READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
GEORGE GROTE'S HISTORY OF GREECECHAPTER LIV.
TRUCE FOR ONE YEAR.—RENEWAL OF, WAR AND BATTLE OF
AMPHIPOLIS.—PEACE OF NICIAS.
The eighth year of the war, described in the last
chapter, had opened with sanguine hopes for Athens, and with dark promise for
Sparta, chiefly in consequence of the memorable capture of Sphacteria toward
the end of the preceding summer. It included, not to mention other events, two
considerable and important enterprises on the part of Athens—against Megara and
against Boeotia; the former plan, partially successful—the latter, not merely
unsuccessful, but attended with a ruinous defeat. Lastly, the losses in Thrace
following close upon the defeat at Delium, together
with the unbounded expectations everywhere entertained from the future career
of Brasidas, had again seriously lowered the impression entertained of Athenian
power. The year thus closed amid humiliations the more painful to Athens, as
contrasted with the glowing hopes with which it had begun.
It was now that Athens felt the full value of those
prisoners whom she had taken at Sphacteria. With those prisoners, as Kleon and
his supporters had said truly, she might be sure of making peace whenever she
desired it. Having such a certainty to fall back upon, she had played a bold
game, and aimed at larger acquisitions during the past year. This speculation,
though not in itself unreasonable, had failed: moreover, a new phenomenon,
alike unexpected by all, had occurred, when Brasidas broke open and cut up her
empire in Thrace. Still, so great was the anxiety of the Spartans to regain
their captives, who had powerful friends and relatives at home, that they
considered the victories of Brasidas chiefly as a stepping-stone toward that
object, and as a means of prevailing upon Athens to make peace. To his animated
representations sent home from Amphipolis, setting forth the prospects of still
farther success and entreating re-enforcements, they had returned a
discouraging reply, dictated in no small degree by the miserable jealousy of
some of their chief men; who, feeling themselves cast into the shade, and
looking upon his splendid career as an eccentric movement breaking loose from
Spartan routine, were thus on personal as well as political grounds disposed to
labour for peace. Such collateral motives, working upon the caution usual with
Sparta, determined her to make use of the present fortune and realized
conquests of Brasidas, as a basis for negotiation and recovery of the
prisoners; without opening the chance of ulterior enterprises, which, though
they might perhaps end in results yet more triumphant, would unavoidably put in
risk that which was now secure. The history of the Athenians during the past
year might, indeed, serve as a warning to deter the Spartans from playing an
adventurous game.
Ever since the capture of Sphacteria, the
Lacedaemonians had been attempting, directly or indirectly, negotiations for
peace and the recovery of the prisoners. Their pacific dispositions were
especially instigated by King Pleistoanax, whose peculiar circumstances gave
him a strong motive to bring the war to a close. He had been banished from
Sparta, fourteen years before the commencement of the war, and a little before
the Thirty years’ truce, under the charge of having taken bribes from the
Athenians on occasion of invading Attica. For more than eighteen years he lived
in banishment close to the temple of Zeus Lycaeus in Arcadia; in such constant
fear of the Lacedaemonians that his dwelling-house was half within the
consecrated ground. But he never lost the hope of procuring restoration,
through the medium of the Pythian priestess at Delphi, whom he and his brother
Aristokles kept in their pay. To every sacred legation which went from Sparta
to Delphi, she repeated the same imperative injunction—“They must bring back
the seed of (Herakles) the demigod son of Zeus from foreign land to their own;
if they did not, it would be their fate to plow with
a silver ploughshare.” The command of the god, thus incessantly repeated, and
backed by the influence of those friends who supported Pleistoanax at home, at
length produced an entire change of sentiment at Sparta. In the fourth or fifth
year of the Peloponnesian war, the exile was recalled; and not merely recalled,
but welcomed with unbounded honours, received with the same sacrifices and
choric shows as those which were said to have been offered to the primitive
kings, on the first settlement of Sparta.
As in the case of Kleomenes and Demaratus, however, it
was not long before the previous intrigue came to be detected, or at least
generally suspected and believed; to the great discredit of Pleistoanax, though
he could not be again banished. Every successive public calamity which befell
the state, the miscarriages of Alcidas, the defeat of Eurylochus in Amphilochia, and above all, the unprecedented humiliation
in Sphacteria, were imputed to the displeasure of the gods in consequence of
the impious treachery of Pleistoanax. Suffering under such an imputation, this
king was most eager to exchange the hazards of war for the secure march of
peace, so that he was thus personally interested iu opening every door for negotiation with Athens, and in restoring himself to
credit by regaining the prisoners.
After the battle of Delium,
the pacific dispositions of Nicias, Laches, and the philo-Laconian
party, began to find increasing favor at Athens; while the unforeseen losses in
Thrace, coming thick upon each other—each successive triumph of Brasidas
apparently increasing his means of achieving more—tended to convert the
discouragement of the Athenians into positive alarm. Negotiations appear to
have been in progress throughout great part of the winter. The continual hope
that these might be brought to a close, combined with the impolitic aversion of
Nikias and his friends to energetic military action, help to explain the
unwonted apathy of Athens under the pressure of such disgraces. But so much did
her courage flag, toward the close of the winter, that she came to look upon a
truce as her only means of preservation against the victorious progress of
Brasidas. What the tone of Kleon now was, we are not directly informed. He
would probably still continue opposed to the propositions of peace, at least
indirectly, by insisting on terms more favourable than could be obtained. On
this point his political counsels would be wrong; but on another point they
would be much sounder and more judicious than those of his rival Nikias: for he
would recommend a strenuous prosecution of hostilities by Athenian force
against Brasidas in Thrace. At the present moment this was the most urgent
political necessity of Athens, whether she entertained or rejected the views of
peace. And the policy of Nikias, who cradled up the existing depression of the
citizens by encouraging them to rely on the pacific inclinations of Sparta, was
ill-judged and disastrous in its results, as the future will hereafter show.
Attempts were made by the peace party both at Athens
and Sparta to negotiate at first for a definitive peace. But the conditions of
such a peace were not easy to determine, so as to satisfy both parties—and
became more and more difficult, with every success of Brasidas. At length the
Athenians, eager above all things to arrest his progress, sent to Sparta to
propose a truce for one year—desiring the Spartans to send to Athens envoys
with full powers to settle the terms: the truce would allow time and tranquillity
for settling the conditions of a definitive treaty. The proposition of the
truce for one year, together with the first two articles ready prepared, came
from Athens, as indeed we might have presumed even without proof; since the
interest of Sparta was rather against it, as allowing to the Athenians the
fullest leisure for making preparations against farther losses in Thrace. But
her main desire was, not so much to put herself in condition to make the best
possible peace, as to insure some peace which would liberate her captives. She
calculated that when once the Athenians had tasted the sweets of peace for one
year, they would not again voluntarily impose upon themselves the rigorous
obligations of war.
In the month of March, 423 B.C., on the fourteenth day
of the month Elaphebolion at Athens, and on the
twelfth day of the month Gerastius at Sparta, a truce
for one year was concluded and sworn, between Athens on one side, and Sparta,
Corinth, Sicyon, Epidaurus, and Megara on the other. The Spartans, instead of
merely dispatching plenipotentiaries to Athens as the Athenians had desired,
went a step farther. In concurrence with the Athenian envoys, they drew up a
form of truce, approved by themselves and their allies, in such manner that it
only required to be adopted and ratified by the Athenians The general principle
of the truce was uti possidetis, and the conditions were in substance as follows:—
1. Respecting the temple at Delphi, every Greek shall
have the right to make use of it honestly and without fear, pursuant to the
customs of his particular city.—The main purpose of this stipulation, prepared
and sent verbatim from Athens, was to allow Athenian visitors to go thither,
which had been impossible during the war, in consequence of the hostility of
the Boeotians and Phocians. The Delphian authorities also were in the interest
of Sparta, and doubtless the Athenians received no formal invitation to the
Pythian games. But the Boeotians and Phocians were no parties to the truce:
accordingly the Lacedaemonians, while accepting the article and proclaiming the
general liberty in principle, do not pledge themselves to enforce it by arms as
far as the Boeotians and Phocians are concerned, but only to try and persuade
them by amicable representations. The liberty of sacrificing at Delphi was at
this moment the more welcome to the Athenians, as they seem to have fancied
themselves under the displeasure of Apollo.
2. All the contracting parties will inquire out
and punish, each according to its own laws, such persons as may violate the
property of the Delphian god.—This article also is prepared at Athens, for the
purpose seemingly of conciliating the favor of Apollo and the Delphians. The
Lacedaemonians accept the article literally, of course.
3. The Athenian garrisons at Pylus,
Cythera, Nisaea, and Minoa, and Methana in the neighbourhood
of Troezen, are to remain as at present. No
communication to take place between Kythera and any portion of the mainland
belonging to the Lacedaemonian alliance. The soldiers occupying Pylus shall confine themselves within the space between Buphras aud Tomeus;
those in Nisaea and Minoa, within the road which
leads from the chapel of the hero Nisus to the temple of Poseidon—without any
communication with the population beyond that limit. In like manner the
Athenians in the peninsula of Methana near Troezen, and
the inhabitants of the latter city, shall observe the special convention
concluded between them respecting boundaries.
4. The Lacedaemonians and their allies shall make use
of the sea for trading-purposes, on their own coasts, but shall not have
liberty to sail in any ship of war, nor in any rowed merchant-vessel of tonnage
equal to 500 talents. [All war-ships were generally impelled by oar: they
sometimes used sails, but never when wanted for fighting. Merchant-vessels seem
generally to have sailed, but were sometimes rowed: the limitation of size is
added, to insure that the Lacedaemonians shall not, under colour of
merchantmen, get up a warlike navy.]
5. There shall be free communication by sea as
well as by land, between Peloponnesus and Athens for herald or embassy, with
suitable attendants, to treat for a definitive peace or for the adjustment of
differences. .
6. Neither side shall receive deserters from the.
other, whether free or slave. [This article was alike important to both
parties. Athens had to fear the revolt of her subject-allies—Sparta the
desertion of Helots.]
7. Disputes shall be amicably settled, by both
parties, according to their established laws and customs.
Such was the substance of the treaty prepared at
Sparta—seemingly in concert with Athenian envoys—and sent by the Spartans to
Athens for approval, with the following addition—“If there be any provision
which occurs to you, more honourable or just than these, come to Lacedaemon and
tell us: for neither the Spartans nor their allies will resist any just
suggestions. But let those who come bring with them full powers to conclude—in
the same manner as you desire of us. The truce shall be for one year.”
By the resolution which Laches proposed in the
Athenian public assembly, ratifying the truce, the people farther decreed that
negotiations should be opened for a definitive treaty, and directed the
Strategi to propose to the next ensuing assembly, a scheme and principles for
conducting the negotiations. But at the very moment when the envoys between
Sparta and Athens were bringing the truce to final adoption, events happened in
Thrace which threatened to cancel it altogether. Two days after the important
fourteenth of Elaphebolion, but before the truce
could be made known in Thrace, Skione revolted from Athens to Brasidas.
Skione was a town calling itself Achaean, one of the
numerous colonies which, in the want oi an acknowledged mother-city, traced its
origin to warriors returning from Troy. It was situated in the peninsula of
Pallene (the westernmost of those three narrow tongues of land into which Chalcidice
branches out); conterminous with the Eretrian colony Mende. The Skionaeans, not without considerable dissent among
themselves, proclaimed their revolt from Athens, under concert with Brasidas.
He immediately crossed the Gulf into Pallene, himself in a little boat, but
with a trireme close at his side; calculating that she would protect him
against any small Athenian vessel—while any Athenian trireme which he might
encounter would attack his trireme, paying no attention to the little boat in
which he himself was. The revolt of Skione was, from the position of the town,
a more striking defiance of Athens than any of the preceding events. For the
isthmus connecting Pallene with the mainland was occupied by the town of Potidae—a town assigned at the period of its capture, seven
years before, to Athenian settlers, though probably containing some other
residents besides. Moreover the isthmus was so narrow that the wall of Potidae barred it across completely from sea to sea.
