to be given their opportunity by the tepid inertia of the existing order.
It
is something of a paradox to introduce here the increasing persecution of the
Jews, which began and was in theory justified by the fact that they were the
enemies of Christianity, an excrescence in Christian society. Yet hatred of the
Jews had always largely been a racial hatred of aliens in manners and in laws,
and it took on a more national complexion as the nations formed. Mere segregation,
prescribed by the Church, and fanatical massacres were succeeded by systematic
expulsion in the interests of national uniformity in the several States. Edward
I drove the Jews from England in 1290, Philip the Fair from most of France in
1306, the Germati towns and nobles with more prolonged and terrible violence
from Germany. Finally, Ferdinand and Isabella expelled the Jews from Spain in
1492 with the definite aim of national consolidation. It is significant that
the persecuted race found refuge in the loosely constructed teiTitories of
Poland and the Ottoman Empire1. Thus what seemed to be an effort of the
expiring unity of Christendom was really a symptom of a new exclusive force—nationality.
As
the efforts of united Christendom came to open failure in the attempt at the
reform and reorganisation of the Church, so did they in the latter Crusades,
the defence of Europe against Asia and Islam. Those efforts were at times
serious enough, yet they were always sporadic, partial, and halting. The Papacy
made the Crusade against the Ottoman Turks a permanent policy, but among other
policies and more heartfelt objects nearer home; it was only the superfluous energies
of Western knights which were spent in the defeats of Nicopolis and Varna; even
Hungary, Venice, and Genoa, whose vital interests were at stake, seldom if ever
flung their whole weight into the war; the pathetic fiasco of Pius II at Ancona
was an emblem of the impotence of Europe in face of the common peril; and the
fall of the Roman Empire of the East published the collapse of the Crusading
ideal1. When the Catholic Kings unified Spain by the conquest of Granada from
the Moors, it was the triumph of a nation, not of Christendom.
In
the preceding volume of this history it has been seen that Western Europe, most
especially France and England, in the fourteenth century reached the last stage
of feudal monarchy as a political system. A centralised government by the king
and his bureaucracy was superimposed on a class of feudal nobles great and
small, who either as in France still retained in large measure their feudal
franchises or as in England were no less powerful by reason of their armed retinues
and their influence on the royal administration. Beside the nobles two other strata
of society possessed political importance, the clergy held separate by their
celibacy, their unique privileges, and their international organisation, and
the bourgeoisie characterised by their trading vocation and their town-dwelling
communities. By these classes of men and their rights, by the representative
assemblies of them which met round the king for consent and counsel, and by the
law or custom handed down from the past and inherent in each human society, the
kingship was limited and controlled. Government might be monarchic, yet the
king’s powers were circumscribed and shared; he was fettered by hereditary or
official counsellors, by local privileged potentates and corporations.
Similarly, in Germany the Emperor was but the chief of the teeming members of
the Empire, and the princes were themselves limited by the Estates of their
subjects. The republican towns of Germany and Italy were ruled by an entangled
federation of unequal gilds, like their less autonomous congeners elsewhere.
Even in the Church the “parliamentary” collective conception of government had
its place and was gaining ground for a time in the Conciliar Movement. Rule
under law and by consent was the reigning belief and the partial practice,
founded on rights descended from the feudal, contractual, decentralised past.
In
the fifteenth century this intricate, motley system of co-operative, diversely
federated government was brought to moral bankruptcy by its failure to meet the
needs or redress the evils of the times well as by its inability to adapt
itself to the changing conditions of the society which had given it birth.
Feudal armies failed to defend France from the English invasions; barons, clergy,
and towns equally failed to present a united front or to pursue a consistent policy;
the mere maintenance of order and security was beyond their capacity and even
alien to their desires. In England feud and faction, greed and misgovernment
ran riot in the Wars of the Roses. The over-mighty subjects failed to give either
victory or peace or justice. Like the French States General the English Parliament
had proved unequal to its own aims. The same failure in a more veiled form was
to be seen in the lands of the Empire. The feudal constitution of Germany meant
in practice unremitting private war amid princes and cities, and this disorder
was equally or more apparent within the princes’ territories and the
self-governing towns themselves. Feudal jurisdiction seemed to mean anarchy and
brigandage; town autonomy a simmering class-war. In North Italy, again, with
the exception of Venice, republican government had meant the exploitation of
one class by another and the furious short-sighted rivalry of wealthy families.
