UNIVERSAL BIOGRAPHICAL LIBRARY
|
ARISTARCHUS OF SAMOSTHE COPERNICUS OF ANTIQUITYBYTHOMAS HEATH
The title-page of this book necessarily bears the name
of one man; but the reader will find in its pages the story, or part of the
story, of many other Pioneers of Progress. The crowning achievement of
anticipating the hypothesis of Copernicus belongs to Aristarchus of Samos
alone; but to see it in its proper setting it is necessary to have followed in
the footsteps of the earlier pioneers who, by one bold speculation after
another, brought the solution of the problem nearer, though no one before
Aristarchus actually hit upon the truth. This is why the writer has thought it
useful to prefix to his account of Aristarchus a short sketch of the history of
the development of astronomy in Greece down to Aristarchus’s time, which s indeed the most fascinating portion of the story of Greek
astronomy.
The history of Greek astronomy in its beginnings is
part of the history of Greek philosophy, for it was the first philosophers,
Ionian, Eleatic, Pythagorean, who were the first astronomers. Now only very few
of the works of the great original thinkers of Greece have survived. We possess
the whole of Plato and, say, half of Aristotle, namely, those of his writings
which were intended for the use of his school, but not those which, mainly
composed in the form of dialogues, were in a more popular style. But the whole
of the pre-Socratic philosophy is one single expanse of ruins; so is the
Socratic philosophy itself, except for what we can learn of it from Plato and
Xenophon.
But accounts of the life and doctrine of philosophers
begin to appear quite early in ancient Greek literature (cf. Xenophon, who was
born between 430 and 425 B. c.); and very valuable are the allusions in Plato
and Aristotle to the doctrines of earlier philosophers; those in Plato are not
very numerous, but he had the power of entering into the thoughts of other men
and, in stating the views of early philosophers, he does not, as a rule, read
into their words meanings which they do not convey. Aristotle, on the other
hand, while making historical surveys of the doctrines of his predecessors a
regular preliminary to the statement of his own, discusses them too much from
the point of view of his own system; often even misrepresenting them for the
purpose of making a controversial point or finding support for some particular
thesis.
From Aristotle's time a whole literature on the
subject of the older philosophy sprang up, partly critical, partly historical.
This again has perished except for a large number of fragments. Most important
for our purpose are the notices in the Doxographi Graeci, collected and edited by Diels. The main
source from which these retailers of the opinions of philosophers drew,
directly or indirectly, was the great work of Theophrastus, the successor of
Aristotle, entitled Physical Opinions. It would appear that it was Theophrastus's
plan to trace the progress of physics from Thales to Plato in separate chapters
dealing severally with the leading topics. First the leading views were set
forth on broad lines, in groups, according to the affinity of the doctrine,
after which the differences between individual philosophers within the same
group were carefully noted. In the First Book, however, dealing with the
Principles, Theophrastus adopted the order of the various schools, Ionians,
Eleatics, Atomists, &c, down to Plato, although he did not hesitate to
connect Diogenes of Apollonia and Archelaus with the earlier physicists, out of
their chronological order; chronological order was indeed, throughout, less
regarded than the connexion and due arrangement of
subjects. This work of Theophrastus was naturally the chief hunting-ground for
those who collected the 'opinions' of philosophers. There was, however, another
main stream of tradition besides the doxographic ; this was in the different
form of biographies of the philosophers. The first to write a book of
'successions' of the philosophers was Sotion (towards
the end of the third century B. C.); others who wrote 'successions' were a
certain Antisthenes (probably Antisthenes of Rhodes, second century B.C.), Sosicrates, and Alexander Polyhistor.
These works gave little in the way ot doxography, but
were made readable by the incorporation of anecdotes and apophthegms,
mostly unauthentic. The work of Sotion and the Lives
of Famous Men by Satyrus (about 160 B.C.) were
epitomized by Heraclides Lembus.
Another writer of biographies was the Peripatetic Hermippus of Smyrna, known as the Callimachean, who wrote about
Pythagoras in at least two Books, and is quoted by Josephus as a careful
student of all history. Our chief storehouse of biographical details derived
from these and all other available sources is the great compilation which goes
by the name of Diogenes Laertius (more properly Laertius Diogenes). It is a
compilation made in the most haphazard way, without the exercise of any historical
sense or critical faculty. But its value for us is enormous because the
compiler had access to the whole collection of biographies which accumulated
from Sotion's time to the first third of the third
century A. D. (when Diogenes wrote), and consequently we have in him the whole
residuum of this literature which reached such dimensions in the period.
The extraordinary advance in astronomy made by the
Greeks in a period of little more than three centuries is a worthy parallel to
the rapid development, in their hands, of pure geometry, which, created by them
as a theoretical science about the same time, had by the time of Aristarchus
covered the ground of the Elements (including solid geometry and the geometry
of the sphere), had established the main properties of the three conic
sections, had solved problems which were beyond the geometry of the straight
line and circle, and finally, before the end of the third century BC, had been
carried to its highest perfection by the genius of Archimedes, who measured the
areas of curves and the surfaces and volumes of curved surfaces by geometrical
methods practically anticipating the integral calculus.
To understand how all this was possible we have to
remember that the Greeks, preeminently among all the nations of the world,
possessed just those gifts which are essential to the initiation and
development of philosophy and science. They had in the first place a remarkable
power of accurate observation; and to this were added clearness of intellect to
see things as they are, a passionate love of knowledge for its own sake, and a
genius for speculation which stands unrivalled to this day. Nothing that is
perceptible to the senses seems to have escaped them; and when the apparent
facts had been accurately ascertained, they wanted to know the why and the
wherefore, never resting satisfied until they had given a rational explanation,
or what seemed to them to be such, of the phenomena observed. Observation or
experiment and theory went hand in hand. So it was that they developed such
subjects as medicine and astronomy. In astronomy their guiding principle was,
in their own expressive words, to “save the phenomena”. This meant that, as
more and more facts became known, their theories were continually revised to
fit them.