Pallene was therefore a quasi-island, not open to the aid of land force from
the continent, like the towns previously acquired by Brasidas. The Skionaeans thus put themselves, without any foreign aid,
into conflict against the whole force of Athens, bringing into question her
empire not merely over continental towns but over islands.
Even to Brasidas himself, their revolt appeared a step
of astonishing boldness. On being received into the city, he convened a public
assembly, and addressed to them the same language which he had employed at Acanthus
and Torone; disavowing all party preferences as well
as all interference with the internal politics of the town, and exhorting them
only to unanimous efforts against the common enemy. He bestowed upon them at
the same time the warmest praise for their courage. “They, though exposed to
all the hazards of islanders, had stood forward of their own accord to procure
freedom, without waiting like cowards to be driven on by a foreign force toward
what was clearly their own good. He considered them capable of any measure of
future heroism, if the danger now impending from Athens should be averted—and
he should assign to them the very first post of honour among the faithful
allies of Lacedaemon.”
This generous, straightforward, and animating tone of
exhortation—appealing to the strongest political instinct of the Greek mind,
the love of complete city-autonomy, and coming from the lips of one whose whole
conduct had hitherto been conformable to it—had proved highly efficacious in
all the previous towns. But in Skione it roused the population to the highest
pitch of enthusiasm. It worked even upon the feelings of the dissentient
minority, bringing them round to partake heartily in the movement. It produced
a unanimous and exalted confidence which made them look forward cheerfully to
all the desperate chances in which they had engaged themselves; and it produced
at the same time, in still more unbounded manifestation, the same personal
attachment and admiration as Brasidas inspired elsewhere. The Skionaeans not only voted to him publicly a golden crown,
as the liberator of Greece, but when it was placed on his head, the burst of
individual sentiment and sympathy was the strongest of which the Grecian bosom
was capable. “They crowded round him individually, and encircled his head with
fillets, like a victorious athlete,” says the historian. This remarkable
incident illustrates what I observed before—that the achievements, the
self-relying march, the straightforward politics, and probity of this
illustrious man—who in character was more Athenian than Spartan, yet with the
good qualities of Athens predominant—inspired a personal emotion toward him
such as rarely found its way into Grecian political life. The sympathy and
admiration felt in Greece toward a victorious athlete was not merely an intense
sentiment in the Grecian mind, but was perhaps, of all others, the most
wide-spread and Pan-hellenic. It was connected with
the religion, the taste, and the love of recreation common to the whole
nation—while politics tended rather to disunite the separate cities: it was
farther a sentiment at once familiar and exclusively personal. Of its
exaggerated intensity throughout Greece the philosophers often complained, not
without good reason. But Thucydides cannot convey a more lively idea of the
enthusiasm and unanimity with which Brasidas was welcomed at Skione, just after
the desperate resolution taken by the citizens, than by using this simile.
The Lacedaemonian commander knew well how much the
utmost resolution of the Skionaeans was needed, and
how speedily their insular position would draw upon them the vigorous invasion
of Athens. He accordingly brought across to Pallene a considerable portion of
his army, not merely with a view to the defense of
Skione, but also with the intention of surprising both Mende and Potidaea, in
both which places there were small parties of conspirators prepared to open the
gates.
It was in this position that he was found by the
commissioners who came to announce formally the conclusion of the truce for one
year, and to enforce its provisions: Athenaeus from Sparta—one of the three
Spartans who had sworn to the treaty, Aristonymus, from Athens. The face of
affairs was materially altered by this communication; much to the satisfaction
of the newly-acquired allies of Sparta in Thrace, who accepted the truce
forthwith—but to the great chagrin of Brasidas, whose career was thus suddenly arrested.
Yet he could not openly refuse obedience, and his army was accordingly
transferred from the peninsula of Pallene to Torone.
The case of Skione however, immediately raised an
obstruction, doubtless very agreeable to him. The commissioners, who had come
in an Athenian trireme, had heard nothing of the revolt of that place, and
Aristonymus was astonished to find the enemy in Pallene. But on inquiring into
the case, he discovered that the Skionaeans had not
revolted until two days after the day fixed for the commencement of the truce.
Accordingly, while sanctioning the truce for all the other cities in Thrace, he
refused to comprehend Skione in it, sending immediate news home to Athens.
Brasidas, protesting loudly against this proceeding, refused on his part to
abandon Skione, which was peculiarly endeared to him by the recent scenes; and
even obtained the countenance of the Lacedaemonian commissioners, by falsely
asseverating that the city had revolted before the day named in the truce.
Violent was the burst of indignation when the news sent home by Aristonymus
reached Athens. It was nowise softened, when the Lacedaemonians, acting upon
the version of the case sent to them by Brasidas and Athenaeus, dispatched an
embassy thither to claim protection for Skione—or at any rate to procure the
adjustment of the dispute by arbitration or pacific decision. Having the terms
of the treaty on their side, the Athenians were least of all disposed to relax
from their rights in favor of the first revolting islanders. They resolved at
once to undertake an expedition for the reconquest of Skione; and further, on
the proposition of Kleon, to put to death all the adult male inhabitants of
that place as soon as it should have been reconquered. At the same time, they
showed no disposition to throw up the truce generally. The state of feeling on
both sides tended to this result—that while the war continued in Thrace, it was
suspended everywhere else.
Fresh intelligence soon arrived—carrying exasperation
at Athens yet further—of the revolt of Mende, the adjoining town to Skione.
Those Menaeans, who had laid their measures for
secretly introducing Brasidas, were at first baffled by the arrival of the
truce-commissioners. But they saw that he retained his hold on Skione, in spite
of the provisions of the truce; and they ascertained that he was willing still
to protect them if they revolted, though he could not be an accomplice, as
originally projected, in the surprise of the town. Being moreover only a small
party, with the sentiment of the population against them—they were afraid, if
they now relinquished their scheme, of being detected and punished for the
partial steps already taken, when the Athenians should come against Skione.
They therefore thought it on the whole the least dangerous course to persevere.
They proclaimed their revolt from Athens, constraining the reluctant citizens
to obey them. The government seems before to have been democratical, but they
now found means to bring about an oligarchical revolution along with the
revolt. Brasidas immediately accepted their adhesion, and willingly undertook
to protect them; professing to think that he had a right to do so, because they
had revolted openly after the truce had been proclaimed. But the truce upon
this point was clear—which he himself virtually admitted, by setting up as
justification certain alleged matters in which the Athenians had themselves
violated it. He immediately made preparation for the defense both of Mende and Skione against the attack which was now rendered more certain
than before; conveying the women and children of those two towns across to the Chalcidic
Olynthus, and sending thither as garrison 500 Peloponnesian hoplites with 300 Chalcidic
peltasts; the commander of which force, Polydamidas, took possession of the
acropolis with his own troops separately.
Brasidas then withdrew himself with the greater part
of his army, to accompany Perdikkas on an expedition into the interior against
Arrhibaeus and the Lyncestae. On what ground, after
having before entered into terms with Arrhibaeus, he now became his active
enemy, we are left to conjecture. Probably his relations with Perdikkas, whose
alliance was of essential importance, were such that this step was forced upon
him against his will; or he may really have thought that the force under
Polydamidas was adequate to the defense of Mende and
Skione—an idea which the unaccountable backwardness of Athens for the last six
or eight months might well foster. Had he even remained, indeed, he could
hardly have saved them, considering the situation of Pallene and the
superiority of Athens at sea: but his absence made their ruin certain.
While Brasidas was thus engaged far in the interior,
the Athenian armament under Nikias and Nicostratus reached Potidaea; fifty
triremes, ten of them Chian—1000 hoplites and 600 bowmen from Athens—1000
mercenary Thracians—with some peltasts from Methone and other towns in the neighbourhood.
From Potidaea they proceeded by sea to Cape Poseidonium,
near which they landed for the purpose of attacking Mende. Polydamidas, the
Peloponnesian commander in the town, took post with his force of 700 hoplites,
including 300 Skionaeans, upon an eminence near the
city, strong and difficult of approach: upon which the Athenian generals
divided their forces; Nikias, with sixty Athenian chosen hoplites, 120 Methonean peltasts, and all the bowmen, tried to march up
the hill by a side path and thus turn the position—while Nicostratus with the
main army attacked it in front. But such were the extreme difficulties of the
ground that both were repulsed: Nikias was himself wounded, and the division of
Nicostratus was thrown into great disorder, narrowly escaping a destructive
defeat. The Mendaeans, however, evacuated the
position in the night and retired into the city; while the Athenians, sailing
round on the morrow to the suburb on the side of Skione, ravaged the neighbouring
land; Nikias on the ensuing day carried his devastations still further, even to
the border of the Skionaean territory.
But dissensions so serious had already commenced
within the walls, that the Skionaean auxiliaries,
becoming mistrustful of their situation, took advantage of the night to return
home. The revolt of Mende had been brought about against the will of the
citizens, by the intrigues and for the benefit of an oligarchical faction.
Moreover, it does not appear that Brasidas personally visited the town, as he
had visited Skione and the other revolted towns. Had he come, his personal
influence might have done much to soothe the offended citizens, and create some
disposition to adopt the revolt as a fact accomplished, after they had once
been compromised with Athens. But his animating words had not been heard, and
the Peloponnesian troops, whom he had sent to Mende, were mere instruments to
sustain the newly-erected oligarchy, and keep out the Athenians. The feelings
of the citizens generally toward them were soon unequivocally displayed. Nicostratus
with half of the Athenian force was planted before the gate of Mende which
opened toward Potidaea. In the neighbourhood of that gate, within the city, was
the place of arms and the chief station both of the Peloponnesians and of the
citizens. Polydamidas, intending to make a sally forth, was marshaling both of them in battle order, when one of the Mendaean Demos, manifesting with angry vehemence a sentiment common to most of them,
told him “that he would not sally forth, and did not choose to take part in the
contest”. Polydamidas seized hold of the man to punish him, when the mass of
the armed Demos, taking part with their comrade, made a sudden rush upon the
Peloponnesians. The latter, unprepared for such an onset, sustained at first
some loss, and were soon forced to retreat into the acropolis—the rather as
they saw some of the Mendaeans open the gates to the
besiegers without, which induced them to suspect a preconcerted betrayal. No
such concert however existed; though the besieging generals, when they saw the
gates thus suddenly opened, soon comprehended the real position of affairs. But
they found it impossible to restrain their soldiers, who pushed in forthwith,
from plundering the town: and they had even some difficulty in saving the lives
of the citizens.
Mende being thus taken, the Athenian generals desired
the body of the citizens to resume the former government, leaving it to them to
single out and punish the authors of the late revolt. What use was made of this
permission, we are not told: but probably most of the authors had already
escaped into the acropolis along with Polydamidas. Having erected a wall of
circumvallation, round the acropolis, joining the sea at both ends—and left a
force to guard it—the Athenians moved away to begin the siege at Skione, where
they found both the citizens and the Peloponnesian garrison posted on a strong
hill, not far from the walls. As it was impossible to surround the town without
being masters of this hill, the Athenians attacked it at once and were more
fortunate than they had been before Mende; for they carried it by assault,
compelling the offenders to take refuge in the town. After erecting their
trophy, they commenced the wall of circumvallation. Before it was finished, the
garrison who had been shut up in the acropolis of Mende got into Skione at
night, having broken out by a sudden sally where the blockading wall around
them joined the sea. But this did not hinder Nikias from prosecuting his
operations, so that Skione was in no long time completely enclosed, and a
division placed to guard the wall of circumvallation
Such was the state of affairs which Brasidas found on
returning from the inland Macedonia. Unable either to recover Mende or to
relieve Skione, he was forced to confine himself to the protection of Torone. Nicias, however, without attacking Torone, returned soon afterward with his armament to
Athens, leaving Skione under blockade.
The march of Brasidas into Macedonia had been
unfortunate in every way. Nothing but his extraordinary gallantry rescued him
from utter ruin. The joint force of himself and Perdikkas consisted of 3000
Grecian hoplites : Peloponnesian, Acanthian, and Chalcidian,
with 1000 Macedonian and Chalcidian horse, and a considerable number of
non-Hellenic auxiliaries. As soon as they had got beyond the mountain-pass into
the territory of the Lyncestae, they were met by
Arrhibaeus, and a battle ensued, in which that prince was completely worsted.
