READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
BIOGRAPHYCAL UNIVERSAL LIBRARY |
PLATO( 428-347 BC)By Bernard Williams
The Invention of Philosophy
Plato invented the subject of philosophy as we know it. He lived from
427 to 347 BC, and he is the first philosopher whose works have come down to us
complete. He is also the first to have written on the full range of
philosophical questions: knowledge, perception, politics, ethics, art; language
and its relations to the world; death, immortality and the nature of the mind;
necessity, change and the underlying order of things. A. N. Whitehead said that
the European philosophical tradition consisted of “a series of footnotes to
Plato”, and his remark makes a point. Of course, the content of the questions
has changed in all sorts of ways, with the development of the sciences and
radical transformations in society and culture. It is important, too, that we,
unlike Plato, have a strong sense of the importance of history in understanding
human life, but this sense has come about quite recently, and is absent not
only from Plato but from most other philosophers before the nineteenth century,
who tended, like him and under his influence, to think of the most important
truths as timeless.
Western philosophy not only started with Plato, but has spent most of
its life in his company. There was a period in the Middle Ages when almost all
his works were unknown, but before that, and after the rediscovery of his texts
(Petrarch in the fourteenth century had a manuscript of Plato), he has been
read and has been a point of reference. Some thinkers, in various different
styles, have thought of themselves as “Platonists”; most others have not, and
many reject every one of his distinctive positions, but they are all indirectly
under his influence. We are all under the influence of thinkers we do not read,
but in Plato's case, people also turn back continually to his work itself. He
is in any case a great writer, who can command extraordinary ingenuity, charm,
and power, but beyond that, his genius as a philosophical writer is expressed
in a special way. Many philosophers write treatises, analyzing the problem,
arguing with other positions, and setting out their own solutions. Plato did
not: he wrote dialogues. With the exception of some Letters, which are
doubtfully genuine, all Plato’s works are in this form. Because they are
dialogues, there is always something more and different to be drawn from them,
not just in the way that this is true of all great works of philosophy, but
because Plato specially intends it to be so. The dialogue form is not, for most
part, just an artful way of his telling one something. It is an entry and an
invitation to thought.
Plato never appears in the dialogues himself. In most of them, a major
part is taken by the striking figure of Socrates, Plato’s teacher. They are by
far our most important source for what Socrates was like. Socrates is the inspiration
of the dialogues in more than one way. He himself wrote nothing, and indeed
claimed to know nothing, devoting himself, it seems, to engaging people in
conversations in which he questioned their most basic beliefs and showed that
they had no basis for them. This method is described in several of Plato's
dialogues, and many of them display it in action. But Socrates’ legacy was not
just a matter of method. His life, and more particularly his death, left Plato
with some of his deepest concerns.
Socrates was tried by the Athenian courts in 399 BC and executed, on
charges, among other things, of “corrupting the youth”, and this disaster
starkly raised a range of questions: what the evil was in a political order
that could do this; how it was that Socrates’ presence had not made his fellow
citizens (including some of his associates) better people; and how much it
mattered - whether in the end it mattered at all - that Socrates’ life was
lost, granted that his character was uncorrupted. All these were to be central
themes of Plato's philosophy, a philosophy expressed through the dialogue form
which was itself a tribute in writing to Socrates’ style of life and talk.
In some of the dialogues, particularly some that can be dated to late in
Plato's life, the conversational form withers away, and they do function almost
as treatises. In a few, characters other than Socrates do not express much more
than puzzlement, agreement, or admiration. But for the most part, the dialogue
form is an active presence, and this affects in more than one way our relations
to Plato’s ideas. In some dialogues, no one offers a definite conclusion, and
we find that we have been presented with a question, a refutation, or a puzzle.
This particularly applies to those which we can take to have been written in
Plato’s earlier years, but it is also true, to a considerable extent, of a
notably powerful later dialogue, the Theaetetus. Even
when an authoritative figure in a dialogue, usually Socrates, seems to leave us
with a conclusion or theory to be taken away from it, we should not necessarily
suppose that this is what Plato is telling us to believe.
Not everything asserted in a dialogue, even by Socrates, has been
asserted by Plato: Socrates asserting may be Plato suggesting. Because an
immensely serious philosopher, who indeed set philosophy on the path of
claiming to address our deepest concerns by means of argument, orderly enquiry,
and intellectual imagination, and because we project on to him images of
seriousness which are drawn from other philosophy and from later experience, we
may well underestimate the extent to which he could combine intensity,
pessimism, and even a certain religious solemnity, with an ironical gaiety and
an incapacity to take all his own ideas equally seriously.
It is a weakness of scholars who study philosophers to think that
philosophers are just like scholars, and it is particularly a mistake in the
case of Plato. Plato gathered about him a group of people who pursued
philosophical discussion, teaching and enquiries into mathematics and
astronomy. This gave rise, eventually, to a new kind of institution, a place
for what we would now call “research”. From the public space on the edge of
Athens in which Plato carried on his discussions, it was called the Academy,
and in this way Plato gave the word 'academic' to the world, but it is an irony
that he should have done so. We should not be trapped into thinking of him as a
professor.
This point bears on a passage which itself raises a question of how far
we should trust his written works. Towards the end of the Phaedrus, there is
this conversation:
Socrates— Well, then, someone who thinks that he can set down an art in
writing, and equally someone who accepts something from writing as though it
were going to be clear and reliable, must be very simpleminded... how can they
possibly think that words which have been written down can do more than serve
as a reminder to those who already know what the writing is about?
Phaedrus— Quite right.
Socrates— You know, Phaedrus, writing shares a strange feature with
painting. The offspring of painting stand there as if they were alive, but if
anyone asks them anything, they are solemnly silent. The same is true of
written words. You'd think they were speaking as if they had some
understanding, but if you question anything that has been said because you want
to learn more, it gives just the same message over and over. Once it has been
written down, every discourse rolls about everywhere, reaching just as much
those with understanding as those who have no business with it, and it does not
know to whom it should speak and to whom not. And when it is faulted and
attacked unfairly, it always needs its father's support; alone, it cannot
defend itself or come to its own support.
Phaedrus— You are quite right about that too.
Socrates— Now tell me, can we discern another kind of discourse, a
legitimate brother of this one? Can we say how it comes about, and how much
better and more capable it naturally is?
Phaedrus— Which one is that? How do you say it comes about?
Socrates— It is a discourse that is written down, with knowledge, in the
soul of the listener; it can defend itself, and it knows to whom it should
speak, and with whom it should remain silent.
Phaedrus— You mean the living, breathing discourse of the man who knows,
of which the written one can fairly be called an image.
Socrates— Exactly, and tell me this. Would a farmer who was sensible and
cared about his seeds and wanted them to yield fruit plant them in all
seriousness in the gardens of Adonis in the middle of summer and enjoy watching
them become fine plants in a week? Or would he do this as an amusement and in honour of the holiday, if he did it at all? Wouldn't he use
his knowledge of farming to plant the seeds he cared for when it was
appropriate, and be satisfied if they bore fruit eight months later?
Phaedrus— That’s how he would handle those he was serious about,
Socrates, quite differently from the others, as you say.
Socrates— Now what about the man who knows what is just, noble and good?
Shall we say that he is less sensible with his seeds than the farmer is with
his?
Phaedrus— Certainly not.
Socrates— Therefore he wouldn't be serious if he wrote them in ink,
sowing them, through a pen, with words that are unable to speak in their own
defence and unable to teach the truth properly.
Phaedrus— He surely wouldn't.
Socrates— No, he is likely to sow gardens of writing just for fun, and
to write, when he writes, to store up reminders for himself when he arrives at
old age and forgetfulness, and for other people who follow in his footsteps,
and he will like to see them sweetly blooming; and while others take up other
amusements, refreshing themselves with drinking parties and such things, he is
likely to enjoy himself, rather, like this.
Phaedrus— Socrates, you are contrasting a vulgar amusement with a very
fine one, with the amusement of a man who can while away his time telling
stories of justice and the other things you mentioned.
Socrates— That's just how it is, Phaedrus. But there is a much finer
concern about these things, that of someone who uses the art of dialectic, and
takes a suitable soul and plants and sows discourse accompanied with knowledge:
discourse which is capable of helping itself and the sower, which is not barren
but produces a seed from which other discourse grows in other lives, and in
turn can go on to make the seed immortal, making the man who has it as happy as
any man can be.
By “the art of dialectic” here Socrates means argument in speech,
teaching through conversation. There has been discussion of why Plato, after
this, should have gone on writing. But even if we take Socrates’ remarks (a
little stolidly, perhaps) entirely at their face value, they do not mean that
Plato should not write - they give him a reason to write, and that reason is
obviously only one among similar reasons we might imagine. This passage does
not mean the end of philosophical writing. But it does expect an important idea
about the limitations of philosophical writing, an idea which, I shall suggest,
is important in relation to the spirit in which Plato wrote his works and the
spirit in which we should read them.