It would be easy to multiply instances; it must
suffice in this place to mention one, which illustrates not only the certainty
with which the Greeks detected the occurrence of even the rarest phenomena, but
also the persistence with which they sought for the true explanation.
Cleomedes (second century A.D.) mentions that there were
stories of extraordinary eclipses which “the more ancient of the
mathematicians” had vainly tried to explain; the supposed “paradoxical” case
was that in which, while the sun seems to be still above the western horizon,
the eclipsed moon is seen to rise in the east. The phenomenon appeared to be
inconsistent with the explanation of lunar eclipses by the entry of the moon
into the earth’s shadow; how could this be if both bodies were above the
horizon at the same time? The “more ancient” mathematicians essayed a
geometrical explanation; they tried to argue that it was possible that a
spectator standing on an eminence of the spherical earth might see along the
generators of a cone, i.e. a little downwards on all sides instead of merely in
the plane of the horizon, and so might see both the sun and the moon even when
the latter was in the earth’s shadow. Cleomedes denies this and prefers to regard the whole story of such cases as a fiction
designed merely for the purpose of plaguing astronomers and philosophers; no
Chaldean, he says, no Egyptian, and no mathematician or philosopher has
recorded such a case. But the phenomenon is possible, and it is certain that it
had been observed in Greece and that the Greek astronomers did not rest until
they had found out the solution of the puzzle; fur Cleomedes himself gives the explanation, namely that the phenomenon is due to atmospheric
refraction. Observing that such cases of atmospheric refraction were especially
noticeable in the neighbourhood of the Black Sea, Cleomedes goes on to say that it is possible that the
visual rays going out from our eyes are refracted through falling on wet and
damp air, and so reach the sun although it is already below the horizon; and he
compares the well-known experiment of the ring at the bottom of a jug, where
the ring, just out of sight when the jug’s empty, is brought into view when
water is poured in.
The genius of the race being what it was, the Greeks
must from the earliest times have been in the habit of scanning the heavens,
and, as might be expected, we find the beginnings of astronomical knowledge in
the earliest Greek literature.
In the Homeric poems and in Hesiod the earth is a flat
circular disc; round this disc runs the river Oceanus, encircling the earth and
flowing back into itself. The flat earth has above it the vault of heaven, like
a sort of hemispherical dome exactly covering it; this vault remains forever in
one position; the sun, moon and stars move round under it, rising from Oceanus
in the east and plunging into it again in the west.
Homer mentions, in addition to the sun and moon, the
Morning Star, the Evening Star, the Pleiades, the Hyades, Orion, the Great Bear
(“which is also called by the name of the Wain”), Sirius, the late-setting Bootes (the ploughman driving the Wain), i.e. Arcturus, as
it was first called by Hesiod. Of the Great Bear Homer says that it turns round
on the same spot and watches Orion: it alone is without lot in Oceanus’s bath
(i.e. it never sets). With regard to the last statement it is to be noted that
some of the principal stars of the Great Bear do now set in the Mediterranean,
e.g. i places further south than Rhodes (lat.
36º), γ, the
hind foot, and η, the
tip of the tail, and at Alexandria all the seven stars except a, the head. It
might be supposed that here was a case of Homer “nodding”. But no; the old poet
was perfectly right; the difference between the facts as observed by him and as
seen by us respectively is due to the Precession of the Equinoxes, the gradual
movement of the fixed stars themselves about the pole of the ecliptic, which
was discovered by Hipparchus (second century B.C.). We know from the original
writings of the Greek astronomers that in Eudoxus’s time (say 380 B.C.) the whole of the Great Bear remained always well above the
horizon, while in the time of Proclus (say A.D. 460) the Great Bear “grazed”
the horizon.
In Homer astronomical phenomena are only vaguely used
for such purposes as fixing localities or marking times of day or night.
Sometimes constellations are used in giving sailing directions, as when Calypso
directs Odysseus to sail in such a way as always to keep the Great Bear on his
left.
Hesiod mentions practically the same stars as Homer,
but makes more use of celestial phenomena for determining times and seasons.
For example, he marked the time for sowing at the beginning of winter by the
setting of the Pleiades in the early twilight, or again by the early setting of
the Hyades or Orion, which means the 3rd, 7th. or 15th November in the Julian
calendar according to the particular stars taken; the time for harvest he fixed
by the early rising of the Pleiades (19th May), threshing time by the early
rising of Orion (9th July), vintage time by the early rising of Arcturus (18th
September), and so on. Hesiod makes spring begin sixty days after the winter
solstice, and the early summer fifty days after the summer solstice. Thus he
knew about the solstices, though he says nothing of the equinoxes. He had an
approximate notion of the moon’s period, which he put at thirty days.
But this use of astronomical facts for the purpose of
determining, times and seasons or deducing weather indications is a very
different thing from the science of astronomy, which seeks to explain the
heavenly phenomena and their causes. The history of this science, as of Greek
philosophy in general, begins with Thales.
The Ionian Greeks were in the most favorable position
for initiating philosophy. Foremost among the Greeks in the love of adventure
and the instinct of new discovery (as is shown by their leaving their homes to
found settlements in distant lands), and fired, like all Greeks, with a passion
for knowledge, they needed little impulse to set them on the road of
independent thought and speculation. This impulse was furnished by their
contact with two ancient civilizations, the Egyptian and the Babylonian. Acquiring
from them certain elementary facts and rules in mathematics and astronomy which
had been handed down through the priesthood from remote antiquity, they built
upon them the foundation, of the science, as distinct from the mere routine, of
the subjects in question.
THALES.
Thales of Miletus (about 624-547 B.C.) was a man of
extraordinary versatility; philosopher, mathematician, astronomer, statesman,
engineer, and man of business, he was declared one of the Seven Wise Men in
582581 B.C. His propensity to star-gazing is attested by the story of his
having fallen into a well while watching the stars, insomuch that (as Plato has
it) he was rallied by a clever and pretty maidservant from Thrace for being so
“eager to know what goes on in the heavens when he could not see what was in
front of him, nay at his very feet”.
