READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
GEORGE GROTE'S HISTORY OF GREECE
CHAPTER 88.
THE DRAMA—RHETORIC AND DIALECTICS—THE SOPHISTS.
Respecting the political history of Athens during the
few years immediately succeeding the restoration of the democracy, we have
unfortunately little or no information. But in the spring of 399 B.C., between
three and four years after the beginning of the archonship of Euclides, an
event happened of paramount interest to the intellectual public of Greece as
well as to philosophy generally—the trial, condemnation, and execution of
Socrates. Before I recount that memorable incident, it will be proper to say a
few words on the literary and philosophical character of the age in which it
happened. Though literature and philosophy are now becoming separate
departments in Greece, each exercises a marked influence on the other ; and the
state of dramatic literature will be seen to be one of the causes directly
contributing to the fate of Socrates.
During the century of the Athenian democracy between Cleisthenes
and Euclides, there had been produced a development of dramatic genius, tragic
and comic, never paralleled before or afterwards. Aeschylus, the creator of the
tragic drama, or at least the first composer who rendered it illustrious, had
been a combatant both at Marathon and Salamis; while Sophocles and
Euripides, his two eminent followers (the former one of the generals of the
Athenian armament against Samos in 440 B.C.), expired both of them only a year
before the battle of Aegospotami—just in time to escape the bitter humiliation
and suffering of that mournful period. Out of the once numerous compositions of
these poets we possess only a few, yet sufficient to enable us to appreciate in
some degree the grandeur of Athenian tragedy; and when we learn that they were
frequently beaten, even with the best of their dramas now remaining, in fair
competition for the prize against other poets whose names only have reached us,
we seem warranted in presuming that the best productions of these successful
competitors, if not intrinsically finer, could hardly have been inferior in
merit to theirs.
The tragic drama belonged essentially to the festivals
in honour of the god Dionysus; being originally a chorus sung in his honour, to
which were successively superadded an Iambic monologue,—next, a dialogue with
two actors,—lastly, a regular plot with three actors, and the chorus itself
interwoven into the scene. Its subjects were from the beginning, and always
continued to be, persons either divine or heroic, above the level of historical
life and borrowed from what was called the mythical past. The Persae of Aeschylus, indeed, forms a splendid
exception; but the two analogous dramas of his contemporary, Phrynichus—the Phoenissae and the capture of Miletus—were not successful
enough to invite subsequent tragedians to meddle with contemporary events. To
three serious dramas or a trilogy—at first connected together by sequence of
subject more or less loose, but afterwards unconnected and on distinct
subjects, through an innovation introduced by Sophocles, if not before—the
tragic poet added a fourth or satirical drama; the characters of which were
satyrs, the companions of the god Dionysus, and other heroic or mythical
persons exhibited in farce. He thus made up a total of four dramas or a
tetralogy, which he got up and brought forward to contend for the prize at the
festival. The expense of training the chorus and actors was chiefly furnished
by the Choregi, wealthy citizens, of whom one
was named for each of the ten tribes, and whose honour and vanity were greatly
interested in obtaining the prize. At first, these exhibitions took place on a
temporary stage, with nothing but wooden supports and scaffolding; but shortly
after the year 500 B.C., on an occasion when the poets Aeschylus and Pratinas
were contending for the prize, this stage gave way during the ceremony, and
lamentable mischief was the result. After that misfortune, a permanent theatre
of stone was provided. To what extent the project was realized before the
invasion of Xerxes, we do not accurately know; but after his destructive
occupation of Athens, the theatre, if any existed previously, would have to be
rebuilt or renovated along with other injured portions of the city.
It was under that great development of the power of
Athens which followed the expulsion of Xerxes that the theatre with its
appurtenances attained full magnitude and elaboration, and Attic tragedy its
maximum of excellence. Sophocles gained his first victory over Aeschylus in 468
B.C.; the first exhibition of Euripides was in 455 B.C. The names, though
unhappily the names alone, of many other competitors have reached us :
Philocles, who gained the prize even over the Oedipus Tyrannus of Sophocles; Euphorion son of Aeschylus, Xenocles,
and Nikomachus, all known to have triumphed over
Euripides; Neophron, Achaeus, Ion, Agathon, and many more. The continuous
stream of new tragedy, poured out year after year, was something new in the
history of the Greek mind. If we could suppose all the ten tribes contending
for the prize every year, there would be ten tetralogies (or sets of four
dramas each, three tragedies and one satirical farce) at the Dionysiac
festival, and as many at the Lenaean. So great a
number as sixty new tragedies composed every year is not to be thought of; yet
we do not know what was the usual number of competing tetralogies : it was at
least three—since the first, second, and third are specified in the Didaskalies or Theatrical Records—and probably
greater than three. It was rare to repeat the same drama a second time, unless
after considerable alterations, nor would it be creditable to the liberality of
a Choregus to decline the full cost of getting
up a new tetralogy. Without pretending to determine with numerical accuracy how
many dramas were composed in each year, the general fact of unexampled
abundance in the productions of the tragic muse is both authentic and
interesting.
Moreover, what is not less important to notice, all
this abundance found its way to the minds of the great body of the citizens,
not excepting even the poorest. For the theatre is said to have accommodated
30,000 persons : here again it is unsafe to rely upon numerical accuracy, but
we cannot doubt that it was sufficiently capacious to give to most of the citizens, poor as well
as rich, ample opportunity of profiting by these beautiful compositions. At
first, the admission to the theatre was gratuitous; but as the crowd, of
strangers as well as freemen, was found both excessive and disorderly, the
system was adopted of asking a price, seemingly at a time when the permanent
theatre was put in complete order after the destruction caused by Xerxes. The
theatre was let by contract to a manager who engaged to defray (either in whole
or part) the habitual cost incurred by the state in the representation, and who
was allowed to sell tickets of admission. At first it appears that the price of
tickets was not fixed, so that the poor citizens were overbid, and could not
get places. Accordingly Perikles introduced a new system, fixing the price of
places at three oboli (or half-a-drachma) for the better, and one obolus for
the less good. As there were two days of representation, tickets covering both
days were sold respectively for a drachma and two oboli. But in order that the
poor citizens might be enabled to attend, two oboli were given out from the
public treasure to each citizen (rich as well as poor, if they chose to receive
it) on the occasion of the festival. A poor man was thus furnished with the
means of purchasing his place and going to the theatre without cost, on both
days, if he chose; or, if he preferred it, he might go on one day only, or
might even stay away altogether and spend both the two oboli in any other
manner. The higher price obtained for the better seats purchased by the richer
citizens is here to be set against the sum disbursed to the poorer; but we have
no data before us for striking the balance, nor can we tell how the finances of
the state were affected by it.
Such was the original Theorikon or festival-pay introduced by Pericles at Athens—a system of distributing the
public money, gradually extending to other festivals in which there was no
theatrical representation, and which in later times reached a mischievous
excess, having begun at a time when Athens was full of money from foreign
tribute, and continuing, with increased demand, at a subsequent time when she
was comparatively poor and without extraneous resources. It is to be remembered
that all these festivals were portions of the ancient religion, and that,
according to the feelings of that time, cheerful and multitudinous assemblages
were essential to the satisfaction of the god in whose honour the festival was
celebrated. Such disbursements were a portion of the religious, even more than
of the civil, establishment. Of the abusive excess which they afterwards
reached, however, I shall speak hereafter : at present I deal with the Theorikon only in its primitive function and effect,
of enabling all Athenians indiscriminately to witness the representation of the
tragedies.
We cannot doubt that the effect of these compositions
upon the public sympathies, as well as upon the public judgment and
intelligence, must have been beneficial and moralizing in a high degree. Though
the subjects and persons are legendary, the relations between them are all
human and simple—exalted above the level of humanity only in such measure as to
present a stronger claim to the hearer’s admiration or pity. So powerful a body
of poetical influence has probably never been brought to act upon the emotions
of any other population; and when we consider the extraordinary beauty of these
immortal compositions, which first stamped tragedy as a separate department of
poetry, and gave to it a dignity never since reached, we shall be satisfied
that the tastes, the sentiments, and the intellectual standard of the Athenian
multitude must have been sensibly improved and exalted by such lessons. The
reception of such pleasures through the eye and the ear, as well as amidst a
sympathizing crowd, was a fact of no small importance in the mental history of
the people. It contributed to exalt their imagination, like the grand edifices
and ornaments added during the same period to their acropolis. Like them too,
and even more than they, tragedy was the monopoly of Athens; for while tragic
composers came thither from other parts of Greece (Achaeus from Eretria, and
Ion from Chios, at a time when the Athenian empire comprised both those places)
to exhibit their genius, nowhere else were original tragedies composed and acted,
though hardly any considerable city was without a theatre.
The three great tragedians—Aeschylus, Sophocles, and
Euripides—distinguished above all their competitors, as well by contemporaries
as by subsequent critics, are interesting to us, not merely from the positive
beauties of each, but also from the differences between them in handling,
style, and sentiment, and from the manner in which these differences illustrate
the insensible modification of the Athenian mind. Though the subjects, persons,
and events of tragedy always continued to be borrowed from the legendary world,
and were thus kept above the level of contemporaneous life—yet the dramatic
manner of handling them is sensibly modified, even in Sophocles as compared
with Aeschylus—and still more in Euripides, by the atmosphere of democracy,
political and judicial contention, and philosophy, encompassing and acting upon the poet
In Aeschylus, the ideality belongs to the handling no less than to the subjects : the passions appealed to
are the masculine and violent, to the exclusion of Aphrodite and her
inspirations : the figures are vast and majestic, but exhibited only in
half-light and in shadowy outline : the speech is replete with bold metaphor
and abrupt transition—“grandiloquent even to a fault” (as Quintilian remarks),
and often approaching nearer to Oriental vagueness than to Grecian perspicuity.
In Sophocles, there is evidently a closer approach to reality and common life:
the range of emotions is more varied, the figures are more distinctly seen, and
the action more fully and conspicuously worked out. Not only we have a more
elaborate dramatic structure, but a more expanded dialogue, and a comparative
simplicity of speech like that of living Greeks : and we find too a certain
admixture of rhetorical declamation, amidst the greatest poetical beauty which
the Grecian drama ever attained. But when we advance to Euripides, this rhetorical
element becomes still more prominent and developed. The ultra-natural sublimity
of the legendary characters disappears; love and compassion are invoked to a
degree which Aeschylus would have deemed inconsistent with the dignity of the
heroic person: moreover there are appeals to the reason, and argumentative
controversies, which that grandiloquent poet would have despised as petty and
forensic cavils. And—what was worse still, judging from the Aeschylean point of
view—there was a certain novelty of speculation, an intimation of doubt on
reigning opinions, and an air of scientific refinement, often spoiling the
poetical effect.
Such differences between these three great poets are
doubtless referable to the working of Athenian politics and Athenian philosophy
on the minds of the two latter. In Sophokles, we may trace the companion of
Herodotus—in Euripides, the hearer of Anaxagoras, Socrates, and Prodicus; in
both, the familiarity with that widespread popularity of speech, and real,
serious debate of politicians and competitors before the dikastery, which both
had ever before their eyes, but which the genius of Sophocles knew how to keep
in due subordination to his grand poetical purpose.
The transformation of the tragic muse from Aeschylus
to Euripides is the more deserving of notice, as it shows us how tragedy served
as the natural prelude and encouragement to the rhetorical and dialectical age
which was approaching. But the democracy, which thus insensibly modified the
tragic drama, imparted a new life and ampler proportions to the comic; both the
one and the other being stimulated by the increasing prosperity and power of
Athens during the last half century following 480 B.C. Not only was the
affluence of strangers and visitors to Athens continually augmenting, but
wealthy men were easily found to incur the expense of training the chorus and
actors. There was no manner of employing wealth which seemed so appropriate to
Grecian feeling, or tended so much to procure influence and popularity to its
possessors, as that of contributing to enhance the magnificence of the national
and religious festivals. This was the general sentiment both among rich and
among poor; nor is there any criticism more unfounded than that which
represents such an obligation as hard and oppressive upon rich men. Most of
them spent more than they were legally compelled to spend in this way, from the
desire of exalting their popularity. The only real sufferers were the people,
considered as interested in a just administration of law; since it was a
practice which enabled many rich men to acquire importance who had no personal
qualities to deserve it—and which provided them with a stock of factitious
merits to be pleaded before the Dikastery, as a set-off against substantive
accusations.
The full splendour of the comic Muse was considerably
later than that of the tragic. Even down to 460 B.C. (about the time when
Pericles and Ephialtes introduced their constitutional reforms), there was not
a single comic poet of eminence at Athens ; nor was there apparently a single
undisputed Athenian comedy before that date, which survived to the times of the
Alexandrine critics. Magnes, Krates, and Cratinus—probably also Chionides and Ekphanoides—all
belong to the period beginning about (Olympiad 80 or) 460 B.C.; that is, the
generation preceding Aristophanes, whose first composition dates in 427 B.C.
The condition and growth of Attic comedy before this period seems to have been
unknown even to Aristotle, who intimates that the archon did not begin to grant
a chorus for comedy, or to number it among the authoritative solemnities of the
festival, until long after the practice had been established for tragedy. Thus
the comic chorus in that early time consisted of volunteers, without any choregus publicly assigned to bear the expense of
teaching them or getting up the piece—so that there was little motive for
authors to bestow care or genius in the preparation of their song, dance, and
scurrilous monody or dialogue. The exuberant revelry of the phallic festival
and procession—with full licence of scoffing at any one present, which the god
Dionysus was supposed to enjoy—and with the most plain-spoken grossness as well
in language as in ideas—formed the primitive germ, which under Athenian genius
ripened into the old comedy. It resembled in many respects the satiric drama of
the tragedians, but was distinguished from it by dealing not merely with the
ancient mythical stories and persons, but chiefly with contemporary men and
subjects of common life—dealing with them often, too, under their real names,
and with ridicule the most direct, poignant, and scornful. We see clearly how
fair a field Athens would offer for this species of composition, at a time when
the bitterness of political contention ran high—when the city had become a
centre for novelties from every part of Greece—when tragedians, rhetors, and
philosophers were acquiring celebrity and incurring odium—and when the
democratical constitution laid open all the details of political and judicial
business, as well as all the first men of the state, not merely to universal
criticism, but also to unmeasured libel.