They halted here a few days, awaiting—before they pushed forward to attack the
villages in the territory of Arrhibaeus—the arrival of a body of Illyrian mercenaries,
with whom Perdikkas had concluded a bargain. At length Perdikkas became
impatient to advance without them, while Brasidas, on the contrary,
apprehensive of the fate of Mende during his absence, was bent on returning
back. The dissension between them becoming aggravated, they parted company and
occupied separate encampments at some distance from each other—when both
received unexpected intelligence which made Perdikkas as anxious to retreat as
Brasidas. The Illyrians, having broken their compact, had joined Arrhibaeus,
and were now in full march to attack the invaders. The untold number of these
barbarians was reported as overwhelming, while such was their reputation for
ferocity as well as for valour, that the Macedonian army of Perdikkas, seized
with a sudden panic, broke up in the night, and fled without orders, hurrying
Perdikkas himself along with them, and not even sending notice to Brasidas,
with whom nothing had been concerted about the retreat. In the morning the
latter found Arrhibaeus and the Illyrians close upon him: the Macedonians being
already far advanced in their journey homeward.
The contrast between the man of Hellas and of
Macedonia—general as well as soldiers—was never more strikingly exhibited than
on this critical occasion. The soldiers of Brasidas, though surprised as well
as deserted, lost neither their courage nor their discipline; the commander
preserved not only his presence of mind, but his full authority. His hoplites
were directed to form in a hollow square or oblong, with the light-armed and
attendants in the center, for the retreating march.
Youthful soldiers were posted either in the outer ranks, or in convenient
stations, to run out swiftly and repel the assailing enemy; while Brasidas
himself, with 300 chosen men, formed the rear-guard.
The short harangue which (according to a custom
universal with Grecian generals) he addressed to his troops immediately before
the enemy approached, is in many respects remarkable. Though some were Acanthians, some Chalcidians, some Helots, he designates
all by the honourable title of “Peloponnesians.” Reassuring them against the
desertion of their allies, as well as against the superior numbers of the
advancing enemy—he invokes their native, homebred courage. “Ye do not require
the presence of allies to inspire you with bravery—nor do ye fear superior
numbers of an enemy; for ye belong not to those political communities in which
the larger number governs the smaller, but to those in which a few men rule
subjects more numerous than themselves—having acquired their power by no other
means than by superiority in battle.” Next, Brasidas tried to dissipate the
prestige of the Illyrian name. His army had already vanquished the Lyncestae, and these other barbarians were noway better. A nearer acquaintance would soon show that
they were only formidable from the noise, the gestures, the clashing of arms
and the accompaniments of their onset; and that they were incapable of
sustaining the reality of close combat, hand to hand. “They have no regular
order (said he) such as to impress them with shame for deserting their post.
Flight and attack are with them in equally honourable esteem, so that there is
nothing to test the really courageous man: their battle, wherein every man
fights as he chooses, is just the thing to furnish each with a decent pretence
for running away.”—“Repel ye their onset whenever it comes, and so soon as
opportunity offers, resume your retreat in rank and order. Ye will soon arrive
in a place of safety; and ye will be convinced that such crowds, when their
enemy has stood to defy the first onset, keep aloof with empty menace and a
parade of courage which never strikes—while if their enemy gives way, they show
themselves smart and bold in running after him where there is no danger. ”
The superiority of disciplined and regimented force
over disorderly numbers, even with equal individual courage, is now a truth so
familiar, that we require an effort of imagination to put ourselves back into
the fifth century before the Christian era, when this truth was recognized only
among the Hellenic communities; when the practice of all their neighbours,
Illyrians, Thracians, Asiatics, Epirots,
and even Macedonians—implied ignorance or contradiction of it. In respect to
the Epirots, the difference between their military
habits and those of the Greeks has been already noticed—having been pointedly
manifested in the memorable joint attack on the Acarnanian town of Stratus, in
the second year of the war. Both Epirots and
Macedonians, however, are a step nearer to the Greeks than either Thracians, or
these Illyrian barbarians against whom Brasidas was now about to contend, and
in whose case the contrast comes out yet more forcibly. It is not merely the
contrast between two modes of fighting which the Lacedaemonian commander
impresses upon his soldiers. He gives what may be called a moral theory of the
principles on which that contrast is founded; a theory of large range, and
going to the basis of Grecian social life, in peace as well as in war. The
sentiment, in each individual man’s bosom, of a certain place which he has to
fill and duties which he has to perform—combined with fear of the displeasure
of his neighbours as well as of his own self-reproach if he shrinks back—but at
the same time essentially bound up with the feeling, that his neighbours are
under corresponding obligations toward him—this sentiment, which Brasidas
invokes as the settled military creed of his soldiers in their ranks, was not
less the regulating principle of their intercourse in peace as citizens of the
same community. Simple as the principle may seem, it would have found no
response in the army of Xerxes, or of the Thracian Sitalces or of the Gaul
Brennus. The Persian soldier rushes to death by order of the Great King,
perhaps under terror of a whip which the Great King commands to be administered
to him. The Illyrian or the Gaul scorns such a stimulus, and obeys only the
instigation of his own pugnacity, or vengeance, or love of blood, or love of
booty—but recedes as soon as that individual sentiment is either satisfied, or
overcome by fear. It is the Greek soldier alone who feels himself bound to his
comrades by ties reciprocal and indissoluble—who obeys neither the will of a
king, nor his own individual impulse, but a common and imperative sentiment of
obligation—whose honour or shame is attached to his own place in the ranks,
never to be abandoned nor overstepped. Such conceptions of military duty,
established in the minds of these soldiers whom Brasidas addressed, will come
to be farther illustrated when we describe the memorable Retreat of the Ten
Thousand. At present I merely indicate them as forming a part of that general
scheme of morality, social and political as well as military, wherein the
Greeks stood exalted above the nations who surrounded them.
But there is another point in the speech of Brasidas
which deserves notice: he tells his soldiers—“Courage is your homebred
property: for ye belong to communities wherein the small number governs the
larger, simply by reason of superior prowess in themselves and conquest by
their ancestors.” First, it is remarkable that a large proportion of the Peloponnesian
soldiers, whom Brasidas thus addresses, consisted of Helots, the conquered
race, not the conquerors: yet so easily does the military or regimental pride
supplant the sympathies of race, that these men would feel flattered by being
addressed as if they were themselves sprung from the race which had enslaved
their ancestors. Next, we here see the right of the strongest invoked as the
legitimate source of power, and as an honourable and ennobling recollection by
an officer of Dorian race, oligarchical politics, unperverted intellect, and estimable character. We shall accordingly be prepared, when we
find a similar principle hereafter laid down by the Athenian envoys at Melos,
to disallow the explanation of those who treat it merely as a theory invented
by demagogues and sophists—upon one or other of whom it is common to throw the
blame of all that is objectionable in Grecian politics or morality.
Having finished his harangue, Brasidas gave orders for
retreat. As soon as his march began, the Illyrians rushed upon him with all the
confidence and shouts of pursuers against a flying enemy, believing that they
should completely destroy his army. But wherever they approached near, the
young soldiers specially stationed for the purpose turned upon and beat them
back with severe loss; while Brasidas himself with his rear-guard of 300 was
present everywhere rendering vigorous aid. When the Lyncestae and Illyrians attacked, the army halted and repelled them, after which it
resumed its retreating march. The barbarians found themselves so rudely
handled, and with such unwonted Vigor—for they probably had had no previous
experience of Grecian troops—that after a few trials they desisted from
meddling with the army in its retreat along the plain. They ran forward
rapidly, partly in order to overtake the Macedonians under Perdikkas, who had
fled before—partly to occupy the narrow pass, with high hills on each side,
which formed the entrance into Lyncestis, and which lay in the road of
Brasidas. When the latter approached this narrow pass, he saw the barbarians
masters of it. Several of them were already on the summits, and more were
ascending to re-enforce them; while a portion of them were moving down upon his
rear. Brasidas immediately gave orders to his chosen 300, to charge up the most
assailable of the two hills, with their best speed, before it became more
numerously occupied—not staying to preserve compact ranks. This unexpected and
vigorous movement disconcerted the barbarians, who fled, abandoning the
eminence to the Greeks, and leaving their own men in the pass exposed on one of
their flanks. The retreating army, thus master of one of the side hills, was
enabled to force its way through the middle pass, and to drive away the Lyncestian and Illyrian occupants. Having got through this
narrow outlet, Brasidas found himself on the higher ground. His enemies did not
dare to attack him farther: so that he was enabled to reach, even in that day’s
march, the first town or village in the kingdom of Perdikkas, called Arnissa.
So incensed were his soldiers with the Macedonian subjects of Perdikkas, who
had fled on the first news of danger without giving them any notice —that they
seized and appropriated all the articles of baggage, not inconsiderable in
number, which happened to have been dropped in the disorder of a nocturnal
flight. They even unharnessed and slew the oxen out of the baggage carts.
Perdikkas keenly resented this behaviour of the troops
of Brasidas, following as it did immediately upon his own quarrel with that
general, and upon the mortification of his repulse from Lyncestis. From this
moment he broke off his alliance with the Peloponnesian, and opened
negotiations with Nikias, then engaged in constructing the wall of blockade
round Skione. Such was the general faithlessness of this prince, however, that
Nikias required as a condition of the alliance, some manifest proof of the
sincerity of his intentions; and Perdikkas was soon enabled to afford a proof
of considerable importance.
The relation between Athens and Peloponnesus, since
the conclusion of the truce in the preceding March, had settled into a curious
combination. In Thrace, war was prosecuted by mutual understanding, and with
unabated vigour; but everywhere else the truce was observed. The main purpose
of the truce, however, that of giving time for discussion preliminary to a
definite peace, was completely frustrated. The decree of the Athenian people
(which stands included in their vote sanctioning the truce), for sending and
receiving envoys to negotiate such a peace, seems never to have been executed.
Instead of this, the Lacedaemonians dispatched a considerable reinforcement by
land to join Brasidas; probably at his own request, and also instigated by
hearing of the Athenian armament now under Nikias in Pallene. But Ischagoras,
the commander of the re-enforcement, on reaching the borders of Thessaly, found
all farther progress impracticable, and was compelled to send back his troops.
For Perdikkas, by whose powerful influence alone Brasidas had been enabled to
pass through Thessaly, now directed his Thessalian guests to keep the
new-comers off; which was far more easily executed, and was gratifying to the
feelings of Perdikkas himself, as well as an essential service to the
Athenians. Ischagoras however, with a few companions but without his army made
his way to Brasidas having been particularly directed by the Lacedaemonians to
inspect and report upon the state of affairs. He numbered among his companions
a few select Spartans of the military age, intended to be placed as harmosts or
governors in the cities reduced by Brasidas. This was among the first
violations, apparently often repeated afterwards, of the ancient Spartan
custom—that none except elderly men, above the military age, should be named to
such posts. Indeed Brasidas himself was an illustrious departure from the
ancient rule. This mission of these officers was intended to guard against the
appointment of any but Spartans to such posts—for there were no Spartans in the
army of Brasidas. One of the new-comers, Klearidas, was made governor of
Amphipolis—another, Pasitelidas, of Torone. It is probable that these inspecting commissioners
may have contributed to fetter the activity of Brasidas. Moreover the
newly-declared hostility of Perdikkas, together with disappointment in the
non-arrival of the fresh troops intended to join him, much abridged his means.
We hear of only one exploit performed by him at this time—and that too, more
than six months after the retreat from Macedonia—about January or February, 422
B.C. Having established intelligence with some parties in the town of Potidaea,
in the view of surprising it, he contrived to bring up his army in the night to
the foot of the walls, and even to plant his scaling-ladders, without being
discovered. The sentinel carrying and ringing the bell had just passed by on
the wall, leaving for a short interval an unguarded space (the practice
apparently being, to pass this bell round along the walls from one sentinel to
another throughout the night)—when some of the soldiers of Brasidas took
advantage of the moment to try and mount. But before they could reach the top
of the wall, the sentinel came back, alarm was given, and the assailants were
compelled to retreat.
