READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
GEORGE GROTE'S HISTORY OF GREECECHAPTER XI.SOLONIAN LAWS AND CONSTITUTION.
We now approach a new era in Grecian history,—the first known example of a
genuine and disinterested constitutional reform, and the first foundation-stone
of that great fabric, which afterwards became the type of democracy in Greece.
The archonship of the eupatrid Solon dates in 594 B. C., thirty years
after that of Drako, and about eighteen years after the conspiracy of Kylôn,
assuming the latter event to be correctly placed B. C. 612.
The life of Solon by Plutarch and by Diogenês,
especially the former, are
our principal sources of information respecting this remarkable man; and while
we thank them for what they have told us, it is impossible to avoid expressing
disappointment that they have not told us more. For Plutarch certainly had
before him both the original poems, and the original laws, of Solon, and the
few transcripts which he gives from one or the other form the principal charm
of his biography: but such valuable materials ought to have been made available
to a more instructive result than that which he has brought out. There is
hardly anything more to be deplored, amidst the lost treasures of the Grecian
mind, than the poems of Solon; for we see by the remaining fragments, that they
contained notices of the public and social phenomena before him, which he was
compelled attentively to study,—blended with the touching expression of his own
personal feelings, in the post, alike honorable and difficult, to which the
confidence of his countrymen had exalted him.
Solon, son of Exekestidês, was a eupatrid of middling
fortune, but of the purest heroic blood, belonging to the gens or family
of the Kodrids and Neleids, and tracing his origin to the god Poseidôn. His
father is said to have diminished his substance by prodigality, which compelled
Solon in his earlier years to have recourse to trade, and in this pursuit he
visited many parts of Greece and Asia. He was thus enabled to enlarge the
sphere of his observation, and to provide material for thought as well as for
composition: and his poetical talents displayed themselves at a very early age,
first on light, afterwards on serious subjects. It will be recollected that
there was at that time no Greek prose writing, and that the acquisitions as
well as the effusions of an intellectual man, even in their simplest form,
adjusted themselves not to the limitations of the period and the semicolon, but
to those of the hexameter and pentameter: nor in point of fact do the verses of
Solon aspire to any higher effect than we are accustomed to associate with an
earnest, touching, and admonitory prose composition. The advice and appeals
which he frequently addressed to his countrymen were delivered in this
easy metre, doubtless far less difficult than the elaborate prose of subsequent writers or speakers, such as Thucydidês, Isokratês, or
Demosthenês. His poetry and his reputation became known throughout many parts
of Greece, and he was classed along with Thalês of Milêtus, Bias of Priênê,
Pittakus of Mytilênê, Periander of Corinth, Kleobulus of Lindus, Cheilôn of
Lacedæmon,—altogether forming the constellation afterwards renowned as the
Seven wise men.
The first particular event in respect to which Solon
appears as an active politician, is the possession of the island of Salamis,
then disputed between Megara and Athens. Megara was at that time able to
contest with Athens, and for sometime to contest with success, the occupation
of this important island,—a remarkable fact, which perhaps may be explained by
supposing that the inhabitants of Athens and its neighborhood carried on the
struggle with only partial aid from the rest of Attica. However this may be, it
appears that the Megarians had actually established themselves in Salamis, at
the time when Solon began his political career, and that the Athenians had
experienced so much loss in the struggle, as to have formally prohibited any
citizen from ever submitting a proposition for its reconquest. Stung with this
dishonorable abnegation, Solon counterfeited a state of ecstatic excitement,
rushed into the agora, and there, on the stone usually occupied by the official
herald, pronounced to the crowd around a short elegiac poem, which he had
previously composed on the subject of Salamis. He enforced upon them the
disgrace of abandoning the island, and wrought so powerfully upon their
feelings, that they rescinded the prohibitory law: “Rather (he exclaimed) would
I forfeit my native city, and become a citizen of Pholegandrus, than be still
named an Athenian, branded with the shame of surrendered Salamis!” The
Athenians again entered into the war, and conferred upon him the command of
it,—partly, as we are told, at the instigation of Peisistratus, though the
latter must have been at this time (600-594 B. C.) a very young man,
or rather a boy.
The stories in Plutarch, as to the way in which
Salamis was recovered, are contradictory as well as apocryphal, ascribing to
Solon various stratagems to deceive the Megarian occupiers; unfortunately, no
authority is given for any of them. According to that which seems the most
plausible, he was directed by the Delphian god, first to propitiate the local
heroes of the island; and he accordingly crossed over to it by night, for the
purpose of sacrificing to the heroes Periphêmus and Kychreus, on the Salaminian
shore. Five hundred Athenian volunteers were then levied for the attack of the
island, under the stipulation that if they were victorious they should hold it
in property and citizenship. They were safely landed on an outlying
promontory, while Solon, having been fortunate enough to seize a ship which the
Megarians had sent to watch the proceedings, manned it with Athenians, and
sailed straight towards the city of Salamis, to which the five hundred
Athenians who had landed also directed their march. The Megarians marched out
from the city to repel the latter, and during the heat of the engagement,
Solon, with his Megarian ship, and Athenian crew, sailed directly to the city:
the Megarians, interpreting this as the return of their own crew, permitted the
ship to approach without resistance, and the city was thus taken by surprise.
Permission having been given to the Megarians to quit the island, Solon
took possession of it for the Athenians, erecting a temple to Enyalius, the god
of war, on Cape Skiradium, near the city of Salamis.
The citizens of Megara, however, made various efforts
for the recovery of so valuable a possession, so that a war ensued long as well
as disastrous to both parties. At last, it was agreed between them to refer the
dispute to the arbitration of Sparta, and five Spartans were appointed to
decide it,—Kritolaidas, Amompharetus, Hypsêchidas, Anaxilas, and Kleomenês. The
verdict in favor of Athens was founded on evidence which it is somewhat curious
to trace. Both parties attempted to show that the dead bodies buried in the
island conformed to their own peculiar mode of interment, and both parties are
said to have cited verses from the catalogue of the Iliad,—each accusing the
other of error or interpolation. But the Athenians had the advantage on two
points; first, there were oracles from Delphi, wherein Salamis was mentioned
with the epithet Ionian; next, Philæus and Eurysakês, sons of the Telamonian
Ajax, the great hero of the island, had accepted the citizenship of Athens,
made over Salamis to the Athenians, and transferred their own residences to
Braurôn and Melitê in Attica, where the deme or gens Philaidæ still worshipped
Philæus as its eponymous ancestor. Such a title was held sufficient, and
Salamis was adjudged by the five Spartans to Attica, with which it ever
afterwards remained incorporated until the days of Macedonian supremacy.
Two centuries and a half later, when the orator Æschinês argued the Athenian
right to Amphipolis against Philip of Macedon, the legendary elements of the
title were indeed put forward, but more in the way of preface or introduction
to the substantial political grounds. But in the year 600 B. C.,
the authority of the legend was more deep-seated and operative, and adequate by
itself to determine a favorable verdict.
In addition to the conquest of Salamis, Solon
increased his reputation by espousing the cause of the Delphian temple against
the extortionate proceedings of the inhabitants of Kirrha, of which more will
be said in a coming chapter; and the favor of the oracle was probably not
without its effect in procuring for him that encouraging prophecy with which
his legislative career opened.
It is on the occasion of Solon’s legislation, that we
obtain our first glimpse—unfortunately, but a glimpse—of the actual state of
Attica and its inhabitants. It is a sad and repulsive picture, presenting to us
political discord and private suffering combined.
Violent dissensions prevailed among the inhabitants of
Attica, who were separated into three factions,—the pedieis, or men of the
plain, comprising Athens, Eleusis, and the neighboring territory, among whom
the greatest number of rich families were included; the mountaineers in the
east and north of Attica, called diakrii, who were on the whole the poorest
party; and the paralii in the southern portion of Attica, from sea to sea,
whose means and social position were intermediate between the two. Upon
what particular points these intestine disputes turned we are not distinctly
informed; they were not, however, peculiar to the period immediately preceding
the archontate of Solon; they had prevailed before, and they reappear
afterwards prior to the[p. 94] despotism of Peisistratus, the latter standing forward as the leader
of the diakrii, and as champion, real or pretended, of the poorer population.
But in the time of Solon these intestine quarrels were
aggravated by something much more difficult to deal with,—a general mutiny of
the poorer population against the rich, resulting from misery combined with
oppression. The thêtes, whose condition we have already contemplated in the
poems of Homer and Hesiod, are now presented to us as forming the bulk of the
population of Attica,—the cultivating tenants, metayers, and small proprietors
of the country. They are exhibited as weighed down by debts and dependence, and
driven in large numbers out of a state of freedom into slavery,—the whole mass
of them, we are told, being in debt to the rich, who are proprietors of the
greater part of the soil. They
had either borrowed money for their own necessities, or they tilled the lands
of the rich as dependent tenants, paying a stipulated portion of the produce,
and in this capacity they were largely in arrear.
All the calamitous effects were here seen of the old
harsh law of debtor and creditor,—once prevalent in Greece, Italy, Asia, and a
large portion of the world,—combined with the recognition of slavery as a
legitimate status, and of the right of one man to sell himself as well as that of another
man to buy him. Every debtor unable to fulfil his contract was liable to be
adjudged as the slave of his creditor, until he could find means either of
paying it or working it out; and not only he himself, but his minor sons and
unmarried daughters and sisters also, whom the law gave him the power of
selling. The
poor man thus borrowed upon the security of his body, to translate literally
the Greek phrase, and upon that of the persons of his family; and so severely
had these oppressive contracts been enforced, that many debtors had been
reduced from freedom to slavery in Attica itself,—many others had been sold for
exportation,—and some had only hitherto preserved their own freedom by selling
their children. Moreover, a great number of the smaller properties in Attica
were under mortgage, signified,—according to the formality usual in the Attic
law, and continued down throughout the historical times,—by a stone pillar
erected on the land, inscribed with the name of the lender and the amount of
the loan. The proprietors of these mortgaged lands, in case of an unfavorable
turn of events, had no other prospect except that of irremediable slavery for
themselves and their families, either in their own native country, robbed of
all its delights, or in some barbarian region where the Attic accent would
never meet their ears. Some had fled the country to escape legal adjudication
of their persons, and earned a miserable subsistence in foreign parts by
degrading occupations: upon several, too, this deplorable lot had fallen by
unjust condemnation and corrupt judges; the conduct of the rich, in regard to
money sacred and profane, in regard to matters public as well as private, being
thoroughly unprincipled and rapacious.