Out of all the once abundant compositions of Attic
comedy, nothing has reached us except eleven plays of Aristophanes.
That Poet himself singles out Magnes, Crates and Cratts, and Cratinus,
among predecessors whom he describes as numerous, for honourable mention; as
having been frequently, though not uniformly, successful. Kratinus appears to
have been not only the most copious, but also the most distinguished, among all
those who preceded Aristophanes : a list comprising Hermippus,
Telecleides, and the other bitter assailants of Pericles. It was Kratinus who
first extended and systematized the licence of the phallic festival, and the
“careless laughter of the festive crowd,” into a drama of regular structure,
with actors three in number, according to the analogy of tragedy. Standing
forward, against particular persons exhibited or denounced by their names, with
a malignity of personal slander not inferior to the Iambist Archilochus, and
with an abrupt and dithyrambic style somewhat resembling Aeschylus, Kratinus
made an epoch in comedy as the latter had made in tragedy; but was surpassed by
Aristophanes as much as Aeschylus had been surpassed by Sophocles. We are told
that his compositions were not only more rudely bitter and extensively
libellous than those of Aristophanes, but also destitute of that richness of
illustration and felicity of expression which pervades all the wit of the
latter, whether good-natured or malignant. In Kratinus, too, comedy first made
herself felt as a substantive agent and partisan in the political warfare of
Athens. He espoused the cause of Cimon against Pericles ; eulogizing the
former, while he bitterly derided and vituperated the latter. Hermippus, Telecleides, and most of the contemporary comic
writers followed the same political line in assailing that great man, together
with those personally connected with him, Aspasia and Anaxagoras; indeed Hermippus was the person who indicted Aspasia for impiety
before the Dikastery. But the testimony of Aristophanes shows that no comic writer
of the time of Pericles equalled Kratinus either in vehemence of libel or in
popularity.
It is remarkable that in 440 B.C. a law was passed
forbidding comic authors to ridicule any citizen by name in their compositions,
which prohibition, however, was rescinded after two years—an interval marked by
the rare phaenomenon of a lenient comedy from Kratinus. Such enactment denotes
a struggle in the Athenian mind, even at that time, against the mischief of
making the Dionysiac festival an occasion for unmeasured libel against citizens
publicly named and probably themselves present. And there was another style of
comedy taken up by Krates, distinct from the Iambic or Archilochian vein worked
by Kratinus, in which comic incident was attached to fictitious characters and
woven into a story, without recourse to real individual names or direct
personality. This species of comedy (analogous to that which Epicharmus had before exhibited at Syracuse) was continued
by Pherekrates as the successor of Krates. Though for
a long time less popular and successful than the poignant food served up by
Kratinus and others, it became finally predominant after the close of the
Peloponnesian war, by the gradual transition of what is called the Old Comedy
into the Middle and New Comedy.
But it is in Aristophanes that the genius of the old
libellous comedy appears in its culminating perfection. At least we have before
us enough of his works to enable us to appreciate his merits; though perhaps Eupolis, Ameipsias, Phrynicus, Plato (Comicus), and
others, who contended against him at the festivals with alternate victory and
defeat, would be found to deserve similar praise, if we possessed their
compositions. Never, probably, will the full and unshackled force of comedy be
so exhibited again. Without having Aristophanes actually before us, it would
have been impossible to imagine the unmeasured and unsparing licence of attack
assumed by the old comedy upon the gods, the institutions, the politicians,
philosophers, poets, private citizens specially named, and even the women,
whose life was entirely domestic, of Athens. With this universal liberty in
respect of subject there is combined a poignancy of derision and satire, a
fecundity of imagination and variety of turns, and a richness of poetical expression,
such as cannot be surpassed, and such as fully explains the admiration
expressed for him by the philosopher Plato, who in other respects must have
regarded him with unquestionable disapprobation. His comedies are popular in
the largest sense of the word, addressed to the entire body of male citizens on
a day consecrated to festivity, and providing for them amusement or derision
with a sort of drunken abundance, out of all persons or things standing in any
way prominent before the public eye. The earliest comedy of Aristophanes was
exhibited in 427 B.C., and his Muse continued for a long time prolific, since
two of the dramas now remaining belong to an epoch eleven years after the
Thirty and the renovation of the democracy—about 392 B.C. After that
renovation, however (as I have before remarked), the unmeasured sweep and
libellous personality of the old comedy was gradually discontinued; the comic
Chorus was first cut down and afterwards suppressed, so as to usher in what is
commonly termed the Middle Comedy, without any Chorus at all. The “Plutus” of
Aristophanes indicates some approach to this new phase; but his earlier and
more numerous comedies (from the “Acharneis ” in 425
B.C. to the “Frogs” in 405 B.C., only a few months before the fatal battle of
Aegospotami) exhibit the continuous, unexhausted, untempered flow of the stream first opened by Cratinus.
Such abundance both of tragic and comic poetry, each
of first-rate excellence, formed one of the marked features of Athenian life,
and became a powerful instrument in popularizing new combinations of thought
with Athenian variety and elegance of expression. While the tragic Muse
presented the still higher advantage of inspiring elevated and benevolent
sympathies, more was probably lost than gained by the lessons of the comic
Muse, not only bringing out keenly all that was really ludicrous or
contemptible in the phenomena of the day, but manufacturing scornful laughter,
quite as often out of that which was innocent or even meritorious as well as
out of boundless private slander. The “Knights” and the “Wasps” of
Aristophanes, however, not to mention other plays are a standing evidence of
one good point in the Athenian character—that they bore with good-natured
indulgence the full outpouring of ridicule and even of calumny interwoven with
it, upon those democratical institutions to which they were sincerely attached.
The democracy was strong enough to tolerate unfriendly tongues either in
earnest or in jest; the reputations of men who stood conspicuously forward in
politics, on whatever side, might also be considered as a fair mark for
attacks, inasmuch as that measure of aggressive criticism, which is tutelary
and indispensable, cannot be permitted without the accompanying evil,
comparatively much smaller, of excess and injustice; though even here we may
remark that excess of bitter personality is among the most conspicuous sins of
Athenian literature generally. But the warfare of comedy, in the persons of
Aristophanes and other composers, against philosophy, literature, and
eloquence, in the name of those good old times of ignorance, “when an Athenian
seaman knew nothing more than how to call for his barley-cake, and cry Yo-ho,” and the retrograde spirit which induces them to
exhibit moral turpitude as the natural consequence of the intellectual progress
of the age, are circumstances going far to prove an unfavourable and degrading
influence of Comedy on the Athenian mind.
In reference to individual men, and to Socrates
especially, the Athenians seem to have been unfavourably biassed by the
misapplied wit and genius of Aristophanes in “The Clouds,” aided by other
Comedies of Ameipsias and Eupolis;
but on the general march of politics, philosophy, or letters, these composers
had little influence. Nor were they ever regarded at Athens in the light in
which they are presented to us by modem criticism—as men of exalted morality,
stern patriotism, and genuine discernment of the true interests of their
country—as animated by large and steady views of improving their
fellow-citizens, but compelled, in consequence of prejudice or opposition, to
disguise a far-sighted political philosophy under the veil of satire—as good
judges of the most debateable questions, such as the prudence of making war or
peace—and excellent authority to guide us in appreciating the merits or
demerits of their contemporaries, insomuch that the victims of their lampoons
are habitually set down as worthless men. There cannot be a greater
misconception of the old comedy than to regard it in this point of view; yet it
is astonishing how many subsequent writers (from Diodorus and Plutarch down to
the present day) have thought themselves entitled to deduce their facts of
Grecian history, and their estimate of Grecian men, events, and institutions,
from the comedies of Aristophanes. Standing pre-eminent as the latter does in
comic genius, his point of view is only so much the more determined by the
ludicrous associations suggested to his fancy, so that he thus departs the more
widely from the conditions of a faithful witness or candid critic. He presents
himself to provoke the laugh, mirthful or spiteful, of the festival crowd,
assembled for the gratification of these emotions, and not with any expectation
of serious or reasonable impressions. Nor does he at all conceal how much he is
mortified by failure; like the professional jester, or “laughtermaker,”
at the banquets of rich Athenian citizens, the parallel of Aristophanes as to
purpose, however unworthy of comparison in every other respect.
This rise and development of dramatic poetry in
Greece—so abundant, so varied, and so rich in genius—belongs to the fifth
century B.C. It had been in the preceding century nothing more than an
unpretending graft upon the primitive chorus, and was then even denounced by
Solon (or in the dictum ascribed to Solon) as a vicious novelty, tending—by its
simulation of a false character, and by “its effusion of sentiments not genuine
or sincere—to corrupt the integrity of human dealings; a charge of corruption not
unlike that which Aristophanes worked up a century afterwards, in his “Clouds,”
against physics, rhetoric, and dialectics, in the person of Socrates. But the
properties of the graft had overpowered and subordinated those of the original
stem; so that dramatic poetry was now a distinct form, subject to laws of its
own, and shining with splendour equal, if not superior, to the elegiac, choric,
lyric, and epic poetry which constituted the previous stock of the Grecian
world.
Such transformations in the poetry—or, to speak more
justly, in the literature, for before the year 500 B.C. the two
compared expressions were equivalent—of Greece were at once products,
marks, and auxiliaries in the expansion of the national mind. Our minds
have now become familiar with dramatic combinations, which have
ceased to be peculiar to any special form or conditions of political society.
But if we compare the fifth century B.C. with that which preceded it, the recently
born drama will be seen to have been a most important and impressive novelty :
and so assuredly it would have been regarded by Solon, the largest mind of his
own age, if he could have risen again a century and a quarter after his death,
to witness the Antigone of Sophokles, the Medea of Euripides, or the Archameis of Aristophanes.
Its novelty does not consist merely in the high order
of imagination and judgment required for the construction of a drama at once
regular and effective. This, indeed, is no small addition to Grecian poetical
celebrity as it stood in the days of Solon, Alkaeus, Sappho, and Stesichorus;
but we must remember that the epical structure of the Odyssey, so ancient and
long acquired to the Hellenic world, implies a reach of architectonic talent
quite equal to that exhibited in the most symmetrical drama of Sophocles. The
great innovation of the dramatists consisted in the rhetorical, the
dialectical, and the ethical spirit which they breathed into their poetry. Of
all this, the undeveloped germ doubtless existed in the previous epic, lyric,
and gnomic composition ; but the drama stood distinguished from all three by
bringing it out into conspicuous amplitude, and making it the substantive means
of effect. Instead of recounting exploits achieved or sufferings undergone by
the heroes—instead of pouring out his own single-minded impressions in
reference to some given event or juncture—the tragic poet produces the mythical
persons themselves, to talk, discuss, accuse, defend, confute, lament,
threaten, advise, persuade, or appease, among one another, but before the audience.
In the drama (a singular misnomer) nothing is actually done : all is talk,
assuming what is done as passing, or as having passed, elsewhere. The dramatic
poet, speaking continually, but each moment through a different character,
carries on the purpose of each of his characters by words calculated to
influence the other characters and appropriate to each successive juncture.
Here are rhetorical exigences from beginning to end; while since the whole
interest of the piece turns upon some contention or struggle carried on by
speech—since debate, consultation, and retort never cease—since every
character, good or evil, temperate or violent, must be supplied with suitable
language to defend his proceedings, to attack or repel opponents, and generally
to make good the relative importance assigned to him—here again dialectical
skill in no small degree is indispensable.
Lastly, the strength and variety of ethical sentiment
infused into the Grecian tragedy are among the most remarkable characteristics
which distinguish it from the anterior forms of poetry. “ To do or suffer
terrible things ” is pronounced by Aristotle to be its proper subject-matter;
and the internal mind and motives of drama, the doer or sufferer, on which the
ethical interest fastens, are laid open by the Greek tragedians with an
impressive minuteness which neither the epic nor the lyric could possibly parallel.
Moreover, the appropriate subject-matter of tragedy is pregnant not only with
ethical sympathy, but also with ethical debate and speculation. Characters of
mixed good and evil—distinct rules of duty, one conflicting with the
other—wrong done, and justified to the conscience of the doer, if not to that
of the spectator, by previous wrong suffered,—all these are the favourite
themes of Aeschylus and his two great successors. Clytaemnestra kills her
husband Agamemnon on his return from Troy: her defence is, that he had deserved
this treatment at her hands for having sacrificed his own and her daughter
Iphigeneia. Her son Orestes kills her, under a full conviction of the duty of
avenging his father, and even under the sanction of Apollo. The retributive
Eumenides pursue him for the deed, and Aeschylus brings all the parties before
the court of Areopagus with Athene as president; where the case, being fairly
argued, with the Eumenides as accusers and Apollo as counsel for the prisoner,
ends by an equality of votes in the court: upon which Athene gives her
casting-vote to absolve Orestes. Again, let any man note the conflicting
obligations which Sophocles so forcibly brings in his beautiful drama of the
Antigone. Kreon directs that the body of Polyneikes,
as a traitor and recent invader of the country, shall remain unburied :
Antigone, sister of Polyneikes, denounces such
interdict as impious, and violates it, under an overruling persuasion of
fraternal duty. Kreon having ordered her to be buried alive, his youthful son
Haemon, her betrothed lover, is plunged into a heartrending conflict between
abhorrence of such cruelty on the one side, and submission to his father on the
other. Sophocles sets forth both these contending rules of duty in an elaborate
scene of dialogue between the father and the son. Here are two rules both
sacred and respectable, but the one of which cannot be observed without
violating the other. Since a choice must be made, which of the two ought a good
man to obey? This is a point which the great poet is well pleased to leave
undetermined. But if there be any among the audience in whom the least impulse
of intellectual speculation is alive, he will by no means leave it so, without
some mental effort to solve the problem, and to discover some grand and
comprehensive principle from whence all the moral rules emanate—a principle
such as may instruct his conscience in those cases generally, of not infrequent
occurrence, wherein two obligations conflict with each other. The tragedian not
only appeals more powerfully to the ethical sentiment than poetry had ever done
before, but also, by raising these grave and touching questions, addresses a
stimulus and challenge to the intellect, spurring it on to ethical speculation.