Plato's Development
A complication in trying to extract Plato’s philosophy from the
dialogues is that they do not all present the same philosophy, and his views
and interests, not surprisingly, changed over time. It is thus very important
to establish, if we can, the order in which the dialogues were written. There
are various sorts of evidence that can be brought to bear on this. There are
occasionally references to historical events. Some dialogues refer explicitly
or by implication to others. There is a technique called “stylometry”,
which treats certain features of Plato’s style statistically to establish
gradual changes in them over time. In addition, there is the content of the
various dialogues, in terms of which we can try to make sense of Plato’s
philosophical development. Here there is an obvious danger that we shall fall
into a circle, dating the dialogues in terms of their ideas, and working out
the development of the ideas from the order of the dialogues. However, with the
help of all these methods together, scholars have arrived at a fair measure of
agreement.
The earliest is a group of short dialogues often called “Socratic”
because the role played by Socrates does not go beyond what, it is generally
thought, can reasonably be ascribed to the historical Socrates himself. There
is then a pair of dialogues, the Gorgias and the Meno, which, as we shall see, seem to mark a transition from
the concerns of the Socratic dialogues to those of Plato’s Middle Period, in
which, as everyone now agrees, he goes beyond the interests of the historical
Socrates, and develops very distinctive ideas of his own. The Middle Period
contains what may be the most famous of his dialogues, the Phaedo, the Symposium, and the
Republic. These dialogues have particularly helped to form the traditional
picture of “the Platonic philosophy”, which contrasts with the everyday
physical world of appearance a realm of intellectual, eternal objects, which
are the objects of real knowledge and can be directly attained, in some sense,
by the immortal soul. These objects are called “Forms”, and we shall be
concerned later with questions of what Plato thought they could explain, and
how far he had a consistent theory of them.
These famous dialogues of the Middle Period were not by any means Plato’s
last word, and among the hardest questions in Platonic scholarship is to decide
exactly which dialogues are later than the Middle Period, and to form a picture
of how much, and in what ways, Plato may have changed his mind and his approach
as he got older. The late dialogues include the Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus and Laws. The last (from which Socrates has
finally disappeared) is probably the least read of Plato’s major dialogues: it
is a long discussion, in twelve books, of political and social arrangements, in
a more realistic but also much darker tone than that of the Republic.
There are two dialogues that, together, give rise to problems of dating
in a particularly acute form. On stylometric grounds,
the Timaeus seems to be a late dialogue. However, it
gives an elaborate account of the creation of things by a “demiurge” who
imposes form on matter (there is no question in Plato of a divine creation of
the world from nothing, as in the Christian tradition), and it refers to the
Forms in terms very similar to those used in Middle Period works such as, above
all, the Republic. On the other hand, the Parmenides, which cannot be
distinguished stylistically from Middle Period dialogues, contains a number of
extremely serious criticisms of those ways of talking about Forms, criticisms
which many, including Aristotle, have regarded as fatal.
They occur in the first part of the dialogue, where a very young
Socrates is represented conversing with the old and sage figure of Parmenides,
who in fact wrote a bold metaphysical poem claiming the unity of everything and
the impossibility of change, and who was held in great respect by Plato. (It is
just possible, in terms of dates, that Socrates should have met Parmenides,
very unlikely that he did so, and quite certain that they could not have had
such a conversation.) Socrates advances an account of Forms to which Parmenides
(virtually quoting from the Phaedo), makes a series
of objections which Socrates cannot answer. Parmenides says that he needs
training in 'dialectic' (which was, significantly, Plato’s favorite term for
more than one method in philosophy which, at various times, he found most
promising), and suggests that he listen to a demonstration from Parmenides'
companion and pupil, Zeno.
The second part of the dialogue consists of a very elaborate set of
entirely abstract arguments, the content, and indeed the whole point, of which
are still not agreed. On one picture of Plato's development, he started with
the modest methods of enquiry that he acquired from Socrates. He then developed
a “theory of Forms”, with the very ambitious doctrines, particularly about
immortality, that are associated with it in the Republic, the Phaedo, and the Symposium.
He then became convinced that there were deep difficulties with the theory,
difficulties which are expressed in the Parmenides. Then, in later works,
notably the Theaetetus, Sophist, and Statesman, which are without doubt more technical, he pursued in
much more severely analytical detail problems that had been latent in the grand
theories of the Middle Period.
I think that there is some truth in this schema and some of what I say
about Plato's outlook will be in this spirit, but we should not be tied to any
simple version of it. In particular, we should not ask whether or when Plato
gave up “the Theory of Forms”, because, as we shall see, there is no Theory of
Forms. In any case, it is artificial to discuss these matters as though Plato
wrote his dialogues in an order, in the sense that he always finished one
before starting another. He may have had more than one unfinished at once;
still more, the ideas that appeared in various dialogues were at work in his
head at the same time.
Above all, it is a mistake to suppose that Plato spends his time in the
various dialogues adding to or subtracting from his system. Each dialogue is
about whatever it is about, and Plato pursues what seems interesting and
fruitful in that connection. We often cannot know, in fact, exactly what made a
consideration seem to him interesting and fruitful at a given point. Plato was
recognizably, I think, one of those creative thinkers and artists - it is not
true of all, including some of the greatest - who are an immensely rich source
of thoughts and images, too many, perhaps, for them all to have their place and
use. We may think of him as driven forward by his ideas, curious at any given
point to see what will happen if some striking conjunction of them is given its
head. We should not think of him as constantly keeping his accounts, anxious of
how his system will look in the history of philosophy.
The Socratic Dialogues
In the early dialogues Socrates typically appears discussing with one or
more characters a question about the nature of the virtues, and refutes some
claim to knowledge which they have made, while offering his habitual disclaimer
to the effect that he himself knows nothing. To this extent, the dialogues are “aporetic”, that is to say, negative in their outcome, but
there is often some significant suggestion in the offing. In the Laches, a
characteristic example, Socrates is asked by two distinguished citizens, Nikias and Laches, whether young men should be trained to
fight in armor; he draws them into a discussion about the nature of courage.
Their common-sensical suggestions are refuted, and no
conclusion is reached. By the end, however, Socrates has implicitly advanced a
distinctive view, by associating the virtue of courage with knowledge, as he
does elsewhere with other virtues. Moreover, the dramatic frame of the dialogue
introduces a theme which was to be of constant concern to Plato, and which is
brought to focus later in the Meno: how is it that worthy people in an earlier generation,
who basically, if unreflectively, lived by decent values, were unable, as Plato
believed, to pass them on to their children?
One of the dialogues that is assigned to the early group on grounds of
its style and, in general terms, its content, is the Protagoras, but it is a
strikingly special case. Socrates tells how he was woken early in the morning
by an enthusiastic friend wanting him to come to a house where they could see
the great teacher, Protagoras, who is visiting Athens. Protagoras is a “sophist”,
someone who takes fees for teaching, in particular for teaching young people
how to be successful and happy. Plato repeatedly attacks such people, and it is
to him, principally, that they owe their bad reputation, but he clearly had a
genuine respect for Protagoras. He comes out very well from this dialogue, and
later, in the Theaetetus,
though he does not appear himself, Plato discusses as his invention a
sophisticated theory based on his well-known saying, “man is the measure of all
things”.
Admitted to the house, Socrates and his friend find Protagoras
surrounded by admirers, and there is also a notable group of other sophists,
sketched by Plato with a lightly malicious touch. Socrates raises the question
whether virtue can be taught. Protagoras gives a long and brilliant speech in
which he tells a story about the natural defenselessness of human beings and
their survival through their intelligence and inventiveness, and he lays out
what may be seen as a theory of knowledge for democracy: virtue can be taught,
but, unlike the arts, where there is a division of labor and conspicuous
experts, in the matter of virtue citizens teach their children and each other.
Plato gives Protagoras a compelling and thoughtful expression of such an
outlook, though it is exactly what he himself rejected. He himself came to
believe that there were distinctive kinds of knowledge that must underlie
virtue, and the project of the Republic is to design a social order which will
indeed be authoritarian, because it will use political power to express the
authority of knowledge. There is no place in this for democracy. Plato
typically compares a democratic city to a ship navigated by majority vote of
the passengers, and in the Republic it is represented in hostile and embittered
terms, as, in the Gorgias,
the greatest of Athenian democratic leaders, Pericles, is brutally attacked as
a demagogue. Here, however, Protagoras is allowed to offer a different and more
benign conception. It is an example of something that is one of Plato's
strengths, even if his polemics sometimes conceal it - that he can understand,
not just the force of contrary arguments, but the power of an opposing vision.