In the absence of actual war between the ascendent
powers in and near Peloponnesus, during the course of the summer, Thucydides
mentions to us some incidents which perhaps he would have omitted had there
been great warlike operations to describe. The great temple of Here, between Mycenae
and Argos (nearer to the former, and in early times more intimately connected
with it, but now an appendage of the latter; Mycenae itself having been
subjected and almost depopulated by the Argeians)—enjoyed
an ancient Pan-hellenic reputation. The catalogue of
its priestesses, seemingly with a statue or bust of each, was preserved or
imagined through centuries of past time, real and mythical, beginning with the
goddess herself or her immediate nominees. Chrysis, an old woman who had been
priestess there for fifty-six years, happened to fall asleep in the temple with
a burning lamp near to her head; the fillet encircling her head took fire, and
though she herself escaped unhurt, the temple itself, very ancient and perhaps
built of wood, was consumed. From fear of the wrath of the Argeians,
Chrysis fled to Phlius, and subsequently thought it
necessary to seek protection as a suppliant in the temple of Athene Alea at Tegea: Phaeinis was
appointed priestess in her place. The temple was rebuilt on an adjoining spot
by Eupolemus of Argos, continuing as much as possible
the antiquities and traditions of the former, but with greater splendour and
magnitude. Pausanias the traveller, who describes this second edifice as a
visitor near 600 years afterward, saw near it the remnant of the old temple
which had been burnt.
We hear farther of a war in Arcadia, between the two
important cities of Mantineia and Tegea—each attended by its Arcadian allies,
partly free, partly subject. In a battle fought between them at Laodikion, the victory was disputed. Each party erected a
trophy—each sent spoils to the temple of Delphi. We shall have occasion soon to
speak farther of these Arcadian dissensions.
The Boeotians had been no parties to the truce sworn
between Sparta and Athens in the preceding month of March. But they seem to
have followed the example of Sparta in abstaining from hostilities de facto:
and we may conclude that they acceded to the request of Sparta so far as to
allow the transit of Athenian visitors and sacred envoys through Boeotia to the
Delphian temple. The only actual incident which we hear of in Boeotia during
this interval, is one which illustrates forcibly the harsh and ungenerous
ascendency of the Thebans over some of the inferior Boeotian cities. The
Thebans destroyed the walls of Thespiae, and
condemned the city to remain unfortified, on the charge of atticising tendencies. How far this suspicion was well-founded, we have no means of
judging. But the Thespians, far from being dangerous at this moment, were
altogether helpless—having lost the flower of their military force at the
battle of Delium, where their station was on the
defeated wing. It was this very helplessness, brought upon them by their
services to Thebes against Athens, which now both impelled and enabled the
Thebans to enforce the rigorous sentence above-mentioned.
But the month of March (or the Attic Elaphebolion) 422 B.C.— the time prescribed for expiration
of the One year’s truce—had now arrived. It has already been mentioned that
this truce had never been more than partially observed. Brasidas in Thrace had
disregarded it from the beginning. Both the contracting powers had tacitly
acquiesced in the anomalous condition, of war in Thrace coupled with peace
elsewhere. Either of them had thus an excellent pretext for breaking the truce
altogether; and as neither acted upon this pretext, we plainly see that the
paramount feeling and ascendent parties, among both, tended to peace of their
own accord, at that time. There was nothing except the interest of Brasidas,
and of those revolted subjects of Athens to whom he had bound himself, which
kept alive the war in Thrace. Under such a state of feeling, the oath taken to
maintain the truce still seemed imperative on both parties—always excepting
Thracian affairs. Moreover the Athenians were to a certain degree soothed by their
success at Mende and Skione, and by their acquisition of Perdiccas as an ally,
during the summer and autumn of 423 B.C. But the state of sentiment between the
contracting parties was not such as to make it possible to treat for any longer
peace, or to conclude any new agreement; though neither were disposed to depart
from that which had been already concluded.
The mere occurrence of the last day of the truce made
no practical difference at first in this condition of things. The truce had
expired: either party might renew hostilities: but neither actually did renew
them. To the Athenians there was this additional motive for abstaining from
hostilities for a few months longer: the great Pythian festival would be
celebrated at Delphi in July or the beginning of August, and as they had been
excluded from that holy spot during all the interval between the beginning of
the war and the conclusion of the One year’s truce, their pious feelings seem
now to have taken a peculiar longing toward the visits, pilgrimages, and
festivals connected with it. Though the truce therefore had really ceased, no
actual warfare took place until the Pythian games were over.
But though the actions of Athens remained unaltered,
the talk at Athens became very different. Cleon and his supporters renewed
their instances to obtain a vigorous prosecution of the war, and renewed them
with great additional strength of argument; the question being now open to
considerations of political prudence, without any binding obligation.
“At this time (observes Thucydides) the great enemies
of peace were, Brasidas on one side, and Cleon on the other: the former,
because he was in full success and rendered illustrious by the war—the latter
because he thought that, if peace were concluded, he should be detected in his
dishonest politics, and be less easily credited in his criminations of others”.
As to Brasidas, the remark of the historian is indisputable. It would be
wonderful indeed, if he, in whom so many splendid qualities were brought out by
the war, and who had moreover contracted obligations with the Thracian towns
which gave him hopes and fears of his own, entirely apart from Lacedaemon—it
would be wonderful if the war and its continuance were not in his view the
paramount object. In truth his position in Thrace constituted an insurmountable
obstacle to any solid or steady peace, independently of the dispositions of Cleon.
But the colouring which Thucydides gives to Cleon’s
support of the war is open to much greater comment. First, we may well raise
the question, whether Cleon had any real interest in war—whether his personal
or party consequence in the city was at all enhanced by it. He had himself no
talent or competence for warlike operations—which tended infallibly to place
ascendency in the hands of others, and to throw him into the shade. As to his
power of carrying on dishonest intrigues with success, that must depend on the
extent of his political ascendency. Matter of crimination against others
(assuming him to be careless of truth or falsehood) could hardly be wanting
either in war or peace. And if the war brought forward unsuccessful generals
open to his accusations, it would also throw up successful generals, who would
certainly outshine him and would probably put him down. In the life which
Plutarch has given us of Phocion, a plain and straightforward military man, we
read that one of the frequent and criminative speakers of Athens (of character
analogous to that which is ascribed to Cleon) expressed his surprise on hearing
Phocion dissuade the Athenians from embarking in a new war: “Yes (said Phocion),
I think it right to dissuade them: though I know well, that if there be war, I
shall have command over you—if there be peace, you will have command over me”.
This is surely a more rational estimate of the way in which war affects the
comparative importance of the orator and the military officer, than that which
Thucydides pronounces in reference to the interests of Cleon. Moreover, when we
come to follow the political history of Syracuse, we shall find the demagogue
Athenagoras ultra-pacific, and the aristocrat Hermokrates far more warlike. The
former is afraid, not without reason, that war will raise into consequence
energetic military leaders dangerous to the popular constitution. We may add,
that Cleon himself had not been always warlike. He commenced his political
career as an opponent of Pericles, when the latter was strenuously maintaining
the necessity and prudence of beginning the Peloponnesian war. But further—if
we should even grant that Cleon had a separate party-interest in promoting the
war—it will still remain to be considered, whether at this particular crisis,
the employment of energetic warlike measures in Thrace was not really the sound
and prudent policy for Athens. Taking Perikles as the best judge of policy, we
shall find him at the outset of the war inculcating emphatically two important
points—
1. To stand vigorously upon the defensive, maintaining
unimpaired their maritime empire, “keeping their subject-allies well in hand,”
submitting patiently even to see Attica ravaged;
2. To abstain from trying to enlarge their empire or
to make new conquests during the war.
Consistently with this well-defined plan of action,
Perikles, had he lived, would have taken care to interfere vigorously and
betimes to prevent Brasidas from making his conquests. Had such interference
been either impossible or accidentally frustrated, he would have thought no
efforts too great to recover them. To maintain undiminished the integrity of
the empire, as well as that impression of Athenian force upon which the empire
rested, was his cardinal principle. Now it is impossible to deny that in reference
to Thrace, Cleon adhered more closely than his rival Nikias to the policy of
Pericles. It was to Nicias, more than to Cleon, that the fatal mistake made by
Athens in not interfering speedily after Brasidas first broke into Thrace is to
be imputed. It was Nicias and his partisans, desirous of peace at almost any
price, and knowing that the Lacedaemonians also desired it—who encouraged the
Athenians, at a moment of great public depression of spirit, to leave Brasidas
unopposed in Thrace, and rely on the chance of negotiation with Sparta for
arresting his progress. The peace-party at Athens carried their point of the
truce for a year, with the promise, and for the express purpose, of checking
the further conquests of Brasidas; also with the further promise of maturing
that truce into a permanent peace, and obtaining under the peace even the
restoration of Amphipolis.
Such was the policy of Nicias and his party, the
friends of peace, and opponents of Cleon. And the promises which they thus held
out might perhaps appear plausible in March 423, at the moment when the truce
for one year was concluded. But subsequent events had frustrated them in the
most glaring manner, and had even shown the best reason for believing that no
such expectations could possibly be realized, while Brasidas was in unbroken
and unopposed action. For the Lacedaemonians, though seemingly sincere in
concluding the truce on the basis of uti possidetis, and desiring to extend it to Thrace as well
as elsewhere, had been unable to enforce the observance of it upon Brasidas, or
to restrain him even from making new acquisitions—so that Athens never obtained
the benefit of the truce exactly in that region where she most stood in need of
it. Only by the dispatch of her armament to Skione and Mende had she maintained
herself in possession even of Pallene.
Now what was the lesson to be derived from this
experience, when the Athenians came to discuss their future policy, after the
truce was at an end? The great object of all parties at Athens was to recover
the lost possessions in Thrace—especially Amphipolis. Nikias, still urging
negotiations for peace, continued to hold out hopes that the Lacedaemonians
would be willing to restore that place, as the price of their captives now at
Athens. His connection with Sparta would enable him to announce her professions
even upon authority. But to this Cleon might make, and doubtless did make, a
complete reply, grounded upon the most recent experience:—“If the
Lacedaemonians consent to the restitution of Amphipolis (he would say), it will
probably be only with the view of finding some means to escape performance, and
yet to get back their prisoners. But granting that they are perfectly sincere,
they will never be able to control Brasidas, and those parties in Thrace who
are bound up with him by community of feeling and interest; so that after all,
you will give them back their prisoners, on the faith of an equivalent beyond
their power to realize. Look at what has happened during the truce! So
different are the views and obligations of Brasidas in Thrace from those of the
Lacedaemonians, that he would not even obey their order when they directed him
to stand as he was, and to desist from further conquest. Much less will he obey
them when they direct him to surrender what he has already got: least of all,
if they enjoin the surrender of Amphipolis, his grand acquisition and his
central point for all future effort. Depend upon it, if you desire to regain
Amphipolis, you will only regain it by energetic employment of force, as has
happened with Skione and Mende. And you ought to put forth your strength for
this purpose immediately, while the Lacedaemonian prisoners are yet in your
hands, instead of waiting until after you shall have been deluded into giving
them up, thereby losing all your hold upon Lacedaemon.”
Such anticipations were fully verified by the result:
for subsequent history will show that the Lacedaemonians when they had bound
themselves by treaty to give up Amphipolis, either would not, or could not,
enforce performance of their stipulation, even after the death of Brasidas.
Much less could they have done so during his life, when there was his great
personal influence, strenuous will, and hopes of future conquest, to serve as
increased obstruction to them. Such anticipations were also plainly suggested
by the recent past: so that in putting them into the mouth of Cleon, we are
only supposing him to read the lesson open before his eyes.