Putting all these points together, we see how much
wider was the intellectual range of tragedy, and how considerable is the mental
progress which it betokens, as compared with the lyric and gnomic poetry, or
with the Seven Wise Men and their authoritative aphorisms, which formed the
glory and marked the limit of the preceding century. In place of unexpanded
results, or the mere communication of single-minded sentiment, we have even in
Aeschylus, the earliest of the great tragedians, a large latitude of dissent
and debate—a shifting point of view—a case better or worse, made out for
distinct and contending parties—and a divination of the future advent of
sovereign and instructed reason. It was through the intermediate stage of
tragedy that Grecian literature passed into the Rhetoric, Dialectics, and
Ethical speculation, which marked the fifth century B.C.
Other simultaneous causes, arising directly out of the
business of real life, contributed to the generation of these same capacities
and studies. The fifth century B.C. is the first century of democracy, at
Athens, at Sicily, and elsewhere : moreover, at that period, beginning from the
Ionic revolt and the Persian invasions of Greece, the political relations
between one Grecian city and another became more complicated, as well as more
continuous; requiring a greater measure of talent in the public men who managed
them. Without some power of persuading or confuting —of defending himself
against accusation, or, in case of need, accusing others—no man could possibly
hold an ascendant position. He had probably not less need of this talent for
private, informal conversations to satisfy his own political partisans, than
for addressing the public assembly formally convoked. Even as commanding an
army or a fleet, without any laws of war or habits of professional discipline,
his power of keeping up the good humour, confidence, and prompt obedience of
his men, depended not a little on his command of speech. Nor was it only to the
leaders in political life that such an accomplishment was indispensable. In all
the democracies—and probably in several governments which were not democracies
but oligarchies of an open character—the courts of justice were more or less
numerous, and the procedure oral and public : in Athens especially, the Dikasteries (whose constitution has been explained in a
former chapter) were both very numerous, and paid for attendance. Every citizen
had to go before them in person, without being able to send a paid advocate in
his place, if he either required redress fur wrong offered to himself, or was
accused of wrong by another. There was no man, therefore, who might not be cast
or condemned, or fail in his own suit, even with right on his side, unless he
possessed some powers of speech to unfold his case to the Dikasts,
as well as to confute the falsehoods and disentangle the sophistry of an
opponent. Moreover, to any man of known family and station, it would he a
humiliation hardly less painful than the loss of the cause, when standing
before the Dikastery with friends and enemies around him, to find himself
unable to carry on the thread of a discourse without halting or confusion. To
meet such liabilities, from which no citizen, rich or poor, was exempt, a
certain training in speech became not less essential than a certain training in
arms. Without the latter, he could not do his duty as an hoplite in the ranks
for the defence of his country ; without the former, he could not escape danger
to his fortune or honour, and humiliation in the eyes of his friends, if called
before a Dikastery; nor could he lend assistance to any of those friends who
might be placed under the like necessity.
Here then were ample motives, arising out of practical
prudence not less than from the stimulus of ambition, to cultivate the power of
both continuous harangue and of concise argumentation, or interrogation and
reply: motives for all, to acquire a certain moderate aptitude in the use of
these weapons—for the ambitious few, to devote much labour and to shine as
accomplished orators.
Such political and social motives, it is to be
remembered, though acting very forcibly at Athens, were by no means peculiar to
Athens, but prevailed more or less throughout a large portion of the Grecian
cities, especially in Sicily, when all the Governments became popularized after
the overthrow of the Gelonian dynasty. And it was in
Sicily and Italy that the first individuals arose who acquired permanent name
both in Rhetoric and Dialectics; Empedocles of Agrigentum in the former—Zeno of
Elea (in Italy) in the latter.
But these distinguished men bore a conspicuous part in
politics, and both on the popular side; Empedocles against an oligarchy, Zeno
against a despot. But both also were yet more distinguished as philosophers;
and the dialectical impulse in Zeno, if not the rhetorical impulse in
Empedocles, came more from his philosophy than from his politics. Empedocles
(about 470—440 B.C.) appears to have held intercourse at least, if not partial
communion of doctrine, with the dispersed philosophers of the Pythagorean league;
the violent subversion of which, at Croton and elsewhere, I have related in a
previous chapter. He constructed a system of physics and cosmogony,
distinguished for first broaching the doctrine of the Four Elements, and set
forth in a poem composed by himself: besides which he seems to have had much of
the mystical tone and miraculous pretensions of Pythagoras; professing not only
to cure pestilence and other distempers, but to teach how old age might be
averted and the dead raised from Hades—to prophesy—and to raise and calm the
winds at his pleasure. Gorgias his pupil deposed that he had been present at
the magical ceremonies of Empedocles. The impressive character of his poem is
sufficiently attested by the admiration of Lucretius, and the rhetoric ascribed
to him may have consisted mainly in oral teaching or exposition of the same
doctrines. Tisias and Korax of Syracuse, who are also mentioned as the first teachers of rhetoric—and the
first who made known any precepts about the rhetorical practice—were his
contemporaries; while the celebrated Gorgias was his pupil.
The dialectical movement emanated at the same time
from the Eleatic school of philosophers—Zeno, and his contemporary the Samian Melissus (460—440 B.C.)—if not from their common teacher
Parmenides. Melissus also, as well as Zeno and
Empedocles, was a distinguished citizen, as well as a philosopher, having been,
in command of the Samian fleet at the time of the revolt from Athens, and
having in that capacity gained a victory over the Athenians.
All the philosophers of the fifth century B.C., prior
to Socrates, inheriting from their earliest poetical predecessors the vast and
unmeasured problems which had once been solved by the supposition of divine or
superhuman agents, contemplated the world, physical and moral, all in a mass,
and applied their minds to find some hypothesis which would give explanation of
this totality, or at least appease curiosity by something which looked like an
explanation. What were the elements out of which sensible things were made?
What was the initial cause or principle of those changes which appeared to our
senses? What was change?—was it generation or something integrally new, and
destruction of something pre-existent—or was it a decomposition and
recombination of elements still continuing? The theories of the various Ionic
philosophers and of Empedocles after them, admitting one, two, or four
elementary substances, with Friendship and Enmity to serve as causes of motion
or change—the Homoeomeries of Anaxagoras, with Nous
or Intelligence as the stirring and regularizing agent—the atoms and void of
Leucippus and Democritus—all these were different hypotheses answering to a
similar vein of thought. All of them, though assuming that the sensible
appearances of things were delusive and perplexing, nevertheless were borrowed
more or less directly from some of these appearances, which were employed to
explain and illustrate the whole theory, and served to render it plausible when
stated as well as to defend it against attack. But the philosophers of the
Eleatic school—first Xenophanes, and after him Parmenides—took a distinct path
of their own. To find that which was real, and which lay as it were concealed
behind or under the delusive phenomena of sense, they had recourse only to
mental abstractions. They supposed a Substance or Something not perceivable by
sense, but only cogitable or conceivable by reason; a One and All, continuous
and finite, which was not only real and self-existent, but was the only
reality—eternal, immovable and unchangeable, and the only matter knowable. The
phenomena of sense, which began and ended one after the other (they thought),
were essentially delusive, uncertain, contradictory among themselves, and open
to endless diversity of opinion. Upon these, nevertheless, they announced an
opinion; adopting two elements—heat and cold, or light and darkness.
Parmenides set forth this doctrine of the One and All
in a poem, of which but a few fragments now remain, so that we understand very
imperfectly the positive arguments employed to recommend it. The matter of
truth and knowledge, such as he alone admitted, was altogether removed from the
senses and divested of sensible properties, so as to be conceived only as an Ens
Rationis, and described and discussed only in the most general words of the
language. The exposition given by Parmenides in his poem, though complimented
by Plato, was vehemently controverted by others, who deduced from it many
contradictions and absurdities. As a part of his reply,—and doubtless the
strongest part,—Parmenides retorted upon his adversaries— an example followed
by his pupil Zeno with still greater acuteness and success. Those who
controverted his ontological theory—that the real, ultra-phenomenal substance
was One—affirmed it to be not One, but Many; divisible, movable, changeable,
&c. Zeno attacked this latter theory, and proved that it led to
contradictions and absurdities still greater than those involved in the
proposition of Parmenides. He impugned the testimony of sense, affirming that
it furnished premises for conclusions which contradicted each other, and that
it was unworthy of trust. Parmenides had denied that there was any such thing
as real change either of place or colour : Zeno maintained change of place or
motion to be impossible and self-contradictory; propounding many logical
difficulties, derived from the infinite divisibility of matter, against some of
the most obvious affirmations respecting sensible phenomena. Melissus appears to have argued in a vein similar to that
of Zeno, though with much less acuteness; demonstrating indirectly the doctrine
of Parmenides by deducing impossible inferences from the contrary hypothesis.
Zeno published a treatise to maintain the thesis above
described, which he also upheld by personal conversations and discussions, in a
manner doubtless far more efficacious than his writing ; the oral teaching of
these early philosophers being their really impressive manifestation. His
subtle dialectic arguments were not only sufficient to occupy all the
philosophers of antiquity, in confuting them more or less successfully, but
have even descended to modern times as a fire not yet extinguished. The great effect
produced among the speculative minds of Greece by his writing and conversation,
is attested both by Plato and Aristotle. He visited Athens, gave instruction to
some eminent Athenians, for high pay, and is said to have conversed both with
Pericles and with Socrates, at a time when the latter was very young, probably
between 450—440 B.C.
His appearance constitutes a remarkable era in Grecian
philosophy, because he first brought out the extraordinary aggressive or
negative force of the dialectic method. In this discussion respecting the One
and the Many, positive grounds on either side were alike scanty : each party
had to set forth the contradictions deducible from the opposite hypothesis, and
Zeno professed to show that those of his opponents were the more flagrant. We
thus see that along with the methodized question and answer, or dialectic
method, employed from henceforward more and more in philosophical inquiries,
comes out at the same time the negative tendency, the probing, testing, and
scrutinizing force, of Grecian speculation. The negative side of Grecian
speculation stands quite as prominently marked, and occupies as large a measure
of the intellectual force of their philosophers, as the positive side. It is
not simply to arrive at a conclusion, sustained by a certain measure of
plausible premise—and then to proclaim it as an authoritative dogma, silencing
or disparaging all objectors—that Grecian speculation aspires. To unmask not
only positive falsehood, but even affirmation without evidence, exaggerated
confidence in what was only doubtful, and show of knowledge without the reality—to
look at a problem on all sides, and set forth all the difficulties attending
its solution— to take account of deductions from the affirmative evidence, even
in the case of conclusions accepted as true upon the balance—all this will be
found pervading the march of their greatest thinkers. As a condition, of all
progressive philosophy, it is not less essential that the grounds of negation
should be freely exposed than the grounds of affirmation. We shall find the two
going hand in hand, and the negative vein indeed the more impressive and
characteristic of the two, from Zeno downwards in our history. In one of the
earliest memoranda illustrative of Grecian dialectics—the sentences wherein
Plato represents Parmenides and Zeno as bequeathing their mantle to the
youthful Socrates, and giving him precepts for successfully prosecuting those
researches which his marked inquisitive impulse promised—this large and
comprehensive point of view is emphatically inculcated. He is admonished to set
before him both sides of every hypothesis, and to follow out both the negative
and the affirmative chains of argument with equal perseverance and equal
freedom of scrutiny; neither daunted by the adverse opinions around him, nor
deterred by sneers against wasting time in fruitless talk ; since the multitude
are ignorant that without thus travelling round all sides of a question, no
assured comprehension of the truth is attainable.
We thus find ourselves, from the year 450 B.C.
downwards, in presence of two important classes of men in Greece, unknown to
Solon or even to Cleisthenes—the Rhetoricians and the Dialecticians; for whom
(as has been shown) the ground had been gradually prepared by the polities, the
poetry, and the speculation of the preceding period.
Both these two novelties—like the poetry and other
accomplishments of this memorable race—grew up from rude indigenous beginnings,
under native stimulus unborrowed and unassisted from without. The rhetorical
teaching was an attempt to assist and improve men in the power of continuous
speech as addressed to assembled numbers, such as the public assembly or the
dikastery; it was therefore a species of training sought for by men of active
pursuits and ambition, either that they might succeed in public life, or that
they might maintain their rights and dignity if called before the court of
justice. On the other hand, the dialectic business had no direct reference to
public life, to the judicial pleading, or to any assembled large number. It was
a dialogue carried on by two disputants, usually before a few hearers, to
unravel some obscurity, to reduce the respondent to silence and contradiction,
to exercise both parties in mastery of the subject, or to sift the consequences
of some problematical assumption. It was spontaneous conversation systematized
and turned into some predetermined channel; furnishing a stimulus to thought,
and a means of improvement not attainable in any other manner—furnishing to
some also a source of profit or display. It opened a line of serious
intellectual pursuit to men of a speculative or inquisitive turn, who were
deficient in voice, in boldness, in continuous memory, for public speaking; or
who desired to keep themselves apart from the political and judicial
animosities of the moment.