The manifold and long-continued suffering of the poor
under this system, plunged into a state of debasement not more tolerable than
that of the Gallic plebs,—and the injustices of the rich, in whom all political
power was then vested, are facts well attested by the poems of Solon himself, even in the short fragments
preserved to us: and
it appears that immediately preceding the time of his archonship, the evils had
ripened to such a point,—and the determination of the mass of sufferers, to
extort for themselves some mode of relief, had become so pronounced,—that the
existing laws could no longer be enforced. According to the profound remark of
Aristotle,—that seditions are generated by great causes but out of small
incidents,—we may
conceive that some recent events had occurred as immediate stimulants to the
outbreak of the debtors,—like those which lend so striking an interest to the
early Roman annals, as the inflaming sparks of violent popular movements for
which the train had long before been laid. Condemnations by the archons, of
insolvent debtors, may have been unusually numerous, or the maltreatment of
some particular debtor, once a respected freeman, in his condition of slavery,
may have been brought to act vividly upon the public sympathies,—like the case
of the old plebeian centurion at Rome,—first
impoverished by the plunder of the enemy, then reduced to borrow, and lastly
adjudged to his creditor as an insolvent,—who claimed the protection of the people in the forum,
rousing their feelings to the highest pitch by the marks of the slave-whip
visible on his person. Some such incidents had probably happened, though we
have no historians to recount them; moreover, it is not unreasonable to
imagine, that that public mental affliction which the purifier Epimenidês had
been invoked to appease, as it sprung in part from pestilence, so it had its
cause partly in years of sterility, which must of course have aggravated the
distress of the small cultivators. However this may be, such was the condition
of things in 594 B. C., through mutiny of the poor freemen and
thêtes, and uneasiness of the middling citizens, that the governing oligarchy,
unable either to enforce their private debts or to maintain their political
power, were obliged to invoke the well-known wisdom and integrity of Solon.
Though his vigorous protest—which doubtless rendered him acceptable to the mass
of the people—against the iniquity of the existing system had already been
proclaimed in his poems, they still hoped that he would serve as an auxiliary,
to help them over their difficulties, and they therefore chose him, nominally,
as archon along with Philombrotus, but with power in substance dictatorial.
It had happened in several Grecian states, that the
governing oligarchies, either by quarrels among their own members or by the
general bad condition of the people under their government, were deprived of
that hold upon the public mind which was essential to their power; and
sometimes, as in the case of Pittakus of Mitylênê, anterior to the archonship
of Solon, and often in the factions of the Italian republics in the Middle
Ages, the collision of opposing forces had rendered society intolerable, and driven
all parties to acquiesce in the choice of some reforming dictator. Usually,
however, in the early Greek oligarchies, this ultimate crisis was anticipated
by some ambitious individual, who availed himself of the public discontent, to
overthrow the oligarchy, and usurp the powers of a despot; and so, probably, it
might have happened in Athens, had not the recent failure of Kylôn, with all
its miserable consequences, operated as a deterring motive. It is curious to
read, in the words of Solon himself, the temper in which his appointment was
construed by a large portion of the community, but most especially by his own
friends: and we are to bear in mind that at this early day, so far as our knowledge goes,
democratical government was a thing unknown in Greece,—all Grecian governments
were either oligarchical or despotic, the mass of the freemen having not yet
tasted of constitutional privilege. His own friends and supporters were the
first to urge him, while redressing the prevalent discontents, to multiply
partisans for himself personally, and seize the supreme power: they even “chid
him as a madman, for declining to haul up the net when the fish were already
enmeshed.” The
mass of the people, in despair with their lot, would gladly have seconded him
in such an attempt, and many even among the oligarchy might have acquiesced in
his personal government, from the mere apprehension of something worse, if they
resisted it. That Solon might easily have made himself despot, admits of little
doubt; and though the position of a Greek despot was always perilous, he would
have had greater facility for maintaining himself in it than Peisistratus
possessed after him; so that nothing but the combination of prudence and virtue
which marks his lofty character, restricted him within the trust specially
confided to him. To the surprise of every one,—to the dissatisfaction of his
own friends,—under the complaints alike, as he says, of various extreme and
dissentient parties, who required him to adopt measures fatal to the peace of
society,—he set
himself honestly to solve the very difficult and critical problem submitted to
him.
Of all grievances, the most urgent was the condition
of the poorer class of debtors; and to their relief Solon’s first measure, the
memorable seisachtheia, or shaking off of burdens, was directed. The relief which it afforded was
complete and immediate. It cancelled at once all those contracts in which the
debtor had borrowed on the security of either his person or of his land: it
forbade all future loans or contracts in which the person of the debtor was
pledged as security: it deprived the creditor in future of all power to
imprison, or enslave, or extort work from his debtor, and confined him to an
effective judgment at law, authorizing the seizure of the property of the
latter. It swept off all the numerous mortgage pillars from the landed
properties in Attica, and left the land free from all past claims. It
liberated, and restored to their full rights, all those debtors who were
actually in slavery under previous legal adjudication; and it even provided the
means—we do not know how—of repurchasing in foreign lands, and bringing back to
a renewed life of liberty in Attica, many insolvents who had been sold for
exportation. And
while Solon forbade every Athenian to pledge or sell his own person into
slavery, he took a step farther in the same direction, by forbidding him to
pledge or sell his son, his daughter, or an unmarried sister under his
tutelage,—excepting only the case in which either of the latter might be
detected in unchastity. Whether this last ordinance was contemporaneous with the
seisachtheia, or followed as one of his subsequent reforms, seems doubtful.
By this extensive measure the poor debtors,—the thêtes, small tenants, and proprietors,—together with their families, were rescued from suffering and peril. But these were not the only debtors in the state: the creditors and landlords of the exonerated thêtes were doubtless in their turn debtors to others, and were less able to discharge their obligations in consequence of the loss inflicted upon them by the seisachtheia. It was to assist these wealthier debtors, whose bodies were in no danger,—yet without exonerating them entirely,—that Solon resorted to the additional expedient of debasing the money standard; he lowered the standard of the drachma in a proportion something more than twenty-five per cent., so that one hundred drachmas of the new standard contained no more silver than seventy-three of the old, or one hundred of the old were equivalent to one hundred and thirty-eight of the new. By this change, the creditors of these more substantial debtors were obliged to submit to a loss, while the debtors acquired an exemption, to the extent of about twenty-seven per cent. [p. 101]Lastly,
Solon decreed that all those who had been condemned by the archons to
atīmy (civil disfranchisement) should be restored to their full privileges
of citizens,—excepting, however, from this indulgence those who had been
condemned by the ephetæ, or by the areopagus, or by the phylo-basileis (the
four kings of the tribes), after trial in the prytaneium, on charges either of
murder or treason. So
wholesale a measure of amnesty affords strong grounds for believing that the
previous judgments of the archons had been intolerably harsh; and it is to be
recollected that the Drakonian ordinances were then in force.
Such were the measures of relief with which Solon met the dangerous discontent then prevalent. That the wealthy men and leaders of the people, whose insolence and iniquity he has himself so sharply denounced in his poems, and whose views in nominating him he had greatly disappointed, should have detested propositions which robbed them without compensation of so many of their legal rites, it is easy to imagine. But the statement of Plutarch, that the poor emancipated debtors were also dissatisfied, from having expected that Solon would not only remit their debts, but also redivide the soil of Attica, seems utterly incredible; nor is it confirmed by any passage now remaining of the Solonian poems. Plutarch conceives the poor debtors as having in their minds the comparison with Lykurgus, and the equality of property at Sparta, which, as I have already endeavored to show, is a fiction; and even had it been true, as matter of history long past and antiquated, would not have been likely to work upon the minds of the multitude of Attica in the forcible way that the biographer supposes. The seisachtheia must have exasperated the feelings and diminished the fortunes of many persons; but it gave to the large body of thêtes and small proprietors all that they could possibly have hoped. And we are told that after a short interval it became eminently acceptable in the general public mind, and procured for Solon a great increase of popularity,—all ranks concurring in a common sacrifice of thanksgiving and harmony. One incident there was which occasioned an outcry of indignation. Three rich friends of Solon, all men of great family in the state, and bearing names which will hereafter reappear in this history as borne by their descendants,—Konôn, Kleinias, and Hipponikus,—having obtained from Solon some previous hint of his designs, profited by it, first, to borrow money, and next, to make purchases of lands; and this selfish breach of confidence would have disgraced Solon himself, had it not been found that he was personally a great loser, having lent money to the extent of five talents. We should have been glad to learn what authority Plutarch had for this anecdote, which could hardly have been recorded in Solon’s own poems. In regard to the whole measure of the seisachtheia,
indeed, though the poems of Solon were open to every one, ancient authors gave
different statements, both of its purport and of its extent. Most of them
construed it as having cancelled indiscriminately all money contracts; while
Androtion, and others, thought that it did nothing more than lower the rate of
interest and depreciate the currency to the extent of twenty-seven per cent.,
leaving the letter of the contracts unchanged. How Androtion came to maintain
such an opinion we cannot easily understand, for the fragments now remaining
from Solon seem distinctly to refute it, though, on the other hand, they do not
go so far as to substantiate the full extent of the opposite view entertained
by many writers,—that all money contracts indiscriminately were rescinded: against
which there is also a farther reason, that, if the fact had been so, Solon could have had
no motive to debase the money standard. Such debasement supposes that there
must have been some debtors, at least, whose contracts
remained valid, and whom, nevertheless, he desired partially to assist. His
poems distinctly mention three things: 1. The removal of the mortgage pillars.
2. The enfranchisement of the land. 3. The protection, liberation, and
restoration of the persons of endangered or enslaved debtors. All these
expressions point distinctly to the thêtes and small proprietors, whose
sufferings and peril were the most urgent, and whose case required a remedy
immediate as well as complete: we find that his repudiation of debts was
carried far enough to exonerate them, but no farther.
It seems to have been the respect entertained for the
character of Solon which partly occasioned these various misconceptions of his
ordinances for the relief of debtors: Androtion in ancient, and some eminent
critics in modern times, are anxious to make out that he gave relief without
loss or injustice to any one. But this opinion is altogether inadmissible: the
loss to creditors, by the wholesale abrogation of numerous prëexisting
contracts, and by the partial depreciation of the coin, is a fact not to be
disguised. The seisachtheia of Solon, unjust so far as it rescinded previous
agreements, but highly salutary in its consequences, is to be vindicated by
showing that in no other way could the bonds of government have been held together, or the
misery of the multitude alleviated. We are to consider, first, the great
personal cruelty of these preëxisting contracts, which condemned the body of
the free debtor and his family to slavery; next, the profound detestation
created by such a system in the large mass of the poor, against both the judges
and the creditors by whom it had been enforced, which rendered their feelings
unmanageable, so soon as they came together under the sentiment of a common
danger, and with the determination to insure to each other mutual protection.