Now since the war-policy of Kleon, taken at this
moment after the expiration of the One year’s truce, may be thus shown to be
not only more conformable to the genius of Perikles, but also founded on a juster estimate of events both past and future, than the
peace-policy of Nicias, what are we to say to the historian, who, without
refuting such presumptions, every one of which is deduced from his own
narrative—nay, without even indicating their existence—merely tells us that “Cleon
opposed the peace in order that he might cloak dishonest intrigues and find
matter for plausible crimination”? We cannot but say of this criticism, with
profound regret that such words must be pronounced respecting any judgment of
Thucydides, that it is harsh and unfair toward Kleon, and careless in regard to
truth and the instruction of his readers. It breathes not that same spirit of honourable
impartiality which pervades his general history. It is an interpolation by the
officer whose improvidence had occasioned to his countrymen the fatal loss of
Amphipolis, retaliating upon the citizen who justly accused him. It is
conceived in the same tone as his unaccountable judgment in the matter of Sphacteria.
Rejecting on this occasion the judgment of Thucydides,
we may confidently affirm that Cleon had rational public grounds for urging his
countrymen to undertake with energy the reconquest of Amphipolis. Demagogue and
leather-seller though he was, he stands here honourably distinguished, as well
from the tameness and inaction of Nicias, who grasped at peace with hasty
credulity, through sickness of the efforts of war, as from the restless
movement, and novelties, not merely unprofitable, but ruinous, which we shall
presently find springing up under the auspices of Alkibiades. Perikles had said
to his countrymen, at a time when they were enduring all the miseries of
pestilence, and were in a state of despondency even greater than that which
prevailed in BC 422—“You hold your empire and your proud position by the
condition of being willing to encounter cost, fatigue, and danger: abstain from
all views of enlarging the empire, but think no effort too great to maintain it
unimpaired.—To lose what we have once got is more disgraceful than to fail in
attempts at acquisition.” The very same language was probably held by Cleon
when exhorting his countrymen to an expedition for the reconquest of
Amphipolis. But when uttered by him, it would have a very different effect from
that which it had formerly produced when held by Perikles—and different also
from that which it would now have produced if held by Nikias. The entire
peace-party would repudiate it when it came from Cleon—partly out of dislike to
the speaker, partly from conviction, doubtless felt by every one, that an
expedition against Brasidas would be a hazardous and painful service to all
concerned in it, general as well as soldiers—partly also from a persuasion,
sincerely entertained at the time though afterward proved to be illusory by the
result, that Amphipolis might really be got back through peace with the
Lacedaemonians.
If Cleon, in proposing the expedition, originally
proposed himself as the commander, a new ground of objection, and a very
forcible ground, would thus be furnished. Since everything which Kleon does is
understood to be a manifestation of some vicious or silly attribute, we are
told that this was an instance of his absurd presumption, arising out of the
success of Pylus, and persuading him that he was the
only general who could put down Brasidas. But if the success at Pylus had really filled him with such overweening military
conceit, it is most unaccountable that he should not have procured for himself
some command during the year which immediately succeeded the affair at Sphacteria—the
eighth year of the war: a season of most active warlike enterprise, when his
presumption and influence arising out of the Sphacterian victory must have been fresh and glowing. As he obtained no command during this
immediately succeeding period, we may fairly doubt whether he ever really
conceived such excessive personal presumption of his own talents for war, and
whether he did not retain after the affair of Sphacteria the same character
which he had manifested in that affair, reluctance to engage in military
expeditions himself, and a disposition to see them commanded as well as carried
on by others. It is by no means certain that Cleon, in proposing the expedition
against Amphipolis, originally proposed to take the command of it himself: I
think it at least equally probable that his original wish was to induce Nicias
or the Strategi to take the command of it, as in the case of Sphacteria. Nicias
doubtless opposed the expedition as much as he could. When it was determined by
the people, in spite of his opposition, he would peremptorily decline the
command for himself, and would do all he could to force it upon Cleon, or at
least would be better pleased to see it under his command than under that of
any one else. He would be not less glad to exonerate himself from a dangerous
service, than to see his rival entangled in it. And he would have before him
the same alternative which he and his friends had contemplated with so much
satisfaction in the affair of Sphacteria; either the expedition would succeed,
in which case Amphipolis would be taken—or it would fail, and the consequence
would be the ruin of Cleon. The last of the two was really the more probable at
Amphipolis—as Nikias had erroneously imagined it to be at Sphacteria.
It is easy to see, however, that an expedition
proposed under these circumstances by Cleon, though it might command a majority
in the public assembly, would have a large proportion of the citizens unfavourable
to it, and even wishing that it might fail. Moreover, Kleon had neither talents
nor experience for commanding an army; so that the being engaged under his
command in fighting against the ablest officer of the time, could inspire no
confidence to any man in putting on his armour. From all these circumstances
united, political as well as military, we are not surprised to hear that the
hoplites whom he took out with him went with much reluctance. An ignorant
general with unwilling soldiers, many of them politically disliking him, stood
little chance of wresting Amphipolis from Brasidas. But had Nicias or the
Strategi done their duty and carried the entire force of the city under
competent command to the same object, the issue would probably have been
different as to gain and loss—certainly very different as to dishonour.
Cleon started from Peiraeus, apparently toward the
beginning of August, with 1200 Athenian, Lemnian, and Imbrian hoplites, and 300 horsemen—troops of
excellent quality and condition; besides an auxiliary force of allies (number
not exactly known) and thirty triremes. This armament was not of magnitude at
all equal to the taking of Amphipolis; for Brasidas had equal numbers, besides
all the advantages of the position. But it was a part of the scheme of Cleon,
on arriving at Eion, to procure Macedonian and Thracian re-enforcements before
he commenced his attack. He first halted in his voyage near Skione, from which
place he took away such of the hoplites as could be spared from the blockade.
He next sailed across the Gulf from Pallene to the Sithonian peninsula, to a place called the Harbor of the Kolophonians near Torone. Having here learnt that neither Brasidas
himself nor any considerable Peloponnesian garrison were present in Torone, he landed his forces, and marched to attack the
town—sending ten triremes at the same time round a promontory which separated
the harbour of the Kolophonians from Torone to assail the latter place from seaward.
It happened that Brasidas, desiring to enlarge the
fortified circle of Torone, had broken down a portion
of the old wall and employed the materials in building a new and larger wall
inclosing the proasteion or suburb. This new
wall appears to have been still incomplete and in an imperfect state of defense. Pasitelidas, the
Peloponnesian commander, resisted the attack of the Athenians as long as he
could; but when already beginning to give way, he saw the ten Athenian triremes
sailing into the harbour, which was hardly guarded at all. Abandoning the defence
of the suburb, he hastened to repel these new assailants, but came too late, so
that the town was entered from both sides at once. Brasidas, who was not far
off, rendered aid with the utmost celerity, but was yet at five miles’ distance
from the city, when he learnt the capture and was obliged to retire
unsuccessfully. Pasitelidas, the commander, with the
Peloponnesian garrison and the Toronaean male
population, were dispatched as prisoners to Athens; while the Toronaean women and children, by a fate but too common in
those days, were sold as slaves.
After this not unimportant success, Cleon sailed round
the promontory of Athos to Eion at the mouth of the Strymon, within three miles
of Amphipolis. From hence, in execution of his original scheme, he sent envoys
to Perdikkas, urging him to lend effective aid as the ally of Athens in the attack
of Amphipolis with his whole forces; and to Polles,
the king of the Thracian Odomantes, inviting him also
to come with as many Thracian mercenaries as could be levied. The Edonians, the Thracian tribe nearest to Amphipolis, took
part with Brasidas. The local influence of the banished Thucydides would no
longer be at the service of Athens—much less at the service of Kleon. Awaiting
the expected re-enforcements, Kleon employed himself, first in an attack upon Stageirus in the Strymonic Gulf,
which was repulsed; next upon Galepsus, on the coast
opposite the island of Thasos, which was successful. But the re-enforcements
did not at once arrive, and being too weak to attack Amphipolis without them,
he was obliged to remain inactive at Eion; while Brasidas on his side made no
movement out of Amphipolis, but contented himself with keeping constant watch
over the forces of Kleon, the view of which he commanded from his station on
the hill of Kerdylion, on the western bank of the
river, communicating with Amphipolis by the bridge. Some days elapsed in such
inaction on both sides. But the Athenian hoplites, becoming impatient of doing
nothing, soon began to give vent to those feelings of dislike which they had
brought out from Athens against their general, “whose ignorance and cowardice
(says the historian) they contrasted with the skill and bravery of his
opponent.” Athenian hoplites, if they felt such a sentiment, were not likely to
refrain from manifesting it. And Cleon was presently made aware of the fact in
a manner sufficiently painful to force him against his will into some movement;
which, however, he did not intend to be anything else than a march for the
purpose of surveying the ground all round the city, and a demonstration to
escape the appearance of doing nothing—being aware that it was impossible to
attack the place with any effect before his re-enforcements arrived.
To comprehend the important incidents which followed,
it is necessary to say a few words on the topography of Amphipolis, as far as
we can understand it on the imperfect evidence before us. That city was placed
on the left bank of the Strymon, on a conspicuous hill around which the river
makes a bend, first in a south-westerly direction, then, after a short course
to the southward, back in a south-easterly direction. Amphipolis had for its
only artificial fortification one long wall, which began near the point
north-east of the town where the river narrows again into a channel, after
passing through the lake Kerkinitis—ascended along
the eastern side of the hill, crossing the ridge which connects it with Mount Pangaeus—and then descended so as to touch the river again
at another point south of the town—thus being, as it were, a string to the
highly-bent bow formed by the river. On three sides, north, west, and south,
the city was defended only by the Strymon. It was thus visible without any
intervening wall to spectators from the side of the sea (south), as well as
from the side of the continent (or west and north). At some little distance
below the point where the wall touched the river south of the city, was the
bridge, a communication of great importance for the whole country, which
connected the territory of Amphipolis with that of Argilus.
On the western or right bank of the river, bordering it and forming an outer
bend corresponding to the bend of the river, was situated Mount Kerdylium. In fact the course of the Strymon is here
determined by these two steep eminences, Kerdylium on
the west and the hill of Amphipolis on the east, between which it flows. At the
time when Brasidas first took the place, the bridge was totally unconnected
with the long city wall. But during the intervening eighteen months he had
erected a palisade work (probably an earthen bank topped with a palisade)
connecting the two. By means of this palisade the bridge was thus at the time
of Kleon’s expedition comprehended within the fortifications of the city; so
that Brasidas, while keeping watch on Mount Kerdylium,
could pass over whenever he chose into the city without impediment.
In the march which Cleon now undertook, he went up to
the top of the ridge (which runs nearly in an easterly direction from
Amphipolis to Mount Pangaeus) in order to survey the
city and its adjoining ground on the northern and north-eastern side, which he
had not yet seen; that is, the side toward the lake, and toward Thrace which
was not visible from the lower ground near Eion. The road which he was to take
from Eion lay at a small distance eastward of the city long wall, and from the
palisade which connected that wall with the bridge. But he had no expectation
of being attacked in his march—the rather as Brasidas with the larger portion
of his force was visible on Mount Kerdylium. Moreover
the gates of Amphipolis were all shut—not a man was on the wall—nor were many
symptoms of movement to be detected. As there was no evidence before him of
intention to attack, he took no precautions, and marched in careless and
disorderly array. Having reached the top of the ridge, and posted his army on
the strong eminence fronting the highest portion of the Long Wall, he surveyed
at leisure the lake before him, and the side of the city which lay toward
Thrace—or toward Myrkinus, Drabeskus, etc—thus
viewing all the descending portion of the Long Wall northward toward the
Strymon. The perfect quiescence of the city imposed upon and even astonished
him. It seemed altogether undefended, and he almost fancied that if he had
brought battering engines, he could have taken it forthwith. Impressed with the
belief that there was no enemy prepared to fight, he took his time to survey
the ground; while his soldiers became more and more relaxed and careless in
their trim—some even advancing close up to the walls and gates.
But this state of affairs was soon materially changed.