Although there were numerous Athenians, who combined,
in various proportions, speculative with practical study, yet, generally
speaking, the two veins of intellectual movement—one towards active public
business, the other towards enlarged opinions and greater command of
speculative truth, with its evidences—continued simultaneous and separate.
There subsisted between them a standing polemical controversy and a spirit of
mutual detraction. If Plato despised the sophists and the rhetors, Isokrates
thinks himself not less entitled to disparage those who employed their time in
debating upon the unity or plurality of virtue. Even among different teachers,
in the same intellectual walk, also, there prevailed but too often an
acrimonious feeling of personal rivalry, which laid them all so much the more
open to assault from the common enemy of all mental progress—a feeling of
jealous ignorance, stationary or wistfully retrospective, of no mean force at
Athens, as in every other society, and of course blended at Athens with the
indigenous democratical sentiment. This latter sentiment of antipathy to new
ideas and new mental accomplishments has been raised into factitious importance
by the comic genius of Aristophanes, whose point of view modern authors have
too often accepted ; thus allowing some of the worst feelings of Grecian
antiquity to influence their manner of conceiving the facts. Moreover, they
have rarely made any allowance for that force of literary and philosophical
antipathy, which was no less real and constant at Athens than the political,
and which made the different literary classes or individuals perpetually unjust
one towards another.
It was the blessing and the glory of Athens that every
man could speak out his sentiments and his criticisms with a freedom
unparalleled in the ancient world, and hardly paralleled even in the modern, in
which a vast body of dissent both is, and always has been, condemned to
absolute silence. But this known latitude of censure ought to have imposed on
modern authors a peremptory necessity of not accepting implicitly the censure
of any one, where the party inculpated has left no defence; at the very least,
of construing the censure strictly, and allowing for the point of view from
which it proceeds. From inattention to this necessity, almost all the things
and persons of Grecian history are presented to us on their bad side : the
libels of Aristophanes, the sneers of Plato and Xenophon—even the interested
generalities of a plaintiff or defendant before the Dikastery—are received with
little cross-examination as authentic materials for history.
If ever there was need to invoke this rare sentiment
of candour, it is when we come to discuss the history of the persons called
Sophists, who now for the first time appear as of note; the practical teachers
of Athens and of Greece, misconceived as well as misesteemed.
The primitive education at Athens consisted of two
branches— gymnastics, for the body; music, for the mind. The word music is not to be judged according to the limited signification which it now bears.
It comprehended from the beginning everything appertaining to the province of
the Nine Muses—not merely learning the use of the lyre, or how to bear part in
a chorus, but also the hearing, learning, and repeating of poetical
compositions, as well as the practice of exact and elegant pronunciation—which
latter accomplishment, in a language like the Greek, with long words, measured
syllables, and great diversity of accentuation between one word and another,
must have been far more difficult to acquire than it is in any modern European
language. As the range of ideas enlarged, so the words music and musical
teachers acquired an expanded meaning, so as to comprehend matter of
instruction at once ampler and more diversified. During the middle of the fifth
century B.C., at Athens, there came thus to be found, among the musical
teachers, men of the most distinguished abilities and eminence ; masters of all
the learning and accomplishments of the age, teaching what was. known of
astronomy, geography, and physics, and capable of holding dialectical
discussions with their pupils upon all the various problems then afloat among
intellectual men. Of this character were Lamprus,
Agathocles, Pythokleides, Damon, &c. The two
latter were instructors of Pericles; and Damon was even rendered so unpopular
at Athens, partly by his large and free speculations, partly through the
political enemies of his great pupil, that he was ostracised, or at least
sentenced, to banishment. Such men were competent companions for Anaxagoras and
Zeno, and employed in part on the same studies, the field of acquired knowledge
being not then large enough to be divided into separate exclusive compartments.
While Euripides frequented the company and acquainted himself with the opinions
of Anaxagoras, Ion of Chios (his rival as a tragic poet, as well as the friend
of Kimon) bestowed so much thought upon physical subjects as then conceived,
that he set up a theory of his own, propounding the doctrine of three elements
in nature—air, fire, and earth.
Now such musical teachers as Damon and the others
above mentioned were Sophists, not merely in the natural and proper Greek sense
of that word, but, to a certain meaning of extent, even in the special and
restricted meaning which Plato afterwards thought proper to confer upon it. A
Sophist, in the genuine sense of the word, was a wise man—a clever man—one who
stood prominently before the public as distinguished for intellect or talent of
some kind. Thus Solon and Pythagoras are both called Sophists; Thamyras, the skilful bard, is called a Sophist: Socrates
is so denominated, not merely by Aristophanes, but by Aeschines: Aristotle
himself calls Aristippus, anil Xenophon calls Antisthenes, both of them
disciples of Socrates, by that name : Xenophon, in describing a collection of
instructive books, calls them “the writings of the old poets and Sophists,”
meaning by the latter word prose writers generally : Plato is alluded to as a
Sophist, even by Isokrates : Aeschines (the disciple of Socrates, not the orator)
was so denominated by his contemporary Lysias: Isokrates himself was harshly
criticized as a Sophist, and defends both himself and his profession : lastly,
Timon (the friend and admirer of Pyrrho, about
300—280 B.C.), who bitterly satirized all the philosophers, designated them
all, including Plato and Aristotle, by the general name of Sophists. In this
large and comprehensive sense the word was originally used, and always
continued to be so understood, among the general public. But, along with this
idea, the title Sophist also carried with it or connoted a certain invidious
feeling. The natural temper of a people generally ignorant towards superior
intellect—the same temper which led to those charges of magic so frequent in
the Middle Ages—appears to be a union of admiration with something of an
unfavourable sentiment, dislike or apprehension, as the case may be; unless
where the latter element has become neutralized by habitual respect for an
established profession or station. At any rate, the unfriendly sentiment is so
often intended, that a substantive word, in which it is implied without the
necessity of any annexed predicate, is soon found convenient. Timon, who hated
the philosophers, thus found the word Sophist exactly suitable, in sentiment as
well as meaning, to his purpose in addressing them.
Now when (in the period succeeding 450 B.C.) the
rhetorical and musical teachers came to stand before the public at Athens in
such increased eminence, they of course, as well as other men intellectually
celebrated, became designated by the appropriate name of Sophists. But there
was one characteristic peculiar to themselves whereby they drew upon themselves
a double measure of that invidious sentiment which lay wrapped up in the name.
They taught for pay : of course therefore the most eminent among them taught
only the rich, and earned large sums—a fact naturally provocative of envy, to
some extent, among the many who benefited nothing by them, but still more among
the inferior members of their own profession. Even great minds like Socrates
and Plato, though much superior to any such envy, cherished in that age a
genuine and vehement repugnance against receiving pay for teaching. We read in
Xenophon that Sokrates considered such a bargain as nothing less than
servitude, robbing the teacher of all free choice as to persons or proceeding;
and that he assimilated the relation between teacher and pupil to that between
two lovers or two intimate friends, which was thoroughly dishonoured, robbed of
its charm and reciprocity, and prevented from bringing about its legitimate
reward of attachment and devotion, by the intervention of money payment.
However little in harmony with modern ideas, such was the conscientious
sentiment of Socrates and Plato, who therefore considered the name Sophist,
denoting intellectual celebrity combined with an odious association, as
pre-eminently suitable to the leading teachers for pay. The splendid genius,
the lasting influence, and the reiterated polemics of Plato have stamped it
upon the men against whom he wrote as if it were their recognized, legitimate,
and peculiar designation; though it is certain that if, in the middle of the
Peloponnesian war, any Athenian had been asked, “Who are the principal Sophists
in your city?”, he would have named Socrates among the first; for Socrates was
at once eminent as an intellectual teacher, and personally unpopular, not
because he received pay, but on other grounds which will be hereafter noticed;
and this was the precise combination of qualities which the general public
naturally expressed by a Sophist. Moreover, Plato not only stole the name out
of general circulation in order to fasten it specially upon his opponents the
paid teachers, but also connected with it express discreditable attributes,
which formed no part of its primitive and recognized meaning, and were
altogether distinct from, though grafted upon, the vague sentiment of dislike
associated with it. Aristotle, following the example of his master, gave to the
word Sophist a definition substantially the same as that which it bears in the
modern languages—“an imposturous pretender to knowledge; a man who employs what
he knows to he fallacy, for the purpose of deceit and of getting money”. And he
did this at a time when he himself, with his estimable contemporary Isokrates,
were considered at Athens to come under the designation of Sophists, and were
called so by every one who disliked either their profession or their persons.
Great thinkers and writers, like Plato and Aristotle,
have full right to define and employ words in a sense of their own, provided
they give due notice. But it is essential that the reader should keep in mind
the consequences of such change, and not mistake a word used in a new sense for
a new fact or phenomenon. The age with which we are now dealing (the last half
of the fifth Century.) is commonly distinguished in the history of philosophy
as the age of Socrates and the Sophists. The Sophists are spoken of as a new
class of men, or sometimes in language which implies a new doctrinal set or
school, as if they then sprang up in Greece for the first time—ostentatious
impostors, flattering and duping the rich youth for their own personal gain,
undermining the morality of Athens public and private, and encouraging their
pupils to the unscrupulous prosecution of ambition and cupidity. They are even
affirmed to have succeeded in corrupting the general morality, so that Athens
had become miserably degenerated and vicious in the latter years of the
Peloponnesian war, as compared with what she was in the time of Miltiades and
Aristeides. Socrates, on the contrary, is usually described as a holy man
combating and exposing these false prophets—standing up as the champion of
morality against their insidious artifices. Now, though the appearance of a man
so very original as Socrates was a new fact, of unspeakable importance, the
appearance of the Sophists was no new fact; what was new was the peculiar use
of an old word which Plato took out of its usual meaning, and fastened upon the
eminent paid teachers of the Socratic age.
The paid teachers, with whom, under the name of The
Sophists, he brings Socrates into controversy, were Protagoras of Abdera,
Gorgias of Leontini, Polus of Agrigentum, Hippias of Elis, Prodikus of Keos, Thrasymachus of Chalcedon, Euthydemus and Dionysodorus of Chios : Protagoras, to whom Xenophon adds Antiphon of Athens. These men—whom
modern writers set down as The Sophists, and denounce as the moral pestilence
of their age—were not distinguished in any marked or generic way from their
predecessors. Their vocation was to train up youth for the duties, the
pursuits, and the successes of active life, both private and public. Others had
done this before; but these teachers brought to the task a larger range of
knowledge, with a greater multiplicity of scientific and other topics—not only
more impressive powers of composition and speech, serving as a personal example
to the pupil, but also a comprehension of the elements of good speaking, so as
to be able to give precepts conducive to that accomplishment—a considerable
treasure of accumulated thought on moral and political subjects, calculated to
make their conversation very instructive—and discourse ready prepared, on
general heads or commonplaces, for their pupils to learn by heart. But this,
though a very important extension, was nothing more than an extension,
differing merely in degree, of that which Damon and others had done before
them. It arose from the increased demand which had grown up among the Athenian
youth for a larger measure of education and other accomplishments; from an
elevation in the standard of what was required from every man who aspired to
occupy a place in the eyes of his fellow-citizens. Protagoras, Gorgias, and the
rest supplied this demand with an ability and success unknown before their
time: hence they gained a distinction such as none of their predecessors had
attained, were prized all over Greece, travelled from city to city with general
admiration, and obtained considerable pay. While such success, among men
personally strangers to them, attests unequivocally their talent and personal
dignity, of course it also laid them open to increased jealousy, as well from
inferior teachers as from the lovers of ignorance generally; such jealousy
manifesting itself (as I have before explained) by a greater readiness to stamp
them with the obnoxious title of Sophists.
The hostility of Plato against these teachers (for it
is he, and not Socrates, who was peculiarly hostile to them, as may be seen by
the absence of any such marked antithesis in the Memorabilia of Xenophon) may
be explained without at all supposing in them that corruption which modern
writers have been so ready not only to admit but to magnify. It arose from the
radical difference between his point of view and theirs. He was a great
reformer and theorist: they undertook to qualify young men for doing themselves
credit, and rendering service to others, in active Athenian life. Not only is
there room for the concurrent operation of both these veins of thought and
action, in every progressive society, but the intellectual outfit of the
society can never be complete without the one as well as the other. It was the
glory of Athens that both were there adequately represented, at the period
which we have now reached. Whoever peruses Plato’s immortal work—The
Republic—will see that he dissented from society, both democratical and
oligarchical, on some of the most fundamental points of public and private
morality; and throughout most of his dialogues his quarrel is not less with the
statesmen, past as well as present, than with the paid teachers of Athens.
Besides this ardent desire for radical reform of the state, on principles of
his own, distinct from every recognized political party or creed, Plato was
also unrivalled as a speculative genius and as a dialectician; both which
capacities he put forth, to amplify and illustrate the ethical theory and method
first struck out by Socrates, as well as to establish, comprehensive
generalities of his own.
Now his reforming, as well as his theorizing
tendencies, brought him into polemical controversy with all the leading agents
by whom the business of practical life at Athens was carried on. In so far as
Protagoras or Gorgias talked the language of theory, they were doubtless much
inferior to Plato, nor would their doctrines be likely to hold against his
acute dialectics. But it was neither their duty nor their engagement to reform
the state, or discover and vindicate the best theory on ethics. They professed
to qualify young Athenians for an active and honourable life, private as well
as public, in Athens (or in any other given city) : they taught them “to
think, speak, and act,” in Athens; they of course accepted, as the basis
of their teaching, that type of character which estimable men exhibited, and
which the public approved, in Athens—not undertaking to recast the type,
but to arm it with new capacities and adorn it with fresh accomplishments.