These defects were not new, but in the new conditions of larger units and
problems wider and more complex they were far less tolerable and more obstructive.
A curious inability to make any real sacrifice of personal and family immediate
advantage to secure the working and profit of the State jeopardised the existence
of that system of contract, co-operation, and consent in both lands of the Empire.
Common
to all Europe, almost, save England, was the depression of the peasants. As the
elan of increasing population, the cultivation of waste lands, and the need of a
greater food-supply died down after the Plague became a regular visitation in
Europe, the ruling classes became more apt to reimpose or increase old exactions
on their rustic dependants. The more rapid intellectual progress of the upper
classes gave them a fresh advantage over the more primitive lower. The North
Italian town-dwelling landlord knew, indeed, that it was bad business to make
his terms too hard for his tenants—the mezzadria worked for content and stability—but
he kept them in firm subjection. The northern noble was both harsher and more extortionate
in his narrower feudal outlook. Thus, in Germany the fifteenth century is an
age of peasant discontent and revolt1. It is an age of disillusion and deadlock,
when the old ways seem void of hope and profit.
In
these circumstances the growth of untrammelled monarchy almost everywhere met a
public need, and was to find its consummation in the early modern age. In
France especially the kingship stood forth as the saviour of the country from
foreign conquest, as the centre of unity and the expression of nationality, which
was now become in the Hundred Years’ War acutely self-conscious and a deciding
factor in history. The continual inter-communication between European
communities made the smaller differences between allied districts seem less and
the great divergences between distant countries more severing and alien. Monarchy
was the only force which could compel order and give security, which stood above
the strife of classes and personal ambitions, which could foster internal and
external expansion. A public opinion rapidly formed which lifted the king, in
spite of individual defects and particular oppressions, into unchallenged
supremacy. In Spain, and in a more tempered shape in England, the same irresistible
process was seen. Nobles and local powers, after the heyday of their uncurbed
development, seemed smitten with paralysis before the advance of the central kingship
directed with resolution and consistent purpose. Even in Germany and Italy the
same phenomenon was clear. If the Emperor had too long been the chief of a loose
federation to take effective advantage of it, the greater princes were able to
master their nobles and towns in their own lands. Territorialism was but a fractional
kind of monarchy. In Italy, with Venice as the only important exception, class
disunion and city rivalry had produced the despot; and even in the splintered
Papal States there were signs that despotism would be provincial as in
Lombardy, and not a mere form of a city-autonomy, now out-of-date in a more
interconnected world.
The
general appearance of the despot, exalted above all competing authorities, was
made possible by the decay of the nobles in independent military power and,
again especially in France, in material wealth. The feudal noble as such had
become an amateur in war; his inefficiency was shown at Agincourt; he was
outclassed by the professional soldier, who was very usually himself under new
conditions of discipline and wholetime training. Now the maintenance of even a
small regular army was beyond the resources of a feudal estate for any length
of time. Only the kings, who could draw from every kind of wealth over a large
territory, could achieve this. Only they could amass the artillery, which
besides its growing importance in the field could shatter the once secure
stronghold of the feudal castle and the fortified autonomous town. Only they could
levy for long periods the large numbers of foot, pikemen and archers, who were
indispensable in a campaign, and who could repel the wildest charge of feudal
knights. Forethought, co-ordination, system, and routine, which the Middle Ages
had slowly brought forth, were all available to the new resolute monarchy, not to
the disunited feudal survival with its purblind counsels. Ability gravitated to
the king’s service with its wide sphere, its wide outlook, and its manifold
activities. In France, too, feudal independence had been sapped by the
impoverishment of the nobles. Its origins lay far back. The nobles were
unproductive; chivalry was a costly and wasteful mode of life; the strenuous
noble stocks were prolific. From the time of the later Crusades all save the
wealthy and the eldest sons found it steadily harder to live the life of their
class in feudal society. The king’s service became more and more their chief resource.
As his officials, his troopers, and his pensioners, provided with posts and
Church benefices misemployed, they could gain an honourable livelihood. The devotion
of the lesser nobles as a whole to their sovereign, fortified by chivalry and
loyalty, became a characteristic of the fifteenth century.