Brasidas, knowing that the Athenian hoplites would not long endure the tedium
of absolute inaction, calculated that by affecting extreme backwardness and
apparent fear, he should seduce Kleon into some incautious movement, of which
advantage might be taken. His station on Mount Kerdylium enabled him to watch the march of the Athenian army from Eion, and when he saw
them pass up along the road outside of the long wall of Amphipolis, he
immediately crossed the river with his forces and entered the town. But it was
not his intention to march out and offer them open battle. For his army, though
equal in number to theirs, was extremely inferior in arms and equipment; in
which points the Athenian force now present was so admirably provided, that his
own men would not think themselves a match for it, if the two armies faced each
other in open field. He relied altogether 011 the effect of sudden sally and
well-timed surprise, when the Athenians should have been thrown into a feeling
of contemptuous security by an exaggerated show of impotence in their enemy.
Having offered the battle sacrifice at the temple of
Athene, Brasidas called his men together to address to them the usual
encouragements prior to an engagement. After appealing to the Dorian pride of
his Peloponnesians, accustomed to triumph over Ionians, he explained to them
his design of retying upon a bold and sudden movement with comparatively small
numbers, against the Athenian army when not prepared for it—when their courage
was not wound up to battle pitch—and when, after carelessly mounting the hill
to survey the ground, they were thinking only of quietly returning to quarters.
He himself at the proper moment would rush out from one gate, and be foremost
in conflict with the enemy. Klearidas, with that bravery which became him as a
Spartan, would follow the example by sallying out from another gate; and the
enemy, taken thus unawares, would probably make little resistance. For the Amphipolitans, this day and their own behaviour would
determine whether they were to be allies of Lacedaemon, or slaves of
Athens—perhaps sold into captivity, or even put to death, as a punishment for
their recent revolt.
These preparations, however, could not be completed in
secrecy. Brasidas and his army were perfectly visible while descending the hill
of Kerdylium, crossing the bridge and entering
Amphipolis, to the Athenian scouts without. Moreover, so conspicuous was the
interior of the city to spectators without, that the temple of Athene, and
Brasidas with its ministers around him performing the ceremony of sacrifice,
was distinctly recognized. The fact was made known to Cleon as he stood on the
high ridge taking his survey, while at the same time those who had gone near to
the gates reported that the feet of many horses and men were beginning to be
seen under them, as if preparing for a sally. He himself went close to the
gate, and satisfied himself of the circumstance: we must recollect that there
was no defender on the walls, nor any danger from missiles. Anxious to avoid
coming to any real engagement before his re-enforcements should arrive, he at
once gave orders for retreat, which he thought might be accomplished before the
attack from within could be fully organized. For he imagined that a
considerable number of troops would be marched out, and ranged in battle order,
before the attack was actually begun—not dreaming that the sally would be
instantaneous, made with a mere handful of men. Orders having been proclaimed
to wheel to the left, and retreat in column on the left flank toward Eion. Cleon,
who was himself on the top of the hill with the right wing, waited only to see
his left and center actually in march on the road to
Eion, and then directed his right also to wheel to the left and follow them.
The whole Athenian army were thus in full retreat,
marching in a direction nearly parallel to the Long Wall of Amphipolis, with
their right or unshielded side exposed to the enemy—when Brasidas, looking over
the southernmost gates of the Long Wall with his small detachment ready marshalled
near him, burst out into contemptuous exclamations on the disorder of their
array. “These men will not stand us: I see it by the quivering of their spears
and of their heads. Men who reel about in that way never stand an assailing
enemy. Open the gates for me instantly, and let us sally out with confidence.”
With that, both the gate of the Long Wall nearest to
the palisade, and the adjoining gate of the palisade itself, were suddenly
thrown open, and Brasidas with his 150 chosen soldiers issued through them to
attack the retreating Athenians. Running rapidly down the straight road which
joined laterally the road toward Eion along which the Athenians were marching,
he charged their central division on the right flank. Their left wing had
already got beyond him on the road toward Eion. Taken completely unprepared,
conscious of their own disorderly array, and astounded at the boldness of their
enemy—the Athenians of the center were seized with
panic, made not the least resistance, and presently fled. Even the Athenian
left, though not attacked at all, instead of halting to lend assistance, shared
the panic and fled in disorder. Having thus disorganized this part of the army,
Brasidas passed along the line to press his attack on the Athenian right: but
in this movement he was mortally wounded and carried off the field unobserved
by his enemies. Meanwhile Klearidas, sallying forth from the Thracian gate, had
attacked the Athenian right on the ridge opposite to him, immediately after it
began its retreat. But the soldiers on the Athenian right had probably seen the
previous movement of Brasidas against the other division, and though astonished
at the sudden danger, had thus a moment’s warning, before they were themselves
assailed, to halt and form on the hill. Klearidas here found a considerable
resistance, in spite of the desertion of Cleon; who, more astounded than any
man in his army by a catastrophe so unlooked for, lost his presence of mind and
fled at once; but was overtaken by a Thracian peltast from Myrkinus, and slain.
His soldiers on the right wing, however, repelled two or three attacks in front
from Klearidas, and maintained their ground, until at length the Chalcidian
cavalry and the peltasts from Myrkinus, having come forth out of the gates,
assailed them with missiles in flank and rear so as to throw them into
disorder. The whole Athenian army was thus put to flight; the left hurrying to
Eion, the men of the right dispersing and seeking safety among the hilly
grounds of Pangaeus in their rear. Their sufferings
and loss in the retreat, from the hands of the pursuing peltasts and cavalry,
were most severe. When they at last again mustered at Eion, not only the
commander Cleon, but 600 Athenian hoplites, half of the force sent out, were
found missing.
So admirably had the attack been concerted, and so
entire was its success, that only seven men perished on the side of the
victors. But of those seven, one was the gallant Brasidas himself, who being
carried into Amphipolis, lived just long enough to learn the complete victory
of his troops and then expired. Great and bitter was the sorrow which his death
occasioned throughout Thrace, especially among the Amphipolitans.
He received, by special decree, the distinguished honour of interment within
their city—the universal habit being to inter even the most eminent deceased
persons in a suburb without the walls. All the allies attended his funeral, in
arms and with military honours. His tomb was encircled by a railing, and the
space immediately fronting it was consecrated as the great agora of the city,
which was remodelled accordingly. He was also proclaimed Oekist or Founder of
Amphipolis, and as such, received heroic worship with annual games and
sacrifices to his honour. The Athenian Agnon, the real founder and originally
recognized Oekist of the city, was stripped of all his commemorative honours
and expunged from the remembrance of the people; the buildings, which served as
visible memento of his name, being destroyed. Full of hatred as the Amphipolitans now were toward Athens—and not merely of
hatred, but of fear, since the loss which they had just sustained of their
saviour and protector—they felt repugnance to the idea of rendering farther
worship to an Athenian Oekist. It was inconvenient to keep up such a religious
link with Athens, now that they were forced to look anxiously to Lacedaemon for
assistance. Klearidas, as governor of Amphipolis, superintended those numerous
alterations in the city which this important change required, together with the
erection of the trophy, just at the spot where Brasidas had first charged the
Athenians; while the remaining armament of Athens, having obtained the usual
truce and buried their dead, returned home without farther operations.
There are few battles recorded in history wherein the
disparity and contrast of the two generals opposed has been so
manifest—consummate skill and courage on the one side against ignorance and
panic on the other. On the singular ability and courage of Brasidas there can
be but one verdict of unqualified admiration. But the criticism passed by
Thucydides on Kleon, here as elsewhere, cannot be adopted without reserves. He
tells us that Kleon undertook his march, from Eion up to the hill in front of
Amphipolis, in the same rash and confident spirit with which he had embarked on
the enterprise against Pylus—in the blind confidence
that no one would resist him. Now I have already, in a former chapter, shown
grounds for concluding that the anticipations of Kleon respecting the capture
of Sphacteria, far from being marked by any spirit of unmeasured presumption,
were sober and judicious—realized to the letter without any unlooked-for aid
from fortune. The remarks here made by Thucydides on that affair are not more
reasonable than the judgment on it in his former chapter; for it is not true
(as he here implies) that Cleon expected no resistance, in Sphacteria—he
calculated on resistance, but knew that he had force sufficient to overcome it.
His fault even at Amphipolis, great as that fault was, did not consist in
rashness and presumption. This charge at least is rebutted by the circumstance,
that he himself wished to make no aggressive movement until his re-enforcements
should arrive—and that he was only constrained, against his own will, to
abandon his intended temporary inactivity during that interval, by the angry
murmurs of his soldiers, who reproached him with ignorance and backwardness—the
latter quality being the reverse of that with which he is branded by
Thucydides.
When Cleon was thus driven to do something, his march
up to the top of the hill, for the purpose of reconnoitring the ground, was not
in itself ill-judged. It might have been accomplished in perfect safety if he
had kept his army in orderly array, prepared for contingencies. But he suffered
himself to be out-generaled and overreached by that simulated consciousness of
impotence and unwillingness to fight which Brasidas took care to present to
him. Among all military stratagems, this has perhaps been the most frequently
practiced with success against inexperienced generals; who are thrown off their
guard and induced to neglect precaution, not because they are naturally more
rash or presumptuous than ordinary men, but because nothing except either a
high order of intellect, or special practice and training, will enable a man to
keep steadily present to his mind liabilities even real and serious, when there
is no discernible evidence to suggest their approach—much more when there is
positive evidence, artfully laid out by a superior enemy, to create belief in
their absence. A fault substantially the same had been committed by Thucydides
himself and his colleague Eucles a year and a half
before, when they suffered Brasidas to surprise the Strymonian bridge and Amphipolis; not even taking common precautions, nor thinking it
necessary to keep the fleet at Eion. They were not men peculiarly rash and
presumptuous, but ignorant and unpracticed, in a
military sense; incapable of keeping before them dangerous contingencies which
they perfectly knew, simply because there was no present evidence of
approaching explosion.
This military incompetence, which made Cleon fall into
the trap laid for him by Brasidas, also made him take wrong measures against
the danger, when he unexpectedly discovered at last that the enemy within were
preparing to attack him. His fatal error consisted in giving instant order for
retreat, under the vain hope that he could get away before the enemy’s attack
could be brought to bear. An abler officer, before he commenced the retreating
march so close to the hostile walls, would have taken care to marshal his men
in proper array, to warn and address them with the usual harangue, and to wind
up their courage to the fighting-point. Up to that moment they had no idea of
being called upon to fight; and the courage of Grecian hoplites—taken thus
unawares while hurrying to get away in disorder visible both to themselves and
their enemies, without any of the usual preliminaries of battle—was but too apt
to prove deficient. To turn the right or unshielded flank to the enemy was
unavoidable, from the direction of the retreating movement; nor is it reasonable
to blame Cleon for this, as some historians have done—or for causing his right
wing to move too soon in following the lead of the left, as Dr. Arnold seems to think. The grand fault seems to have consisted in not waiting
to marshal his men and prepare them for standing fight during their retreat.
Let us add, however—and the remark, if it serves to explain Cleon’s idea of
being able to get away before he was actually assailed, counts as a double
compliment to the judgment as well as boldness of Brasidas—that no other
Lacedaemonian general of that day (perhaps not even Demosthenes, the most
enterprising general of Athens) would have ventured upon an attack with so very
small a band, relying altogether upon the panic produced by his sudden
movement.
But the absence of military knowledge and precaution
is not the worst of Cleon’s faults on this occasion. His want of courage at the
moment of conflict is yet more lamentable, and divests his end of that personal
sympathy which would otherwise have accompanied it. A commander who has been
out-generaled is under a double force of obligation to exert and expose himself
to the uttermost, in order to retrieve the consequences of his own mistakes. He
will thus at least preserve his own personal honour, whatever censure he may
deserve on the score of deficient knowledge and judgment.