In the course of the exchanges that follow, Socrates demands, as he
often does in the presence of sophists and teachers of rhetoric, that there
should be a real conversation, proceeding by question and answer, and that there
should be no long speeches. The idea (which no doubt came from the historical
Socrates himself) is that only through question and answer is it possible to
construct and follow a logical argument, which will actually prove or disprove
a definite conclusion: speeches allow irrelevance, bad logic, and misleading
emotional appeals. Quite often, characters in the dialogues complain about
Socrates’ method. Even if they do not put it in quite these terms, they might
be said to see the question and answer form as itself a rhetorical contrivance,
one that helps Socrates to force his opponents down a favored train of thought,
often a chain of misleading analogies, instead of giving them a chance to stand
back and ask what other kinds of consideration might bear on the issue. The
criticism certainly occurs to many of Plato's readers.
When Socrates’ procedure invites that criticism, one must in any case
ask, as I suggested earlier, whether Plato necessarily expects the reader to
accept his argument or to question it. But there is a further point, that we
should not assume that 'the force of argument' is an entirely fixed and
determinate notion. It is not so anyway, and it is less so in Plato, for the
special reason that he more or less invented the idea. What one sees in his
dialogues is a process, of his seeking in many different ways to distinguish
sound argument from the mere power of persuasive speech, as it might be heard
in an Athenian law court, for instance. Ancient Greeks, and particularly,
perhaps, the notoriously litigious and political Athenians, were very impressed
by the power of speech. It is significant that the common Greek word logos had
semantic roots in both speech and reason; it can mean 'word', 'utterance',
'story', 'account', 'explanation', 'reason', and 'ratio', among other things.
One of Plato’s major and ongoing undertakings was to construct models of what
it is for an utterance not just to tell a story but to give a reason.
In the Protagoras, after his protests against speeches, Socrates makes a
long one himself, which is an engaging parody of another sophistic method, that
of advancing a view by commencing on a poem, a method which he shows, in
effect, can be used to prove anything you like. He then turns to refuting
Protagoras’s position, but this, too, takes a strange turn, since he claims as
the basis of his argument that the only good is pleasure, something that Plato
himself quite certainly did not believe. At the end of this brilliantly
inventive dialogue, the two protagonists, Socrates and Protagoras, find
themselves in a puzzling situation, with great respect for each other, and much
work still to be done:
—I have only one more question to ask you. Do you still believe, as you
did at first, that some men are extremely ignorant and yet still very
courageous?
—I think you just want to win the argument, Socrates, and that is why
you are forcing me to answer. So I will gratify you and say that on the basis
of what we have agreed upon, it seems to me to be impossible.
—I have no other reason for asking these things than my desire to answer
these questions about virtue, especially what virtue is in itself. For I know
that if we could get clear on that, then we would be able to settle the
question about which we both have had much to say: I, that virtue cannot be
taught, you, that it can. It seems to me that the recent outcome of our
argument has turned on us like a person making fun of us, and that if it had a
voice it would say 'Socrates and Protagoras, how strange you are, both of you.
Socrates, you said earlier that virtue cannot be taught, but now you are
insisting on the opposite, trying to show that everything is knowledge -
justice, temperance, courage - in which case virtue would appear to be
eminently teachable.
On the other hand, if virtue is something other than knowledge, as Progatoras has been trying to say, then clearly it would
not be teachable. But if it turns out to be wholly knowledge, as you are now
insisting, Socrates, it would be very surprising indeed if virtue could not be
taught. Protagoras maintained at first that it could be taught, but now he
thinks the opposite, urging that hardly any of the virtues turn out to be
knowledge. On that view, it hardly could be true that it was teachable. Now, Protagoras,
seeing that everything is upside down and in a terrible confusion, I am most
eager to clear it all up, and I would like us, having come this far, to
continue until we come through to what virtue is in itself, and then to enquire
once more whether it can or cannot be taught... If you are willing, as I said
at the beginning, I would be pleased to investigate these things along with you.
—Socrates, I commend your enthusiasm and your ability to find your way
through an argument. I really don't think I am a bad man, and certainly I am
the last man to be envious. Indeed, I have told many people that I admire you
more than anyone I have met, certainly more than anyone in your generation. And
I say that I would not be surprised if you came to be very well regarded for
wisdom. We shall examine these matters later, whenever you wish. But now the
time has come to turn to other things.
Virtue Is Not Yet Knowledge
The question whether virtue can be taught is taken up in the Meno, and again
it leads to another: how can one answer this question if one does not already
know what virtue is? To ask what a particular virtue is, is a standard Socratic
move, as he asked about courage in the Laches, but now Plato explains rather
more fully than he had earlier what the answer to any such question might be
like. It cannot consist of a list of examples - that will not show what the
examples have in common. It cannot merely be a characteristic that necessarily
goes with the item in question: we cannot say, for instance, that shape is “the
only thing that always accompanies colour” - that is
true, perhaps, but it does not explain what shape is. This discussion of method
gives us some ideas that were implicit in Socratic questioning, but were not
all clearly recognized. One is that the account we are looking for (in this
case, of virtue) must be explanatory - it must not simply capture an adequate
definition of the word, but must give us insight into what virtue is. This in
turn raises the possibility that the account may have to be part of a larger
theory.
A further idea is that the account will not leave everything where it
was. It may revise the ideas that people typically have of the virtues. Indeed,
it may well require them to change their lives. That, certainly, was part of
Socrates’ project, even if it was not clear how it could be so. The
distinctively Platonic idea, which begins to grow in the Meno,
is that it is theory that, in one way or another, must change one’s life.
But now Meno finds an obstacle to the search
for what virtue is:
Meno— How will you
look for something, Socrates, when you do not know at all what it is? What sort
of thing will you set as the target of your search, among the things you do not
know? If you did meet with it, how would you know that this was the thing that
you did not know?
Socrates— I understand what you want to say, Meno.
Do you realize that this is a debater's argument you are bringing up: that a
man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not, know? He
cannot search for what he knows - since he knows it, there is no need for a
search; nor for what he does not know, since he does not know what to look for.
Meno— Does that
argument not seem sound to you, Socrates?
Socrates— Not to me.
Meno— Can you tell me
why?
Socrates— I can.
And he goes on to say something which in terms of the earlier
extraordinary:
Socrates— I have heard from men and women who are wise about divine
things.
Meno— What do they
say?
Socrates— Something, I thought, both true and beautiful.
Meno— What is it, and
who are they?
Socrates— Those who say it are among the priests and priestesses whose
care it is to be able to give an account of their practices. Pindar too says
it, and many other poets, those who are divine. What they say is this; see
whether you think they speak the truth. They say that the human soul is
immortal; at times it comes to an end, which they call dying, at times it is
reborn, but it is never destroyed. So one must live as holy a life as possible:
Persephone will receive the debt of ancient wrong;
In the ninth year she will give back their souls to
the sun above,
And from these there will grow noble kings, and men
great in strength and skill,
And for the rest of time they shall be called sacred
heroes.
As the soul is immortal and has been born often and has seen everything
here and in the underworld, there is nothing that it has not learned; so it is
not surprising that it can recollect the things it knew before, about virtue
and about other things. As the whole of nature is akin, and the soul has
learned everything, nothing prevents a man, after he has recalled just one
thing - the process that people call learning - discovering everything else for
himself, if he is brave and does not tire of the search; for searching and
learning are simply recollection.
These are stories, Socrates admits, not demonstrations, but perhaps
there can be a demonstration. He summons a slave boy, and, in a famous scene,
gets him, merely by questioning him, to see the solution to a geometrical
problem which he had never even heard of at the beginning of their
conversation. How can this be possible? Socrates’ suggestion is that the
demonstration reminded the boy of the answer; he knew it already, but until now
had forgotten it. Since he knew it already, he must have learned it already;
but he did not learn it in this life, so he learned it in an earlier life. The
soul is immortal.
It is not much of an argument. There is in any case an objection, that
even if we have been shown by this episode that the boy's soul existed earlier,
there is nothing here to show that it will exist later - preexistence is less
than immortality. Plato fills in the missing piece by pure sleight of hand. But
there is a deeper and more interesting problem. It is often objected to in this
scene that Socrates leads the boy in the demonstration. This misses the point.
If the question had been one in history or geography, the boy could not, in any
comparable way, have come to see the answer: in such subjects, if one does not
know, one does not know. It is essential that the exercise is in mathematics
and involves what is called a priori knowledge, knowledge which is independent
of experience. Plato offers here the first theory of such knowledge.
The demonstration may well show something about how we become conscious
of a priori knowledge. Indeed, many philosophers have agreed with Plato to this
extent, that such knowledge is in some sense innate. Very few, however, have
agreed that this has anything to do with an earlier existence. For why should
we say that there was some more direct way in which the boy must have
originally learned it? Learning in the way that the boy has just learned, the
way displayed in the demonstration, is how we learn mathematics: how could
there be some more direct, original, way of doing so? Plato thinks, or will
come to think, that there is an answer to this question, that the naked soul
once saw mathematical objects directly by the eye of the intellect. But how
could such a process possibly be a way of coming to know mathematics? It is a
strange, and typically metaphysical, reversal; Plato praises reason over sense
perception, the intellectual over the material, but, trying to give an account
of a priori knowledge, he straight off interprets it as an intellectual version
of sense perception.