Moreover, the law which vests a creditor with power over the person of his
debtor, so as to convert him into a slave, is likely to give rise to a class of
loans, which inspire nothing but abhorrence,—money lent with the foreknowledge
that the borrower will be unable to repay it, but also in the conviction that
the value of his person as a slave will make good the loss; thus reducing him
to a condition of extreme misery, for the purpose sometimes of aggrandizing,
sometimes of enriching, the lender. Now the foundation on which the respect for
contracts rests, under a good law of debtor and creditor, is the very reverse
of this; it rests on the firm conviction that such contracts are advantageous
to both parties as a class, and that to break up the confidence essential to
their existence would produce extensive mischief throughout all society. The
man whose reverence for the obligation of a contract is now the most profound,
would have entertained a very different sentiment if he had witnessed the
dealings of lender and borrower at Athens, under the old ante-Solonian law. The
oligarchy had tried their best to enforce this law of debtor and creditor, with
its disastrous series of contracts, and the only reason why they consented to
invoke the aid of Solon, was because they had lost the power of enforcing it
any longer, in consequence of the newly awakened courage and combination of the
people. That which they could not do for themselves, Solon could not have done
for them, even had he been willing; nor had he in his possession the means
either of exempting or compensating those creditors, who, separately taken,
were open to no reproach; indeed, in following his proceedings, we see plainly
that he thought compensation due, not to the creditors, but to the past
sufferings of the enslaved debtors, since he redeemed several of them from
foreign captivity, and
brought them back to their home. It is certain that no measure, simply and
exclusively prospective, would have sufficed for the emergency: there was an
absolute necessity for overruling all that class of preëxisting rights which
had produced so violent a social fever. While therefore, to this extent, the
seisachtheia cannot be acquitted of injustice, we may confidently affirm that
the injustice inflicted was an indispensable price, paid for the maintenance of
the peace of society, and for the final abrogation of a disastrous system as
regarded insolvents. And
the feeling as well as the legislation universal in the modern European world,
by interdicting beforehand all contracts for selling a man’s person or that of
his children into slavery, goes far to sanction practically the Solonian
repudiation.
One thing is never to be forgotten in regard to this
measure, combined with the concurrent amendments introduced by Solon in the
law,—it settled finally the question to which it referred. Never again do we
hear of the law of debtor and creditor as disturbing Athenian tranquillity. The
general sentiment which grew up at Athens, under the Solonian money-law, and
under the democratical government, was one of high respect for the sanctity of
contracts. Not only was there never any demand in the Athenian democracy for
new tables or a depreciation of the money standard, but a formal abnegation of
any such projects was inserted in the solemn oath taken annually by the
numerous diakasts, who formed the popular judicial body, called hêliæa, or the
hêliastic jurors,—the same oath which pledged them to uphold the democratical constitution, also bound
them to repudiate all proposals either for an abrogation of debts or for a
redivision of the lands. There
can be little doubt that under the Solonian law, which enabled the creditor to
seize the property of his debtor, but gave him no power over the person, the
system of money-lending assumed a more beneficial character: the old noxious
contracts, mere snares for the liberty of a poor freeman and his children,
disappeared, and loans of money took their place, founded on the property and
prospective earnings of the debtor, which were in the main useful to both
parties, and therefore maintained their place in the moral sentiment of the
public. And though Solon had found himself compelled to rescind all the
mortgages on land subsisting in his time, we see money freely lent upon this
same security, throughout the historical times of Athens, and the evidentiary mortgage pillars
remaining ever after undisturbed.
In the sentiment of an early society, as in the old
Roman law, a distinction is commonly made between the principal and the
interest of a loan, though the creditors have sought to blend them indissolubly
together. If the borrower cannot fulfil his promise to repay the principal, the
public will regard him as having committed a wrong which he must make good by
his person; but there is not the same unanimity as to his promise to pay
interest: on the contrary, the very exaction of interest will be regarded by many
in the same light in which the English law considers usurious interest, as
tainting the whole transaction. But in the modern mind, principal, and interest
within a limited rate, have so grown together, that we hardly understand how it
can ever have been pronounced unworthy of an honorable citizen to lend money on
interest; yet such is the declared opinion of Aristotle, and other superior men
of antiquity; while the Roman Cato, the censor, went so far as to denounce the
practice as a heinous crime. It
was comprehended by them among the worst of the tricks of trade,—and they held
that all trade, or profit derived from interchange, was unnatural, as being
made by one man at the expense of another: such pursuits, therefore, could not
be commended, though they might be tolerated to a certain extent as matter of
necessity, but they belonged essentially to an inferior order of citizens. What
is remarkable in Greece is, that the antipathy of a very early state of society
against traders and money-lenders lasted longer among the philosophers than
among the mass of the people,—it harmonized more with the social idéal of
the former, than with the practical instincts of the latter.
In a rude condition, such as that of the ancient
Germans described by Tacitus, loans on interest are unknown: habitually
careless of the future, the Germans were gratified both in giving and receiving
presents, but without any idea that they thereby either imposed or contracted
an obligation. To a
people in this state of feeling, a loan on interest presents the repulsive idea
of making profit out of the distress of the borrower; moreover, it is worthy of
remark, that the first borrowers must have been for the most part men driven to
this necessity by the pressure of want, and contracting debt as a desperate
resource, without any fair prospect of ability to repay: debt and famine run
together, in the mind of the poet Hesiod. The
borrower is, in this unhappy state, rather a distressed man soliciting aid, than a solvent man
capable of making and fulfilling a contract; and if he cannot find a friend to
make him a free gift in the former character, he will not, under the latter
character, obtain a loan from a stranger, except by the promise of exorbitant
interest, and
by the fullest eventual power over his person which he is in a condition to
grant. In process of time a new class of borrowers rise up, who demand money for temporary convenience or
profit, but with full prospect of repayment,—a relation of lender and borrower
quite different from that of the earlier period, when it presented itself in
the repulsive form of misery on the one side, set against the prospect of very
large profit on the other. If the Germans of the time of Tacitus had looked to
the condition of the poor debtors in Gaul, reduced to servitude under a rich
creditor, and swelling by hundreds the crowd of his attendants, they would not
have been disposed to regret their own ignorance of the practice of
money-lending. How
much the interest of money was then regarded as an undue profit extorted from
distress, is powerfully illustrated by the old Jewish law; the Jew being permitted to take
interest from foreigners (whom the lawgiver did not think himself obliged to
protect), but not from his own countrymen. The Koran follows out this point of view consistently, and prohibits
the taking of interest altogether. In most other nations, laws have been made
to limit the rate of interest, and at Rome, especially, the legal rate was
successively lowered,—though it seems, as might have been expected, that the
restrictive ordinances were constantly eluded. All such restrictions have been
intended for the protection of debtors; an effect which large experience proves
them never to produce, unless it be called protection to render the obtaining
of money on loan impracticable for the most distressed borrowers. But there was
another effect which they did tend to produce,—they softened
down the primitive antipathy against the practice generally, and confined the
odious name of usury to loans lent above the fixed legal rate.
In this way alone could they operate beneficially, and
their tendency to counterwork the previous feeling was at that time not
unimportant, coinciding as it did with other tendencies arising out of the
industrial progress of society, which gradually exhibited the relation of
lender and borrower in a light more reciprocally beneficial, and less repugnant
to the sympathies of the bystander.
At Athens, the more favorable point of view prevailed
throughout all the historical times,—the march of industry and commerce, under
the mitigated law which prevailed subsequently to Solon, had been sufficient to
bring it about at a very early period, and to suppress all public antipathy
against lenders at interest. We
may remark, too, that this more equitable tone of opinion grew up
spontaneously, without any legal restriction on the rate of interest,—no such restriction having
ever been imposed, and the rate being expressly declared free by a law ascribed
to Solon himself. The
same may probably be said of the communities of Greece generally,—at least
there is no information to make us suppose the contrary. But the feeling
against lending money at interest remained in the bosoms of the philosophical
men long after it had ceased to form a part of the practical morality of the
citizens, and long after it had ceased to be justified by the appearances of
the case as at first it really had been. Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, and
Plutarch, treat the practice as a branch of that commercial and money-getting
spirit which they are anxious to discourage; and one consequence of this was,
that they were less disposed to contend strenuously for the inviolability of
existing money-contracts. The conservative feeling on this point was stronger
among the mass than among the philosophers. Plato even complains of it as
inconveniently preponderant, and
as arresting the legislator in all comprehensive projects of reform. For the
most part, indeed, schemes of cancelling debts and redividing lands were never
thought of except by men of desperate and selfish ambition, who made them
stepping-stones to despotic power. Such men were denounced alike by the
practical sense of the community and by the speculative thinkers; but when we
turn to the case of the Spartan king Agis the Third, who proposed a complete
extinction of debts and an equal redivision of the landed property of the state, not with any
selfish or personal views, but upon pure ideas of patriotism, well or ill
understood, and for the purpose of renovating the lost ascendency of Sparta,—we
find Plutarch expressing
the most unqualified admiration of this young king and his projects, and
treating the opposition made to him as originating in no better feelings than
meanness and cupidity. The philosophical thinkers on politics conceived—and to
a great degree justly, as I shall show hereafter—that the conditions of
security, in the ancient world, imposed upon the citizens generally the
absolute necessity of keeping up a military spirit and willingness to brave at
all times personal hardship and discomfort; so that increase of wealth, on
account of the habits of self-indulgence which it commonly introduces, was
regarded by them with more or less of disfavor. If in their estimation any
Grecian community had become corrupt, they were willing to sanction great interference
with preëxisting rights for the purpose of bringing it back nearer to their
ideal standard: and the real security for the maintenance of these rights lay
in the conservative feelings of the citizens generally, much more than in the
opinions which superior minds imbibe from the philosophers.
Those conservative feelings were in the subsequent
Athenian democracy peculiarly deep-rooted: the mass of the Athenian people
identified inseparably the maintenance of property, in all its various shapes,
with that of their laws and constitution. And it is a remarkable fact, that
though the admiration entertained at Athens for Solon, was universal, the
principle of his seisachtheia, and of his money-depreciation, was not only
never imitated, but found the strongest tacit reprobation; whereas at Rome, as
well as in most of the kingdoms of modern Europe, we know that one debasement
of the coin succeeded another,—the temptation, of thus partially eluding the
pressure of financial embarrassments, proved, after one successful trial, too
strong to be resisted, and brought down the coin by successive depreciations
from the full pound of twelve ounces to the standard of half an ounce. It is of
some importance to take notice of this fact, when we reflect how much “Grecian faith” has
been degraded by the Roman writers into a byword for duplicity in pecuniary
dealings. The
democracy of Athens,—and, indeed, the cities of Greece generally, both
oligarchies and democracies,—stands far above the senate of Rome, and far above
the modern kingdoms of France and England, until comparatively recent times, in
respect of honest dealing with the coinage: moreover,
while there
occurred at Rome several political changes which brought about new tables, or at
least a partial depreciation of contracts, no phenomenon of the same kind ever
happened at Athens, during the three centuries between Solon and the end of the
free working of the democracy. Doubtless there were fraudulent debtors at
Athens, and the administration of private law, though it did not in any way
connive at their proceedings, was far too imperfect to repress them as
effectually as might have been wished. But the public sentiment on the point
was just and decided, and it may be asserted with confidence, that a loan of
money at Athens was quite as secure as it ever was at any time or place of the
ancient world,—in spite of the great and important superiority of Rome with
respect to the accumulation of a body of authoritative legal precedent, the
source of what was ultimately shaped into the Roman jurisprudence. Among the
various causes of sedition or mischief in the Grecian communities,[ we
hear little of the pressure of private debt.