Thales’s claim to a place in the history of scientific
astronomy rests on one achievement attributed to him, that of predicting an
eclipse of the sun. The evidence for this is fairly conclusive, though the
accounts of it differ slightly. Endemus, the pupil of
Aristotle, who wrote histories of Greek geometry and astronomy, is quoted by
three different Greek writers as the authority for the story. But there is
testimony much earlier than this. Herodotus, speaking of a war between the
Lydians and the Medes, says that, “when in the sixth year they encountered one
another, it fell out that, after they had joined battle, the day suddenly
turned into night. Now that this change of day into night would occur was
foretold to the Ionians by Thales of Miletus, who fixed as the limit of time
this very year in which the change took place”. Moreover Xenophanes, who was
born some twenty-three years before Thales’s death, is said to have lauded
Thales’s achievement; this would amount to almost contemporary evidence.
Could Thales have known the cause of solar eclipses?
Aetius (a.d. 100), the author of an epitome of an
older collection of the opinions of philosophers, says that Thales was the
first to declare that the sun is eclipsed when the moon comes in a direct line
below it, the image of the moon then appearing on the sun’s disc as on a
mirror; he also associates Thales with Anaxagoras, Plato, Aristotle, and the
Stoics as holding that the moon is eclipsed by reason of its falling into the
shadow made by the earth when the earth is between the sun and the moon. But,
as regards the eclipse of the moon, Thales could not have given this
explanation, because he held that the earth (which he presumably regarded as a
fiat disc) floated on the water like a log. And if he had given the true
explanation of a solar eclipse, it is impossible that all the succeeding Ionian
philosophers should have exhausted their imaginations in other fanciful
explanations such as we find recorded.
The key to the puzzle may be afforded by the passage
of Herodotus according to which the prediction was a rough one, only specifying
that the eclipse would occur within a certain year. The prediction was probably
one of the same kind as had long been made by the Chaldeans. The Chaldeans, no
doubt as the result of observations continued through many centuries, had
discovered the period of 223 lunations after which lunar eclipses recur. (This
method would very often fail for solar eclipses because no account was taken of
parallax; and Assyrian cuneiform inscriptions record failures as well as
successful predictions). Thales, then, probably learnt about the period of 223
lunations either in Egypt or more directly through Lydia, which was an outpost
of Assyrio-Babylonian culture. If there happened to
be a number of possible solar eclipses in the year which (according to
Herodotus) Thales fixed for the eclipse, he was, in using the Chaldean rule,
not taking an undue risk; but it was great luck that the eclipse should have
been total. It seems practically certain that the eclipse in question was that
of the (Julian) 28th May, 585.
Thales, as we have seen, made the earth a circular or
cylindrical disc floating on the water like a log or a cork and, so far as we
can judge of his general conception of the universe, he would appear to have
regarded it as a mass of water (that on which the earth floats) with the
heavens encircling it in the form of a hemisphere and also bounded by the
primeval water. This view of the world has been compared with that found in
ancient Egyptian papyri. In the beginning existed the Nu, a primordial liquid
mass in the limitless depths of which floated the germs of things. When the sun
began to shine, the earth was flattened out and the water separated into two
masses. The one gave rise to the rivers and the ocean, the other, suspended
above, formed the vault of heaven, the waters above, on which the stars and the
gods, borne by an eternal current, began to float. The sun, standing upright in
his sacred barque which had endured for millions of
years, glides slowly, conducted by an army of secondary gods, the planets and
the fixed stars. The assumption of an upper and lower ocean is also old
Babylonian (cf. the division in Genesis 1.7 of the waters which were under the
firmament from the waters which were above the firmament).
It would follow from Thales’s general view of the
universe that the sun, moon and stars did not, between their setting and rising
again, continue their circular path below the earth but (as with Anaximenes
later) moved laterally round the earth.
Thales’s further contributions to observational
astronomy may be shortly stated. He wrote two works On the solstice and On the
equinox, and he is said by Eudemus to have discovered
that “the period of the sun with respect to the solstices is not always the
same”, which probably means that he discovered the inequality of the four
astronomical seasons. His division of the year into 365 days he probably learnt
from the Egyptians. He said of the Hyades that there are two, one north and the
other south. He observed the Little Bear and used it as a means of finding the
pole; he advised the Greeks to follow the Phoenician plan of sailing by the
Little Bear in preference to their own habit of steering by the Great Bear.
Limited as the certain contributions of Thales to
astronomy are, it became the habit of the Greek Doxographi,
or retailers of the opinions of philosophers, to attribute to Thales, in common
with other astronomers in each case, a number of discoveries which were not
made till later. The following is a list, with (in brackets) the names of the
astronomers to whom the respective discoveries may with most certainty be
assigned: (1) the fact that the moon takes its light from the sun (Anaxagoras),
(2) the sphericity of the earth (Pythagoras), (3) the division of the heavenly
sphere into five zones (Pythagoras and Parmenides), (4) the obliquity of the
ecliptic (Oenopides of Chios), and (5) the estimate
of the sun’s apparent diameter as 1/720th of the sun’s circle (Aristarchus of
Samos).
ANAXIMANDER.
Anaximander (about 611-547 B.C.), a contemporary and
fellow-citizen of Thales was a remarkably original thinker. He was the first
Greek philosopher who ventured to put forward his views in a formal written
treatise. This was a work About Nature and was not given to the world till he
was about sixty-four years old. His originality is illustrated by his theory of
evolution. According to him animals first arose from slime evaporated by the
sun; they lived in the sea and had prickly coverings; men at first resembled
fishes.
But his astronomical views were not less remarkable.