Their direct business was with ethical precept, not with ethical theory : all
that was required of them as to the latter was that their theory should be
sufficiently sound to lead to such practical precepts as were accounted
virtuous by the most estimable society in Athens. It ought never to be
forgotten that those who taught for active life were bound by the very
conditions of their profession to adapt themselves to the place and the society
as it stood. With the Theorist Plato, not only there was no such obligation,
but the grandeur and instructiveness of his speculations were realized only by
his departing from it, and placing himself on a loftier pinnacle of vision ;
while he himself not only admits, but even exaggerates, the unfitness and
repugnance, of men taught in his school, for practical life and duties.
To understand the essential difference between the
practical and the theoretical point of view, we need only look to Isokrates,
the pupil of Gorgias, and himself a Sophist. Though not a man of commanding
abilities, Isokrates was one of the most estimable men of Grecian antiquity. He
taught for money, and taught young men to “think, speak, and act,” all with a
view to an honourable life of active citizenship : not concealing his marked
disparagement of speculative study and debate, such as the dialogues of Plato
and the dialectic exercises generally. He defends his profession much in the
same way as his master Gorgias, or Protagoras, would have defended it, if we
had before us vindications from their pens. Socrates at Athens, and Quintilian,
a man equally estimable at Rome, are in their general type of character and
professional duty the fair counterpart of those whom Plato arraigns as The
Sophists.
We know these latter chiefly from the evidence of
Plato, their pronounced enemy; yet even his evidence, when construed candidly
and taken as a whole, will not be found to justify the charges of corrupt and
immoral teaching, imposturous pretence of knowledge, &c., which the modern
historians pour forth in loud chorus against them. I know few characters in
history who have been so hardly dealt with as these so-called Sophists, the
penalty of their name, in its modern sense—a misleading association, from which
few modern writers take pains to emancipate either themselves or their readers,
though the English or French word Sophist is absolutely inapplicable to
Protagoras or Gorgias, who ought to be called rather “Professors or Public
Teachers”. It is really surprising to examine the expositions prefixed, by
learned men like Stallbaum and others, to the Platonic dialogues entitled
Protagoras, Gorgias, Euthydemus, Theaetetus, &c., where Plato introduces
Socrates either in personal controversy with one or other of these Sophists, or
as canvassing their opinions. We continually read from the pen of the expositor
such remarks as these—“Mark how Plato puts down the shallow and worthless
Sophist”—the obvious reflection, that it is Plato himself who plays both games
on the chess-board, being altogether overlooked. And again—“This or that
argument, placed in the mouth of Socrates, is not to be regarded as the real
opinion of Plato : he only takes it up and enforces it at this moment, in order
to puzzle and humiliate an ostentatious pretender”—a remark which converts
Plato into an insincere disputant and a Sophist in the modern sense, at the
very moment when the commentator is extolling his pure and lofty morality as an
antidote against the alleged corruption of Gorgias and Protagoras.
Plato has devoted a long and interesting dialogue to
the inquiry, What is a Sophist? and it
is curious to observe that the definition which he at last brings out suits
Socrates himself, intellectually speaking, better than any one else whom we
know. Cicero defines the Sophist to be one who pursues philosophy for the sake
of ostentation or of gain; which, if it is to be held as a reproach, will
certainly bear hard upon the great body of modern teachers, who are determined
to embrace their profession and to discharge its important duties, like other
professional men, by the prospect either of deriving an income or of making a
figure in it, or both—whether they have any peculiar relish for the occupation
or not. But modern writers, in describing Protagoras or Gorgias, while they
adopt the sneering language of Plato against teaching for pay, low purposes,
tricks to get money from the rich, &c, use terms which lead the reader to
believe that there was something in these Sophists peculiarly greedy, exorbitant,
and truckling; something beyond the mere fact of asking and receiving
remuneration. Now, not only there is no proof that any of them (speaking of
those conspicuous in the profession) were thus dishonest or exorbitant, but, in
the case of Protagoras, even his enemy Plato furnishes a proof that he was not
so. In the Platonic dialogue termed Protagoras, that Sophist is introduced as
describing the manner in which he proceeded respecting remuneration from his
pupils. I make no stipulation
beforehand: when a pupil part from me, I ask from him such a sum as I think the
time and the circumstances warrant; and I add, that if he deems the demand too
great, he has only to make up his own mind what is the amount of improvement
which my company has procured to him, and what sum he considers an equivalent
for it. I am content to accept the sum so named by himself, only requiring him
to go into a temple and make oath that it is his sincere belief.” It is not
easy to imagine a more dignified way of dealing than this, nor one which more
thoroughly attests an honourable reliance on the internal consciousness of the
scholar; on the grateful sense of improvement realized, which to every teacher
constitutes a reward hardly inferior to the payment that proceeds from it, and
which (in the opinion of Socrates) formed the only legitimate reward. Such is
not the way in which the corrupters of mankind go to work.
That which stood most prominent in the teaching of
Gorgias and the other Sophists was, that they cultivated and improved the
powers of public speaking in their pupils—one of the most essential
accomplishments to every Athenian of consideration. For this, too, they have
been denounced by Ritter, Brandis, and other learned writers on the history of
philosophy, as corrupt and immoral. “Teaching their pupils rhetoric (it has
been said), they only enable them to second unjust designs, to make the worse
appear the better reason, and to delude their hearers, by trick and artifice,
into false persuasion and show of knowledge without reality. Rhetoric (argues
Plato in the dialogue called Gorgias) is no art whatever, but a mere
unscientific knack, enslaved to the dominant prejudices, and nothing better
than an imposturous parody on the true political art.” Now, though Aristotle,
following the Platonic vein, calls this power of making the worse appear the
better reason “the promise of Protagoras, the accusation ought never to be
urged as if it bore specially against the teachers of the Socratic age. It is
an argument against rhetorical teaching generally; against all the most
distinguished teachers of pupils for active life throughout the ancient world
from Protagoras, Gorgias, Isokrates, tec., down to Quintilian. Not only does
the argument bear equally against all, but it was actually urged against all.
Isokrates and Quintilian both defend themselves against it: Aristotle was
assailed by it, and provides a defence in the beginning of his treatise on
Rhetoric : nor was there ever any man, indeed, against whom it was pressed with
greater bitterness of calumny than Sokrates—by Aristophanes in his comedy of
the “Clouds,” as well as by other comic composers. Socrates complains of it in
his defence before his judges characterizing such accusations in their true
point of view, as being “the stock reproaches against all who pursue
philosophy”. They are indeed only one of the manifestations, ever varying in
form though the same in spirit, of the antipathy of ignorance against
dissenting innovation or superior mental accomplishments; which antipathy
intellectual men themselves, when it happens to make on their side in a
controversy, are but too ready to invoke. Considering that we have here the
materials of defence, as well as of attack, supplied by Socrates and Plato, it
might have been expected that modern writers would have refrained from
employing such an argument to discredit Gorgias or Protagoras; the rather, as
they have before their eyes, in all the countries of modern Europe, the
profession of lawyers and advocates, who lend their powerful eloquence without
distinction to the cause of justice or injustice, and who, far from being
regarded as the corrupters of society, are usually looked upon, for that very
reason among others, as indispensable auxiliaries to a just administration of
law.
Though writing was less the business of these Sophists
than personal teaching, several of them published treatises. Thrasymachus and
Theodorus both set forth written precepts on the art of Rhetoric; precepts
which have not descended to us, but which appear to have been narrow and
special, bearing directly upon practice, and relating chiefly to the proper
component parts of an oration. To Aristotle, who had attained that large and
comprehensive view of the theory of Rhetoric which still remains to instruct us
in his splendid treatise, the views of Thrasymachus appeared unimportant,
serving to him only as hints and materials. But their effect must have been
very different when they first appeared, and when young men were first enabled
to analyse the parts of a harangue, to understand the dependence of one upon
the other, and call them by their appropriate names; all illustrated, let us
recollect, by oral exposition on the part of the master, which was the most
impressive portion of the whole.
Prodicus, again, published one or more treatises
intended to elucidate the ambiguities of words, and to point out the different
significations of terms apparently, but not really, equivalent. For this Plato
often ridicules him, and the modern historians of philosophy generally think it
right to adopt the same tone. Whether the execution of the work was at all
adequate to its purpose, we have no means of judging; but assuredly the purpose
was one pre-eminently calculated to aid Grecian thinkers and dialecticians; for
no man can study their philosophy without seeing how lamentably they were
hampered by enslavement to the popular phraseology, and by inferences founded
on mere verbal analogy. At a time when neither dictionary nor grammar existed,
a teacher who took care, even punctilious care, in fixing the meaning of
important words of his discourse, must be considered as guiding the minds of
his hearers in a salutary direction; salutary, we may add, even to Plato
himself, whose speculations would most certainly have been improved by
occasional hints from such a monitor.
Protagoras, too, is said to have been the first who
discriminated and gave names to the various modes and forms of address — an
analysis well-calculated to assist his lessons on right speaking, he appears
also to have been the first who distinguished the three genders of noun. We
hear further of a treatise which he wrote on wrestling—or most probably on
gymnastics generally—as well as a collection of controversial dialogues. But
his most celebrated treatise was one entitled “Truth,” seemingly on philosophy generally.
Of this treatise we do not even know the general scope or purport. In one of
his treatises he confessed his inability to satisfy himself about the existence
of the gods, in these words—“Respecting the gods, I neither know whether they
exist, nor what are their attributes : the uncertainty of the subject, the
shortness of human life, and many other causes debar me from this knowledge”.
That the believing public of Athens were seriously indignant at this passage,
and that it caused the author to be threatened with prosecution and forced to
quit Athens, we can perfectly understand, though there seems no sufficient
proof of the tale that he was drowned in his outward voyage. But that modern
historians of philosophy, who consider the Pagan gods to be fictions, and the
religion to be repugnant to any reasonable mind, should concur in denouncing
Protagoras on this ground as a corrupt man, is to me less intelligible.
Xenophanes, and probably many other philosophers, had said the same thing
before him. Nor is it easy to see what a superior man was to do, who could not
adjust his standard of belief to such fictions; or what he could say, if he
said anything, less than the words cited above from Protagoras; which appear,
as far as we can appreciate them standing without the context, to be a brief
mention, in modest and circumspect phrase, of the reason why he said nothing
about the gods, in a treatise where the reader would expect to find much upon
the subject. Certain it is that in the Platonic dialogue called “Protagoras,”
that Sophist is introduced speaking about the gods exactly in the manner that
any orthodox Pagan might naturally adopt.
The other fragment preserved of Protagoras relates to
his view of the cognitive process, and of truth generally. He taught that “Man
is the measure of all things, both of that which exists, and of that which does
not exist”: a doctrine canvassed and controverted, by Plato, who represents
that Protagoras affirmed knowledge to consist in sensation, and considered the
sensations of each individual man to be, to him, the canon measure of truth. We
know scarce anything of relative the elucidations or limitations with
which Protagoras may have accompanied his general position: and if even Plato,
who had good means of knowing them, felt it ungenerous to insult an orphan
doctrine whose father was recently dead, and could no longer defend it—much
more ought modern authors, who speak with mere scraps of evidence before them,
to be cautious how they heap upon the same doctrine insults much beyond those
which Plato recognizes. In so far as we can pretend to understand the theory,
it was certainly not more incorrect than several others then afloat, from the
Eleatic school and other philosophers; while it had the merit of bringing into
forcible relief the essentially relative nature of cognition—relative, not
indeed to the sensitive faculty alone, but to that reinforced and guided by the
other faculties of man, memorial and ratiocinative.
And had it been even more incorrect than it really is, there would be no
warrant for those imputations which modern authors build upon it, against the
morality of Protagoras. No such imputations are countenanced in the discussion
which Plato devotes to the doctrine : indeed, if the vindication which he sets
forth against himself on behalf of Protagoras be really ascribable to that
Sophist, it would give an exaggerated importance to the distinction between
Good and Evil, into which the distinction between Truth and Falsehood is
considered by the Platonic Protagoras as resolvable. The subsequent theories of
Plato and Aristotle respecting cognition were much more systematic and
elaborate, the work of men greatly superior in speculative genius to
Protagoras; but they would not have been what they were, had not Protagoras as
well as others gone before them, with suggestions more partial and imperfect.
From Gorgias there remains one short essay, preserved
in one of the Aristotelian or pseudo-Aristotelian treatises, on a metaphysical
thesis. He professes to demonstrate that nothing exists: that if anything
exist, it is unknowable : and granting it even to exist and to be knowable by
any one man, he could never communicate it to others. The modern historians of
philosophy here prefer the easier task of denouncing the scepticism of the
Sophist, instead of performing the duty incumbent on them of explaining his
thesis in immediate sequence with the speculations which preceded it. In our
sense of the words, it is a monstrous paradox; but construing them in their
legitimate filiation from the Eleatic philosophers immediately before him, it
is a plausible, not to say conclusive, deduction from principles which they
would have acknowledged. The word Existence, as they understood it, did not
mean phenomenal, but ultra-phenomenal existence. They looked upon the phenomena
of sense as always coming and going—as something essentially transitory,
fluctuating, incapable of being surely known, and furnishing at best grounds
only for conjecture. They searched by cogitation for what they presumed to be
the really existent Something or Substance—the Noumenon, to use a Kantian
phrase—lying behind or under the phenomena, which Noumenon they recognized as
the only appropriate object of knowledge. They discussed much (as I have before
remarked) whether it was One or Many— Noumenon in the singular, or Noumena in
the plural. Now the thesis of Gorgias related to his ultra-phenomenal
existence, and bore closely upon the arguments of Zeno and Melissus,
the Eleatic reasoners of his elder contemporaries. He denied that any such
ultra-phenomenal Something, or Noumenon, existed, or could be known, or could
be described. Of this tripartite thesis, the first negation was neither more
untenable nor less untenable than that of those philosophers who before him had
argued for the affirmative: on the two last points his conclusions were neither
paradoxical nor improperly sceptical, but perfectly just, and have been
ratified by the gradual abandonment, either avowed or implied, of such
ultra-phenomenal researches among the major part of philosophers. It may fairly
be presumed that these doctrines were urged by Gorgias for the purpose of
diverting his disciples from studies which he considered as unpromising and
fruitless, just as we shall find his pupil Isokrates afterwards enforcing the
same view, discouraging speculations of this nature, and recommending
rhetorical exercise as preparation for the duties of an active citizen. Nor
must we forget that Socrates himself discouraged physical speculations even
more decidedly than either of them.