By the measures of relief above described, Solon
had accomplished results surpassing his own best hopes. He had healed the
prevailing discontents; and such was the confidence and gratitude which he had
inspired, that he was now called upon to draw up a constitution and laws for
the better working of the government in future. His constitutional changes were great and
valuable: respecting his laws, what we hear is rather curious than important.
It has been already stated that, down to the time of Solon, the classification received in Attica was that of the four Ionic tribes, comprising in one scale the phratries and gentes, and in another scale the three trittyes and forty-eight naukraries,—while the eupatridæ, seemingly a few specially respected gentes, and perhaps a few distinguished families in all the gentes, had in their hands all the powers of government. Solon introduced a new principle of classification, called, in Greek, the timocratic principle. He distributed all the citizens of the tribes, without any reference to their gentes or phratries, into four classes, according to the amount of their property, which he caused to be assessed and entered in a public schedule. Those whose annual income was equal to five hundred medimni of corn (about seven hundred imperial bushels) and upwards,—one medimnus being considered equivalent to one drachma in money,—he placed in the highest class; those who received between three hundred and five hundred medimni, or drachms, formed the second class; and those between two hundred and three hundred, the third. The fourth and most numerous class comprised all those who did not possess land yielding a produce equal to two hundred medimni. The first class, called pentakosiomedimni, were alone eligible to the archonship and to all commands: the second were called the knights or horsemen of the state, as possessing enough to enable them to keep a horse and perform military service in that capacity: the third class, called the zeugitæ, formed the heavy-armed infantry, and were bound to serve, each with his full panoply. Each of these three classes was entered in the public schedule as possessed of a taxable capital, calculated with a certain reference to his annual income, but in a proportion diminishing according to the scale of that income,—and a man paid taxes to the state according to the sum for which he stood rated in the schedule; so that this direct taxation acted really like a graduated income-tax. The ratable property of the citizens belonging to the richest class, the pentakosiomedimnus, was calculated and entered on the state-schedule at a sum of capital equal to twelve times his annual income: that of the hippeus, or knight, at a sum equal to ten times his annual income: that of the zeugite, at a sum equal to five times his annual income. Thus a pentakosiomedimnus, whose income was exactly five hundred drachms, the minimum qualification of his class, stood rated in the schedule for a taxable property of six thousand drachms, or one talent, being twelve times his income,—if his annual income were one thousand drachms, he would stand rated for twelve thousand drachms, or two talents, being the same proportion of income to ratable capital. But when we pass to the second class, or knights, the proportion of the two is changed,—the knight possessing an income of just three hundred drachms, or three hundred medimni, would stand rated for three thousand drachms, or ten times his real income, and so in the same proportion for any income above three hundred and below five hundred. Again, in the third class. or below three hundred, the proportion is a second time altered,—the zeugite possessing exactly two hundred drachms of income, was rated upon a still lower calculation, at one thousand drachms, or a sum equal to five times his income; and all incomes of this class, between two hundred and three hundred drachms, would in like manner be multiplied by five in order to obtain the amount of ratable capital. Upon these respective sums of scheduled capital, all direct taxation was levied: if the state required one per cent, of direct tax, the poorest pentakosiomedimnus would pay (upon six thousand drachms) sixty drachms; the poorest hippeus would pay (upon three thousand drachms) thirty; the poorest zeugite would pay (upon one thousand drachms) ten drachms. And thus this mode of assessment would operate like a graduated income-tax, looking at it in reference to the three different classes,—but as an equal income-tax, looking at it in reference to the different individuals comprised in one and the same class. All persons in the state whose annual income amounted to less than two hundred medimni, or drachms, were placed in the fourth class, and they must have constituted the large majority of the community. They were not liable to any direct taxation, and, perhaps, were not at first even entered upon the taxable schedule, more especially as we do not know that any taxes were actually levied upon this schedule during the Solonian times. It is said that they were all called thêtes, but this appellation is not well sustained, and cannot be admitted: the fourth compartment in the descending scale was indeed termed the thetic census, because it contained all the thêtes, and because most of its members were of that humble description; but it is not conceivable that a proprietor whose land yielded to him a clear annual return of one hundred, one hundred and twenty, one hundred and forty, or one hundred and eighty drachms, could ever have been designated by that name. Such were the divisions in the political scale
established by Solon, called by Aristotle a timocracy, in which the rights,
honors, functions, and liabilities of the citizens were measured out according
to the assessed property of each. Though the scale is stated as if nothing but
landed property were measured by it, yet we may rather presume that property of
other kinds was intended to be included, since it served as the basis of every
man’s liability to taxation. The highest honors of the state,—that is, the
places of the nine archons annually chosen, as well as those in the senate of
areopagus, into which the past archons always entered,—perhaps also the posts
of prytanes of the naukrari,—were reserved for the first class: the poor
eupatrids became ineligible; while rich men, not eupatrids, were admitted.
Other posts of inferior distinction were filled by the second and third
classes, who were, moreover, bound to military service, the one on horseback, the other as heavy-armed
soldiers on foot. Moreover, the liturgies of the state, as they were
called,—unpaid functions, such as the trierarchy, chorêgy, gymnasiarchy, etc.,
which entailed expense and trouble on the holder of them,—were distributed in
some way or other between the members of the three classes, though we do not
know how the distribution was made in these early times. On the other hand, the
members of the fourth or lowest class were disqualified from holding any individual
office of dignity,—performed no liturgies, served in case of war only as
light-armed, or with a panoply provided by the state, and paid nothing to the
direct property-tax, or eisphora. It would be incorrect to say that they
paid no taxes; for indirect taxes, such as duties on imports,
fell upon them in common with the rest; and we must recollect that these latter
were, throughout a long period of Athenian history, in steady operation, while
the direct taxes were only levied on rare occasions.
But though this fourth class, constituting the great
numerical majority of the free people, were shut out from individual office,
their collective importance was in another way greatly increased. They were
invested with the right of choosing the annual archons, out of the class of
pentakosiomedimni; and what was of more importance still, the archons and the
magistrates generally, after their year of office, instead of being accountable
to the senate of areopagus, were made formally accountable to the public
assembly sitting in judgment upon their past conduct. They might be impeached
and called upon to defend themselves, punished in case of misbehavior, and
debarred from the usual honor of a seat in the senate of areopagus.
Had the public assembly been called upon to act alone,
without aid or guidance, this accountability would have proved only nominal.
But Solon converted it into a reality by another new institution, which will
hereafter be found of great moment in the working out of the Athenian
democracy. He created the pro-bouleutic or pre-considering senate, with
intimate and especial reference to the public assembly,—to prepare matters for
its discussion, to convoke and superintend its meetings, and to insure the execution
of its decrees. This senate, as first constituted by Solon, comprised four hundred members, taken in
equal proportions from the four tribes,—not chosen by lot, as they will be
found to be in the more advanced stage of the democracy, but elected by the
people, in the same way as the archons then were,—persons of the fourth or
poorest class of the census, though contributing to elect, not being themselves
eligible.
But while Solon thus created the new pre-considering
senate, identified with and subsidiary to the popular assembly, he manifested
no jealousy of the preëxisting areopagitic senate: on the contrary, he enlarged
its powers, gave to it an ample supervision over the execution of the laws
generally, and imposed upon it the censorial duty of inspecting the lives and
occupations of the citizens, as well as of punishing men of idle and dissolute
habits. He was himself, as past archon, a member of this ancient senate, and he
is said to have contemplated that, by means of the two senates, the state would
be held fast, as it were with a double anchor, against all shocks and storms.
Such are the only new political institutions, apart
from the laws to be noticed presently, which there are grounds for ascribing to
Solon, when we take proper care to discriminate what really belongs to Solon
and his age, from the Athenian constitution as afterwards remodelled. It has
been a practice common with many able expositors of Grecian affairs, and
followed partly, even by Dr. Thirlwall, to
connect the name of Solon with the whole political and judicial state of Athens
as it stood between the age of Periklês and that of Dêmosthenês,—the regulations of the senate of five hundred, the numerous
public dikasts or jurors taken by lot from the people, as well as the body
annually selected for law-revision, and called nomothets, and the prosecution,
called the graphê paranomôn, open to be instituted against the proposer of any
measure illegal, unconstitutional, or dangerous. There is, indeed, some
countenance for this confusion between Solonian and post-Solonian Athens, in
the usage of the orators themselves; for Dêmosthenês and Æschinês employ the name
of Solon in a very loose manner, and treat him as the author of institutions
belonging evidently to a later age for example, the striking and characteristic
oath of the heliastic jurors, which Demosthenês ascribes
to Solon, proclaims itself in many ways as belonging to the age after Kleisthenês, especially by
the mention of the senate of five hundred, and not of four hundred. Among the
citizens who served as jurors or dikasts, Solon was venerated generally as the
author of the Athenian laws; and the orator, therefore, might well employ his
name for the purpose of emphasis, without provoking any critical inquiry
whether the particular institution, which he happened to be then impressing
upon his audience, belonged really to Solon himself or to the subsequent
periods. Many of those institutions, which Dr. Thirlwall mentions in
conjunction with the name of Solon, are among the last refinements and
elaborations of the democratical mind of Athens,—gradually prepared, doubtless,
during the interval between Kleisthenês and Periklês, but not brought into full
operation until the period of the latter (460-429 B. C.); for it is
hardly possible to conceive these numerous dikasteries and assemblies in
regular, frequent, and long-standing operation, without an assured payment to
the dikasts who composed them. Now such payment first began to be made about
the time of Periklês, if not by his actual proposition; and
Dêmosthenês had good reason for contending that, if it were suspended, the
judicial as well as the administrative system of Athens would at once fall to pieces. And
it would be a marvel, such as nothing short of strong direct evidence would
justify us in believing, that in an age when even partial democracy was yet
untried, Solon should conceive the idea of such institutions: it would be a
marvel still greater, that the half-emancipated thêtes and small proprietors,
for whom he legislated,—yet trembling under the rod of the eupatrid archons,
and utterly inexperienced in collective business,—should have been found
suddenly competent to fulfil these ascendent functions, such as the citizens of
conquering Athens in the days of Periklês,—full of the sentiment of force and
actively identifying themselves with the dignity of their community,—became
gradually competent, and not more than competent, to exercise with effect. To
suppose that Solon contemplated and provided for the periodical revision of his
laws by establishing a nomothetic jury, or dikastery, such as that which we
find in operation during the time of Dêmosthenês, would be at variance, in my
judgment, with any reasonable estimate either of the man or of the age.
Herodotus says that Solon, having exacted from the Athenians solemn oaths
that they would not rescind any of his laws for ten years,
quitted Athens for that period, in order that he might not be compelled to
rescind them himself: Plutarch informs us that he gave to his laws force for a
century absolute. Solon
himself, and Drako before him, had been lawgivers, evoked and empowered by the
special emergency of the times; the idea of a frequent revision of laws, by a
body of lot-selected dikasts, belongs to a far more advanced age, and could not
well have been present to the minds of either. The wooden rollers of Solon,
like the tables of the Roman decemvirs, were
doubtless intended as a permanent “fons omnis publici privatique juris.”