Anaximander boldly maintained that the earth is in the centre of the universe, suspended freely and without support, whereas Thales regarded
it as resting on the water and Anaximenes as supported by the air. It remains
in its position, said Anaximander, because it is at an equal distance from all
the rest of the heavenly bodies. The earth was, according to him,
cylinder-shaped, round “like a stone pillar”; one of its two plane faces is
that on which we stand; its depth is one-third of its breadth.
Anaximander postulated as his first principle, not
water (like Thales) or any of the elements, but the Infinite; this was a
substance, not further defined, from which all the heavens and the worlds in
them were produced; according to him the worlds themselves were infinite in
number, and there were always some worlds coming into being and others passing
away ad infinitum. The origin of the stars, and their nature, he explained as
follows. “That which is capable of begetting the hut and the cold out of the eternal
was separated off during the coming into being of our world, and from the flame
thus produced a sort of sphere was made which grew round the air about the
earth as the bark round the tree; then this sphere was torn off and became
enclosed in certain circles or rings, and thus were formed the sun, the moon
and the stars”. “The stars are produced as a circle of tire, separated off from
the fire in the universe and enclosed by air. They have as vents certain
pipe-shaped passages at which the stars are seen”. “The stars are compressed
portions of air, in the shape of wheels filled with fire, and they emit flames
at some point from small openings”. “The stars are borne round by the circles
in which they are enclosed”. “The sun is a circle twenty-eight times (v. l. 27
times) the size of the earth; it is like a wheel of a chariot the rim of which
is hollow and full of fire and lets the fire shine out at a certain point in it
through an opening like the tube of a blow-pipe; such is the sun”. “The sun is
equal to the earth”. “The eclipses of the sun occur through the opening by
which the fire finds vent being shut up”. “The moon is a circle nineteen times
the size of the earth; it is similar to a chariot-wheel the rim of which is
hollow and full of fire like the circle of the sun, and it is placed obliquely
like the other; it has one vent like the tube of a blow-pipe; the eclipses of
the moon depend on the turnings of the wheel”. “The moon is eclipsed when the
opening in the rim of the wheel is stopped up”. “The moon appears sometimes as
waxing, sometimes as waning, to an extent corresponding to the closing or
opening of the passages”. “The sun is placed highest of all, after it the moon,
and under them the fixed stars and the planets”.
It has been pointed out that the idea of the formation
of tubes of compressed air within which the fire of each star is shut up except
for the one opening through which the flame shows (like a gas-jet, as it were)
is not unlike Laplace’s hypothesis with reference to the origin of Saturn’s
rings. In any case it is a sufficiently original conception.
When Anaximander says that the hoops carrying the sun
and moon “lie obliquely”, this is no doubt an attempt to explain, in addition
to the daily rotation, the annual movement of the sun and the monthly movement
of the moon.
We have here too the first speculation about the sizes
and distances of the heavenly bodies. The sun is as large as the earth. The
ambiguity between the estimates of the size of the sun’s circle as twenty-seven
or twenty-eight times the size of the earth suggests that it is a question
between taking the inner and outer circumferences of the sun’s ring
respectively, and a similar ambiguity may account for the circle of the moon
being stated to be nineteen times, not eighteen times, the size of the earth.
No estimate is given of the distance of the planets from the earth, but as,
according to Anaximander, they are nearer to the earth than the sun and moon
are, it is possible that, if a figure had been stated, it would have been nine
times the size of the earth, in which case we should have had the numbers 9,
18, 27, three terms in arithmetical progression and all of them multiples of 9,
the square of 3. It seems probable that these figures were not arrived at by
any calculation based on geometrical considerations, but that we have here
merely an illustration of the ancient cult of the sacred numbers 3 and 9. Three
is the sacred number in Homer, 9 in Theognis. The
cult of 3 and its multiples 9 and 27 is found among the Aryans, then among the
Finns and Tartars and then again among the Etruscans. Therefore Anaximander’s
figures probably say little more than what the Indians tell us, namely, that
three Vishnu-steps reach from earth to heaven.
Anaximander is said to have been the first to discover
the gnomon (or sun-dial with a vertical needle). This is, however, incorrect,
for Herodotus says that the Greeks learnt the use of the gnomon and the polos
from the Babylonians. Anaximander may have been the first to introduce the gnomon
into Greece. He is said to have set it up in Sparta and to have shown on it
“the solstices, the times, the seasons, and the equinox”.
But Anaximander has another title to fame. He was the
first who ventured to draw a map of the inhabited earth. The Egyptians indeed
had drawn maps before, but only of special districts. Anaximander boldly
planned out the whole world with “the circumference of the earth and of the
sea”. Hecataeus, a much-travelled man, is said to
have corrected Anaximander’s map so that it became the object of general
admiration.
ANAXIMENES.
With Anaximenes of Miletus (about 585-528/4 B.C.) the
earth is still flat like a table, but, instead of being suspended freely
without support as with Anaximander, it is supported by the air, riding on it
as it were. The sun, moon and stars are all made of fire and (like the earth)
they ride on the air because of their breadth. The sun is flat like a leaf.
Anaximenes also held that the stars are fastened on a crystal sphere like nails
or studs. It seems clear therefore that by the stars which “ride on the air
because of their breadth” he meant the planets only. A like apparent
inconsistency applies to the motion of the stars. If the stars are fixed in the
crystal sphere like nails, they must be carried round complete circles by the
revolution of the sphere about a diameter.
Yet Anaximenes also said that the stars do not move or
revolve under the earth as some suppose, but round the earth, just as a cap can
be turned round on the head. The sun is hidden from sight, not because it is
under the earth, but because it is covered by the higher parts of the earth and
because its distance from us is greater. Aristotle adds the detail that the sun
is carried round the northern portion of the earth and produces night because
the earth is lofty towards the north. We must again conclude that the stars
which, like the sun and moon, move laterally round the earth between their
setting and rising again are the planets, as distinct from the fixed stars. It
would therefore seem that Anaximenes was the first to distinguish the planets
from the fixed stars in respect of their irregular movements. He improved on
Anaximander in that he relegated the fixed stars to the region most distant
from the earth.