It
was a kind of apotheosis. The nobles for honour and support, the townsmen for wealth
and safety, the peasants for protection to live and labour, all looked to the
national or territorial ruler by right divine, the embodiment of law, of order,
of justice, and ancient right. The very advance in individual initiative and
freedom which was taking place as the sequel of organised civilisation made the
older forms of group and class life not only inefficient for men’s growing
needs but also fetters to their action and self-help. The single master who gave
them security and opportunity was himself the representative individual in the
State. Under him the individual could move more freely. Thus the political
ideals of Western Europe were being transformed in correspondence with
contemporary practice. The concerted action of Christendom under the leadership
of the visionary Empire and the spiritual Papacy, always since the latter
thirteenth century at least more a sentiment than a reality, lost its appeal
with the defeat of the Council of Basle and the fall of Constantinople. So did
the ideal of a graded government partitioned down among a feudal and ecclesiastical
hierarchy co-operating with their chiefs in matters of general concern. This,
too, had been diseased or moribund in practice, as Pope and kings centralised
their dominion, long before feudalist and prelate by their own behaviour seemed
to make its pretensions hollow. With comparatively few exceptions the most
respectable bishops appeared, not as guides to holiness, but as shrewd men of
affairs administering an extortionate and rigidly technical business and legal
system. Chivalry appeared to have become in like manner a matter of parade and
convention cloaking reckless greed and callous brutality. The discredit was not
wholly just, for the solid achievements of churchman and knight in the past had
created a more civilised world by which their successors were judged. Ancient
faults became more glaring with a higher standard more diffused. None the less
there had been a degeneracy in morale, as the first enthusiasms died down, and
men discovered that the mere machinery for improvement did not necessarily
imply a renovation in human nature. They grasped at the untried remedy of
national or territorial monarchy.
Another
facet of the same process was apparent in the obsolescence of the feudal tie of
homage and fealty. Time had been when this contractual bond had constituted the
suzerain’s principal hold on his feudal inferiors; it was by means of it and
the rights it conferred that he had fortified and given reality to the infant
and shadowy conception of sovereignty and the State. In the fifteenth century,
become complicated, inconsistent, and artificial, it exercised less and less
moral compulsion on the vassal conscience. But it was replaced by the yet stronger
charm of the allegiance of the subject to his natural lord, the sovereign of
the State. Herein the continuous study of the Roman Civil Law produced its full
effect. From the legal theorists and the lawyers in the king’s service the belief
in absolute monarchic power spread to the theologians and infiltrated into the
general thought. The community no longer appeared as an association of grades
and diverse functions but as a mass of individuals bound together in the State,
whose concentrated powers resided in its head—“amat enim unitatem suprema
potestas.” The Roman Law had partly shaped the history of the later Middle Ages
by its direct influence, but that influence grew more potent as the times
became more apt for the reception of its maxims and conceptions. When despotism
was men’s refuge, its doctrine of the omnicompetent State and the absolute
monarch took effect. Even if in Germany the Reception of Roman Law in 1495 did
not benefit the Emperor, it strengthened the territorial princes. Yet the
fifteenth century is still preparatory; the older notions still lived and
struggled; the new were not fully accepted for many years, and were never the
one temporal creed of Christendom.