If we examine the facts of the case, we shall see that
nothing more than the bare foundation of the democracy of Athens as it stood in
the time of Periklês, can reasonably be ascribed to Solon. “I gave to the
people,” Solon says, in one of his short remaining fragments, “as
much strength as sufficed for their needs, without either enlarging or
diminishing their dignity: for those too who possessed power and were noted for
wealth, I took care that no unworthy treatment should be reserved. I stood with
the strong shield cast over both parties, so as not to allow an unjust triumph
to either.” Again, Aristotle tells us that Solon bestowed upon the people no
greater measure of power than was barely necessary,—to elect
their magistrates and to hold them to accountability: if the people had had
less than this, they could not have been expected to remain tranquil,—they
would have been in slavery and hostile to the constitution. Not less distinctly
does Herodotus speak, when he describes the revolution subsequently operated by
Kleisthenês—the latter, he tells us, found “the Athenian people excluded from everything.” These
passages seem positively to contradict the supposition, in itself sufficiently
improbable, that Solon is the author of the peculiar democratical institutions
of Athens, such as the constant and numerous dikasts for judicial trials and
revision of laws. The genuine and forward democratical movement of Athens
begins only with Kleisthenês, from the moment when that distinguished
Alkmæônid, either spontaneously, or from finding himself worsted in his party
strife with Isagoras, purchased by large popular concessions the hearty
coöperation of the multitude under very dangerous circumstances. While Solon,
in his own statement as well as in that of Aristotle, gave to the people as
much power as was strictly needful, but no more,—Kleisthenês (to use the significant
phrase of Herodotus), “being vanquished in the party contest with his
rival, took the people into partnership.” It
was thus to the interests of the weaker section, in a strife of contending
nobles, that the Athenian people owed their first admission to political
ascendency,—in part, at least, to this cause, though the proceedings of
Kleisthenês indicate a hearty and spontaneous popular sentiment. But such
constitutional admission of the people would not have been so astonishingly
fruitful in positive results, if the course of public events for the
half-century after Kleisthenês had not been such as to stimulate most
powerfully their energy, their self-reliance, their mutual sympathies, and
their ambition. I shall recount in a future chapter those historical causes,
which, acting upon the Athenian character, gave such efficiency and expansion
to the great democratical impulse communicated by Kleisthenês: at present, it
is enough to remark that that impulse commences properly with Kleisthenês, and
not with Solon.
But the
Solonian constitution, though only the foundation, was yet the indispensable
foundation, of the subsequent democracy; and if the discontents of the
miserable Athenian population, instead of experiencing his disinterested and
healing management, had fallen at once into the hands of selfish power-seekers,
like Kylôn or Peisistratus, the memorable expansion of the Athenian mind during
the ensuing century would never have taken place, and the whole subsequent
history of Greece would probably have taken a different course. Solon left the
essential powers of the state still in the hands of the oligarchy, and the
party combats—to be recounted hereafter—between Peisistratus, Lykurgus, and
Megaklês, thirty years after his legislation, which ended in the despotism of
Peisistratus, will appear to be of the same purely oligarchical character as
they had been before he was appointed archon. But the oligarchy which he
established was very different from the unmitigated oligarchy which he found,
so teeming with oppression and so destitute of redress, as his own poems
testify.
It was he who first gave both to the citizens of
middling property and to the general mass, a locus standi against
the eupatrids; he enabled the people partially to protect themselves, and
familiarized them with the idea of protecting themselves, by the peaceful
exercise of a constitutional franchise. The new force, through which this
protection was carried into effect, was the public assembly called heliæa, regularized
and armed with enlarged
prerogatives, and farther strengthened by its indispensable ally,—the
pro-bouleutic or pre-considering senate. Under the Solonian constitution, this
force was merely secondary and defensive, but after the renovation of
Kleisthenês, it became paramount and sovereign; it branched out gradually into
those numerous popular dikasteries which so powerfully modified both public and
private Athenian life, drew to itself the undivided reverence and submission of
the people, and by degrees rendered the single magistracies essentially
subordinate functions. The popular assembly as constituted by Solon, appearing
in modified efficiency, and trained to the office of reviewing and judging the
general conduct of a past magistrate,—forms the intermediate stage between the
passive Homeric agora, and those omnipotent assemblies and dikasteries which
listened to Periklês or Dêmosthenês. Compared with these last, it has in it but
a faint streak of democracy,—and so it naturally appeared to Aristotle, who
wrote with a practical experience of Athens in the time of the orators; but
compared with the first, or with the ante-Solonian constitution of Attica, it
must doubtless have appeared a concession eminently democratical. To impose
upon the eupatrid archon the necessity of being elected, or put upon his trial
of after-accountability, by the rabble of freemen (such would
be the phrase in eupatrid society), would be a bitter humiliation to those
among whom it was first introduced; for we must recollect that this was the
most extensive scheme of constitutional reform yet propounded in Greece, and
that despots and oligarchies shared between them at that time the whole Grecian
world. As it appears that Solon, while constituting the popular assembly with
its pro-bouleutic senate, had no jealousy of the senate of areopagus, and indeed even enlarged its powers,—we may infer
that his grand object was, not to weaken the oligarchy generally, but to
improve the administration and to repress the misconduct and irregularities of
the individual archons; and that too, not by diminishing their powers, but by
making some degree of popularity the condition both of their entry into office,
and of their safety or honor after it.
It is, in my judgment, a mistake to suppose that Solon
transferred the judicial power of the archons to a popular dikastery; these
magistrates still continued self-acting judges, deciding and condemning without
appeal,—not mere presidents of an assembled jury, as they afterwards came to be
during the next century. For
the general exercise of such power they were accountable after their year of
office; and this accountability was the security against abuse,—a very
insufficient security, yet not wholly inoperative. It will be seen, however,
presently, that these archons, though strong to coerce, and perhaps to oppress,
small and poor men,—had no means of keeping down rebellious nobles of their own rank, such as Peisistratus,
Lykurgus, and Megaklês, each with his armed followers. When we compare the
drawn swords of these ambitious competitors, ending in the despotism of one of
them, with the vehement parliamentary strife between Themistoklês and
Aristeidês afterwards, peaceably decided by the vote of the sovereign people,
and never disturbing the public tranquillity,—we shall see that the democracy
of the ensuing century fulfilled the conditions of order, as well as of progress,
better than the Solonian constitution.
To distinguish this Solonian constitution from the
democracy which followed it, is essential to a due comprehension of the
progress of the Greek mind, and especially of Athenian affairs. That democracy
was achieved by gradual steps, which will be hereafter described: Dêmosthenês
and Æschinês lived under it as a system consummated and in full activity, when
the stages of its previous growth were no longer matter of exact memory; and
the dikasts then assembled in judgment were pleased to hear the constitution to
which they were attached identified with the names either of Solon, or of
Theseus, to which they were no less partial. Their inquisitive contemporary
Aristotle was not thus misled: but even the most common-place Athenians of the
century preceding would have escaped the same delusion. For during the whole
course of the democratical movement from the Persian invasion down to the
Peloponnesian war, and especially during the changes proposed by Periklês and
Ephialtês, there was always a strenuous party of resistance, who would not
suffer the people to forget that they had already forsaken, and were on the
point of forsaking still more, the orbit marked out by Solon. The illustrious
Periklês underwent innumerable attacks both from the orators in the assembly
and from the comic writers in the theatre; and among these sarcasms on the
political tendencies of the day, we are probably to number the complaint
breathed by the poet Kratinus, of the desuetude into which both Solon and Drako
had fallen. “I swear, said
he, in a fragment of one of his comedies, by Solon and Drako, whose wooden tablets (of
laws) are now employed by people to roast their barley.” The laws of Solon
respecting penal offences, respecting inheritance and adoption, respecting the
private relations generally, etc., remained for the most part in force; his
quadripartite census also continued, at least for financial purposes until the
archonship of Nausinikus in 377 B. C.; so that Cicero and others
might be warranted in affirming that his laws still prevailed at Athens: but
his political and judicial arrangements had undergone a revolution not
less complete and memorable than the character and spirit of the Athenian
people generally. The choice, by way of lot, of archons and other magistrates,
and the distribution by lot of the general body of dikasts or jurors into
pannels for judicial business, may be decidedly considered as not belonging to
Solon, but adopted after the revolution of Kleisthenês, probably,
the choice of senators by lot also. The lot was a symptom of pronounced
democratical spirit, such as we must not seek in the Solonian institutions.
It is not easy to make out distinctly what was the
political position of the ancient gentes and phratries, as Solon left them. The
four tribes consisted altogether of gentes and phratries, insomuch that no one
could be included in any one of the tribes who was not also a member of some
gens and phratry. Now the new pro-bouleutic or pre-considerate senate consisted
of four hundred members,—one hundred from each of the tribes: persons not included in any gens or phratry could therefore
have had no access to it. The conditions of eligibility were similar, according
to ancient custom, for the nine archons,—of course, also, for the senate of
areopagus. So that there remained only the public assembly, in which an
Athenian not a member of these tribes could take part: yet he was a citizen,
since he could give his vote for archons and senators, and could take part in
the annual decision of their accountability, besides being entitled to claim
redress for wrong from the archons in his own person,—while the alien could
only do so through the intervention of an avouching citizen, or prostatês. It
seems, therefore, that all persons not included in the four tribes, whatever
their grade of fortune might be, were on the same level in respect to political
privilege as the fourth and poorest class of the Solonian census. It has
already been remarked that, even before the time of Solon, the number of
Athenians not included in the gentes or phratries was probably considerable: it
tended to become greater and greater, since these bodies were close and
unexpansive, while the policy of the new lawgiver tended to invite industrious
settlers from other parts of Greece to Athens. Such great and increasing
inequality of political privilege helps to explain the weakness of the
government in repelling the aggressions of Peisistratus, and exhibits the
importance of the revolution afterwards wrought by Kleisthenês, when he
abolished (for all political purposes) the four old tribes, and created ten new
comprehensive tribes in place of them.
In regard to the regulations of the senate and the
assembly of the people, as constituted by Solon, we are altogether without
information: nor is it safe to transfer to the Solonian constitution the
information, comparatively ample, which we possess respecting these bodies
under the later democracy.
The laws of Solon were inscribed on wooden rollers and
triangular tablets, in the species of writing called boustrophêdon (lines
alternating first from left to right, and next from right to left, like the
course of the ploughman), and preserved first in the acropolis, subsequently in
the prytaneium. On the tablets, called kyrbeis, were chiefly commemorated the
laws respecting sacred rites and sacrifices: on
the pillars, or rollers, of which there were at least sixteen, were placed the regulations
respecting matters profane. So small are the fragments which have come down to
us, and so much has been ascribed to Solon by the orators, which belongs really
to the subsequent times, that it is hardly possible to form any critical
judgment respecting the legislation as a whole, or to discover by what general
principles or purposes he was guided.
He left unchanged all the previous laws and practices
respecting the crime of homicide, connected as they were intimately with the
religious feelings of the people. The laws of Drako on this subject therefore
remained, but on other subjects, according to Plutarch, they were altogether
abrogated: there
is, however, room for supposing, that the repeal cannot have been so sweeping
as this biographer represents.