Anaximenes was also original in holding that, in the
region occupied by the stars, bodies of an earthy nature are carried round
along with them. The object of these invisible bodies of an earthy nature
carried round along with the stars is clearly to explain the eclipses and
phases of the moon. It was doubtless this conception which, in the hands of
Anaxagoras and others, ultimately led to the true explanation of eclipses.
The one feature of Anaximenes’s system which was
destined to an enduring triumph was the conception of the stars being fixed on
a crystal sphere as in a rigid frame. This really remained the fundamental
principle in all astronomy down to Copernicus.
PYTHAGORAS.
With Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans we come to a
different order of things. Pythagoras, born at Samos about 572 B.C., is
undoubtedly one of the greatest names in the history of science. He was a
mathematician of brilliant achievements; he was also the inventor of the
science of acoustics, an astronomer of great originality, a theologian and
moral reformer, and the founder of a brotherhood which admits comparison with
the orders of mediaeval chivalry. Perhaps his most epoch-making discovery was
that of the dependence of musical tones on numerical proportions, the octave
representing the proportion of 2 : I in length of string at the same tension,
the fifth 3 : 2, and the fourth 4 : 3. Mathematicians know him as the reputed
discoverer of the famous theorem about the square on the hypotenuse of a
right-angled triangle (= Euclid I. 47); but he was also the first to make
geometry a part of a liberal education and to explore its first principles
(definitions, etc.).
Pythagoras is said to have been the first to maintain
that the earth is spherical in shape; on what ground, is uncertain. One
suggestion is that he may have argued from the roundness of the shadow cast by
the earth in the eclipses of the moon; but Anaxagoras was the first to give the
true explanation of such eclipses. Probably Pythagoras attributed spherical
shape to the earth for the mathematical or mathematico-aesthetical
reason that the sphere is the most beautiful of all solid figures. It is
probable too, and for the same reason, that Pythagoras gave the same spherical
shape to the sun and moon, and even to the stars, in which case the way lay
open for the discovery of the true cause of eclipses and of the phases of the
moon. Pythagoras is also said to have distinguished five zones in the earth. It
is true that the first declaration that the earth is spherical and that it has
five zones is alternatively attributed to Parmenides (born perhaps about 516 or
514 B.C.), on the good authority of Theophrastus. It is possible that, although
Pythagoras was the real author of these views, Parmenides was the first to
state them in public.
Pythagoras regarded the universe as living,
intelligent, spherical, enclosing the earth at the centre,
and rotating about an axis passing through the centre of the earth, the earth remaining at rest.
He is said to have been the first to observe that the
planets have an independent motion of their own in a direction opposite to that
of the fixed stars, i.e. the daily rotation. Alternatively with Parmenides he
is said to have beer, the first to recognize that the Morning and the Evening
Stars are one and the same. Pythagoras is hardly likely to have known this as
the result of observations of his own; he may have learnt it from Egypt or Chaldaea along with other facts about the planets.
PARMENIDES.
We have seen that certain views are alternatively
ascribed to Pythagoras and Parmenides. The system of Parmenides was in fact a
kind of blend of the theories of Pythagoras and Anaximander. In giving the
earth spherical form with five zones he agreed with Pythagoras. Pythagoras,
however, made the spherical universe rotate about an axis through the centre of the earth; this implied that the universe is
itself limited, but that something exists round it, and in fact that beyond the
finite rotating sphere there is limitless void or empty space. Parmenides, on
the other hand, denied the existence of the infinite void and was therefore
obliged to make his finite sphere motionless and to hold that its apparent
rotation is only an illusion.
In other portions of his system Parmenides followed
the lead of Anaximander. Like Anaximander (and Democritus later) he argued that
the earth remains in the centre because, being
equidistant from all points on the sphere of the universe, it is in equilibrium
and there is no more reason why it should tend to move in one direction than in
another. Parmenides also had a system of wreaths or bands round the sphere of
the universe which contained the sun, the moon and the stars; the wreaths
remind us of the hoops of Anaximander, but their nature is different. The
wreaths, according to the most probable interpretation of the texts, are,
starting from the outside, (1) a solid envelope like a wall; (2) a band of fire
(the aether-fire); (3) mixed bands, made up of light
and darkness in combination, which exhibit the phenomenon of “fire shining out
here and there”. these mixed bands including the Milky Way as well as the sun,
moon and planets; (4) a band of fire, the inner side of which is our
atmosphere, touching the earth. Except that Parmenides placed the Morning Star
first in the aether and therefore above the sun, he
did not apparently differ from Anaximander’s view of the relative distances of
the heavenly bodies, according to which both the planets and the other stars
are all placed below the sun and moon.
Two lines from Parmenides’s poem have been quoted to
show that he declared that the moon is illuminated by the sun. The first line
speaks of the moon as “a night-shining foreign light wandering round the
earth”; but, even if the line is genuine, “foreign” need not mean “borrowed”.
The other line speaks of the moon as “always fixing its gaze on the sun”; but,
though this states an observed fact, it is far from explaining the cause. We
have, moreover, positive evidence against the attribution of the discovery of
the opacity of the moon to Parmenides. It is part of the connected prose
description of his system that the moon is a mixture of air and fire, and in
other passages we are told that he held the moon to be of fire. Lastly, Plato
speaks of “the fact which Anaxagoras lately asserted, that the moon has its
light from the sun”. It seems impossible that Plato would speak in such terms
if the fact in question had been stated for the first time either by Parmenides
or by the Pythagoreans.
ANAXAGORAS.