Something
of the same bankruptcy of older ideals, the same changing of conditions, and the
same emergence of new impulses which blindly created the revolutionary future
was to be seen in the economic aspects of fifteenth-century society. Roughly
speaking, the two preceding centuries had seen the growth of capitalism in long-distance
trading and in large-scale manufacture for export. But that capitalism had had
its chief home in a certain number of great towns situated on the main routes
of traffic, and in those towns it was regimented in wealthy gilds which controlled
to some extent the individual capitalist. Not only that: the local retail trade
was organised in its own gilds, all on the lines of strict regulation and of
restraint of undercutting competition. Among the employees of the rich manufacturers,
too, the revolutionary movements in the Low Countries, Italy, and Germany
tended to introduce similar gilds, which in their turn worked for regulation
and protection from native employers and outside rivals. In short, trade, even
in its most capitalistic form, was subject to the local group system rooted in
the older towns and by consequence was fettered by the narrow local spirit of
monopoly which did not transcend its town of origin. Trade was being choked by
the multitude of restrictions imposed by concerted action. But a change was
coming in conditions. As the stretch of territory under a single monarchical
authority widened, as for instance in the Low Countries under the house of Burgundy,
it became impossible for the towns and the classes within them to play the
dog-in-the-manger to the country round them. While the Flemish towns saw their
carefully regulated cloth manufacture dwindle, a new race of capitalists
employed the villagers without restrictions or traditions, pliant to changes of
demand and supply, and captured the European market. In like manner the new
free port of Antwerp drew to itself the international merchant and banker by
the liberty he had there, unhindered by meddling, local greed, to manage
business sensitive to far-off and uncontrollable events. How much this freedom
meant can be seen later even in the older Flemish towns, where certain industries
prospered because they were new and had no gild. To sum up, the tide of
individualism, in the shape of the single person or private firm, whether in
the Netherlands, France1, South Germany, or Italy, was more and more eluding
and undermining the joint control of the group. This, too, meant a decline at
least in old ideals: the theory of the “just price”, according to which a fair
reward apportioned to his status and need could be dealt out by authority in
due shares to each who was concerned in the production; the condemnation of
interest on moral grounds; the duty of maintaining a joint control of quality, of
product, of work, and of play. But the loss was less than it seems. Minute,
vexatious regulations, incessantly and hypocritically evaded, were after all a
nuisance and a clog; in spite of the very real decay of scruple, honesty and
fairness could and did survive. Individual responsibility in the wider world
that fostered it was a dynamic, creative force; it supplied a public need, and
in the long run submitted to the sway of a public conscience.
These
changes were being effected not only by the growth of wider areas under a
single monarch who could bring peace and loosen restrictions, but also by
changes in the trade-routes and in the commercial centres along those trade-routes.
No little of the prosperity of Nuremberg and the Swabian and Rhine towns was
due to the disorder of France in the Hundred Years’ War. That England in the
fifteenth century increasingly exported rough cloth instead of wool helped in
the decay of Ghent and Bruges. Similar causes were beginning to destroy the
cloth-trade of Florence. In the middle of the century the decay of the Scanian
herring fisheries and the development of those of the North Sea were diminishing
the prosperity of the Hansa towns of the Baltic and enhancing that of Holland
and the English eastern coasts. Large-scale industry, in fact, was becoming diffused
over Europe amid political changes which steadily weakened the predominance of
the old autonomous towns with their unyielding traditions. The Hansa were
worsted in their long contest with the Duke of Burgundy, against whose wide
lands their commercial boycott was inefficient. The subjection of the Teutonic
Order to Poland depressed their Prussian allies; that of Novgorod to the Great Prince
of Muscovy left them helpless in the Russian trade. They could no longer insist
on their methods and monopoly. In like manner the advance of the Ottoman Turks was
depriving Venice and Genoa of their central position in European commerce and of
their eastern outlets. The fall of Constantinople meant the loss of the Black
Sea trade and most of that of the Aegean. Only the route to Alexandria, whither
the spices came from India, remained to enrich Venice, and this was costly and
precarious. The diminution of the papal income from beyond the Alps after the
Great Schism prevented the return of the Papacy to Rome from being a sufficient
makeweight, and Italy was becoming merely the source of a few expensive luxuries,
spices, armour, glass, and silk, while the volume of European trade was moving north.
Even in the Mediterranean, unified France and Spain were too powerful rivals
for the city States. The country States, too, secure in their wide home market,
could deliberately exclude foreign imports which competed with their own
productions, whereas the retaliatory protection instituted by the autonomous
Italian towns was useless as a weapon and a miserable compensation for a once
European trade. A rapid decline in the cloth-making firms was visible. North Italy
was beginning to live on stored-up wealth, and her unrivalled skill in banking.
It is no wonder that investment in land was becoming the fashion in Florence
and Venice, and that Venice turned to territorial ambitions both for their own
sake and to secure her route to Germany. Over all the West the star of the city
State was paling before the formation and cultural advance of the country State
with its varied and abundant resources.