Socrates says that the boy does not yet properly know this mathematical
truth (in this life), because he has no secure hold on it, will no doubt forget
it, and, most importantly, cannot explain it. At the moment it is a mere
belief, which will become knowledge only if it is “tied down by a chain of
reasoning”. Later on in the Meno, he illustrates this important distinction between
knowledge and true belief by a different sort of example. He contrasts a man
who knows the way to Larissa, because he has been there, with one who simply
happens to have got it right. Put like this, the distinction is not confined to
any particular subject matter: if you have a true belief, and you have the
reasons, the backing, or the experience appropriate to that kind of belief,
then you have knowledge. This does not suggest, as the experiment with the
geometry problem might perhaps suggest, that only a priori knowledge is really
knowledge. Still less does it suggest - indeed, it contradicts the suggestion -
that knowledge might have one subject matter and belief another. As we shall
see, Plato does come to some such position in the Republic, but that is to move
a long way, and in a rather perverse direction, from what is first offered in
the Meno.
Socrates uses the Meno’s distinction between
knowledge and true belief to answer the familiar question: how can decent men
have failed to teach their sons to have their own virtues? He and Meno, even though they do not know what virtue is, have
agreed to conduct their argument on an assumption, which if virtue is
knowledge, then it must be teachable. Certainly virtue has not been taught. The
sophists claim to do so, but if they have any effect at all, it is to make their
pupils worse people. More significantly, worthy men, who care above all that
their sons should share their virtues, have failed to bring this about. So, it
seems, virtue is not teachable, and therefore, on the assumption which they
have accepted, it is not knowledge. That is, in a way, correct, but given the Meno’s distinction, it does not mean that virtue could not
become knowledge. What we learn from the worthy men's experience is only that
their virtue was not knowledge. It was not nothing, however: they did have
virtue, but it took the form of true belief. That worked all right for them in
practice, just as a true belief about the road to Larissa will get you there,
and will enable you to lead others there if they are actually with you. It does
not enable you to teach another to get there by himself. But if we could find
the right chains of reasoning to tie these beliefs down, so they do not run
away, then they might become knowledge, and then they could be taught.
Philosophy will provide those chains of reasoning, and this is how it will
change our lives.
That Plato should present Socrates as making this point has a special
pathos about it, for the most striking instance of someone who failed to teach
his virtue was Socrates himself. Socrates had a pupil and a lover, Alcibiades,
who was very talented and, it seems, very beautiful. His life was a disaster:
vain and petulant, he betrayed Athens and others as well, and died a ruined
man. The case of Alcibiades was a reproach to Socrates as a teacher, and Plato's
recurrent and developing concern with the issues discussed in the Meno is a
response to that reproach, an ongoing apology.
In the Symposium Plato
confronts squarely the relations between Socrates and Alcibiades, and one of
the less obvious features of that wonderful dialogue is the ethical assurance
with which he does so. In his own contribution to the series of speeches,
Socrates had already said that the goddess Diotima had told him that he himself would not reach the highest level of intellectual
love, which in outline she describes to him, love in the presence of the Form
of beauty; this signals the metaphysical deficit, so to speak, which Plato
diagnosed in Socrates’ experience. Alcibiades, drunk, bursts into the party
after the speeches (his part has to be something separate, dramatic, not a
contribution under the rules of the occasion). He gives a vivid account of
Socrates, and of their strange relations. It is an encomium, and we are to take
it as true; it reveals some understanding; but at the same time it shows that,
whatever might possibly be learned from Socrates, Alcibiades, inside an invincible
vanity, could not learn it.
It was not merely that decent people did not manage to pass on their
values, because they did not grasp and could not explain reasons for leading a
decent life. There were also people who argued that there was no reason to lead
a decent life, and that the best idea would be a life of ruthless
self-interest. How many people argued this as a philosophic position we do not
know but certainly there was a social attitude, to the effect that the
conventional values of justice - to behave fairly and cooperatively, keep one’s
word, consider others’ interests - were a racket, which was encouraged by
people who were intelligent and powerful and did not need to live like this
themselves.
There are two characters in the dialogues who express this view. One,
the more colorful and formidable, is Callicles in the Gorgias. Callicles’ first speech offers a powerfully expressed challenge
both to the life of justice and to the activity of philosophy, as contrasted
with a political life in which one can exercise power. Besides the reference to
Socrates' trial and execution, perhaps one can hear, too, what Plato knew might
be said of himself if he had got it wrong about applying his talents to
philosophy:
-We mould the best and the most powerful among
us, taking them while they’re still young, like lion cubs, and with charms and
incantations we subdue them into slavery, telling them that one is supposed to
get no more than his fair share, and that this is what is fair and just. But I
believe that if there were to be a man whose nature was up to it, one who had
shaken off, torn apart, and escaped all this, who had trampled under foot our documents, our trickery and charms, and all
those laws that are against nature - he, the slave, would rise up and be
revealed as our master, and then the justice of nature would shine out ...
-Philosophy is no doubt a charming thing, Socrates, if someone is
exposed to it in moderation at the appropriate time of life. But if one spends
more time on it than he should, it is the undoing of mankind. For even if
someone has great natural advantages, if he engages in philosophy far beyond
the appropriate time of life, he will inevitably turn out to be inexperienced
in all those things in which a man has to be experienced if he is to be
admirable and good and well thought of. Such people have no experience of the
laws of their city or of the kind of speech one must use to deal with people on
matters of business, public or private; they have no experience in human
pleasures and appetites; no experience, in short, of human character
altogether. So when they venture into some private or political activity, they
become a laughing stock ... So when I see an older man still engaging in
philosophy and not giving it up, I think such a man by this time needs a
flogging. As I was just saying, such a man, even with natural advantages, will
end up becoming unmanly and avoiding the middle of the city and its meeting
places - where, as the poet said, men become really distinguished - and will
slink away for the rest of his life, whispering with three or four boys in a corner,
never coming out with anything free-spirited, important, or worth anyone's
attention ... As it is, if someone got hold of you or of anyone else like you
and took you off to prison on the charge that you're doing something unjust
when you're not, be assured that you wouldn't be able to do yourself any good.
You would get dizzy, your mouth would hang open, and you would not know what to
say. You would come up for trial and face some no-good wretch of an accuser and
be put to death, if death is what he wanted as your sentence. How can this be a
wise thing, Socrates, “the craft which took a well-favoured man and made him worse”, not able to protect himself or to rescue himself or
anyone else from the gravest dangers, to be robbed by his enemies, and to live
a life without honour in the city? To put it rather
crudely, you could give such a man a smack on the jaw and get away with it.
Listen to me, friend, and stop this refuting. “Practise the sweet music of an active life and do it where you'll get a reputation for
being intelligent. Leave these subtleties to others” - whether we call them
merely silly, or outright nonsense - 'which will cause you to live in empty
houses', and do not envy those who go in for these fiddling refutations, but
those who have a life, and fame, and many other good things as well.
Socrates has already had two conversations before Callicles appears, and they are carefully structured to show how radical Callicles’ outlook is. The first speaker is Gorgias, a famous orator and teacher of rhetoric, who gives
a defence of his profession. Plato believes that this profession is dangerous
and its claims to any expertise hollow, and in this notably angry dialogue he
goes on to denounce the rhetorician as a technician of mere appearances, like
someone who serves the sick with rich and unhealthy pastries or paints the face
of the dying. But Gorgias himself is treated with
some respect. He indeed gives a respectable defence: he thinks that his skills
serve the cause of justice, that the life of justice is worth living, and that
to be a just person is kalon - a significant ethical
term for the Greeks, which means that it is worthy of admiration, and that a
person would properly be well regarded and would have self-respect for living
such a life.
He is succeeded in the conversation (as, Plato believes, also in social
reality) by a younger and more belligerent figure, who is called Polus. He thinks that the life of justice is not
reasonable; given an alternative, it is not worth pursuing. Under Socrates'
questioning, however, he makes the mistake of admitting both that justice is kalon, worth admiring, and also (reasonably) that something
worth admiring is worth pursuing. Having said that justice is not worth
pursuing, he is faced, Socrates shows him, with a contradiction. Granted that
he thinks that we have reason to do what will make us admired, and no reason to
do what will make us feel foolish or ashamed of ourselves - that is to say, he
still attaches value to the kalon - he should not go
on saying that just behavior is to be admired and injustice is something to be
ashamed of. This is what Callicles, stormily breaking
into the conversation, points out. It is a purely conventional idea, he
insists, which must be given up if we are going to have a realistic view of
what is worth doing. Callicles himself does still
subscribe to the value of the kalon, but he does not
apply it to justice. He thinks that a reasonable person will want to be admired
and envied, to think well of himself, and not to be an object of contempt, but
the way to bring this about is through power and the exploitation of others,
having no concern for justice. Implicit in this, indeed very near the surface
of it, is the idea that people do secretly admire the successful exploiter and
despise the virtuously exploited, whatever they say about the value of justice.