Anaxagoras, a man of science if ever there was one,
was born at Clazomenae in the neighbourhood of Smyrna about 500 B.C. He neglected his possessions, which were considerable,
in order to devote himself to science. Someone once asked him what was the
object of being born, and he replied, “The investigation of sun, moon and
heaven”. He took up his abode at Athens, where he enjoyed the friendship of
Pericles. When Pericles became unpopular shortly before the outbreak of the
Peloponnesian war, he was attacked through his friends, and Anaxagoras was
accused of impiety for declaring that the sun was a red-hot stone and the moon
made of earth. One account says that he was fined and banished; another that he
was imprisoned, and that it was intended to put him to death, but that Pericles
obtained his release; he retired to Lampsacus, where
he died at the age of seventy-two.
One epoch-making discovery belongs to him, namely,
that the moon does not shine by its own light but receives its light from the
sun: Plato, as we have seen, is one authority for this statement. Plutarch also
in his De facie in orbe lunae says, “Now when our comrade in his discourse had expounded that proposition of
Anaxagoras that the sun places the brightness in the moon, he was greatly
applauded”.
This discovery enabled Anaxagoras to say that “the
obscurations of the moon month by month were due to its following the course of
the sun by which it is illuminated, and the eclipses of the moon were caused by
its falling within the shadow of the earth which then comes between the sun and
the moon, while the eclipses of the sun were due to the interposition of the
moon”. Anaxagoras was therefore the first to give the true explanation of
eclipses. As regards the phases of the moon, his explanation could only have
been complete if he had known that the moon is spherical; in fact, however, he
considered the earth (and doubtless the other heavenly bodies also) to be flat.
To his true theory of eclipses Anaxagoras added the unnecessary assumption that
the moon was sometimes eclipsed by other earthy bodies below the moon but
invisible to us. In this latter assumption he followed the lead of Anaximenes.
The other bodies in question were probably invented to explain why the eclipses
of the moon are seen oftener than those of the sun.
Anaxagoras’s cosmogony contained some fruitful ideas.
According to him, the formation or the world began with a vortex set up, in a
portion of the mixed mass in which “all things were together”, by Mind. This
rotatory movement began at one point and then gradually spread, taking in wider
and wider circles. The first effect was to separate two great masses, one
consisting of the rare, not, light, dry, called the aether,
and the other of the opposite categories and called air The nether took the
outer place, the air the inner. Out of the air were separated successively
clouds, water, earth, and stones. The dense, the moist, the dark and cold, and
all the heaviest things, collect in the centre as the
result of the circular motion, and it is from these elements when consolidated
that the earth is formed. But after this, “in consequence of the violence of
the whirling motion, the surrounding fiery aether tore stones away from the earth and kindled them into stars”. Anaxagoras
conceived therefore the idea of a centrifugal force, as distinct from that of
concentration brought about by the motion of the vortex, and he assumed a
series of projections or “hurlings-off” of precisely
the same kind as the theory of Kant and Laplace assumed for the formation of
the solar system.
In other matters than the above Anaxagoras did not
make much advance on the crude Ionian theories. “The sun is a red-hot mass or a
stone on fire”. “It is larger (or many times larger) than the Peloponnese”. He
considered that “the stars were originally carried round (laterally) like a
dome, the pole which is always visible being thus vertically above the earth,
and it was only afterwards that their course became inclined”.
But he put forward a remarkable and original
hypothesis to explain the Milky Way. He thought the sun to be smaller than the
earth. Consequently, when the sun in its revolution passes below the earth, the
shadow cast by the earth extends without limit. The trace of this shadow on the
heavens is the Milky Way. The stars within this shadow are not interfered with
by the light of the sun, and we therefore see them shining: those stars, on the
other hand, which are outside the shadow are overpowered by the light of the
sun which shines on them even during the night, so that we cannot see them.
Aristotle easily disposes of this theory by observing that, the sun being much
larger than the earth, and the distance of the stars from the earth being many
times greater than the distance of the sun, the sun's shadow would form a cone
with its vertex not very far from the earth, so that the shadow of the earth,
which we call night, would not reach the stars at all.
EMPEDOCLES.
Empedocles of Agrigentum (about 494-434 B.C.) would hardly deserve mention for his astronomy alone, so
crude were his views where they differed from those of his predecessors. The
earth, according to Empedocles, is kept in its place by the swiftness of the
revolution of the heaven, just as we may swing a cup with water in it round and
round so that in some positions the top of the cup may even be turned downwards
without the water escaping. Day and night he explained as follows. Within the
crystal sphere to which the fixed stars are attached (as Anaximenes held), and
filing it, is a sphere consisting of two hemispheres, one of which is wholly of
fire and therefore light, while the other is a mixture of air with a little
fire, which mixture is darkness or night. The revolution of these two
hemispheres round the earth produces at each point on its surface the
succession of day and night. Empedocles held the sun to be, not fire, but a
reflection of fire similar to that which takes place from the surface of water,
the fire of a whole hemisphere of the world being bent back from the earth,
which is circular, and concentrated into the crystalline sun which is carried
round by the motion of the fiery hemisphere.
Empedocles’s one important scientific achievement was
his theory that light travels and takes time to pass from one point to another.
The theory is alluded to by Aristotle, who says that, according to Empedocles,
the light from the sun reaches the intervening space before it reaches the eye
or the earth; there was therefore a time when the ray was not yet seen, but was
being transmitted through the medium.
THE PYTHAGOREANS.
We have seen that Pythagoras was the first to give
spherical form to the earth and probably to the heavenly bodies generally, and
to assign to the planets a revolution of their own in a sense opposite to that
of the daily rotation of the fixed stars about the earth as centre.
But a much more remarkable development was to follow
in the Pythagorean school. This was nothing less than the abandonment of the
geocentric hypothesis and the reduction of the earth to the status of a planet
like the others. The resulting system, known as the Pythagorean, is attributed
(on the, authority probably of Theophrastus) to Philolaus;
but Diogenes Laertius and Aetius refer to one Hicetas of Syracuse in this connection; Aristotle attributes the system to the
Pythagoreans. It is a partial anticipation of the theory of Copernicus but
differs from it in that the earth and the planets do not revolve round the sun
but about an assumed central fire, and the sun itself as well as the moon does
the same. There were thus eight heavenly bodies, in addition to the sphere of
the fixed stars, all revolving about the central fire. The number of
revolutions being thus increased to nine, the Pythagoreans postulated yet
another, making ten. The tenth body they called the counter-earth, and its
character and object will appear from the following general description of the
system.