By
a fatal coincidence the westerly countries, too, were enlarging both their products
and their enterprise. As the shifting of the herring fisheries stimulated Dutch
and English shipping, so had the multiplication of Spanish flocks, a new source
of wool, and their share of the Bay salt of the Loire mouth profited both Spain
and the Low Countries. The Portuguese, already active by sea as far as England
and Flanders, were turning to the exploration of the African coast. The art of
ship-building was advancing by slow experience among the westerly nations on
their varied ocean coasts rather than in the limited, monotonous Mediterranean.
It was the learned Prince Henry the Navigator of Portugal, himself no seaman, who
planned and directed the enterprise in the spirit of a crusader: so might the Muslims
of Morocco be evaded and the distant, legendary heathen be converted, and even
the fabulous Prester John and his Christians be reached in the East. Continual
expeditions crept slowly along the North African coast line. The difficult
navigation round Cape Bojador was accomplished in 1434, and the immediate
objective, the heathen negro population in fertile lands round the River
Senegal, within twenty years. The progress was slow, but the profits in the
trade in gold and ivory and the swarms of negro slaves were great. It was still
in the Middle Ages when in 1486 Bartholomew Dias rounded the Cape of Good Hope
and opened the route, soon to be traversed, to India. With that discovery the
Italian transit trade to the East, cumbrous, scanty, and costly, rapidly became
insignificant. It was a discovery made in the open sea away from routine by a
nation State under a despotic king. So, too, was the expedition of Columbus
which intended, like the Portuguese, to reach the Spice Islands, and in fact unveiled
the New World. The “oceanic” period of commerce, thus begun, when the main
route and centre of wealth were in the countries of the Atlantic coast, belongs
to modem times, but that revolution, which reduced the Mediterranean and Italy
to a side artery, had taken its first steps earlier with the formation of
national kingdoms in the West and the restriction of papal authority and
revenue in the fifteenth century.
When
we turn to the intellectual preoccupations of men, apart from them social or
economic activity, we find even more the evidence of the sterility and decay of
those leading ideas which had once been so fecund. The whole fabric of scholastic
thought seemed to be smitten by a secret sense of failure. It had aspired to
formulate a system of the philosophic explanation of the universe, where reason
should be the loyal ally of faith and revelation, and “justify the ways of God
to men”. Its purpose had been religious and even devotional, yet it rested on a
conviction not only of man’s potential capacity to understand the reality of the
spiritual and material world but also that man had discovered the infallible recipe
to achieve that understanding. Shred by shred by the fourteenth-century
thinkers that certitude was stripped away from scholasticism. The “sons of
Ockham,” the “moderni,” denied the possibility of proving by reason any part of
the Christian verity, or even of metaphysical verity. They were Christians by an
act of theological faith alone. The “antiqui,” the realist opponents of the new
nominalists, could only reply by a lifeless adherence to Aquinas, a petrified
repetition on all essentials. This agnosticism, which so severely limited the
province of reason and was answered inadequately, produced its slow
disintegrating effects on a study which thus renounced its own goal. When nothing
great could be proved, men spent themselves on verbal subtleties. It was good
to know how to reason, it was the avenue to promotion in the universities and the
clerical career; so there flourished the compendium, the explanation of former
explanations, the barren exploitation of method and teaching of dexterity, the
alleviated path to a degree. The names of “antiqui” and “moderni” became badges
of factions in the universities, indeed of universities themselves, changing
sides at the order of their sovereign, and now numerous and no longer
international as Paris had been. When Nicholas of Cusa attempted a system of
compromise and contradiction, he bound it together by the tenet of intuition of
the incomprehensible, indescribable infinite. But this intuition, vouchsafed to
the individual mystic, was hardly of service to a common effort of mankind to
grasp a coherent scheme of things. The same paralysis of will rather than of
thought seemed to strike the consideration of those single sensible impressions,
which to the Ockhamists appeared to give some secure foothold. In induction
from them, as some fourteenth-century thinkers saw, lay the hope of advance,
but the true “modernus,” Cardinal d’Ailly, was “palsied with a doubt” here too:
God might give the illusion of a sensible impression without the external object
to make it. A preference for the arbitrary aspect of omnipotence—not alien to earthly
despotism—grew stronger: it was open to God to make evil good and good evil.