Socrates does refute Callicles, but only by
forcing him into a position which, critics have thought, he has no reason to
accept. He ends up defending a crudely gluttonous form of hedonism, which not
many people are likely to envy. But this, surely, was not supposed to be the
idea. The successfully unjust man was supposed to be a rather grand and
powerful figure, whom others, if they were honest, would admire and envy, but
he has ended up in Socrates' refutation as a squalid addict whom anyone with
any taste would despise. It is easy to think that Socrates wins the argument
only because Plato has changed the subject. But Plato does not suppose that he
has changed the subject. His point is that without some idea of values that
apply to people generally, there will be no basis for any kind of admiration,
and if Callicles wants still to think of himself in
terms of the kalon, he will have to hold on to
something more than bare egoism, which by itself offers nothing for admiration
and really does lead only to an unstructured and unrewarding hedonism. Plato
himself, of course, believes something that goes beyond this, that only a life
of justice can offer the structure and order that are needed to make any life
worth living.
This is what the Republic is meant to show: “It is not a trivial
question we are discussing”, Socrates says towards the end of the first book of
that dialogue: “what we are talking about is how one should live”. He says it
to Thrasymachus, Plato’s other (and rhetorically less
impressive) representative of the enemies of justice. Thrasymachus has been defending the idea that if a person has a reason to act justly, it
will always be because it does somebody else some good. It is not very hard for
Socrates to refute this in the version that Thrasymachus offers; attached as he is to the rather flashy formula “justice is the interest
of the stronger”, Thrasymachus has not noticed that
the 'stronger' typically take the form of a group, a collective agent (such as
the people in the Athenian democracy), and that they can be a collective agent
only because they individually follow rules of justice.
This leads naturally to the idea that justice is not so much a device of
the strong to exploit the weak, as a device of the weak to make themselves
strong. This idea is spelled out in Book II by two further speakers, Glaukon and Adeimantus, who say
that they do not want to believe it themselves, but that they need to have it
refuted by Socrates. It is bound to seem to us ethically a lot more attractive
than Thrasymachus's proposition: it is the origin, in
fact, of the social contract theories that have played an important part in
later political philosophy. It is interesting, then, that Glaukon and Adeimantus, as much as Socrates himself, regard
this position as only a more effective variant of Thrasymachus’s.
The reason for this is that on this account justice still comes out as a second
best. Just as much as in Thrasymachus's cruder
account, it is an instrument or device for satisfying one's desires. An
adequate defence of justice, Plato thought, must show that it is rational for
each person to want to be just, whatever his circumstances, and the suggestion
of Glaukon and Adeimantus fails this test: if someone were powerful and intelligent and well enough
placed, he would reasonably have no interest in justice. What Socrates must
show is that justice is prized not simply for its effects, but for its own
sake.
But why is this the demand? Why is the standard for a defence of justice
raised so high? The answer fully emerges only after one has followed the whole
long discussion of the Republic. That discussion takes the form of considering
justice both in an individual and in a city, and Plato constructs a complex
analogy between the two. He discusses in great detail what the institutions of
a just city must be. He pursues this, as indeed Socrates makes clear, for its
own sake, but the main features of the analogy are needed to answer the question
about the value of justice in itself', and indeed to show why that has to be the
question in the first place.
A just person is one in whom reason rules, as opposed to the other two
'parts' of the soul that Plato distinguishes, a 'spirited', combative and
competitive, part, and a part that consists of hedonistic desires. Just people,
who will have this balance and stability in their soul, need to be brought up
in a just city, one that is governed by its own rational element; that is to
say, by a class of people who are themselves like this. Those people certainly
need to see justice as a good in itself; there is nothing to make them pursue
it except their own understanding of justice and of the good. They will be able
to do this, since their education will give them a philosophical understanding
of the good, and of why justice represents the proper development of the
rational soul. So, Plato hoped, the Republic would have answered the question
about the transmission of virtue from one generation to another: it could be
brought about only in a just city, and a just city must be one in which the
authority of reason is represented politically, by the unquestioned authority
of a class of Guardians who - and Socrates recognizes that it will be seen as a
very surprising solution - have been educated in philosophy.
In one sense, the foundation of a just city is supposed to be the final,
the only, answer to the question of how to keep justice alive. But even in the
Republic Plato does not suppose that it could in practice be a final answer,
for no earthly institution can last uncorrupted, and even if we imagine the
city coming about, it will ultimately degenerate, in a process which Plato lays
out in Books VIII and IX. There is a parallel story about the effects of the
ethical degeneration among individual people, and together they give an
opportunity, not only for an evaluation of different kinds of society, but for
a good deal of social and psychological observation."'
Out Of The Cave
Books V to VII of the Republic are devoted for the most part to the
education of the Guardians, and they also express some of Plato’s highest
metaphysical ambitions. This is because the further reaches of what the
Guardians learn extend to a reality which in some sense lies beyond everyday
experience, and it is only an encounter with this reality that secures the firm
hold on the good that underlies the stability of their own characters and their
just governance of the city. (It is worth mentioning that Plato says that women
should not, as such, be excluded from the highest and most abstract studies, an
idea that sets him apart from most of his contemporaries and, as often, from
the more conventional Aristotle.)
Plato pictures the progress of the soul under education in terms of an
ascent from what, in a vivid and very famous image, he represents as the
ordinary condition of human beings:
—Next, compare our nature, and the effect of its having or not having
education, to this experience. Picture human beings living in an underground
dwelling like a cave, with a long entrance open to the light, as wide as the
cave. They are there from childhood, with chains on their legs and their necks
so that they stay where they are and can only see in front of them, unable to
turn their heads because of the fetters. Light comes from a fire which is
burning higher up and some way behind them; and also higher up, between the
fire and the prisoners, there is a road along which a low wall is built, like
the screen in front of puppeteers above which they show their puppets.
—I can picture it.
—Now imagine that there are men along this wall, carrying all sorts of
implements which reach above the wall, and figures of men and animals in stone
and wood and every material, and some of the men who are doing this speak,
presumably, and others remain silent.
—It is a strange image you are describing, and strange prisoners.
—They are like us: for do you think that they would see anything of
themselves or each other except the shadows that were cast by the fire on the
wall in front of them?
—How could they, if they are forced to keep their heads motionless for
all their lives?
—And what about the objects that are being carried along the wall?
Wouldn't it be the same?
—Of course.
—And if they could talk to each other, don't you think they would
suppose that the names they used applied to the things passing before them?
—Certainly.
—And if the prison had an echo from the wall facing them? Wouldn't they
suppose that it was the shadow going by that was speaking, whenever one of
those carrying the objects spoke?
—Of course.
—Altogether then, they would believe that the truth was nothing other
than the shadows of those objects.
—They would indeed.
—But now consider what it would be like for them to be released from
their bonds and cured of their illusions, if such a thing could happen to them.
When one of them was freed and forced suddenly to stand up and turn his head
and walk and look up towards the light, doing all these things he would be in
pain, and because he was dazzled he would not be able to see the things of
which he had earlier seen the shadows. What do you think he would reply if
someone said to him that what he had seen earlier was empty illusion, but that
now he is rather closer to reality, and turned to things that are more real,
and sees more correctly? Don't you think he would be at a loss and would think
that the things he saw earlier were truer than the things he was now being shown?
—Much truer.
—And if he were forced to look at the light itself, wouldn't his eyes
hurt, and wouldn't he turn away and run back to the things he was able to see,
and think that they were really clearer than the things that he had been shown?
—Yes.
—And if someone dragged him by force up the rough steep path, and did
not let him go until he had been dragged out into the light of the sun,
wouldn't he be in pain and complain at being dragged like this, and when he got
to the light, with the sun filling his eyes, wouldn't he be unable to see a
single one of the things now said to be true?
—He would, at least at first.
—He would need practice, if he were going to see the things above. First
he would most easily see shadows, and then the images of men and other things
reflected in water, and then those things themselves; and the things in the
heavens and the heavens themselves he would see more easily at night, looking
at the light of the moon and the stars, than he could see the sun and its light
by day.
—Certainly.
—Finally he would be able to look at the sun itself, not reflected in
-water or in anything else, but as it is in itself and in its own place: to
look at it and see what kind of thing it is.
This image brings together two different ideas of what is wrong with the
empirical world and with the skills, such as rhetoric, that live off it and its
politics of illusion: that it is all empty appearance, and that nevertheless it
involves coercive forces (symbolized by the chains) from which people need to
be freed. The everyday world, with its sensations, desires, and inducements, is
at once flimsy and powerful. In this it resembles what later times would
understand as magic: the world that Prospero brings into being in The Tempest
is merely the baseless fabric of a vision, and yet he can claim graves at my
command
Have wak'd their sleepers, op'd, and let 'em forth
By my so potent Art.