The universe is spherical in shape and finite in size.
Outside it is infinite void, which enables the universe to breathe, as it were.
At the centre is the central fire, the Hearth of the
Universe, called by various names such as the Tower or Watch-tower of Zeus, the
Throne of Zeus, the Mother of the Gods. In this central fire is located the
governing principle, the force which directs the movement and activity of the
universe. The outside boundary of the sphere is an envelope of fire; this is
called Olympus, and in this region the elements are found in all their purity;
below this is the universe. In the universe there revolve in circles round the
central fire the following bodies: nearest to the central fire the
counter-earth which always accompanies the earth, then the earth, then the
moon, then the sun, next to the sun the five planets, and last of all, outside
the orbits of the planets, the sphere of the fixed stars. The counter-earth,
which accompanies the earth but revolves in a smaller orbit, is not seen by us
because the hemisphere on which we live is turned away from the counter-earth.
It follows that our hemisphere is always turned away from the central fire,
that is, it faces outwards from the orbit towards Olympus (the analogy of the
moon which always turns one side towards us may have suggested this); this
involves a rotation of the earth about its axis completed in the same time as
it takes the earth to complete a revolution about the central fire.
Although there was a theory that the counter-earth was
introduced in order to bring the number of the moving bodies up to ten, the
perfect number according to the Pythagoreans, it is clear from a passage of Aristotle
that this was not the real reason. Aristotle says, namely, that the eclipses of
the moon were considered to be due sometimes to the interposition of the earth,
sometimes to the interposition of the counter-earth. Evidently therefore the
purpose of the counter-earth was to explain the frequency with which eclipses
of the moon occur.
The Pythagoreans held that the earth, revolving, like
one of the stars, about the central fire, makes night and day according to its
position relatively to the sun; it is therefore day in that region which is lit
up by the sun and night in the cone formed by the earth’s shadow. As the same
hemisphere is always turned outwards, it follows that the earth completes one
revolution about the central fire in a day and a night or in about twenty-four
hours. This would account for the apparent diurnal rotation of the heavens from
east to west; but for parallax (of which, if we may believe Aristotle, the
Pythagoreans made light), it would be equivalent to the rotation of the earth on
its own axis once in twenty-four hours. This would make the revolution of the
sphere of the fixed stars unnecessary. Yet the Pythagoreans certainly gave some
motion to the latter sphere. What it was remains a puzzle. It cannot have been
the precession of the equinoxes, for that was first discovered by Hipparchus
(second century B.C.). Perhaps there was a real incompatibility between the two
revolutions which was unnoticed by the authors of the system.
OEXOPIDES OF CHIOS.
Oenopides of Chios (a little younger than Anaxagoras) is
credited with two discoveries. The first, which was important, was that of the
obliquity of the zodiac circle or the ecliptic; the second was that of a Great
Year, which (Oenopides put at fifty-nine years. He
also (so we are told) found the length of the year to be 365’22/59 days. He
seems to have obtained this figure by a sort of circular argument. Starting
first with 365 days as the length of a year and 29’1/2 days as the length of
the lunar month, approximate figures known before his time, he had to find the
least integral number of complete years containing an exact number of lunar
months; this is clearly fifty-nine years, which contain twice 365 or 730 lunar
months. Oenopides seems by his knowledge of the
calendar to have determined the number of days in 730 lunar months to be
21,557, and this number divided by fifty-nine, the number of years, gives 365
as the number of days in the year.
PLATO.
We come now to Plato (427-347 B.C.). In the astronomy
of Plato, as we find it in the Dialogues, there is so large an admixture of
myth and poetry that it is impossible to be sure what his real views were on
certain points of detail. In the Phaedo we have certain statements about the
earth to the effect that it is of very large dimensions, the apparent hollow
(according to Plato) in which we live being a very small portion of the whole,
and that it is in the middle of the heaven, in equilibrium, without any
support, by virtue of the uniformity in the substance of the heaven. In the
Republic we have a glimpse of a more complete astronomical system. The
outermost revolution is that of the sphere of the fixed stars, which carries
round with it the whole universe including the sun, moon and planets, the latter
seven bodies, while they are so carried round by the general rotation, have
slower revolutions of their own in addition, one inside the other, these
revolutions being at different speeds but all in the opposite sense to the
general rotation of the universe. The quickest rotation is that of the fixed
stars and the universe, which takes place once in about twenty-four hours. The
slower speeds of the sun, moon and planets are not absolute but relative to the
sphere of the fixed stars regarded as stationary. The earth in the centre is unmoved; the successive revolutions about it and
within the sphere of the fixed stars are (reckoning from the earth outwards)
those of the moon, the sun, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn; the speed of
the moon is the quickest, that of the sun the next quickest, while Venus and
Mercury travel with the sun and have the same speed, taking about a year to
describe their orbits ; after these in speed comes Mars, then Jupiter and, last
and slowest of all, Saturn. There is nothing said in the Republic about the
seven bodies revolving in a circle different from and inclined to the equator
of the sphere of the fixed stars; that is, the obliquity of the ecliptic does
riot appear; hence the standpoint of the whole system is that of Pythagoras as
distinct from that of the Pythagoreans.
Plato’s astronomical system is, however, most fully
developed in the Timaeus. While other details remain substantially the same,
the zodiac circle in which the sun, moon and planets revolve is distinguished
from the equator of the sphere of the fixed stars. The latter is called the
circle of the Same, the former that of the Other, and we are told (quite
correctly) that, since the revolution of the universe in the circle of the Same
carries all the other revolutions with it, the effect on each of the seven
bodies is to turn their actual motions in space into spirals. There a
difficulty in interpreting a phrase in Plato’s description which says that
Venus and Mercury, though moving in a circle having equal speed with the sun, “have
the contrary tendency to it”. Literally this would seem to mean that Venus and
Mercury describe their circles the opposite way to the sun, but this is so
contradicted by observation that Plato could hardly have maintained it; hence the
words have been thought to convey a vague reference to the apparent
irregularities in the motion of Venus and Mercury, their standings-still and
retrogradations.