The Solonian laws seem to have borne more or less upon
all the great departments of human interest and duty. We find regulations
political and religious, public and private, civil and criminal, commercial,
agricultural, sumptuary, and disciplinarian. Solon provides punishment for
crimes, restricts the profession and status of the citizen, prescribes detailed
rules for marriage as well as for burial, for the common use of springs and
wells, and for the mutual interest of conterminous farmers in planting or hedging
their properties. As far as we can judge, from the imperfect manner in which his laws come before us, there
does not seem to have been any attempt at a systematic order or classification.
Some of them are mere general and vague directions, while others again run into
the extreme of speciality.
By far the most important of all was the amendment of the law of debtor and creditor which has already been adverted to, and the abolition of the power of fathers and brothers to sell their daughters and sisters into slavery. The prohibition of all contracts on the security of the body, was itself sufficient to produce a vast improvement in the character and condition of the poorer population,—a result which seems to have been so sensibly obtained from the legislation of Solon, that Boeckh and some other eminent authors suppose him to have abolished villenage and conferred upon the poor tenants a property in their lands, annulling the seignorial rights of the landlord. But this opinion rests upon no positive evidence, nor are we warranted in ascribing to him any stronger measure in reference to the land, than the annulment of the previous mortgages. The first pillar of his laws contained a regulation respecting exportable produce. He forbade the exportation of all produce of the Attic soil, except olive-oil alone, and the sanction employed to enforce observance of this law deserves notice, as an illustration of the ideas of the time;—the archon was bound, on pain of forfeiting one hundred drachms, to pronounce solemn curses against every offender. We are probably to take this prohibition in conjunction with other objects said to have been contemplated by Solon, especially the encouragement of artisans and manufacturers at Athens. Observing, we are told, that many new emigrants were just then flocking into Attica to seek an establishment, in consequence of its greater security, he was anxious to turn them rather to manufacturing industry than to the cultivation of a soil naturally poor. He forbade the granting of citizenship to any emigrants, except such as had quitted irrevocably their former abodes, and come to Athens for the purpose of carrying on some industrious profession; and in order to prevent idleness, he directed the senate of areopagus to keep watch over the lives of the citizens generally, and punish every one who had no course of regular labor to support him. If a father had not taught his son some art or profession, Solon relieved the son from all obligation to maintain him in his old age. And it was to encourage the multiplication of these artisans, that he insured, or sought to insure, to the residents in Attica a monopoly of all its landed produce except olive-oil, which was raised in abundance more than sufficient for their wants. It was his wish that the trade with foreigners should be carried on by exporting the produce of artisan labor, instead of the produce of land. This commercial prohibition is founded on principles substantially similar to those which were acted upon in the early history of England, with reference both to corn and to wool, and in other European countries also. In so far as it was at all operative, it tended to lessen the total quantity of produce raised upon the soil of Attica, and thus to keep the price of it from rising,—a purpose less objectionable—if we assume that the legislator is to interfere at all—than that of our late Corn Laws, which were destined to prevent the price of grain from falling. But the law of Solon must have been altogether inoperative, in reference to the great articles of human subsistence; for Attica imported, both largely and constantly, grain and salt provisions,—probably, also, wool and flax for the spinning and weaving of the women, and certainly timber for building. Whether the law was ever enforced with reference to figs and honey, may well be doubted; at least these productions of Attica were in after-times generally consumed and celebrated throughout Greece. Probably also, in the time of Solon, the silver-mines of Laureium had hardly begun to be worked: these afterwards became highly productive, and furnished to Athens a commodity for foreign payments not less convenient than lucrative.[ It is interesting to notice the anxiety, both of Solon
and of Drako, to enforce among their fellow-citizens industrious and
self-maintaining habits; and
we shall find the same sentiment proclaimed by Periklês, at the time when
Athenian power was at its maximum. Nor ought we to pass over this early
manifestation in Attica, of an opinion equitable and tolerant towards sedentary
industry, which in most other parts of Greece was regarded as comparatively
dishonorable. The general tone of Grecian sentiment recognized no occupations
as perfectly worthy of a free citizen except arms, agriculture, and athletic
and musical exercises; and the proceedings of the Spartans, who kept aloof even
from agriculture, and left it to their Helots, were admired, though they could
not be copied throughout most part of the Hellenic world. Even minds like
Plato, Aristotle, and Xenophon concurred to a considerable extent in this
feeling, which they justified on the ground that the sedentary life and
unceasing house-work of the artisan was inconsistent with military aptitude:
the town-occupations are usually described by a word which carries with it
contemptuous ideas, and though recognized as indispensable to the existence of
the city, are held suitable only for an inferior and semi-privileged order of
citizens. This, the received sentiment among Greeks, as well as foreigners, found a strong and growing
opposition at Athens, as I have already said,—corroborated also by a similar
feeling at Corinth. The
trade of Corinth, as well as of Chalkis in Eubœa, was extensive, at a time when
that of Athens had scarce any existence. But while the despotism of Periander
can hardly have failed to operate as a discouragement to industry at Corinth,
the contemporaneous legislation of Solon provided for traders and artisans a
new home at Athens, giving the first encouragement to that numerous
town-population both in the city and in the Peiraeus, which we find actually
residing there in the succeeding century. The multiplication of such
town-residents, both citizens and metics, or non-freemen, was a capital fact in
the onward march of Athens, since it determined not merely the extension of her
trade, but also the preëminence of her naval force,—and thus, as a farther
consequence, lent extraordinary vigor to her democratical government. It seems,
moreover, to have been a departure from the primitive temper of Atticism, which
tended both to cantonal residence and rural occupation. We have, therefore, the
greater interest in noting the first mention of it as a consequence of the
Solonian legislation.
To Solon is first owing the admission of a power of
testamentary bequest at Athens, in all cases in which a man had no legitimate
children. According to the preëxisting custom, we may rather presume that if a
deceased person left neither children nor blood relations, his property
descended, as at Rome, to his gens and phratry. Throughout
most rude states of society, the power of willing is unknown, as among the
ancient Germans,—among the Romans prior to the twelve tables,—in the old laws
of the Hindus, etc.
Society limits a man’s interest or power of enjoyment to his life, and considers his
relatives as having joint reversionary claims to his property, which take
effect, in certain determinate proportions, after his death; and this view was
the more likely to prevail at Athens, inasmuch as the perpetuity of the family
sacred rites, in which the children and near relatives partook of right, was
considered by the Athenians as a matter of public as well as of private
concern. Solon gave permission to every man dying without children to bequeathe
his property by will as he should think fit, and the testament was maintained,
unless it could be shown to have been procured by some compulsion or improper
seduction. Speaking generally, this continued to be the law throughout the
historical times of Athens. Sons, wherever there were sons, succeeded to the
property of their father in equal shares, with the obligation of giving out
their sisters in marriage along with a certain dowry. If there were no sons,
then the daughters succeeded, though the father might by will, within certain
limits, determine the person to whom they should be married, with their rights
of succession attached to them; or might, with the consent of his daughters,
make by will certain other arrangements about his property. A person who had no
children, or direct lineal descendants, might bequeathe his property at
pleasure: if he died without a will, first his father, then his brother or
brother’s children, next his sister or sister’s children succeeded: if none
such existed, then the cousins by the father’s side, next the cousins by the
mother’s side,—the male line of descent having preference over the female. Such
was the principle of the Solonian laws of succession, though the particulars
are in several ways obscure and doubtful. Solon,
it appears, was the first who gave power of superseding by testament the rights
of agnates and gentiles to succession,—a proceeding in consonance with his plan
of encouraging both industrious occupation and the consequent multiplication of individual acquisitions.
It has been already mentioned that Solon forbade the sale of daughters or sisters into slavery, by fathers or brothers,—a prohibition which shows how much females had before been looked upon as articles of property. And it would seem that before his time the violation of a free woman must have been punished at the discretion of the magistrates; for we are told that he was the first who enacted a penalty of one hundred drachms against the offender, and twenty drachms against the seducer of a free woman.Moreover, it is said that he forbade a bride when given in marriage to carry with her any personal ornaments and appurtenances, except to the extent of three robes and certain matters of furniture not very valuable. Solon farther imposed upon women several restraints in regard to proceedings at the obsequies of deceased relatives: he forbade profuse demonstrations of sorrow, singing of composed dirges, and costly sacrifices and contributions; he limited strictly the quantity of meat and drink admissible for the funeral banquet, and prohibited nocturnal exit, except in a car and with a light. It appears that both in Greece and Rome, the feelings of duty and affection on the part of surviving relatives prompted them to ruinous expense in a funeral, as well as to unmeasured effusions both of grief and conviviality; and the general necessity experienced for interference of the law is attested by the remark of Plutarch, that similar prohibitions to those enacted by Solon were likewise in force at his native town of Chæroneia. Other penal
enactments of Solon are yet to be mentioned. He forbade absolutely
evil-speaking with respect to the dead: he forbade it likewise with respect to
the living, either in a temple or before judges or archons, or at any public
festival,—on pain of a forfeit of three drachms to the person aggrieved, and
two more to the public treasury. How mild the general character of his
punishments was, may be judged by this law against foul language, not less than
by the law before mentioned against rape: both the one and the other of these
offences were much more severely dealt with under the subsequent law of
democratical Athens. The peremptory edict against speaking ill of a deceased
person, though doubtless springing in a great degree from disinterested repugnance,
is traceable also in part to that fear of the wrath of the departed which
strongly possessed the early Greek mind.
It seems generally that Solon determined by law the outlay for the public sacrifices, though we do not know what were his particular directions: we are told that he reckoned a sheep and a medimnus (of wheat or barley?) as equivalent, either of them, to a drachm, and that he also prescribed the prices to be paid for first-rate oxen intended for solemn occasions. But it astonishes us to see the large recompense which he awarded out of the public treasury to a victor at the Olympic or Isthmian games: to the former five hundred drachms, equal to one year’s income of the highest of the four classes on the census; to the latter one hundred drachms. The magnitude of these rewards strikes us the more when we compare them with the fines on rape and evil speaking; and we cannot be surprised that the philosopher Xenophanês noticed, with some degree of severity, the extravagant estimate of this species of excellence, current among the Grecian cities. At the same time, we must remember both that these Pan-Hellenic sacred games presented the chief visible evidence of peace and sympathy among the numerous communities of Greece, and that in the time of Solon, factitious reward was still needful to encourage them. In respect to land and agriculture, Solon proclaimed a public reward of five drachms for every wolf brought in, and one drachm for every wolf’s cub: the extent of wild land has at all times been considerable in Attica. He also provided rules respecting the use of wells between neighbors, and respecting the planting in conterminous olive-grounds. Whether any of these regulations continued in operation during the better-known period of Athenian history cannot be safely affirmed. In respect to theft, we find it stated that Solon
repealed the punishment of death which Drako had annexed to that crime, and
enacted as a penalty, compensation to an amount double the value of the
property stolen. The simplicity of this law perhaps affords ground for
presuming that it really does belong to Solon, but the law which prevailed
during the time of the orators respecting theft must
have been introduced at some later period, since it enters into distinctions and mentions both
places and forms of procedure, which we cannot reasonably refer to the 46th
Olympiad. The public dinners at the prytaneium, of which the archons and a
select few partook in common, were also either first established, or perhaps
only more strictly regulated, by Solon: he ordered barley cakes for their
ordinary meals, and wheaten loaves for festival days, prescribing how often
each person should dine at the table. The
honor of dining at the table of the prytaneium was maintained throughout as a
valuable reward at the disposal of the government.