It is just this profound ambivalence, about its power and its emptiness,
that inspires Plato's attack on painting, poetry, and the other arts, an attack
which is expressed at various points in the Republic but most concentratedly in Book X.
When the future Guardians go up from the cave into the open air, they
may eventually even be able to look directly at the sun. The sun, in Plato’s
story, stands for the Good, and the analogy is a complex one. As the sun makes
living things grow, so the existence of everything is explained by the Good; as
the sun enables everything to be seen, including itself, so the Good enables
everything, including itself, to be known. What this means is that explanation
and understanding must reveal why it is 'for the best' that things should be so
rather than otherwise. Plato's conception of 'the best' must be understood in a
very abstract way: he is concerned with such matters as the mathematical beauty
and simplicity of the ultimate relations between things, an interest which he seems
to have derived (together, probably, with his belief in immortality) from the
mystical and mathematical tradition of the Pythagoreans, which he encountered
on his visits to Greek communities in Italy, first in about 387 BC.
When Plato talks of things being “for the best”, we should not think of
him as like Dr Pangloss in
Voltaire’s Candide, who claims that this is the best
of all possible worlds and that if we knew enough we would see that everything,
however disastrous, is ultimately for the best in humanly recognizable terms
such as happiness and welfare. That outlook is a shallow version of
Christianity, a religion which is committed (at least after Augustine) to
believing that human history and everyday human experience do matter in the
ultimate scale of things. Plato, in the Republic and, notably, in the Phaedo (but by no means everywhere else), expresses
something different, the aspiration to be released and distanced from finite
human concerns altogether, and this is reflected in his conception of what is
'for the best'. Dr Pangloss and his metaphysically more distinguished model, Leibniz, are regarded as
optimists, but even in the Utopian Republic Plato is pessimistic about everyday
life, and although these Middle Period works frequently remind us of finite and
fleeting happiness, particularly through friendship, the ascent from the cave
into the sunlight signals a departure from human concerns altogether.
Plato offers us in the Republic another model of the relation between
everyday experience and the 'higher' reality. We are to imagine a line, divided
into two sections. The top part corresponds to knowledge, and also, therefore,
to those things that we can know; the lower part corresponds to belief, and to
those things about which we can have no better than belief. These two parts are
each divided again into two sub-sections. When we consider these sub-sections
the emphasis is not so much on different things about which we may have
knowledge or belief, but rather on more or less direct methods of acquiring
knowledge or belief. The lowest sub-section is said to relate to shadows and
reflections, while the sub-section above relates to ordinary,
three-dimensional, things. Plato can hardly think that there is a special state
of mind involved simply in looking at shadows and reflections. The point is
that relying on shadows and reflections is a poor or second-best way of
acquiring beliefs about ordinary solid objects. The sub-sections of the upper
part of the line make a similar point, one that is also expressed in the story
of the cave. There is a state of mind that is a poor or second-best way of
getting to know about unchanging reality. This, according to Plato, is the
state of mind of mathematicians in his time.
He saw two limitations to that mathematics. One was that although it
understood, of course, that its propositions were not literally true of any
physical diagram - no line is quite straight, no equalities are really equal,
no units are unequivocally units - nevertheless, it relied on diagrams.
Moreover, it relied on unproved assumptions or axioms, and Plato takes the
opportunity of describing the Guardians' education to sketch an ultimately
ambitious research programme, which will derive all
mathematical assumptions from some higher or more general truths, arriving
ultimately at an entirely rational and perspicuous structure which in some
sense depends on the self-explanatory starting point of the Good. It is made
quite clear that Socrates cannot explain what this will be like, not just because
his hearers will not understand it but because he does not understand it
himself. It involves an intellectual project and a vision that lay beyond the
historical Socrates, obviously enough, but also beyond Plato when he wrote the
Republic. In fact, it was a project that was never to be carried out on such a
grandiose scale.
The reality that corresponds to the highest section of the line consists
of Forms, objects which are - whatever else - eternal, immaterial, unchanging,
and the objects of rational, a priori, knowledge (which, in the Republic’s
scheme of things, is the only knowledge there is).
Commentators discuss 'the Theory of Forms', but there is really no such
thing (which is why there is no question to be answered of whether or when
Plato gave it up). It is more helpful to see Plato as having a general
conception of a Form, in the sense of some such abstract, intellectual, object;
having also a set of philosophical questions; and as continually asking how
such objects might contribute, in various ways, to answering those various
questions. The Republic represents the boldest version of the idea that one and
the same set of objects could answer all those questions. Plato did not cease
to think that there were abstract objects of rational understanding, existing
independently of the material world, but he came to see that one and the same
kind of object could not serve in all the roles demanded of it by the Republic.
Aristotle says that Socrates was interested in questions of definition,
but that Plato was the first to make Forms 'separate'. In this connection, a
Form can be understood as the quality or character in virtue of which many
particular things are of the same kind; and to say that it is 'separate' marks
the point that the quality would exist even if there were no particulars that
possessed it, as one might say that there would be a virtue of courage even if
there were no courageous people. (As we shall see, Plato also wants to say
that, for more than one reason, particulars cannot properly, perfectly, or
without qualification instantiate Forms.) This is the approach to Forms from
the theory of meaning; in the Republic Plato seems to give an entirely general
formulation of this idea when he says: “Shall we start the enquiry with our usual
procedure? We are in the habit, I take it, of positing a single idea or Form
for each case in which we give the same name to many things”.
Aristotle also says that Plato, “Having in his youth first become
familiar with Cratylus and the Heracleitean doctrines (that all sensible things are always in a state of flux and there is
no knowledge about them), these views he held even in later years”. In this
connection, Forms are, or are very closely associated with, the objects of
mathematical study. As the image of the divided line makes clear, geometers use
material, particular, diagrams, but they cannot be talking directly about those
diagrams, or what they say ('the line AB is equal to the line AC' and so on)
would be simply untrue. They must be talking about something else, triangles
formed of absolutely straight lines with no breadth. This is the approach from
the possibility of a priori knowledge. It is in this role that Forms can also
be naturally taken to be those objects of intellectual vision that the argument
of the Meno needed as the archetypal source of the
beliefs recovered in recollection.
The geometers’ triangles, unlike scrawled or carpentered triangles of
everyday life, are perfect. This is an idea that Plato applied to some other
kinds of objects as well: a Form was a paradigm. So when a craftsman makes an artefact, his aim is to approximate to the best that such a
thing could be, an ideal which, it may well be, neither he nor anyone else will
ever adequately express in a particular material form. So it is with a couch in
Book X of the Republic and a shuttle in the Cratylus.
The conceptions of a Form as a paradigm, and of a Form as a general quality or
characteristic, come together with special force when there is a quality that
we find in particular things, but which occurs in them in a way that is
imperfect in the strong sense that our experience of them carries with it an
aspiration, a yearning, for an ideal. The most powerful example of this, for
Plato, is beauty.
The geometers’ triangles, on the one hand, and qualities or
characteristics such as courage or dampness, on the other, are all uncreated
and unchanging. The world changes: damp things dry out, particular people
become courageous or cease to be so. But dampness and courage and such things
do not themselves change, except in the boring sense that beauty changes if at
one time it characterizes Alcibiades and at a later time it does not, and this
is not a change in it (any more than it is a change in Socrates that young Theaetetus, who is growing, is shorter than him one year
and taller the next year). So there is a fundamental contrast between Forms and
the world in which things change, our everyday world.
Sometimes, Plato invokes Forms to explain change. This is notably so in
the Phaedo, which uses conceptions that are hard to
fit together with the discussions, particularly in the Republic, which
emphasize the metaphysical distance between Forms and particulars. It treats
Forms as though parts of them could be transitory ingredients or occupants of
material things (as we speak of the dampness in the wall). It is relevant that
this discussion has a very special aim, to support a curious proof of the
immortality of the soul (which Plato nowhere else uses or relies on). This
proof requires the indestructible Form, life, in the sense of “aliveness”, to
join with a particular, Socrates, in such a way that there will be an item, “Socrates’
aliveness”, which is as indestructible as the Form but as individual as
Socrates. This is Socrates' soul; indeed, it is Socrates himself, when he is
freed of the irrelevance of his body.
When Plato says that, in contrast to the Forms, particulars in the
material world are 'changing', he means more than that they are changing in
time. He also means that when we say that a material thing is round or red, for
instance, what we say is only relatively or qualifiedly true: it is round or
red from one point of view but not another, to one observer rather than
another, by comparison with one thing and not another. So what we say about
material things is only relatively or qualifiedly true. Indeed, if our
statements mean what they seem to say, for instance that this surface is red
without qualification, then they are not true at all - not really true. Only
what we say about Forms can be absolutely or unqualifiedly true.