If the censures cast upon the alleged scepticism of
Gorgias and Protagoras are partly without sufficient warrant—partly without any
warrant at all—much more may the same remark be made respecting the graver
reproaches heaped upon their teaching on the score of immorality or corruption.
It has been common with recent German historians of philosophy to translate
from Plato and dress up a fiend called “Die Sophistik”
(Sophistic) ; whom they assert to have poisoned and demoralized by corrupt
teaching, the Athenian moral character,
so that it became degenerate at the end of the Peloponnesian war, compared with
what it had been in the time of Miltiades and Aristeides.
Now, in the first place, if the abstraction “Die Sophistik ” is to have any definite meaning, we ought to
have proof that the persons styled Sophists had some doctrines, principles, or
method, both common to them all and common distinguishing them from others. But
such a supposition is untrue; there were no such common doctrines, or
principles, or method belonging to them. Even the name by which they are known
did not belong to them, any more than to Socrates and others; they had nothing
in common except their profession as paid teachers, qualifying young men “to
think, speak, and act” (these are the words of Isocrates, and better words it
would not be easy to find) with credit to themselves as citizens. Moreover,
such community of profession did not at that time imply so much analogy of
character as it does now, when the path of teaching has been beaten into a broad
and visible high road, with measured distances and stated intervals: Protagoras
and Gorgias found predecessors indeed, but no binding precedents to copy; so
that each struck out, more or less, a road of his own. And, accordingly, we
find Plato, in his dialogue called “Protagoras,” wherein Protagoras, Prodicus,
and Hippias are all introduced, imparting a distinct type of character and
distinct method to each, not without a strong admixture of reciprocal jealousy
between them; while Thrasymachus, in the “Republic,” and Euthydemus, in the
dialogue so called, are again painted each with colours of his own, different
from all the three above named. We do not know how far Gorgias agreed in the
opinion of Protagoras—“Man is the measure of all things”: and we may infer,
even from Plato himself, that Protagoras would have opposed the views expressed
by Thrasymachus in the first book of the “Republic”. It is impossible,
therefore, to predicate anything concerning doctrines, methods, or tendencies
common and peculiar to all the Sophists. There were none such; nor has the
abstract word—“Die Sophistik’’—any real meaning,
except such qualities (whatever they may be) as are inseparable from the
profession or occupation of public teaching. And if, at present, every candid
critic would be ashamed to cast wholesale aspersions on the entire body of
professional teachers, much more is such censure unbecoming in reference to the
ancient Sophists, who were distinguished from each other by stronger individual
peculiarities.
If, then, it were true that in the interval between
480 B.C. and the end of the Peloponnesian war a great moral deterioration had
taken place in Athens and in Greece generally, we should have to search for
some other cause than the imaginary abstraction called Sophistic. But—and this
is the second point—the matter of fact here alleged is as untrue as the cause
alleged is unreal. Athens, at the close of the Peloponnesian war, was not more
corrupt than Athens in the days of Miltiades and Aristeides. If we revert to
that earlier period, we shall find that scarcely any acts of the Athenian
people have drawn upon them sharper censure (in my judgment, unmerited) than
their treatment of these very two statesmen—the condemnation of Miltiades and
the ostracism of Aristeides. In writing my history of that time, far from
finding previous historians disposed to give the Athenians credit for public
virtue, I have been compelled to contend against a body of adverse criticism,
imputing to them gross ingratitude and injustice. Thus the contemporaries of
Miltiades and Aristeides, when described as matter of present history, are
presented in anything but flattering colours ; except their valour at Marathon
and Salamis, which finds one unanimous voice of encomium. But when these same
men have become numbered among the mingled recollections and fancies belonging
to the past—when a future generation comes to be present, with its appropriate
stock of complaint and denunciation —then it is that men find pleasure in
dressing up the virtues of the past, as a count in the indictment against their
own contemporaries. Aristophanes, writing during the Peloponnesian war,
denounced the Demos of his day as degenerated from the virtue of that Demos
which had surrounded Miltiades and Aristeides; while Isocrates, writing as an
old man between 350—340 B.C., complains in like manner of his own time,
boasting how much better the state of Athens had been in his youth : which
period of his youth fell exactly during the life of Aristophanes, in the last
half of the Peloponnesian war.
Such illusions ought to impose on no one without a
careful comparison of facts; and most assuredly that comparison will not bear
out the allegation of increased corruption and degeneracy, between the age of
Miltiades and the end of the Peloponnesian war. Throughout the whole of
Athenian history, there are no acts which attest be large a measure of virtue
and judgment pervading the whole people, as the proceedings after the Four
Hundred and after the Thirty. Nor do I believe that the contemporaries of Miltiades
would have been capable of such heroism; for that appellation is by no means
too large for the case. I doubt whether they would have been competent to the
steady self-denial of retaining a large sum in reserve during the time of
peace, both prior to the Peloponnesian war and after the peace of Nicias—or of
keeping back the reserve fund of 1000 talents, while they were forced year
after year to pay taxes for the support of the war—or of acting upon the
prudent yet painfully trying policy recommended by Pericles, so as to sustain
an annual invasion without either going out to fight or purchasing peace by
ignominious concessions. If bad acts such as Athens committed during the later
years of the war—for example, the massacre of the Melian population—were not
done equally by the contemporaries of Miltiades, this did not arise from any
superior humanity or principle on their part, but from the fact that they were
not exposed to the like temptation, brought upon them by the possession of
imperial power. The condemnation of the six generals after the battle of
Arginusae, if we suppose the same conduct on their part to have occurred in 490
B.C., would have been decreed more rapidly and more unceremoniously than it was
actually decreed in 406 B.C. For at that early date there existed no psephism
of Kannonus, surrounded by prescriptive respect—no
Graphs Paranomon—no such habits of established deference to a Dikastery
solemnly sworn, with full notice to defendants and full time of defence
measured by the water-glass—none of those securities which a long course of
democracy had gradually worked into the public morality of every Athenian, and
which (as we saw in a former chapter) interposed a serious barrier to the
impulse of the moment, though ultimately overthrown by its fierceness. A far
leas violent impulse would have sufficed for the same mischief in 490 B.C.,
when no such barriers existed. Lastly, if we want a measure of the appreciating
sentiment of the Athenian public, towards a strict and decorous morality in the
narrow sense, in the middle of the Peloponnesian war, we have only to consider
the manner in which they dealt with Nicias. I have shown, in describing the
Sicilian expedition, that the gravest error which the Athenians ever committed,
power at home, arose from their unmeasured esteem for the respectable and pious
Nicias which blinded them to the grossest defects of generalship and public conduct. Disastrous as such misjudgement was, it counts at least as
a proof that the moral corruption; alleged to have been operated in their
characters, is a mere fiction. Nor let it be supposed that the nerve and
resolution which once animated the combatants of Marathon and Salamis had
disappeared in the latter years of the Peloponnesian war. On the contrary, the
energetic and protracted struggle of Athens, after the irreparable calamity at
Syracuse, forms a worthy parallel to her resistance in the time of Xerxes, and
maintained unabated that distinctive attribute which Pericles had set forth as
the mam foundation of her glory—that of never giving way before misfortune.
Without any disparagement to the armament at Salamis, we may remark that the
patriotism of the fleet at Samos, which rescued Athens from the Four Hundred,
was equally devoted and more intelligent; and that the burst of effort, which
sent a subsequent fleer to victory at Arginusae, was to the full as strenuous.
If then we survey the eighty-seven years of Athenian
history, between the battle of Marathon and the renovation of the democracy
after the Thirty, we shall see no ground for the assertion, so often made, of
increased and increasing moral and political corruption. It is my belief that
the people had become both morally and politically better, and that their
democracy had worked to their improvement. The remark made by Thucydides, on
the occasion of the Corcyraean bloodshed—on the violent and reckless political
antipathies, arising out of the confluence of external warfare with internal
party-feud—wherever else it may find its application, has no bearing upon
Athens : the proceedings after the Four Hundred and after the Thirty prove the
contrary. And while Athens may thus be vindicated on the moral side, it is
indisputable that her population had acquired a far larger range of ideas and
capacities than they possessed at the tune of the battle of Marathon. This
indeed is the very matter of fact deplored by Aristophanes, and admitted by
those writers who, while denouncing the Sophists, connect such enlarged range
of ideas with the dissemination of the pretended sophistical poison. In my judgment, not only the charge against the Sophists as poisoners,
but even the existence of such poison in the Athenian system, deserves nothing
less than an emphatic denial.
Let us examine again the names of these professional
teachers, beginning with Prodicus, one of the most renowned. Who is there that
has not read the well-known fable called “The Choice of Hercules,” which is to
be found in every book professing to collect impressive illustrations of
elementary morality? Who does not know that its express purpose is to kindle
the imaginations of youth in favour of a life of labour for noble objects, and
against a life of indulgence? It was the favourite theme on which Prodicus
lectured, and on which he obtained the largest audience. If it be of striking simplicity and effect
even to a modern reader, how much more powerfully must it have worked upon the
audience for whose belief it was specially adapted, when, set off by the oral
expansions of its author! Xenophon
wondered that the Athenian Dikaste dealt with
Socrates as a corrupter of youth; Isocrates wondered that a portion of the
public made the like mistake about himself; and I confess my wonder to be not
less, that not only Aristophanes, but even the modern writers on Grecian
philosophy, should rank Prodicus in the same unenviable catalogue. This is the
only composition remaining from him; indeed, the only composition remaining
from any one of the Sophists, excepting the thesis of Gorgias above noticed. It
serves not merely as a vindication of Prodicus against such reproach, but also
as a warning against implicit confidence in the sarcastic remarks of Plato,
which include Prodicus as well as the other Sophists, and in the doctrines
which he puts into the mouth of the Sophists generally, in order that Socrates
may confute them. The commonest candour would teach us that if a polemical
writer of dialogue chooses to put indefensible doctrine into the mouth of the
opponent, we ought to be cautious of condemning the latter upon such very
dubious proof.
Weicker and other modern authors treat Prodicus as
“the most innocent” of the Sophists, and except him from the sentence which
they pass upon the class generally. Let us see, therefore, what Plato himself
says about the rest of them, and first about Protagoras. If it were not the
established practice with readers of Plato to condemn Protagoras beforehand,
and to put upon every passage relating to him not only a sense as bad as it
will bear, but much worse than it will fairly bear, they would probably carry away
very different inferences from the Platonic dialogue called by that Sophist’s
name, and in which he is made to bear a chief part. That dialogue is itself
enough to prove that Plato did not conceive Protagoras either as a corrupt, or
unworthy, or incompetent teacher. The course of the dialogue exhibits him as
not master of the theory of ethics, and unable to solve various difficulties
with which that theory is expected to grapple; moreover, as no match for
Socrates in dialectics, which Plato considered as the only efficient method of
philosophical investigation. In so far, therefore, as imperfect acquaintance
with the science or theory upon which rules of art, or the precepts bearing on
practice, repose, disqualifies a teacher from giving instruction in such art or
practice, to that extent Protagoras is exposed as wanting. And if an expert
dialectician like Plato had passed Isokrates or Quintilian, or the large
majority of teachers past or present, through a similar cross-examination as to
the theory of their teaching, an ignorance not less manifest than that of
Protagoras would be brought out. The antithesis which Plato sets forth, in so
many of his dialogues, between precept or practice, accompanied by full
knowledge of the scientific principles from which it must be deduced, if its
rectitude be disputed, and unscientific practice, without any such power of
deduction or defence, is one of the most valuable portions of his speculations;
he exhausts his genius to render it conspicuous in a thousand indirect ways,
and to shame his readers, if possible, into the loftier and more rational walk
of thought. But it is one thing to say of a man that he does not know the
theory of what he teaches or of the way in which he teaches; it is another
thing to say that he actually teaches that which scientific theory would not
prescribe as the best; it is a third thing, graver than both, to say that his
teaching is not only below the exigences of science, but even corrupt and
demoralizing. Now, of these three points it is the first only which Plato in
his dialogue makes out against Protagoras; even the second, he neither affirms
nor insinuates; and as to the third, not only he never glances at it, even
indirectly, but the whole tendency of the discourse suggests a directly
contrary conclusion. As if sensible that when an eminent opponent was to be
depicted as puzzled and irritated by superior dialectics, it was but common
fairness to set forth his distinctive merits also, Plato gives a fable, and
expository harangue, from the mouth of Protagoras, upon the question whether
virtue is teachable. This harangue is, in my judgment, very striking and
instructive; and so it would have been probably accounted, if commentators had
not read it with a pre-established persuasion that whatever came from the lips
of a Sophist must be either ridiculous or immoral. It is the only part of
Plato’s works wherein any account is rendered of the growth of that floating,
uncertified, self-propagating body of opinion upon which the cross-examining analysis
of Socrates is brought to bear, as will be seen in the following chapter.