It
was, perhaps, a natural concomitant of this disbelief in the validity of reason
that led to the more pronounced belief in the crude, age-long superstitions
handed down among the masses from a prehistoric past. They had always been
there; they were, indeed, allied to the belief in stellar influences, in the
mysterious properties of stones and times, in charms and spells, which had been
part of the matrix of infant science; they were fostered by the ignorant panic
roused to fever by the Black Death; now they became prominent and, so to say,
official. The “ witchcraft delusion,” with its accompanying horrors, was a not
unnatural vagary of educated men to whom anything was possible because nothing
was disprovable. The extremes of scepticism and credulity met in that circle.
Yet
the decadence of the great edifice of thought raised by the Middle Ages helped
to clear the way for a fresh advance unhindered by its prepossessions of
doctrine, aim, and method. The stress laid upon sensible experience by the Ockhamists
not only anticipated a distant future, it also expressed the less conscious
mental orientation of men who were not schoolmen. The home of this new direction
of thought and interest lay in Italy. It took its start from the solid
acquisitions in knowledge and culture of earlier times, but it was fired by the
appetite for more and wider-based knowledge, for which an unexhausted source
lay open in the writings of classical antiquity. One constant feature of medieval
development had been a slow approximation, however partial, towards the cultural
standard of the ancients. As men became more literate and civilised, they
became more capable of appreciating the higher civilisation of the past. They
progressively absorbed what they became fit to realise. In Italy, with its
classic temper, this particular evolution grew speedier in the fourteenth
century. Dante still regarded Virgil as a sage of the undifferentiated former
time, not essentially strange to his own; just as his contemporaries looked on
Aristotle. With Petrarch and Boccaccio, and far more with their successors, the
Latin classics seemed the relics of a nobler age, a greater race of men. True
knowledge, true insight, and instructed modes of thought were there, to be learnt
and imitated by their devotees. The humanist enthusiasm was afoot. It was clear
from their Latin oracles that the yet unknown Greek literature was the fount
and the main current of this dimly descried sea. Virgil pointed the way to
Homer. The disasters of the time themselves were auspicious, for the Byzantine
Empire in its struggle for existence against the Ottoman Turks was painfully for
the first half of the fifteenth century courting the West and ready to give
what the Italians had grown to wish; and the Byzantines in the long ebb of
their culture and in the antiquarian passion for their greater past were at last
in real mental contact with the West, which had grown literate as they grew “medieval.”
The coming of Chrysoloras and his foundation of Greek studies in Italy marks an
epoch.
It
is not here in question to narrate the bitter war between humanists and scholastic
theologians, the strife and the compromise between the classical and the ascetic
ideals of life, the long survival of medieval traditions, the contest between
the outworn subtleties of the Schools and the pretentious rival imaginings of
the Italian Neo-Platonists. But it is essential to remark that the humanists
were engaged in afresh and fervid study of facts, a method of experience. They
were exploring Latin and Greek as concrete languages, learning the arts of
expression and taste from ancient masters, finding out what they had thought
and felt, seeing the world through their eyes, replacing the monotonous web of
an a priori metaphysic by a variegated display of life and nature. Here lay
their achievement; they were discoverers and cartographers of new lands of
intellectual wealth and inspiration. That their own first efforts at rivalry
might be vapid in style and shallow in thought was of little account: by the
close of the fifteenth century their successors, steeped in the classics, were
creating thought solid and profound, literature that with exquisite or reckless
touch ran through the gamut of life itself.
The
humanistic movement, in fact, did eminently in its sphere of learning with
revolutionary consequences what others tended to do with reluctant or blindfold
steps. The appreciation of the multitudinous direct facts of the visible,
audible world, the joy in this life, the absorbing interest in man in his
concrete variety, in his passions and capacities, replaced exhausted schemes of
the unseen, supersensible universe, of refinements of the theory of knowledge,
which were ending in questioning its possibility. In a time of failure and
disillusion it brought triumphant hope, a boundless employment of man’s
faculties with a boundless reward. The earth renewed “ its winter weeds
outworn.” If it seems strange that a tribe of pedantic grammarians should so
exalt themselves, it is to be remembered that the ancient authors they idolised
covered the whole field of knowledge and literature and gave the outlook, the
freedom of spirit, and the new programme the age was seeking.