This gives a broader sense in which things in the material world are
imperfect compared with Forms. Only in some cases, such as beauty, does the
imperfection of particular things evoke the pathos of incompleteness, of
regret, indeed (given Plato’s idea of recollection) of nostalgia. But in the
sense that nothing is unqualifiedly or absolutely what we say it is, but is so
only for a time, to an observer, or from a point of view - in that sense,
everything in the material world is imperfect. In the Republic this contrast is
expressed in the strongest terms, which we have already encountered in the
image of the line. Only what is in the world of Forms 'really is'; the world of
everyday perception is 'between being and not being', and is mere appearance or
like a dream; only 'being' can be the object of knowledge, while the world of
'becoming' is the object of mere belief or conjecture.
There has been much discussion of what exactly Plato meant by these
formulations. We should certainly try to make the best sense we can of them,
but we should not expect an overall interpretation that is fully intelligible
in our terms. To do so is to ignore a vital point, that, however exactly his
thought developed, he himself certainly came to think that the Republic's
formulations would not do. There are many ways in which the later dialogues
acknowledge this. Most generally, Plato came to recognize the tensions that the
various approaches to the Forms, taken together, must create. The approach from
the theory of meaning implies, unless it is restricted, that there should be a
Form for every general term we can use, but other approaches imply that Forms,
being perfect, have something particularly grand and beautiful about them. So
are there Forms for general terms which stand for low and unlovely things, such
as mud and hair? Again, some approaches imply that a Form itself has the
quality it imparts.
The Form of beauty is itself beautiful, paradigmatically so; the Phaedo’s theory
of explanation seems to imply that the dampness in an object is indeed damp.
The theory of meaning approach, on the other hand, and perhaps others, imply
that this had better not be so, or we may be confronted with a regress: shall
we need another Form to explain how the first Form has the properties that it
has? All these are among the questions that are put to the embarrassed Socrates
in the first part of the Parmenides.
In the Sophist, Plato explores
with very great care the complex relations between five particularly abstract
concepts, which he calls “the greatest kinds” rather than Forms - being,
sameness, difference, motion and rest -and reaches subtle conclusions about the
ways in which they apply to each other and to themselves. In the course of
this, he distinguishes various ways in which a thing “is” something or other, and
invents powerful instruments for solving the logical and semantic problems that
underlie some of the central formulations of the Republic. He also recognizes
there, gravely dissociating himself from the admired Parmenides, that there
cannot be two worlds of appearance and reality. If something appears to be so,
then it really does so appear: appearance must itself be part of reality. This
conclusion in itself represents a direct repudiation of the detailed
metaphysics of the Republic.
The Theaetetus,
which offers a most powerful and subtle discussion of knowledge, develops a
theory of sense perception which at least refines the Republic’s view out of
all recognition, and on one reading, is opposed to it. In the same dialogue,
and in the Sophist, Plato advances in discussion of false belief, and of being
and not being, to a point at which it is clear that many things said in the
Republic need revision. Moreover, he goes back in the Theaetetus to the point
acknowledged in the Meno,
that it must be possible for one person merely to believe what another person
knows. The ideas of knowledge and belief that are articulated in the Republic
and expressed in the images of the line and the cave are controlled by
consideration of subject matter, of what might be or become a body of
systematic a priori knowledge. The Republic is not interested, for example, in
the state of mind of someone who makes a mathematical mistake (it cannot be
belief, because he is thinking about the eternal, and it cannot be knowledge, because
he is wrong.)
This would not matter if Plato were concerned only with the nature of
the sciences, but, as he recognizes, we must be able to talk about knowledge
and belief as states of individual people. The ascent from the cave must be a
story of personal enlightenment, if the Republic is to fulfill its promise of
helping us to understand how to live, and this needs a psychology of belief
which can bridge the metaphysical gulf between the eternal and the changing.
Plato’s Philosophy And The Denial Of Life
The sharp oppositions of the Republic between eternal reality and the
illusions of the changing material world not only left deep problems of
philosophical theory; they defeated Plato's ethical purposes. The problem of
how justice is to be preserved in the world was solved by the return of the
Guardians to rule, unwillingly, in the cave. There is a question, touched on in
the Republic, of why they should do this. Certainly, Plato thinks that it is
better that the just and wise should rule unwillingly, rather than that those
who actually want power should have it. But that must mean, better for the
world, and Plato must acknowledge the reality of the material world to this
extent, that Socrates' fate and other injustices, and the horrors described in
the degeneration of the city, are real evils, which are better prevented.
Although the just city (and only the just city) suits the Guardians' nature,
even there the activity of philosophy is more satisfying than ruling. Returning
to the cave is good for them only because it is a good thing to do.
But why is it a good thing to do, and why is it better “for the world”
that it should be ruled justly? The returning Guardians cannot abolish the cave
and its apparatus, as Parsifal with the sign of the cross destroys Klingsor’s magic garden. Do they release its prisoners?
(Here again we meet the ambivalence between power and mere illusion.) Most of
the prisoners could not be released, for the ascent to the light is reserved
for those special people in whom reason is strong and who are capable of
becoming Guardians themselves. But those who are not like this will at least be
saved from exploitation, and they can be helped by the laws and institutions of
the city not to become unjust exploiters themselves, making others and
themselves miserable. So it does matter, a great deal, what happens in this
world, and the sense, which it is easy to get from the Republic, that in being
required to rule, the Guardians are displaced or sentenced to it, like
intellectual imperialists in a dark place, cannot really be adequate to Plato's
conception of them and of society's need for justice.
The same tensions surface, differently, in the Gorgias. There, Socrates asserts
the paradoxes that it is better to have injustice done to one than to do
injustice, and that the good man 'cannot be harmed', because the only thing
that really matters to him is his virtue and that is inviolate against the
assaults of the world. This outlook (which was to be developed by some
philosophers in later antiquity into an extreme asceticism) leaves an
impossible gap between the motivations that it offers for an ethical life, and
what one is supposed to do if one leads it. The motivations to justice are said
to lie in the care of the soul, and, along with that, in the belief that what
happens to one’s body or one’s possessions does not really matter; but, if we
have that belief, why do we suppose, as justice requires us to suppose, that it
matters whether other people's bodies and possessions are assaulted or
appropriated?
In the Phaedo,
Plato seems to present in the strongest terms the idea that the good person is
better off outside the world. We are told that Socrates’ very last words, as
the hemlock took its effect, were, “Crito, we owe a
cockerel to Asclepius”, and since Asclepius was a god of healing, this has been
taken to mean that life is a disease, a “terrible and ridiculous last word”, as
Nietzsche put it, a “veiled, gruesome, pious and blasphemous saying”. Spinoza,
equally, rejected the Phaedo’s suggestion that philosophy
should be a “meditation” or preparation of death, urging that it should be a “meditation
of life”. It might be said that the dialogue’s disparagement of this life as
opposed to the metaphysical beyond is forgivable granted the occasion. Yet that
is not right either, since the end of the Phaedo is,
hardly surprisingly, run through with a deep sorrow, and we are not supposed to
think that Socrates’ friends are grieving simply because they have not been
convinced by the arguments for immortality. It registers, rather, that, even
given immortality and the world of Forms, this world and its friendships are of
real value, and that its losses are at some level as bad as they seem.
Plato’s will to transcend mortal life, to reach for the “higher”, is
part of the traditional image of his philosophy, and is one element in the
equally traditional contrast between him and the more empirically rooted
Aristotle, a contrast expressed most famously, perhaps, in Raphael’s fresco in
the Vatican, The School of Athens, which displays at its center the figures of
Plato and Aristotle, the one turning his hand towards heaven, the other
downwards towards earth. In our own century, Yeats wrote:
Plato thought nature but a spume that plays
Upon a ghostly paradigm of things;
Solider Aristotle played the taws
Upon the bottom of a king of kings ...
But Plato is not always drawing us beyond the concerns of this world.
Even those works in which 'the higher' is celebrated do not always take the
tone of the Phaedo’s official message, or of the
Republic. In the case of the Republic, we spoke first in terms of ascent, the
journey out of the cave, but in fact it is the Guardians' return that lends its
color to the work as a whole, an impression strengthened as it goes on by the long
story of social and personal decline. The world of desire, politics, and
material bodies is essentially seen from above, from outside the cave, and we
are left with a sense of it as denatured and unreal or as powerfully
corrupting. But elsewhere, and above all in the Symposium, the picture really
is of ascent, and the material world is seen with the light behind it, as it
were, giving an image not of failure and dereliction but of promise. The
participants in the dinner party which the Symposium describes, talk about what eros is, what it is to be a lover. The lover and his
desires have some relation to beauty, or beautiful things; in particular,
beautiful young men. We learn more precisely what these desires are. His desire
is not a desire for the beautiful, at least in an obvious sense:
—Love is not love of the beautiful, as you think.