Protagoras professes to teach his pupils “good
counsel” in their domestic and family relations, as well as how to speak and
act in the most effective manner for the weal of the city. Since this comes
from Protagoras, the commentators of Plato pronounce it to be miserable
morality; but it coincides, almost to the letter, with that which Isokrates
describes himself as teaching, a generation afterwards, and substantially even
with that which Xenophon represents Socrates as teaching; nor is it easy to set
forth, in a few words, a larger scheme of practical duty. And if the measure of
practical duty, which Protagoras devoted himself to teach, was thus serious and
extensive, even the fraction of theory assigned to him in his harangue includes
some points better than that of Plato himself. For Plato seems to have
conceived the Ethical End, to each individual, as comprising nothing more than
his own permanent happiness and moral health; and in this very dialogue he
introduces Socrates as maintaining virtue to consist only in a right
calculation of a man’s own personal happiness and misery. But here we find
Protagoras speaking in a way which implies a larger, and in my opinion a juster, appreciation of the Ethical End, as including not
only reference to a man’s own happiness, but also obligations towards the
happiness of others. Without at all agreeing in the harsh terms of censure
which various critics pronounce upon that theory which Socrates is made to set
forth in the Platonic Protagoras, I consider his conception of the Ethical End
essentially narrow and imperfect, not capable of being made to serve as basis
for deduction of the best ethical precepts. Yet such is the prejudice with
which the history of the Sophists has been written, that the commentators on
Plato accuse the Sophists of having originated what they ignorantly term “the
base theory of utility,” here propounded by Socrates himself; complimenting the
latter on having set forth those larger views which in this dialogue belong
only to Protagoras.
So far as concerns Protagoras, therefore, the evidence
of Plato himself may be produced to show that he was not a corrupt teacher, but
a worthy companion of Prodicus; worthy also of that which we know him to have
enjoyed—the society and conversation of Pericles. Let us now examine what Plato
says about a third Sophist— Hippias of Elis; who figures both in the dialogue
called “Protagoras,” and in two distinct dialogues known by the titles of Hippias Major and Minor”. Hippias is
represented as distinguished for the wide range of his accomplishments, of
which in these dialogues he ostentatiously boasts. He could teach astronomy,
geometry, and arithmetic—which subjects Protagoras censured him for enforcing
too much upon his pupils; so little did these Sophists agree in any one scheme
of doctrine or education. Besides this, he was a poet, a musician, an expositor
of the poets, and a lecturer with a large stock of composed matter—on subjects
moral, political, and even legendary—treasured up in a very retentive memory.
He was a citizen much employed as envoy by his fellow-citizens: to crown all,
his manual dexterity was such that he professed to have made with his own hands
all the attire and ornaments which he wore on his person. If, as is
sufficiently probable, he was a vain and ostentatious man—defects not excluding
an useful and honourable career—we must at the same time give him credit for a
variety of acquisitions such as to explain a certain measure of vanity. The
style in which Plato handles Hippias is very different from that in which he
treats Protagoras. It is full of sneer and contemptuous banter, insomuch that
even Stallbaum, after having repeated a great many times that this was a vile
Sophist who deserved no better treatment, is forced to admit that the petulance
is carried rather too far, and to suggest that the dialogue must have been a
juvenile work of Plato. Be this as it may, amidst so much unfriendly handling,
not only we find no imputation against Hippias of having preached a low or
corrupt morality, but Plato inserts that which furnishes good, though indirect,
proof of the contrary. For Hippias is made to say that he had already
delivered, and was about to deliver again, a lecture composed by himself with
great care, wherein he enlarged upon the aims and pursuits which a young man
ought to follow. The scheme of his discourse was, that after the capture of
Troy the youthful Neoptolemus was introduced as asking the advice of Nestor
about his own future conduct; in reply to which, Nestor sets forth to him what
was the plan of life incumbent on a young man of honourable aspirations, and
unfolds to him the full details of regulated and virtuous conduct by which it
ought to be filled up. The selection of two such names, among the most
venerated in all Grecian legend, as monitor and pupil, is a stamp clearly
attesting the vein of sentiment which animated the composition. Morality
preached by Nestor for the edification of Neoptolemus might possibly be too
high for Athenian practice; but most certainly it would not err on the side of
corruption, selfishness, or over-indulgence. We may fairly presume that this
discourse composed by Hippias would not be unworthy, in spirit and purpose, to
be placed by the side of “The Choice of Hercules,” nor its author by that of
Prodicus as a moral teacher.
The dialogue entitled “Gorgias” in Plato is carried on
by Socrates with three different persons one after the other—Gorgias, Polus,
and Kallicles. Gorgias (of Leontini in Sicily), as a rhetorical teacher,
acquired greater celebrity than any man of his time during the Peloponnesian
war; his abundant powers of illustration, his florid ornaments, his artificial
structure of sentences distributed into exact antithetical fractions,—all
spread a new fashion in the art of speaking, which for the time was very popular,
but afterwards became discredited. If the line could be clearly drawn between
rhetors and sophists, Gorgias ought rather to be ranked with the former. In the
conversation with Gorgias, Socrates exposes the fallacy and imposture of
rhetoric and rhetorical teaching, as cheating an ignorant audience into
persuasion without knowledge, and as framed to satisfy the passing caprice,
without any regard to the permanent welfare and improvement of the people.
Whatever real inculpation may be conveyed in these arguments against a
rhetorical teacher, Gorgias must bear in common with Isocrates and Quintilian,
and under the shield of Aristotle. But save and except rhetorical teaching, no
dissemination of corrupt morality is ascribed to him by Plato, who indeed treats
him with a degree of respect which surprises the commentators.
The tone of the dialogue changes materially when it
passes to Polus and Kallicles, the former of whom is described as a writer on
rhetoric, and probably a teacher also. There is much insolence in Polus, and no
small asperity in Socrates. Yet the former maintains no arguments which
justify the charge of immorality against himself or his fellow-teachers. He
defends the tastes and sentiments common to every man in Greece, and shared
even by the most estimable Athenians—Pericles, Nicias, and Aristocrates,
while Socrates prides himself on standing absolutely alone, and having no
support except from his irresistible dialectics, whereby he is sure of
extorting reluctant admission from his adversary. How far Socrates may be right
I do not now inquire. It is sufficient that Polus, standing as he does amidst
company at once so numerous and so irreproachable, cannot be fairly denounced
as a poisoner of the youthful mind.
Polus presently hands over the dialogue to Kallicles,
who is here represented, doubtless, as laying down doctrines openly and
avowedly antisocial. He distinguishes between the law of nature and the law
(both written. and unwritten, for the Greek word substantially includes both)
of society. According to the law of nature (Kallicles says) the strong man—the
better or more capable man—puts forth his strength to the full, for his own
advantage, without limit or restraint; overcomes the resistance which weaker men
are able to offer; and seizes for himself as much as he pleases of the matter
of enjoyment. He has no occasion to restrain any of his appetites or
desires—the more numerous and pressing they are, so much the better for
him—since his power affords him the means of satiating them all. The many, who
have the misfortune to be weak, must be content with that which he leaves them,
and submit to it as best they can. This (Kallicles says) is what actually
happens in a state of nature ; this is what is accounted just, as is evident by
the practice of independent communities, not included in one common political
society, towards each other; this is justice, by nature, or according to the
law of nature. But when men come into society, all this is reversed. The majority
of individuals know very well that they are weak, and that their only chance of
security or comfort consists in establishing laws to restrain the strong man,
reinforced by a moral sanction of praise and blame devoted to the same general
end. They catch him like a young lion whilst his mind is yet tender, and
fascinate him by talk and training into a disposition conformable to that
measure and equality which the law enjoins. Here, then, is justice according to
the law of society: a factitious system built up by the many for their own
protection and happiness, to the subversion of the law of nature, which arms
the strong man with a right to encroachment and licence. Let a fair opportunity
occur, and the favourite of nature will be seen to kick off his harness, tread
down the laws, break through the magic circle of opinion around him, and stand
forth again as lord and master of the many; regaining that glorious position
which nature has assigned to him as his right. Justice by nature and justice by
law and society are thus, according to Kallicles, not only distinct, but
mutually contradictory. He accuses Socrates of having jumbled the two together
in his argument.
It has been contended by many authors that this
anti-social reasoning (true enough, in so far it states simple matter of fact
and probability; immoral, in so far as it erects the power of the strong man
into a right; and inviting many comments, if I could find a convenient place
for them) represents the morality commonly and publicly taught by the persons
called Sophists at Athens. I deny this assertion emphatically. Even if I had no
other evidence to sustain my denial, except what has been already extracted
from the unfriendly writings of Plato himself, respecting Protagoras and
Hippias, with what we know from Xenophon about Prodicus, I should consider my
case made out as vindicating the Sophists generally from such an accusation. If
refutation to the doctrine of Kallicles were needed, it would be obtained quite
as efficaciously from Prodicus and Protagoras as from Sokrates and Plato.
But this is not the strongest part of the vindication.
First, Kallicles himself is not a Sophist, nor
represented by Plato as such. He is a young Athenian citizen, of rank and
station, belonging to the deme Acharnae; he is
intimate with other young men of condition in the city, has recently entered
into active political life, and bends his whole soul towards it; he disparages
philosophy, and speaks with utter contempt about the Sophists. If, then, it
were even just (which I do not admit) to infer from opinions put into the mouth
of one Sophist that the same were held by another or by all of them, it would
not be the less unjust to draw the like inference from opinions professed by
one who is not a Sophist, and who despises the whole profession.
Secondly, if any man will read attentively the course
of the dialogue, he will see that the doctrine of Kallicles is such as no one
dared publicly to propound. So it is conceived both by Kallicles himself and by
Socrates. The former first takes up the conversation by saying that his
predecessor Polus had become entangled in a public contradiction, because he
had not courage enough openly to announce an unpopular and odious doctrine; but
he (Kallicles) was less shamefaced, and would speak out boldly that doctrine
which others kept to themselves for fear of shocking the hearers. “Certainly
(says Sokrates to him) your audacity is abundantly shown by the doctrine which
you have just laid down—you set forth plainly that which other people think,
but do not choose to utter.” Now, opinions of which Polus, an insolent young
man, was afraid to proclaim himself the champion, must have been revolting
indeed to the sentiments of hearers. How then can any reasonable man believe
that such opinions were not only openly propounded, but seriously inculcated as
truth upon audiences of youthful hearers by the Sophists? We know that the
teaching of the latter was public in the highest degree ; publicity was
pleasing as well as profitable to them; among the many disparaging epithets
heaped upon them, ostentation and vanity are two of the most conspicuous.
Whatever they taught, they taught publicly; and I contend, with full
conviction, that had they even agreed with Kallicles in this opinion, they
could neither have been sufficiently audacious, nor sufficiently their own
enemies, to make it a part of their public teaching, but would have acted like
Polus, and kept the doctrine to themselves.
Thirdly, this latter conclusion will be rendered
doubly certain, when we consider of what city we are now speaking. Of all
places in the world, the democratical Athens is the last in which the doctrine
advanced by Kallicles could possibly have been professed by a public teacher,
or even by Kallicles himself in any public meeting. It is unnecessary to remind
the reader how profoundly democratical was the sentiment and morality of the
Athenians—how much they loved their laws, their constitution, and their political
equality—how jealous their apprehension was of any nascent or threatening
despotism. All this is not simply admitted, but even exaggerated, by Mr.
Mitford, Wachsmuth, and other anti-democratical writers, who often draw from it
materials for their abundant censures. Now the very point which Sokrates (in
this dialogue called “Gorgias”) seeks to establish against Kallicles, against
the Rhetors, and against the Sophists, is that they courted, flattered, and
truckled to the sentiment of the Athenian people, with degrading subservience;
that they looked to the immediate gratification simply, and not to permanent
moral improvement of the people—that they had not courage to address to them
any unpalatable truths, however salutary, but would shift and modify opinions
in every way so as to escape giving offence—that no man who put himself
prominently forward at Athens had any chance of success, unless he became
moulded and assimilated, from the core, to the people and their type of
sentiment. Granting such charges to be true, how is it conceivable that any
Sophist or any Rhetor could venture to enforce upon an Athenian public audience
the doctrine laid down by Kallicles? To tell such audience—“Your laws and
institutions are all violations of the law of nature, contrived to disappoint
the Alkibiades or Napoleon among you of his natural right to become your
master, and to deal with you petty men as his slaves. All your unnatural
precautions and conventional talk, in favour of legality and equal dealing,
will turn out to be nothing better than pitiful impotence, as soon as he finds
a good opportunity of standing forward in his full might and energy—so as to
put you into your proper places, and show you what privileges Nature intends
for her favourite!’’. Conceive such a doctrine propounded by a lecturer to
assembled Athenians!—a doctrine just as revolting to Nicias as to Cleon, and
which even Alcibiades would be forced to affect to disapprove; since it is not
simply anti-popular—not simply despotic—but the drunken extravagance of
despotism. The Great man as depicted by Kallicles stands m the same relation to
ordinary mortals as Jonathan Wild the Great in the admirable parody of
Fielding.
That Sophists, whom Plato accuses of slavish flattery
to the democratical ear, should gratuitously insult it by the proposition of
such tenets, is an assertion not merely untrue, but utterly absurd. Even as to
Sokrates, we know from Xenophon how much the Athenians were offended with him,
and how much it was urged by the accusers on his trial, that in his
conversations he was wont to cite with peculiar relish the description (in the
second book of the Iliad) of Odysseus following the Grecian crowd when running
away from the agora to get on shipboard, and prevailing upon them to come
back—by gentle words addressed to the chiefs, but by blows of his stick,
accompanied with contemptuous reprimand, to the common people. The indirect
evidence thus afforded that Sokrates countenanced unequal dealing and ill-usage
towards the Many told much against him in the minds of the Dikasts.
What would they have felt then towards a Sophist who publicly professed the
political morality of Kallicles? The truth is, not only was it impossible that
any such morality, or anything of the same type even much diluted, could find
its way into the educational lectures of professors at Athens, but the fear
would be in the opposite direction. If the Sophist erred in either way, it
would be in that which Socrates imputes—by making his lectures
over-democratical. Nay, if we suppose any opportunity to have arisen of
discussing the doctrine of Kallicles, he would hardly omit to flatter the ears
of the surrounding democrats by enhancing the beneficent results of legality
and equal dealing, and by denouncing this “natural despot” or undisclosed
Napoleon as one who must either take his place under such restraints, or find a
place in some other city.