It
was only slowly that the new humanism spread beyond the Alps, although the
inclination towards scientific knowledge was early obvious, but the practical invention
which was to have so great an influence in the diffusion of both was made in
Germany on the Rhine. Printing by movable type, following, it seems, on some
obscure preludes in Holland, was made into a workable method of reproducing
books by John Gutenberg at Mayence round about the year 1450. In some ten
years, by him and his allies Fust, the necromancer Faust of the legend, and
Schoeffer, the new art had been proved capable of rivalling manuscripts in its
beauty and accuracy, and far surpassing them in prolificness and accessibility.
Journeymen and pupils carried it rapidly over Germany, Italy, and France; it
entered England with Caxton; by 1500 tens of thousands of editions of books had
been published in Western Europe. The humanists had sought far and wide for the
rare manuscripts of long neglected classic works. Now those works were multiplied
beyond the risk of destruction or of seclusion in a few libraries. New works
shared the fortune of the old. The extension of literacy and education had been
one of the achievements of the Middle Ages, and this invention at their close
not only immensely widened the reading public but allowed the rapid participation
and secure possession of learning, literature, and thought. It made
indestructible the gains amassed by the effort of seven hundred years.
The
same zeal to know and admiration for the visible, multifarious world and man,
its denizen, which were vocal in the humanists, inspired also the plastic and
pictorial art of the Italian Renaissance. The Italians from Giotto onwards
shared in the general advance in artistic technique which was being made all through
the West, and in the fifteenth century they were discoverers in perspective, in
anatomy, in psychologic insight. Whatever ideal or religious forms it took, at
the foundation of this art lay the instinct for reality: to represent men in
their fashion as they lived, the earth as the eye might see it, heaven and hell
as the abodes of verifiable human emotion and desire. But the passion for the
beauty of what the natural existing world presented them was no less strong;
Italian quattrocento art is filled with the delight in life, and the conscious
mastery of the skill to express it. In nothing was the classic nature, akin to
humanism, of this mastery displayed more than in the native Italian aptitude
for form and composition. The picture becomes a harmonious whole, not a mere
collection of observations however exact, skilled, and poignant. Not only in the
formal arrangement of what they chose to shew but in grading the spiritual
significance, in the choice of emphasis in their representations, the Italians excelled.
In this lucidity in the world of fact, unhampered by metaphysical questioning,
in the will to grasp and control it for human exploitation, they knew themselves
like the ancients whose civilisation they emulated. There was an element of classical
revival and imitation in their work which grew with the years and acted for
long, though not permanently, as an inspiration and not a chilling fetter. For
their art, like humanism, was home-grown and a true development from the later
Middle Ages.
But
if we can only speak of the fifteenth-century Renaissance in respect of Italian
ait, the essential realism, the sense of the individual, external fact, from
which it grew, was rife in Europe, and so was the technical proficiency which
was its condition. The portraiture, the scenes of devotion or homely life, the
exquisiteness in minute, exact detail of the Flemings give the elements of the
new mentality without their fusion in a new artistic creed. In architecture the
builders seem to disguise the monotony of purpose they habitually revere, in
the English perpendicular by the multitudinous, gorgeous incidents of the
stained windows, in French flamboyant by the inexhaustible wealth of tracery
and fretted stone. The decoration drew more interest than the design. Strong
and full of vitality as the art remained, virtuosity in detail appealed most to
its practitioners and accorded with the temper of the age. Romanesque and then
Gothic art in its prime had revealed its structure, its details had a confessed
architectural purpose; just as the design of its churches responded to
doctrinal, ceremonial, or social needs—we see the uplifted presbytery of the
Hildebrandine age, when the priesthood were the mediators between God and man,
the processional, monastic church with its many altars for the unending opus
Dei, the open-spaced church of the Friars built for preaching to the city
throng. But flamboyant art conceals its essential functions with functionless
decoration; the pillar can be twined with wreaths, the keystone apes a
stalactite, even the vaulting which is visible may be merely a painted design;
exquisite monuments and private chapels break up the unity of the whole. It was
a fit emblem of a time when men led by personal or national instinct still
subscribed mechanically to the formulae of Catholic Christendom.