—What is it, then?
—Of reproduction and birth in the beautiful.
This desire itself turns out to be an expression, or form, of a desire
to be immortal.
Now this provides a schema, to put it in rather formal terms, which can
be filled out differently for different types of love. A man’s love for a woman
defines “birth” literally; “in”, “in association with”, is sexual; and the
immortality in question is genetic. A man may bring forth or generate not
babies but ideas or poems, and live for ever (or at
least for longer) through those. The beauty in question may now be that of a
particular youth, or something more general - as we might say, youthful beauty;
again, it may be beauty of soul rather than of body. There is nothing to imply
that the various abstractions, as we might call them, necessarily keep step
with one another. Socrates has been disposed to generate ideas and good
thoughts but in association with youths who had beautiful bodies. Conversely,
Alcibiades, we learn later, is drawn to Socrates' beautiful soul, but he has
little idea of what an appropriate birth would be.
Then Diotima gives her account of the end of
the progress, to the “final and highest mysteries of love”, which she doubts
that Socrates can achieve. Here, in a famous passage, the lover is said to turn
to the great sea of beauty, and will come to see something 'wonderfully
beautiful in its nature', which always is and neither comes to be nor passes
away, neither waxes nor wanes; it is not beautiful in one way and ugly in
another, nor beautiful at one time and not at another, nor beautiful in
relation to one thing and ugly in relation to another, nor beautiful in one
place and ugly in another, as it would be if it were beautiful to some people
and ugly to others ... and it is not embodied in any face or body, or idea, or
knowledge, or, indeed, in anything at all. This culminating, ultimately
fulfilling, encounter still fits the original schema. This would indeed be a
worthwhile life for a man; he would bring forth, not images of virtue, but true
virtue, and his relation to the Form of beauty, which is what has just been
described, would be that of seeing it and being with it, words reminiscent of
the language originally applied to sexual relations with a beautiful person. Diotima’s account of this progress or ascent does not
imply, as some have thought, that no one ever really loves a particular person,
but only the beauty in that person, or beauty itself. On the contrary, one can
love a particular person in any of the various ways that count as bringing
something to birth in the presence of that person's beauty. The account
directly denies, in fact, that all love is love of beauty. Moreover, it does
not suggest that the particulars, sights and sounds and bodies, were only
seemingly or illusorily beautiful. They are not unconditionally, or
unqualifiedly, or absolutely, beautiful, which is what the item of the final
vision is. Indeed, Diotima can say that from the
vantage point of the vision, colors and human bodies and other such things are
merely 'mortal nonsense', but that is only by comparison with the vision, and
it does not imply that the mortals who thought that those things were beautiful
were simply mistaken, or that they were mistaken to have pursued them. The
undertaking she teaches is something like a growth in aesthetic taste, from
kitschy music, say, to more interesting music. It does not deny the point or
the object of the earlier taste, and indeed the earlier taste is a condition of
the process, which is a progress rather than the mere detection of error or the
elimination of a misunderstanding.
Diotima says that the earlier pursuits were for the sake of' the final secrets. This does
not mean that unless the ultimate state is reached the earlier states are
pointless. It means that from the latter perspective we can see a point to them
which they do not reveal at all to some people, and reveal only imperfectly
even to those who are going about them in the right way. For those who do go
about them in the right way, that imperfection is expressed in an obscure unsatisfactoriness or incompleteness in those earlier
relationships, which can be traced to their failure to express adequately the
desire to be immortal, to have the Good for ever. How
far such a feeling may come even to those who are not going about the erotic in
the right way and could never reach the vision, is something about which the
earlier speeches have things to say.
All of this, certainly, expresses a discontent with the finite, and a
sense of a greater splendor that lies beyond our ordinary passions, but it does
so in way that, far more than the Republic or the rather dismal Phaedo, allows those passions to have their own life and to
promise more. This effect is achieved in the dialogue by the later intervention
of Alcibiades, and by the earlier speeches, which are variously funny and
idiosyncratic and one of which, that of Aristophanes, tells a suitably absurd
and touching story about the origins of sexual attraction. The sense that the
Symposium knows what it is talking about in its dealings with desire - in this
respect it is like some other less sunny dialogues - lends colour to another comment of Nietzsche’s: “All philosophical idealism to date was
something like a disease, unless it was, as in Plato’s case, the caution of an
over-rich and dangerous health, the fear of over-powerful senses ...”
Plato set higher than almost any other thinker the aspirations of philosophy,
and, as we have seen, its hopes to change one's life through theory. Granted
the distrust and even the rejection of the empirical world which do play a
significant role in his outlook; granted, too, the fact that his politics are
far removed from any that could serve us now, not only in time but by an
unashamedly aristocratic temperament; we may ask how his dialogues can remain
so vividly alive. They are, indeed, sometimes sententious, and Socrates
speaking on behalf of virtue can be tiring and high-minded, just as his
affectation of ignorance and simplicity, the famous “irony”, can be
irritatingly coy. But their faults are almost always those of a real person.
They speak with a recognizable human voice, or more than one, and they do not
fall into the stilted, remote complacency or quaint formalism to which moral
philosophy is so liable. In part this is because of the dialogue form. In part,
it is because (as Nietzsche’s remark implies) Plato is constantly aware of the
forces - of desire, of aesthetic seduction, of political exploitation - against
which his ideals are a reaction. The dialogues preserve a sense of urgency and
of the social and psychological insecurity of the ethical. Plato never forgets
that the human mind is a very hostile environment for goodness, and he takes it
for granted that some new device, some idea or imaginative stroke, may be
needed to keep it alive there and to give it a hold on us. A treatise which
supposedly offered in reader-friendly form the truth about goodness could not
do anything that really needed doing.
The dialogues are never closed or final. They do not offer the ultimate
results of Plato’s great enquiry. They contain stories, descriptions, jokes,
arguments, harangues, streams of free intellectual invention, powerful and
sometimes violent rhetoric, and much else. Nothing in them straightforwardly
reports those theoretical findings on which everything was supposed to turn,
and they never take the tone that now you have mastered this, your life will be
changed. There are theoretical discussions, often very complex, subtle, and
original. There are many statements of how our lives need to be changed and of
how philosophy may help to change them. But the action is always somewhere
else, in a place where we, and typically Socrates himself, have not been. The
results are never in the text before us. They could not be. The passage from
the Phaedrus from which we started was true to Plato’s outlook, as it seems to
me, in claiming that what most importantly might come from philosophy cannot be
written down.
This does not mean that it could be written down, but somewhere else.
Nor does it mean, I think, that it could not be written down but could be
spoken as a secret lore among initiates. The Pythagoreans in Italy from whom
Plato may have got some initial inspiration seem to have had esoteric
doctrines, and some scholars have thought that the same was true of Plato's
Academy, but there is not much reason to believe it. The limitations of writing
do not apply only to writing. Rather, Plato seems to have thought that the
final significance of philosophy for one's life does not lie in anything that
could be embodied in its findings, but emerges, rather, from its activities.
One will find one’s life changed through doing something other than researching
the changes that one's life needs -through mathematics, Plato thought, or
through dialectical discussion of such things as the metaphysical problems of
not being, conducted not with the aim of reaching edifying moral conclusions, but
the aim of getting it right (particularly if one has got it wrong before, and
intellectual honesty, or - come to that - a most powerful curiosity, demand
that one try again).
Plato did think that if you devoted yourself to theory, this could change
your life. He did think, at least at one period, that pure studies might lead
one to a transforming vision. But he never thought that the materials or
conditions of such a transformation could be set down in a theory, or that a
theory would, at some suitably advanced level, explain the vital thing you
needed to know. So the dialogues do not present us with a statement of what
might be most significantly drawn from philosophy, but that is not a
peculiarity of them or of us; nothing could present us with that, because it
cannot be stated anywhere, but can only, with luck and in favorable
surroundings, emerge. Plato probably did think himself that the most favorable
surroundings would be a group of people entirely dedicated to philosophy, but
clearly he supposed that reading the dialogues, thinking about them, entering
into them, were activities that could offer something to people outside such a
group. He acknowledged, as Socrates makes clear in the Phaedrus, that they
could not be the vehicles of one determinate message, and it is just because
they are not intended to control the minds of his readers, but to open them,
that they go on having so much to offer.
It is pointless to ask who is the world's greatest philosopher: for one
thing, there are many different ways of doing philosophy. But we can say what
the various qualities of great philosophers are: intellectual power and depth;
a grasp of the sciences; a sense of the political, and of human destructiveness
as well as creativity; a broad range and a fertile imagination; an
unwillingness to settle for the superficially reassuring; and, in an unusually
lucky case, the gifts of a great writer. If we ask which philosopher has, more
than any other, combined all these qualities — to that question there is certainly
an answer, Plato.
|