I have thus shown, even from Plato himself, that the
doctrine ascribed to Kallicles neither did enter, nor could have entered, into
the lectures of a Sophist or .professed teacher. The same conclusion may be
maintained respecting the doctrine of Thrasymachus in the first book of the
“Republic”. Thrasymachus was a rhetorical teacher, who had devised precepts
respecting the construction of an oration and the training of young men for
public speaking. It is most probable that he confined himself, like Gorgias, to
this department, and that he did not profess to give moral lectures, like
Protagoras and Prodicus. But granting him to have given such, he would not talk
about justice in the way in which Plato makes him talk, if he desired to give
any satisfaction to an Athenian audience. The mere brutality and ferocious
impudence of demeanour, even to exaggeration, with which Plato invests him, is
in itself a strong proof that the doctrine, ushered in with such a preface, was
not that of a popular and acceptable teacher, winning favour in public
audiences. He defines justice to be “the interest of the superior power; that
rule which, in every society, the dominant power prescribes as being for its
own advantage”. A man is just (he says) for the advantage of another, not for
his own : he is weak, cannot help himself, and must submit to that which the
stronger authority, whether despot, oligarchy, or commonwealth, commands.
The theory is essentially different from the doctrine
of Kallicles, as set forth a few pages back; for Thrasymachus does not travel
out of society to insist upon anterior rights dating from a supposed state of
nature—he takes societies as he finds them, recognizing the actual governing
authority of each as the canon and it is the constituent of justice or
injustice. Stallbaum and other writers have incautiously treated the two
theories as they were the same; and with something even worse than want of
caution, while they pronounce the theory of Thrasymachus to be detestably
immoral, announce it as having been propounded not by him only, but by The
Sophists—thus, in their usual style, dealing with the Sophists as if they were
a school, sect, or partnership with mutual responsibility. Whoever has followed
the evidence which I have produced respecting Protagoras and Prodicus will know
how differently these latter handled the question of justice.
But the truth is that the theory of Thrasymachus,
though incorrect and defective, is not so detestable as these writers
represent. What makes it seem detestable is the style and manner in which he is
made to put it forward, which causes the just man to appear petty and
contemptible, while it surrounds the unjust man with enviable attributes. Now
this is precisely the circumstance which revolts the common sentiments of
mankind, as it revolts also the critics who read what is said by Thrasymachus.
The moral sentiments exist in men’s minds in complex and powerful groups,
associated with some large, words and emphatic forms of speech. Whether an
ethical theory satisfies the exigences of reason, or commands and answers to
all the phenomena, a common audience will seldom give themselves the trouble to
consider with attention; but what they imperiously exact, and what is
indispensable to give the theory any chance of success, is that it shall
exhibit to their feelings the just man as respectable and dignified, and the
unjust man as odious and repulsive. Now that which offends in the language
ascribed to Thrasymachus is, not merely the absence, but the reversal, of this
condition—the presentation of the just man as weak and silly, and of injustice
in all the prestige of triumph and dignity. And for this very reason I venture
to infer that such a theory was never propounded by Thrasymachus to any public
audience in the form in which it appears in Plato. For Thrasymachus was a
rhetor, who had studied the principles of his art: now we know that these
common sentiments of an audience were precisely what the rhetors best
understood, and always strove to conciliate. Even from the time of Gorgias,
they began the practice of composing beforehand declamations upon the general heads
of morality, which were ready to be introduced into actual speeches as occasion
presented itself, and in which appeal was made to the moral sentiments
foreknown as common, with more or less of modification, to all the Grecian
assemblies. The real Thrasymachus, addressing any audience at Athens, would
never have wounded these sentiments, as the Platonic Thrasymachus is made to do
in the “Republic . Least of all would he have done this, if it be true of him,
as Plato asserts of the Rhetors and Sophists generally, that they thought about
nothing but courting popularity, without any sincerity of conviction.
Though Plato thinks fit to bring out the opinion of
Thrasymachus with accessories unnecessarily offensive, and thus to enhance the
dialectical triumph of Sokrates by the brutal manners of the adversary, he was
well afterwards aware that he had not done justice to the opinion itself, much
less confuted it. The proof of this is, that in the second book of the
“Republic,” after Thrasymachus has disappeared, the very same opinion is taken
up by Glaukon and Adeimantus, and set forth by both of them (though they disclaim
entertaining it as their own), as suggesting grave doubts and difficulties
which they desire to hear solved by Socrates. Those who read attentively the
discourses of Glaukon and Adeimantus will see that the substantive opinion
ascribed to Thrasymachus, apart from the brutality with which he is made to
state it, does not even countenance the charge of immoral teaching against
him—much less against the Sophists generally. Hardly anything in Plato’s
compositions is more powerful than those discourses. They present, in a
perspicuous and forcible manner, some of the most serious difficulties with
which ethical theory is required to grapple. And Plato can answer them only in
one way—by taking society to pieces and reconstructing it in the form of his imaginary
republic. The speeches of Glaukon and Adeimantus form the immediate preface to
the striking and elaborate description which he goes through, of his new state
of society, nor do they receive any other answer than what is applied in that
description. Plato indirectly confesses that he cannot answer them, assuming
social institutions to continue unreformed ; and his reform is sufficiently
fundamental.
I call particular attention to this circumstance,
without which we cannot fairly estimate the Sophists, or practical teachers of
Athens, face to face with their accuser-general—Plato. He was a great and
systematic theorist, whose opinions on ethics, politics, cognition, religion,
&c., were all wrought into harmony by his own mind, and stamped with that
peculiarity which is the mark of an original intellect. So splendid an effort
of speculative genius is among the marvels of poets and the Grecian world. His dissent
from all the societies which he saw around him, not merely democratical, but
oligarchical and despotic also, was of the deepest and most radical character.
Nor did he delude himself by the belief that any partial amendment of that
which he saw around could bring about the end which he desired : he looked to
nothing short of a new genesis of the man and the citizen, with institutions
calculated from the beginning to work out the full measure of perfectibility.
His fertile scientific imagination realized this idea in the “Republic”. But
that very systematic and original character, which lends so much value and
charm to the substantive speculations of Plato, counts as a deduction from his
trustworthiness as critic or witness, in reference to the living agents whom he
saw at work in Athens and other cities, as statesmen, generals, or teachers.
His criticisms are dictated by his own point of view, according to which the
entire society was corrupt, and all the instruments who carried on its
functions were of essentially base metal. Whoever will read either the
“Gorgias” or the “Republic” will see in how sweeping and indiscriminate a
manner he passes his sentence of condemnation. Not only all the Sophists and
all the Rhetors, but all the musicians and dithyrambic or tragic poets—all the
statesmen, past as well as present, not excepting even the great Pericles—receive from his hands one
common stamp of dishonour. Every one of these men is numbered by Plato among
the numerous category of flatterers, who minister to the immediate
gratification and to the desires of the people, without looking to their
permanent improvement or making them morally better. “Pericles and Cimon (says
Socrates in the “Gorgias”) are nothing but servants or ministers who supply the
immediate appetites and tastes of the people; just as the baker and the
confectioner do in their respective departments, without knowing or caring
whether the food will do any real good—a point which the physician alone can
determine. As ministers, they are clever enough: they have provided the city
amply with tribute, walls, docks, ships, and such other follies: but I
(Socrates) am the only man in Athens who aim, so far as my strength permits, at
the true purpose of politics—the mental improvement of the people.” So
wholesale a condemnation betrays itself as the offspring, and the consistent
offspring, of systematic peculiarity of vision—the prejudice of a great and
able mind.
It would be not less unjust to appreciate the Sophists
or the it is unjust statesmen of Athens from the point of view of Plato, than
the present teachers and politicians of England or France from that of Mr. Owen
or Fourier. Both the one and the other class laboured for society as it stood
at Athens : the statesmen carried on the business of practical politics, the
Sophist trained up youth for practical life in all its departments, as family
men, citizens, and leaders, to obey as well as to command. Both accepted the
system as it stood without contemplating the possibility of a new birth of
society; both ministered to certain exigences, held their anchorage upon
certain sentiments, and bowed to a certain morality, actually felt among the
living men around them. That which Plato says of the statesmen of Athens is
perfectly true—that they were only servants or ministers of the people. He who
tried the people and the entire society by comparison with an imaginary
standard of his own might deem all these ministers worthless in the lump, as
carrying on a system too bad to be mended; but nevertheless the difference
between a competent and an incompetent minister—between Pericles and Nicias—was
of unspeakable moment to the security and happiness of the Athenians. What the
Sophists on their part undertook was to educate young men so as to make them
better qualified for statesmen or ministers; and Protagoras would have thought
it sufficient honour to himself, as well as sufficient benefit to Athens, which
assuredly it would have been, if he could have inspired any young Athenian with
the soul and the capacities of his friend and companion Pericles.
So far is Plato from considering the Sophists as the
corrupters of Athenian morality, that he distinctly protests against that
supposition, in a remarkable passage of the “Republic”. It is (he says) the
whole people, or the society, with its established morality, intelligence, and
tone of sentiment, which is intrinsically vicious : the teachers of such a
society must be vicious also, otherwise their teaching would not be received;
and even if their private teaching were ever so good, its effect would be washed
away, except in some few privileged natures, by the overwhelming deluge of
pernicious social influences. Nor let any one imagine (as modern readers are
but too ready to understand it) that this poignant censure is intended for
Athens so far forth as a democracy. Plato was not the man to preach
king-worship, or wealth-worship as social or political remedies: he declares
emphatically that not one of the societies then existing was such that a truly
philosophical nature could be engaged in active functions under it. These
passages would be alone sufficient to repel the assertions of those who
denounce the Sophists as poisoners of Athenian morality, on the alleged
authority of Plato.
Nor is it at all more true that they were men of mere
words, and made their pupils no better—a charge just as vehemently pressed
against Socrates as against the Sophists, and by the same class of enemies,
such as Anytus, Aristophanes, Eupolis, &c. It was
mainly from Sophists like Hippias that the Athenian youth learnt what they knew
of geometry, astronomy, and arithmetic; but the range of what is called special
science, possessed even by the teacher, was at that time very limited; and the
matter of instruction communicated was expressed under the general title of
“Words or Discourses,” which were always taught by the Sophists, in connexion
with thought and in reference to a practical use. The capacities of thought,
speech, and action are conceived in conjunction by Greeks generally, and by
teachers like Isocrates and Quintilian especially ; and when young men in
Greece, like the Boeotian Proxenus, put themselves under training by Gorgias or
any other Sophist, it was with a view of qualifying themselves, not merely to
speak, but to act.
Most of the pupils of the Sophists (as of Sokrates
himself) were young men of wealth—a fact at which Plato sneers, and others copy
him, as if it proved that they cared only about high pay. But I do not hesitate
to range myself on the side of Isocrates, and to contend that the Sophist
himself had much to lose by corrupting his pupils (an argument used by Socrates
in defending himself before the Dikastery, and just as good effect valid in
defence of Protagoras or Prodicus) and strong personal interest in sending them
forth accomplished and virtuous; that the best taught youth were decidedly the
most free from crime, and the most active towards good ; that among the
valuable ideas and feelings which a young Athenian had in his mind, as well as
among the good pursuits which he followed, those which he learnt from the
Sophists counted nearly as the best; that if the contrary had been the fact,
fathers would not have continued so to send their sons and pay their money. It
was not merely that these teachers countervailed in port the temptations to
dissipated enjoyment, but also that they were personally unconcerned in the
acrimonious slander and warfare of party in his native city; that the topics
with which they familiarized him were the general interests and duties of men
and citizens; that they developed the germs of morality in the ancient legends
(as in Prodicus’s fable), and amplified in his mind
all the undefined cluster of associations connected with the great words of
morality; that they vivified in him the sentiment of Pan-hellenic brotherhood; and that in teaching him the art of persuasion, they could not but
make him feel the dependence in which he stood towards those who were to be
persuaded, together with the necessity under which he lay of so conducting
himself as to conciliate their goodwill.
The intimations given in Plato of the enthusiastic
reception which Protagoras, Prodicus, and other Sophists met with in the
various cities; the description which we read (in the dialogue called
Protagoras) of the impatience of the youthful Hippocrates, on healing of the
arrival of that Sophist, insomuch that he awakens Socrates before daylight, in
order to obtain an introduction to the newcomer and profit by his teaching; the
readiness of such rich young men to pay money, and to devote time and trouble for
the purpose of acquiring a personal superiority apart from their wealth and
station; the ardour with which Kallias is represented as employing his house
for the hospitable entertainment, and his fortune for the aid of the Sophists
all this makes upon my mind an impression directly the reverse of that ironical
and contemptuous phraseology with which it is set forth by Plato. Such Sophists
had nothing to recommend them except superior knowledge and intellectual force,
combined with an imposing personality, making itself felt in their lectures and
conversation. It is to this that the admiration was shown; and the fact that it
was so shown brings to view the best attributes of the Greek, especially the
Athenian mind. It exhibits those qualities of which Pericles made emphatic
boast in his celebrated funeral oration—conception of public speech as a
practical thing, not meant as an excuse for inaction, but combined with
energetic action, and turning it to good account by full and open discussion
beforehand—profound sensibility to the charm of manifested intellect, without
enervating the powers of execution or endurance. Assuredly a man like
Protagoras, arriving in a city with all his train of admiration laid before
him, must have known very little of his own interest or position if he began to
preach a low or corrupt morality. If it be true generally, as Voltaire has
remarked, that “any man who should come to preach a relaxed morality would be
pelted”, much more would it be true of a Sophist like Protagoras, arriving in a
foreign city with all the prestige of a great intellectual name, and with the
imagination of youths on fire to hear and converse with him, that any similar
doctrine would destroy his reputation at once. Numbers oi teachers have made
their reputation by inculcating overstrained asceticism ; it will be hard to
find an example of success in the opposite vein.
|