There
may be found an analogy to this phase of the plastic and pictorial arts in the
vernacular literature of the fifteenth century, which, like them, appealed to
the wider public. A tedious conventionality enwrapped the tale of chivalry and
the moral allegory. In the lyrics, technique, ever more elaborated, replaces in
general both genuine feeling and poetic inspiration. It was an age of the
pedantic manufacture of literature on bygone themes under set rules. Yet here
too men’s real interests found expression and gave life. An unforced characterisation
of his personages pervades the Mort Darthur of Malory. Historians, like
Chastellain and Commynes, could draw portraits—realism is their true bent.
Villon made the elaborate ballade vibrate with as poignant a personal truth as
Dante’s. Even the endless mysteries, allegoric and religious plays, awake to
drama when they treat of persons, passions, and the absurdities of mankind. The
living theme was what men felt and did. To this the new humanism arising in
Italy brought a kind of consecration, and in its development it brought more
tangible gains, form and plan and coherence, the rationality of the classics.
It
is curious to see how the reforming, yet conservative endeavour to revivify
asceticism and the monastic life, in its attempt to be both reactionary towards
ancient prescriptions and appropriate to new needs, admitted the dangerous ally
of humanism within the cloister. The Brethren of the Common Life were scribes,
educators, and grammarians. The reformed Benedictines, renewing the long-forgotten
manual labour of the Order, zealously copied and bound manuscripts. Both
furthered, first unconsciously, then consciously, the new learning of humanism.
In both, perhaps, the individual mystic was harboured. That the pen of the
copyists might be snatched from their hands by Gutenberg’s invention, that the
scholar might stray from accepted solutions and ideals to new interpretations,
that collective asceticism might prove an unequal rival to individual freedom
and unalluring to the majority of fifteenth-century monks, however
old-fashioned, may be claimed as signs that changes in men themselves and their
surroundings were outrunning changes in their scheme of life.
The
growing unreality of its professed aims was perhaps the source of the decadent
aspect of the fifteenth century. The Church, feudalism, chivalry, the crusade,
asceticism received a formal homage, less and less sincere. But beside them was
the vivid desire of men to know, to dominate, and to possess, the intense interest
inhuman capacity and human fate. Hence came that appetite for personal fame,
for an immortality among future men, which was stimulated by the humanists.
They could not really wish for a personality submerged in the undifferentiated
blessedness of heaven. For the expression of personality, of all that a man
embodied of talent and strength, the Italians used their untranslatable word, virtù;
he should be assessed not by the group or institution to which he belonged, but
by himself, on his naked merits. The century was full of the evils and the triumphs
of this rampant individualism, the crumbling of a social system on its way to
transformation. It is, perhaps, too easy to forget that these years also produced
heroic patriotism, as in Joan of Arc, and unselfish devotion to secular and
Christian learning. These, too, instances as they are of liberated personality,
had their share in the coming of a new age.
In
closing the survey of a wide historical period such as the Middle Ages, the
student must inevitably be impressed by the relativity of history, and be
conscious that he looks at the past through the medium of his own time, that
contemporary perplexities and dominant factors will appear to him in higher
relief among the bygone events he considers. And he will see that this, too,
characterised history as seen by his predecessors. Democratic nationalism
colours the spectacles of one generation, economic problems those of another,
the cataclysm of war those of a third. Then, too, there is the influence of his
personal temperament and prepossessions. The high lights of interest will fall
on different aspects of the panorama. To one it will seem the jostling of an
illimitable throng of men, a profusion of greater and lesser and
indistinguishable stars; to another an almost impersonal conflict and consent of
forces, material or spiritual, themselves diversely perceived and appraised by
his kindred thinkers; to one a catalogue of single things, to another a vast,
dim pattern working itself out with resistless impetus always unforeseen, whose
unending variety is never staled. To different onlookers the same scene will be
sombre or sunlit, the same sound may come plangent or muffled to the ear. For,
had we the precise knowledge, history, which is mankind and all its fortunes,
is too vast to be held in one view and subjected, as a medieval thinker would
have done, to one simple interpretation. We take narrow views of a world of
which each-one of us is an infinitesimal part, secluded within a straitened limit.
Perhaps only one general impression is universal—the turbulent movement, the
infinite perspective and variety, in great things and in small, of that unfathomed
sea.
|