Among the various laws of Solon, there are few which
have attracted more notice than that which pronounces the man, who in a
sedition stood aloof and took part with neither side, to be dishonored and
disfranchised. Strictly
speaking, this seems more in the nature of an emphatic moral denunciation, or a
religious curse, than a legal sanction capable of being formally applied in an
individual case and after judicial trial,—though the sentence of atīmy,
under the more elaborated Attic procedure, was both definite in its penal
consequences and also judicially delivered. We may, however, follow the course
of ideas under which Solon was induced to write this sentence on his tables,
and we may trace the influence of similar ideas in later Attic institutions. It
is obvious that his denunciation is confined to that special case in which a
sedition has already broken out: we must suppose that Kylôn has seized the
acropolis, or that Peisistratus, Megaklês, and Lykurgus are in arms at the head
of their partisans. Assuming these leaders to be wealthy and powerful men,
which would
in all probability be the fact, the constituted authority—such as Solon saw
before him in Attica, even after his own organic amendments—was not strong
enough to maintain the peace; it became, in fact, itself one of the contending
parties. Under such given circumstances, the sooner every citizen publicly
declared his adherence to some one of them, the earlier this suspension of
legal authority was likely to terminate. Nothing was so mischievous as the
indifference of the mass, or their disposition to let the combatants fight out
the matter among themselves, and then to submit to the victor: nothing
was so likely to encourage aggression on the part of an ambitious malcontent,
as the conviction that, if he could once overpower the small amount of physical
force which surrounded the archons and exhibit himself in armed possession of
the prytaneium or the acropolis, he might immediately count upon passive
submission on the part of all the freemen without. Under the state of feeling
which Solon inculcates, the insurgent leader would have to calculate that every
man who was not actively in his favor would be actively against him, and this
would render his enterprise much more dangerous; indeed, he could then never
hope to succeed except on the double supposition of extraordinary popularity in
his own person, and universal detestation of the existing government. He would
thus be placed under the influence of powerful deterring motives, and mere
ambition would be far less likely to seduce him into a course which threatened
nothing but ruin, unless under such encouragements from the preëxisting public
opinion as to make his success a result desirable for the community. Among the
small political societies of Greece,—and especially in the age of Solon, when
the number of despots in other parts of Greece seems to have been at its
maximum,—every government, whatever might be its form, was sufficiently weak to
make its overthrow a matter of comparative facility. Unless upon the
supposition of a band of foreign mercenaries,—which would render it a
government of naked force, and which the Athenian lawgiver would of course
never contemplate,—there was no other stay for it except a positive and
pronounced feeling of attachment on the part of the mass of citizens: indifference on their part would render them a
prey to every daring man of wealth who chose to become a conspirator. That they
should be ready to come forward not only with voice but with arms,—and that
they should be known beforehand to be so,—was essential to the maintenance of
every good Grecian government. It was salutary in preventing mere personal
attempts at revolution, and pacific in its tendency, even where the revolution
had actually broken out,—because, in the greater number of cases, the proportion
of partisans would probably be very unequal, and the inferior party would be
compelled to renounce their hopes.
It will be observed that in this enactment of Solon,
the existing government is ranked merely as one of the contending parties. The
virtuous citizen is enjoined not to come forward in its support, but to come
forward at all events, either for it or against it: positive and early action
is all that is prescribed to him as matter of duty. In the age of Solon, there
was no political idea or system yet current which could be assumed as an
unquestionable datum,—no conspicuous standard to which the citizens could be
pledged under all circumstances to attach themselves. The option lay only
between a mitigated oligarchy in possession and a despot in possibility; a
contest wherein the affections of the people could rarely be counted upon in
favor of the established government. But this neutrality in respect to the
constitution was at an end after the revolution of Kleisthenês, when the idea
of the sovereign people and the democratical institutions became both familiar
and precious to every individual citizen. We shall hereafter find the Athenians
binding themselves by the most sincere and solemn oaths to uphold their
democracy against all attempts to subvert it; we shall discover in them a
sentiment not less positive and uncompromising in its direction, than energetic
in its inspirations. But while we notice this very important change in their
character, we shall at the same time perceive that the wise precautionary
recommendation of Solon, to obviate sedition by an early declaration of the
impartial public between two contending leaders, was not lost upon them. Such,
in point of fact, was the purpose of that salutary and protective institution
which is called Ostracism. When two party-leaders, in the early stages of the
Athenian democracy, each powerful in adherents and influence, had become passionately embarked
in bitter and prolonged opposition to each other, such opposition was likely to
conduct one or other to violent measures. Over and above the hopes of party
triumph, each might well fear that if he himself continued within the bounds of
legality, he might fall a victim to aggressive proceedings on the part of his
antagonists. To ward off this formidable danger, a public vote was called for
to determine which of the two should go into temporary banishment, retaining
his property and unvisited by any disgrace. A number of citizens, not less than
six thousand, voting secretly and therefore independently, were required to
take part, pronouncing upon one or other of these eminent rivals a sentence of
exile for ten years: the one who remained became of course more powerful, yet
less in a situation to be driven into anti-constitutional courses, than he was
before. I shall in a future chapter speak again of this wise precaution, and
vindicate it against some erroneous interpretations to which it has given rise;
at present, I merely notice its analogy with the previous Solonian law, and its
tendency to accomplish the same purpose of terminating a fierce party-feud by
artificially calling in the votes of the mass of impartial citizens against one
or other of the leaders,—with this important difference, that while Solon
assumed the hostile parties to be actually in arms, the ostracism averted that
grave public calamity by applying its remedy to the premonitory symptoms.
I have already considered, in a previous chapter, the
directions given by Solon for the more orderly recital of the Homeric poems;
and it is curious to contrast his reverence for the old epic with the
unqualified repugnance which he manifested towards Thespis and the drama,—then
just nascent, and holding out little promise of its subsequent excellence.
Tragedy and comedy were now beginning to be grafted on the lyric and choric
song. First, one actor was provided to relieve the chorus,—subsequently, two actors
were introduced to sustain fictitious characters and carry on a dialogue, in
such manner that the songs of the chorus and the interlocution of the actors
formed a continuous piece. Solon, after having heard Thespis acting (as all the
early composers did, both tragic and comic) in his own comedy, asked him
afterwards if he was not ashamed to pronounce such falsehoods before so large
an audience. And when Thespis answered that there was no harm in saying and doing such things merely for
amusement, Solon indignantly exclaimed, striking the ground with his stick, “If
once we come to praise and esteem such amusement as this, we shall quickly find
the effects of it in our daily transactions.” For the authenticity of this
anecdote it would be rash to vouch, but we may at least treat it as the protest
of some early philosopher against the deceptions of the drama; and it is
interesting, as marking the incipient struggles of that literature in which
Athens afterwards attained such unrivalled excellence.
It would appear that all the laws of Solon were proclaimed, inscribed, and accepted without either discussion or resistance. He is said to have described them, not as the best laws which he could himself have imagined, but as the best which he could have induced the people to accept; he gave them validity for the space of ten years, for which period both the senate collectively and the archons individually swore to observe them with fidelity, under penalty, in case of non-observance, of a golden statue, as large as life, to be erected at Delphi. But though the acceptance of the laws was accomplished without difficulty, it was not found so easy either for the people to understand and obey, or for the framer to explain them. Every day, persons came to Solon either with praise, or criticism, or suggestions of various improvements, or questions as to the construction of particular enactments; until at last he became tired of this endless process of reply and vindication, which was seldom successful either in removing obscurity or in satisfying complainants. Foreseeing that, if he remained, he would be compelled to make changes, he obtained leave of absence from his countrymen for ten years, trusting that before the expiration of that period they would have become accustomed to his laws. He quitted his native city, in the full certainty that his laws would remain unrepealed until his return; for, says Herodotus, “the Athenians could not repeal them, since they were bound by solemn oaths to observe them for ten years.” The unqualified manner in which the historian here speaks of an oath, as if it created a sort of physical necessity, and shut out all possibility of a contrary result, deserves notice as illustrating Grecian sentiment. On departing from Athens, Solon first visited Egypt, where he communicated largely with Psenôphis of Heliopolis and Sonchis of Saïs, Egyptian priests, who had much to tell respecting their ancient history, and from whom he learned matters, real or pretended, far transcending in alleged antiquity the oldest Grecian genealogies,—especially the history of the vast submerged island of Atlantis, and the war which the ancestors of the Athenians had successfully carried on against it, nine thousand years before. Solon is said to have commenced an epic poem upon this subject, but he did not live to finish it, and nothing of it now remains. From Egypt he went to Cyprus, where he visited the small town of Æreia, said to have been originally founded by Demophôn, son of Theseus; it was then under the dominion of the prince Philokyprus,—each town in Cyprus having its own petty prince. It was situated near the river Klarius, in a position precipitous and secure, but inconvenient and ill-supplied; and Solon persuaded Philokyprus to quit the old site, and establish a new town down in the fertile plain beneath. He himself stayed and became œkist of the new establishment, making all the regulations requisite for its safe and prosperous march, which was indeed so decisively manifested that many new settlers flocked into the new plantation, called by Philokyprus Soli, in honor of Solon. To our deep regret, we are not permitted to know what these regulations were; but the general fact is attested by the poems of Solon himself, and the lines, in which he bade farewell to Philokyprus on quitting the island, are yet before us. On the dispositions of this prince, his poem bestowed unqualified commendation. Besides his visit to Egypt and Cyprus, a story was also current of his having conversed with the Lydian king Crœsus, at Sardis; and the communication said to have taken place between them, has been woven by Herodotus into a sort of moral tale, which forms one of the most beautiful episodes in his whole history. Though this tale has been told and retold as if it were genuine history, yet, as it now stands, it is irreconcilable with chronology,—although, very possibly, Solon may at some time or other have visited Sardis, and seen Crœsus as hereditary prince. But even if
no chronological objections existed, the moral purpose of the tale is so
prominent, and pervades it so systematically, from beginning to end, that these internal grounds are of
themselves sufficiently strong to impeach its credibility as a matter of fact,
unless such doubts happen to be outweighed—which in this case they are not—by
good contemporary testimony. The narrative of Solon and Crœsus can be taken for
nothing else but an illustrative fiction, borrowed by Herodotus from some
philosopher, and clothed in his own peculiar beauty of expression, which on
this occasion is more decidedly poetical than is habitual with him. I cannot
transcribe, and I hardly dare to abridge it. The vainglorious Crœsus, at the
summit of his conquests and his riches, endeavors to win from his visitor Solon
an opinion that he is the happiest of mankind. The latter, after having twice preferred
to him modest and meritorious Grecian citizens, at length reminds him that his
vast wealth and power are of a tenure too precarious to serve as an evidence of
happiness,—that the gods are jealous and meddlesome, and often make the show of
happiness a mere prelude to extreme disaster,—and that no man’s life can be
called happy until the whole of it has been played out, so that it may be seen
to be out of the reach of reverses. Crœsus treats this opinion as absurd, but
“a great judgment from God fell upon him, after Solon was departed,—probably
(observes Herodotus) because he fancied himself the happiest of all men.”