What is said about the disgraceful flight of Kleon
himself must be applied, with hardly less severity of criticism, to the
Athenian hoplites under him. They behaved in a manner altogether unworthy of
the reputation of their city; especially the left wing, which seems to have
broken and run away without waiting to be attacked. And when we read in
Thucydides that the men who thus disgraced themselves were among the best and
the best-armed hoplites in Athens—that they came out unwillingly under Cleon—that
they began their scornful murmurs against him before he had committed any
error, despising him for backwardness when he was yet not strong enough to
attempt anything serious, and was only manifesting a reasonable prudence in
awaiting the arrival of expected re-enforcements—when we read this, we shall be
led to compare the expedition against Amphipolis with former artifices
respecting the attack of Sphacteria, and to discern other causes for its
failure besides the military incompetence of the commander. These hoplites
brought out with them from Athens the feelings prevalent among the political
adversaries of Cleon. The expedition was proposed and carried by him, contrary
to the wishes of these adversaries. They could not prevent it, but their
opposition enfeebled it from the beginning, kept within too narrow limits the
force assigned, and was one main reason which frustrated its success. Had Pericles
been alive, Amphipolis might perhaps still have been lost, since its capture
was the fault of the officers employed to defend it. But if lost, it would
probably have been attacked and recovered with the same energy as the revolted
Samos had been; with the full force, and the best generals, that Athens could
furnish. With such an armament under good officers, there was nothing at all
impracticable in the reconquest of the place; especially as at that time it had
no defense on three sides except the Strymon, and
might thus be approached by Athenian ships on that navigable river. The
armament of Cleon, even if his re-enforcements had arrived, was hardly
sufficient for the purpose. But Perikles would have been able to concentrate
upon it the whole strength of the city, without being paralyzed by the
contentions of political party. He would have seen as clearly as Kleon that the
place could only be recovered by force, and that its recovery was the most
important object to which Athens could devote her energies.
It was thus that the Athenians, partly from political
intrigue, partly from the incompetence of Cleon, underwent a disastrous defeat
instead of carrying Amphipolis. But the death of Brasidas converted their
defeat into a substantial victory. There remained no Spartan, like or second to
that eminent man, either as a soldier or a conciliating politician; none who
could replace him in the confidence and affection of the allies of Athens in
Thrace; none who could prosecute those enterprising plans against Athens on her
unshielded side, which he had first shown to be practicable. With him the fears
of Athens, and the hopes of Sparta, in respect to the future, alike
disappeared. The Athenian generals Phormio and Demosthenes had both of them
acquired among the Acarnanians an influence personal to themselves, apart from
their post and from their country. But the career of Brasidas exhibited an
extent of personal ascendency and admiration, obtained as well as deserved,
such as had never before been paralleled by any military chieftain in Greece:
and Plato might well select him as the most suitable historical counterpart to
the heroic Achilles. All the achievements of Brasidas were his own
individually, with nothing more than bare encouragement, sometimes even without
encouragement, from his country. And when we recollect the strict and narrow
routine in which as a Spartan he had been educated, so fatal to the development
of everything like original thought or impulse, and so completely estranged
from all experience of party or political discussion—we are amazed at his
resource and flexibility of character, his power of adapting himself to new
circumstances and new persons, and his felicitous dexterity in making himself
the rallying-point of opposite political parties in each of the various cities
which he acquired. The combination “of every sort of practical excellence”—valour,
intelligence, probity, and gentleness of dealing—which his character presented,
was never forgotten among the subject-allies of Athens; and procured for other
Spartan officers in subsequent years favourable presumptions, which their
conduct was seldom found to realize. At the time when Brasidas perished, in the
flower of his age, he was unquestionably the first man in Greece. And though it
is not given to us to predict what he would have become had he lived, we maybe
sure that the future course of the war would have been sensibly modified,
perhaps even to the advantage of Athens, since she might have had sufficient,
occupation at home to keep her from undertaking her disastrous enterprise in
Sicily.
Thucydides seems to take pleasure in setting forth the
gallant exploits of Brasidas, from the first at Methone to the last at
Amphipolis—not less than the dark side of Cleon; both, though in different
senses, the causes of his banishment. He never mentions the latter except in
connection with some proceeding represented as unwise or discreditable. The
barbarities which the offended majesty of empire thought itself entitled to
practice in ancient times against dependencies revolted and reconquered,
reached their maximum in the propositions against Mitylene and Skione: both of
them are ascribed to Cleon by name as their author. But when we come to the
slaughter of the Melians—equally barbarous, and worse in respect to grounds of
excuse, inasmuch as the Melians had never been subjects of Athens—we find
Thucydides mentioning the deed without naming the proposers.
Respecting the foreign policy of Cleon, the facts
already narrated will enable the reader to form an idea of it as compared with
that of his opponents. I have shown grounds for believing that Thucydides has
forgotten his usual impartiality in criticising this personal enemy; that in
regard to Sphacteria, Cleon was really one main and indispensable cause of
procuring for his country the greatest advantage which she obtained throughout
the whole war; and that in regard to his judgment, as advocating the
prosecution of war, three different times must be distinguished—1. After the
first blockade of the hoplites in Sphacteria—2. After the capture of the
island—3. After the expiration of the One-year truce. On the earliest of those
three occasions, he was wrong, for he seems to have shut the door on all
possibilities of negotiation, by his manner of dealing with the Lacedaemonian
envoys. On the second occasion, he had fair and plausible grounds to offer on
behalf of his opinion, though it turned out unfortunate: moreover, at that
time, all Athens was warlike, and Kleon is not to be treated as the peculiar
adviser of that policy. On the third and last occasion, after the expiration of
the truce, the political counsel of Cleon was right, judicious, and truly Periclean—much
surpassing in wisdom that of his opponents. We shall see in the coming chapters
how those opponents managed the affairs of the state after his death—how Nicias
threw away the interests of Athens in the enforcement of the conditions of
peace—how Nicias and Alcibiades together shipwrecked the power of their country
on the shores of Syracuse. And when we judge the demagogue Cleon in this
comparison, we shall find ground for remarking that Thucydides is reserved and
even indulgent toward the errors and vices of other statesmen—harsh only toward
those of his accuser.
As to the internal policy of Cleon, and his conduct as
a politician in Athenian constitutional life, we have but little trustworthy
evidence. There exists, indeed, a portrait of him drawn in colours broad and
glaring—most impressive to the imagination, and hardly effaceable from the
memory; the portrait in the “Knights” of Aristophanes. It is through this
representation that Cleon has been transmitted to posterity, crucified by a
poet who admits himself to have a personal grudge against him, just as he has
been commemorated in the prose of an historian whose banishment he had
proposed. Of all the productions of Aristophanes, so replete with comic genius
throughout, the “Knights” is the most consummate and irresistible—the most
distinct in its character, symmetry, and purpose. Looked at with a view to the
object of its author, both in reference to the audience and to Cleon, it
deserves the greatest possible admiration, and we are not surprised to learn
that it obtained the first prize. It displays the maximum of that which wit
combined with malice can achieve, in covering an enemy with ridicule, contempt,
and odium. Dean Swift could have desired nothing worse, even for Ditton and
Whiston. The old man Demos of Pnyx, introduced on the stage as personifying the
Athenian people—Kleon, brought on as his newly-bought Paphlagonian slave, who by coaxing, lying, impudent and false denunciation of others, has
gained his master’s ear, and heaps ill-usage upon every one else, while he
enriches himself—the Knights or chief members of what we may call the Athenian
aristocracy, forming the chorus of the piece as Cleon’s pronounced enemies—the
sausage-seller from the market-place, who instigated by Nicias and Demosthenes
along with these Knights, overdoes Cleon in all his own low arts, and supplants
him in the favor of Demos—all this, exhibited with inimitable vivacity of
expression, forms the masterpiece and glory of libelous comedy. The effect
produced upon the Athenian audience when this piece was represented at the Lenaean festival (January, 424, about six months after the
capture of Sphacteria), with Kleon himself and most of the real Knights
present, must have been intense beyond what we can now easily imagine. That Cleon
could maintain himself after this humiliating exposure, is no small proof of
his mental vigour and ability. It does not seem to have impaired his
influence—at least not permanently. For not only do we see him the most
effective opponent of peace during the next two years, but there is ground for
believing that the poet himself found it convenient to soften his tone toward
this powerful enemy.
So ready are most writers to find Cleon guilty, that
they are satisfied with Aristophanes as a witness against him; though no other
public man, of any age or nation, has ever been condemned upon such evidence.
No man thinks of judging Sir Robert Walpole, or Mr. Fox, or Mirabeau, from the numerous
lampoons put in circulation against them. No man will take measure of a
political Englishman from Punch, or of a Frenchman from the Charivari. The unrivalled
comic merit of the “Knights” of Aristophanes is only one reason the more for
distrusting the resemblance of its picture to the real Kleon.
We have means too of testing the Candor and accuracy
of Aristophanes by his delineation of Socrates, whom he introduced in the
comedy of “Clouds” in the year after that of the “Knights.” As a comedy, the
“Clouds” stands second only to the “Knights:” as a picture of Sokrates, it is
little better than pure fancy: it is not even a caricature, but a totally
different person. We may, indeed, perceive single features of resemblance; the
bare feet, and the argumentative subtlety, belong to both: but the entire
portrait is such, that if it bore a different name, no one would think of
comparing it with Sokrates, whom we know well from other sources. With such an
analogy before us, not to mention what we know generally of the portraits of
Pericles by these authors, we are not warranted in treating the portrait of Cleon
as a likeness, except on points where there is corroborative evidence. And we
may add, that some of the hits against him, where we can accidentally test
their pertinence, are decidedly not founded in fact—as, for example, where the
poet accuses Cleon of having deliberately and cunningly robbed Demosthenes of
his laurels in the enterprise against Sphacteria.
In the prose of Thucydides, we find Cleon described as
a dishonest politician—a wrongful accuser of others—the most violent of all the
citizens. Throughout the verse of Aristophanes, these same charges are set
forth with his characteristic emphasis, but others are also superadded—Cleon
practices the basest artifices and deceptions to gain favor with the people,
steals the public money, receives bribes, and extorts compositions from private
persons by wholesale, and thus enriches himself under pretense of zeal for the public treasury. In the comedy of the “Acharnians,”
represented one year earlier than the “Knights,” the poet alludes with great
delight to a sum of five talents, which Cleon had been compelled “to disgorge”,
a present tendered to him by the insular subjects of Athens (if we may believe
Theopompus) for the purpose of procuring a remission of their tribute, and
which the Knights, whose evasions of military service he had exposed, compelled
him to relinquish.
But when we put together the different heads of
indictment accumulated by Aristophanes, it will be found that they are not
easily reconcilable one with the other. For an Athenian, whose temper led him
to violent crimination of others, at the inevitable price of multiplying and
exasperating personal enemies, would find it peculiarly dangerous, if not
impossible, to carry on peculation for his own account. If, on the other hand,
he took the latter turn, he would be inclined to purchase connivance from others
even by winking at real guilt on their part, far from making himself
conspicuous as a calumniator of innocence. We must therefore discuss the side
of the indictment which is indicated in Thucydides; not Kleon as truckling to
the people and cheating for his own pecuniary profit (which is certainly not
the character implied in his speech about the Mitylenians as given to us by the
historian), but Kleon as a man of violent temper and fierce political
antipathies—a bitter speaker—and sometimes dishonest in his calumnies against
adversaries. These are the qualities which, in all countries of free debate, go
to form what is called a great opposition speaker. It was thus that the elder
Cato—the universal biter, whom Persephone was afraid even to admit into Hades
after his death”—was characterized at Rome, even by the admission of his
admirers to some extent, and in a still stronger manner by those who were
unfriendly to him, as Thucydides was to Cleon. In Cato such a temper was not
inconsistent with a high sense of public duty. And Plutarch recounts an
anecdote respecting Cleon, that on first beginning his political career, he
called his friends together, and dissolved his intimacy with them, conceiving
that private friendships would distract him from his paramount duty to the
commonwealth.