First, he lost his favorite son Atys, a brave and intelligent youth,—his only
other son being dumb. For the Mysians of Olympus, being ruined by a destructive
and formidable
wild boar which they were unable to subdue, applied for aid to Crœsus, who sent
to the spot a chosen hunting force, and permitted, though with great
reluctance, in consequence of an alarming dream,—that his favorite son should
accompany them. The young prince was unintentionally slain by the Phrygian
exile Adrastus, whom Crœsus had sheltered and protected; and
he had hardly recovered from the anguish of this misfortune, when the rapid
growth of Cyrus and the Persian power induced him to go to war with them,
against the advice of his wisest counsellors. After a struggle of about three
years he was completely defeated, his capital Sardis taken by storm, and
himself made prisoner. Cyrus ordered a large pile to be prepared, and placed
upon it Crœsus in fetters, together with fourteen young Lydians, in the
intention of burning them alive, either as a religious offering, or in
fulfilment of a vow, “or perhaps (says Herodotus) to see whether some of the
gods would not interfere to rescue a man so preëminently pious as the king of
Lydia.” In
this sad extremity, Crœsus bethought him of the warning which he had before
despised, and thrice pronounced, with a deep groan, the name of Solon. Cyrus
desired the interpreters to inquire whom he was invoking, and learned in reply
the anecdote of the Athenian lawgiver, together with the solemn memento which
he had offered to Crœsus during more prosperous days, attesting the frail
tenure of all human greatness. The remark sunk deep into the Persian monarch,
as a token of what might happen to himself: he repented of his purpose, and
directed that the pile, which had already been kindled, should be immediately
extinguished. But the orders came too late; in spite of the most zealous
efforts of
the bystanders, the flame was found unquenchable, and Crœsus would still have
been burned, had he not implored with prayers and tears the succor of Apollo,
to whose Delphian and Theban temples he had given such munificent presents. His
prayers were heard, the fair sky was immediately overcast, and a profuse rain
descended, sufficient to extinguish the flames. The
life of Crœsus was thus saved, and he became afterwards the confidential friend
and adviser of his conqueror.
Such is the brief outline of a narrative which
Herodotus has given with full development and with impressive effect. It would
have served as a show-lecture to the youth of Athens, not less admirably than
the well-known fable of the Choice of Hêraklês, which the philosopher Prodikus, a
junior contemporary of Herodotus, delivered with so much popularity. It
illustrates forcibly the religious and ethical ideas of antiquity; the deep
sense of the jealousy of the gods, who would not endure pride in any one except
themselves;[ the
impossibility, for any man, of realizing to himself more than a very moderate
share of happiness; the danger from reactionary nemesis, if at any time he had
overpassed such limit; and the necessity of calculations taking in the whole of
life, as a basis for rational comparison of different individuals; and as a
practical consequence from these feelings, a constant protest on the part of
the moralists against vehement impulses and unrestrained aspirations. The more
valuable this narrative appears, in its illustrative character, the less can we
presume to treat it as a history.
It is much to be regretted that we have no information
respecting events in Attica immediately after the Solonian laws and
constitution, which were promulgated in 594 B. C., so as to
understand better the practical effect of these changes. What we next hear
respecting Solon in Attica refers to a period immediately preceding the first
usurpation of Peisistratus in 560 B. C., and after the return of Solon from his long absence.
We are here again introduced to the same oligarchical dissensions as are
reported to have prevailed before the Solonian legislation: the pedieis, or
opulent proprietors of the plain round Athens, under Lykurgus; the parali of
the south of Attica, under Megaklês: and the diakrii, or mountaineers of the
eastern cantons, the poorest of the three classes, under Peisistratus, are in a
state of violent intestine dispute. The account of Plutarch represents Solon as
returning to Athens during the height of this sedition. He was treated with
respect by all parties, but his recommendations were no longer obeyed, and he
was disqualified by age from acting with effect in public. He employed his best
efforts to mitigate party animosities, and applied himself particularly to
restrain the ambition of Peisistratus, whose ulterior projects he quickly
detected.
The future greatness of Peisistratus is said to have
been first portended by a miracle which happened, even before his birth, to his
father Hippokratês at the Olympic games. It was realized, partly by his bravery
and conduct, which had been displayed in the capture of Nisæa from the
Megarians,—partly by
his popularity of
speech and manners, his championship of the poor, and
his ostentatious disavowal of all selfish pretensions,—partly by an artful
mixture of stratagem and force. Solon, after having addressed fruitless
remonstrances to Peisistratus himself, publicly denounced his designs in verses
addressed to the people. The deception, whereby Peisistratus finally
accomplished his design, is memorable in Grecian tradition. He
appeared one day in the agora of Athens in his chariot with a pair of mules: he
had intentionally wounded both his person and the mules, and in this condition
he threw himself upon the compassion and defence of the people, pretending that
his political enemies had violently attacked him. He implored the people to
grant him a guard, and at the moment when their sympathies were freshly aroused
both in his favor and against his supposed assassins, Aristo proposed formally to the ekklesia,—the pro-bouleutic
senate, being composed of friends of Peisistratus, had previously authorized
the proposition,—that a
company of fifty club-men should be assigned as a permanent body-guard for the
defence of Peisistratus. To this motion Solon opposed a strenuous resistance, but
found himself overborne, and even treated as if he had lost his senses. The
poor were earnest in favor of it, while the rich were afraid to express their
dissent; and he could only comfort himself, after the fatal vote had been
passed, by exclaiming that he was wiser than the former and more determined
than the latter. Such was one of the first known instances in which this
memorable stratagem was played off against the liberty of a Grecian community.
The unbounded popular favor which had procured the
passing of this grant, was still farther manifested by the absence of all
precautions to prevent the limits of the grant from being exceeded. The number
of the body-guard was not long confined to fifty, and probably their clubs were
soon exchanged for sharper weapons. Peisistratus thus found himself strong
enough to throw off the mask and seize the acropolis. His leading opponents,
Megaklês and the Alkmæônids, immediately fled the city, and it was left to the
venerable age and undaunted patriotism of Solon to stand forward almost alone
in a vain attempt to resist the usurpation. He publicly presented himself in
the market-place, employing encouragement, remonstrance, and reproach, in order
to rouse the spirit of the people. To prevent this despotism from coming, he
told them would have been easy; to shake it off now was more difficult, yet at
the same time more glorious. But
he spoke in vain; for all who were not actually favorable to Peisistratus
listened only to their fears, and remained passive; nor did any one join Solon,
when, as a last appeal, he put on his armor and planted himself in military
posture before the door of his house. “I have done my duty, he exclaimed at
length; I have sustained to the best of my power my country and the laws:” and he then renounced all farther hope of
opposition,—though resisting the instances of his friends that he should flee,
and returning for answer, when they asked him on what he relied for protection,
“On my old age.” Nor did he even think it necessary to repress the inspirations
of his Muse: some verses yet remain, composed seemingly at a moment when the
strong hand of the new despot had begun to make itself sorely felt, in which he
tells his countrymen: “If ye have endured sorrow from your own baseness of
soul, impute not the fault of this to the gods. Ye have yourselves put force
and dominion into the hands of these men, and have thus drawn upon yourselves
wretched slavery.”
It is gratifying to learn that Peisistratus, whose
conduct throughout his despotism was comparatively mild, left Solon untouched.
How long this distinguished man survived the practical subversion of his own
constitution, we cannot certainly determine; but according to the most probable
statement he died the very next year, at the advanced age of eighty.
We have only to regret that we are deprived of the
means of following more in detail his noble and exemplary character. He
represents the best tendencies of his age, combined with much that is
personally excellent; the improved ethical sensibility; the thirst for enlarged
knowledge and observation, not less potent in old age than in youth; the
conception of regularized popular institutions, departing sensibly from the
type and spirit of the governments around him, and calculated to found a new
character in the Athenian people; a genuine and reflecting sympathy with the
mass of the poor, anxious not merely to rescue them from the oppressions of the
rich, but also to create in them habits of self-relying industry; lastly,
during his temporary possession of a power altogether arbitrary, not merely an
absence of all selfish ambition, but a rare discretion in seizing the mean
between conflicting exigencies. In reading his poems we must always recollect
that what now appears common-place was once new, so that to his comparatively
unlettered age, the social pictures which he draws were still fresh, and his
exhortations calculated to live in the memory. The poems composed on moral
subjects, generally inculcate a spirit of gentleness towards others and
moderation in personal objects; they represent the gods as irresistible,
retributive,
favoring the good and punishing the bad, though sometimes very tardily. But his
compositions on special and present occasions are usually conceived in a more
vigorous spirit; denouncing the oppressions of the rich at one time, and the
timid submission to Peisistratus at another,—and expressing, in emphatic
language, his own proud consciousness of having stood forward as champion of
the mass of the people. Of his early poems hardly anything is preserved; the
few lines which remain seem to manifest a jovial temperament, which we may well
conceive to have been overlaid by the political difficulties against which he
had to contend,—difficulties arising successively out of the Megarian war, the
Kylonian sacrilege, the public despondency healed by Epimenidês, and the task
of arbiter between a rapacious oligarchy and a suffering people. In one of his
elegies, addressed to Mimnermus, he marked out the sixtieth year as the longest
desirable period of life, in preference to the eightieth year, which that poet
had expressed a wish to attain; but
his own life, as far as we can judge, seems to have reached the longer of the
two periods, and not the least honorable part of it—the resistance to
Peisistratus—occurs immediately before his death.
There prevailed a story, that his ashes were collected and scattered around the island of Salamis, which Plutarch treats as absurd,—though he tells us at the same time that it was believed both by Aristotle, and by many other considerable men: it is at least as ancient as the poet Kratinus, who alluded to it in one of his comedies, and I do not feel inclined to reject it. The inscription on the statue of Solon at Athens described him as a Salaminian: he had been the great means of acquiring the island for his country,—and it seems highly probable that among the new Athenian citizens who went to settle there, he may have received a lot of land and become enrolled among the Salaminian demots. The dispersion of his ashes in various parts of the island connects him with it as in some sort the œkist; and we may construe that incident, if not as the expression of a public vote, at least as a piece of affectionate vanity on the part of his surviving friends. We have now reached the period of the usurpation of
Peisistratus (B. C. 560), whose dynasty governed Athens—with two
temporary interruptions during the life of Peisistratus himself—for fifty
years. The history of this despotism, milder than Grecian despotism generally,
and productive of important consequences to Athens, will be reserved for a
succeeding chapter.
|