Moreover, the reputation of Cleon, as a frequent and
unmeasured accuser of others, may be explained partly by a passage of his enemy
Aristophanes: a passage the more deserving of confidence as a just
representation of fact, since it appears in a comedy (the “Frogs”) represented
(405 B.C.) fifteen years after the death of Kleon, and five years after that of
Hyperbolus, when the poet had less motive for misrepresentations against
either. In the “Frogs,” the scene is laid in Hades, whither the god Dionysus
goes, in the attire of Heracles and along with his slave Xanthias, for the
purpose of bringing up again to earth the deceased poet Euripides. Among the
incidents, Xanthias in the attire which his master had worn, is represented as
acting with violence and insult toward two hostesses of eating-houses;
consuming their substance, robbing them, refusing to pay when called upon, and
even threatening their lives with a drawn sword. Upon which the women, having
no other redress left, announce their resolution of calling, the one upon her
protector Cleon, the other on Hyperbolus, for the purpose of bringing the
offender to justice before the dikastery. This passage shows us (if inferences
on comic evidence are to be held as admissible) that Cleon and Hyperbolus
became involved in accusations partly by helping poor-persons, who had been
wronged, to obtain justice before the dikastery. A rich man who had suffered
injury might purchase of Antipho or some other rhetor, advice and aid as to the
conduct of his complaint. But a poor man or woman would think themselves happy
to obtain the gratuitous suggestion, and sometimes the auxiliary speech, of Cleon
or Hyperbolus, who would thus extend their own popularity, by means very
similar to those practiced by the leading men in Rome.
But besides lending aid to others, doubtless Cleon was
often also a prosecutor, in his own name, of official delinquents, real or
alleged. That some one should undertake this duty was indispensable for the
protection of the city; otherwise the responsibility to which official persons
were subjected after their term of office would have been merely nominal, and
we have proof enough that the general public morality of these official
persons, acting individually, was by no means high. But the duty was at the
same time one which most persons would and did shun. The prosecutor, while
obnoxious to general dislike, gained nothing even by the most complete success;
and if he failed so much as not to procure a minority of votes among the dikasts, equal to one-fifth of the numbers present, he was
condemned to pay a fine of 1000 drachmas. What was still more serious, he drew
upon himself a formidable mass of private hatred, from the friends, partisans,
and the political club of the accused party—extremely menacing to his own
future security and comfort, in a community like Athens. There was therefore
little motive to accept, and great motive to decline, the task of prosecuting
on public grounds. A prudent politician at Athens would undertake it
occasionally, and against special rivals: but he would carefully guard himself
against the reputation of doing it frequently or by inclination—and the orators
constantly do so guard themselves, in those speeches which yet remain.
It is this reputation which Thucydides fastens upon
Kleon, and which, like Cato the censor at Rome, he probably merited; from
native acrimony of temper, from a powerful talent for invective, and from his
position both inferior and hostile to the Athenian knights or aristocracy, who
overshadowed him by their family importance. But in what proportion of cases
his accusations were just or calumnious—the real question upon which a candid
judgment turns—we have no means of deciding, either in his case or in that of
Cato. “To lash the wicked (observes Aristophanes himself) is not only no blame,
but is even a matter of honour to the good.” It has not been common to allow to
Kleon the benefit of this observation, though he is much more entitled to it
than Aristophanes. For the attacks of a poetical libeller admit neither of defence
nor retaliation; whereas a prosecutor before the dikastery found his opponent
prepared to reply or even to retort—and was obliged to specify his charge, as
well as to furnish proof of it—so that there was a fair chance for the innocent
man not to be confounded with the guilty.
The quarrel of Cleon with Aristophanes is said to have
arisen out of an accusation which he brought against that poet in the senate of
Five Hundred, on the subject of his second comedy, the “Babylonians,” exhibited
at the festival of the urban Dionysia in the month of March, 426 B.C. At that
season many strangers were present at Athens; especially many visitors and
deputies from the subject-allies who were bringing their annual tribute. And as
the “Babylonians” (now lost), like so many other productions of Aristophanes,
was full of slashing ridicule not only against individual citizens, but against
the functionaries and institutions of the city, Kleon instituted a complaint
against it in the senate, as an exposure dangerous to the public security
before strangers and allies. We have to recollect that Athens was then in the
midst of an embarrassing war—that the fidelity of her subject-allies was much
doubted—that Lesbos, the greatest of her allies, had been reconquered only in
the preceding year, after a revolt both troublesome and perilous to the
Athenians. Under such circumstances, Kleon might see plausible reason for
thinking that a political comedy of the Aristophanic vein and talent tended to degrade the city in the eyes of strangers, even
granting that it was innocuous when confined to the citizens themselves. The
poet complains that Cleon summoned him before the senate, with terrible threats
and calumny: but it does not appear that any penalty was inflicted. Nor indeed,
had the senate competence to find him guilty or punish him, except to the
extent of a small fine. They could only bring him to trial before the
dikastery, which in this case plainly was not done. He himself, however, seems
to have felt the justice of the warning: for we find that three out of his four
next following plays, before the peace of Nikias (the “Acharnians,”
the “Knights,” and the “Wasps”), were represented at the Lenaean festival, in the month of January, a season when no strangers nor allies were
present. Kleon was doubtless much incensed with the play of the “Knights,” and
seems to have annoyed the poet either by bringing an indictment against him for
exercising freeman’s rights without being duly qualified (since none but
citizens were allowed to appear and act in the dramatic exhibitions), or by
some other means which are not clearly explained. We cannot make out in what
way the poet met him, though it appears that finding less public sympathy than
he thought himself entitled to, he made an apology without intending to be
bound by it. Certain it is, that his remaining plays subsequent to the
“Knights,” though containing some few bitter jests against Kleon, manifest no
second deliberate plan of attack against him.
The battle of Amphipolis removed at once the two most
pronounced individual opponents of peace, Cleon and Brasidas. Athens, too, was
more than ever discouraged and averse to prolonged fighting; for the number of
hoplites slain at Amphipolis doubtless filled the city with mourning, besides
the unparalleled disgrace now tarnishing Athenian soldiership. The peace-party
under the auspices of Nicias and Laches, relieved at once from the internal
opposition of Cleon, as well as from the foreign enterprise of Brasidas, were
enabled to resume their negotiations with Sparta in a spirit promising success.
King Pleistoanax, and the Spartan ephors of the year, were on their side
equally bent on terminating the war, and the deputies of all the allies were
convoked at Sparta for discussion with the envoys of Athens. Such discussion
was continued during the whole autumn and winter after the battle of
Amphipolis, without any actual hostilities on either side. At first the pretentions
advanced were found very conflicting; but at length, after several debates, it
was agreed to treat upon the basis of each party surrendering what had been
acquired by war, The Athenians insisted at first on the restoration of Plataea;
but the Thebans replied that Plataea was theirs neither by force nor by
treason—but by voluntary capitulation and surrender of the inhabitants. This
distinction seems to our ideas somewhat remarkable, since the capitulation of a
besieged town is not less the result of force than capture by storm. But it was
adopted in the present treaty; and under it the Athenians, while foregoing
their demand of Plataea, were enabled to retain Nisaea,
which they had acquired from the Megarians, and Anactorium and Sollium which they had taken from Corinth. To
insure accommodating temper on the part of Athens, the Spartans held out the
threat of invading Attica in the spring, and of establishing a permanent
fortification in the territory: and they even sent round proclamation to their
allies, enjoining all the details requisite for this step. Since Attica had now
been exempt from invasion for three years, the Athenians were probably not
insensible to this threat of renewal under a permanent form.
At the beginning of spring—about the end of March, 421
B.C.—shortly after the urban Dionysia at Athens—the important treaty was
concluded for the term of fifty years. The following were its principal
conditions:—
1. All shall have full liberty to visit all the
public temples of Greece—for purposes of private sacrifice, consultation of
oracle, or visit to the festivals. Every man shall be undisturbed both in going
and coming.—[The value of this article will be felt when we recollect that the
Athenians and their allies had been unable to visit either the Olympic or the
Pythian festival since the beginning of the war].
2. The Delphians shall enjoy full autonomy and
mastery of their temple and their territory.—[This article was intended to
exclude the ancient claim of the Phocian confederacy to the management of the
temple; a claim which the Athenians had once supported, before the Thirty
years’ truce: but they had now little interest in the matter, since the Phocians
were in the ranks of their enemies.]
3. There shall be peace for fifty years between
Athens and Sparta with their respective allies, with abstinence from mischief
either overt or fraudulent, by land as well as by sea.
4. Neither party shall invade for purposes of
mischief the territory of the other—not by any artifice or under any pretence.
Should any subject of difference arise, it shall be settled by equitable means,
and by oaths tendered and taken, in form to be hereafter agreed on.
5. The Lacedaemonians and their allies shall
restore Amphipolis to the Athenians. They shall farther relinquish to the
Athenians Argilaus, Stageirus,
Acanthus, Skolus, Olynthus, and Spartolus. But these
cities shall remain autonomous, on condition of paying tribute to Athens
according to the assessment of Aristeides. Any citizen of these cities
(Amphipolis as well as the others) who may choose to quit them shall be at
liberty to do so, and to carry away his property. Nor shall the cities be
counted hereafter either as allies of Athens or of Sparta, unless Athens shall
induce them by amicable persuasions to become her allies, which she is at
liberty to do if she can.
The inhabitants of Mekyberna,
Sane, and Singe, shall dwell independently in their respective cities, just as
much as the Olynthians and Acanthians.—[These
were towns which adhered to Athens and were still numbered as her allies;
though they were near enough to be molested by Olynthus and Akanthus,
against which this clause was intended to insure them.]
The Lacedaemonians and their allies shall restore
Panaktum to the Athenians.
6. The Athenians shall restore to Sparta Koryphasium, Kythera, Methone, Pteleum,
Atalante—with all the captives in their hands from Sparta or her allies. They
shall farther release all Spartans or allies of Sparta now blocked up in
Skione.
7. The Lacedaemonians and their allies shall give
back all the captives in their hands, from Athens or her allies.
8. Respecting Skione, Torone, Sermylus, or any other town in the possession of
Athens—the Athenians may take their own measures.
9. Oaths shall be exchanged between the
contracting parties according to the solemnities held most binding in each city
respectively, and in the following words—“I will adhere to this convention and
truce sincerely and without fraud.” The oaths shall be annually renewed, and
the terms of peace shall be inscribed on columns at Olympia, Delphi, and the
Isthmus, as well as at Sparta and Athens.
10. Should any matter have been forgotten in the
present convention, the Athenians and Lacedaemonians may alter it by mutual
understanding and consent, without being held to violate their oaths.
These oaths were accordingly exchanged. They were,
taken by seventeen principal Athenians, and as many Spartans, on behalf of
their respective countries—on the 26th day of the month Artemisius at Sparta,
and on the 24th day of Elaphebolion at Athens,
immediately after the urban Dionysia; Pleistolas being Ephor eponymus at Sparta, and Alkaeus
Archon eponymus at Athens. Among the
Lacedaemonians swearing are included the two kings, Agis and Pleistoanax—the
Ephor Pleistolas (and perhaps other ephors, but this
we do not know)—and Tellis, the father of Brasidas. Among the Athenians sworn
are comprised Nikias, Laches, Agnon, Lamaclius, and
Demosthenes.
Such was the peace (commonly known by the name of the
peace of Nikias) concluded in the beginning of the eleventh spring of the war,
which had just lasted ten full years. Its conditions being put to the vote at
Sparta in the assembly of deputies from the Lacedaemonian allies, the majority
accepted them; which, according to the condition adopted and sworn to by every
member of the confederacy, made it binding upon all. There was, indeed, a
special reserve allowed to any particular state in case of religious scruple,
arising out of the fear of offending some of their gods or heroes. Saving this
reserve, the peace had been formally acceded to by the decision of the
confederates. But it soon appeared how little the vote of the majority was
worth, even though enforced by the strong pressure of Lacedaemon herself—when
the more powerful members were among the dissentient minority. The Boeotians,
Megarians and Corinthians all refused to accept it.
The Corinthians were displeased because they did not
recover Sollium and Anactorium;
the Megarians, because they did not regain Nisaea;
the Boeotians, because they were required to surrender Panaktum. In spite of
the urgent solicitations of Sparta, the deputies of all these powerful states
not only denounced the peace as unjust, and voted against it in the general
assembly of allies—but refused to accept it when the vote was carried, and went
home to their respective cities for instructions.
Such were the conditions, and such the accompanying
circumstances, of the peace of Nicias, which terminated, or professed to
terminate, the great Peloponnesian War, after a duration of ten years. Its
consequences and fruits in many respects, such as were not anticipated by
either of the concluding parties, will be seen in the following chapters.
|