But the most disputed point in the system is the part
assigned in it to the earth. An expression is used with regard to its relation
to the axis of the heavenly sphere which might mean either (1) that it is
wrapped or globed about that axis but without motion, or (2) that it revolves
round the axis. If the word means revolving about the axis of the sphere, the
revolution would be either (a) rotation about its own axis supposed to be
identical with that of the sphere, or (b) revolution about the axis of the
heavenly sphere in the same way that the sun, moon and planets revolve about an
axis obliquely inclined to that axis. But (a) if the earth rotated about its
own axis, this would make unnecessary the rotation of the sphere of the fixed
stars once in twenty-four hours, which, however, is expressly included as part
of the system. The hypothesis (b) would make the system similar to the
Pythagorean except that the earth would revolve about the axis of the heavenly
sphere instead of round the central fire. The supporters of this hypothesis
cite two passages of Plutarch to the effect that Plato was said in his old age
to have repented of having given the earth the middle place in the universe
instead of placing it elsewhere and giving the middle and chiefest place to some worthier occupant. It is a sufficient answer to this argument
that, if Plato really meant in the passage of the Timaeus to say that the earth
revolves about the axis of the heavenly sphere, he had nothing to repent of. We
must therefore, for our part, conclude that in his written Dialogues Plato
regarded the earth as at rest in the center of the universe.
We have it on good authority that Plato set it as a
problem to all earnest students “to find what are the uniform and ordered
movements by the assumption of which the apparent movements of the planets can
be accounted for”. The same authority adds that Eudoxus was the first to formulate a theory with this object; and Heraclides of Pontus followed with an entirely new hypothesis. Both were pupils of Plato
and, in so far as the statement of his problem was a stimulus to these
speculations, he rendered an important service to the science of astronomy.
EUDOXUS, CALLIPPUS, ARISTOTLE.
Eudoxus of Cnidos (about 408-355
B.C.) was one of the very greatest of the Greek mathematicians. He was the
discoverer and elaborator of the great theory of proportion applicable to all
magnitudes whether commensurable or incommensurable which is given in Euclid’s
Book V. He was also the originator of the powerful method of exhaustion used by
all later Greek geometers for the purpose of finding the areas of curves and
the volumes of pyramids, cones, spheres and other curved surfaces. It is not
therefore surprising that he should have invented a remarkable geometrical
hypothesis for explaining the irregular movements of the planets. The problem
was to find the necessary number of circular motions which by their combination
would produce the motions of the planets as actually observed, and in
particular the variations in their apparent speeds, their stations and
retrogradations and their movements in latitude. This Eudoxus endeavored to do by combining the motions of several concentric spheres, one
inside the other, and revolving about different axes, each sphere revolving on
its own account but also being carried round bodily by the revolution of the
next sphere encircling it. We are dependent on passages from Aristotle and Simplicius for our knowledge of Eudoxus’s system, which he had set out in a work On Speeds, now lost. Eudoxus assumed three revolving spheres for producing the apparent motions of the sun
and moon respectively, and four for that of each of the planets. In his
hypothesis for the sun he seems deliberately to have ignored the discovery made
by Meton and Euctemon some
sixty or seventy years before that the sun does not take the same time to describe
the four quadrants of its orbit between the equinoctial and solstitial points.
It should be observed that the whole hypothesis of the
concentric spheres is pure geometry, and there is no mechanics in it. We will
shortly describe the arrangement of the four spheres which by their revolution
produced the motion of a planet. The first and outermost sphere produced the
daily rotation in twenty-four hours; the second sphere revolved about an axis
perpendicular to the plane of the zodiac or ecliptic, thereby producing the
motion along the zodiac “in the respective periods in which the planets appear
to describe the zodiac circle”, i.e. in the case of the superior planets, the
sidereal periods of revolution, and in the case of Mercury and Venus (on a
geocentric system) one year. The third sphere had its poles at two opposite
points on the zodiac circle, the poles being carried round in the motion of the
second sphere; the revolution of the third sphere about the axis connecting the
two poles was again uniform and took place in a period equal to the synodic
period of the planet, or the time elapsing between two successive oppositions
or conjunctions with the sun.
The poles of the third sphere were different for all
the planets, except that for Mercury and Venus they were the same. On the
surface of the third sphere the poles of the fourth sphere were fixed, and its
axis of revolution was inclined to that of the former at an angle constant for
each planet but different for the different planets. The planet was fixed at a
point on the equator of the fourth sphere. The third and fourth spheres
together cause the planet’s movement in latitude. Simplicius explains clearly the effect of these two rotations. If, he says, the planet had
been on the third sphere (by itself), it would actually have arrived at the
poles of the zodiac circle; but, as things are, the fourth sphere, which turns
about the poles of the inclined circle carrying the planet and rotates in the
opposite sense to the third, i.e. from east to west, but in the same period,
will prevent any considerable divergence on the part of the planet from the
zodiac circle, and will cause the planet to describe about this same zodiac
circle the curve called by Eudoxus the hippopede (horse-fetter), so that the breadth of this curve
will be the maximum amount of the apparent deviation of the planet in latitude.
The curve in question is an elongated figure-of-eight lying along and bisected
by the zodiac circle. The motion then round this figure-of-eight combined with the
motion in the zodiac circle produces the acceleration and retardation of the
motion of the planet, causing the stations and retrogradations. Mathematicians
will appreciate the wonderful ingenuity and beauty of the construction.
Eudoxus spent sixteen months in Egypt about 381-380 B.C.,
and, while there, he assimilated the astronomical knowledge of the priests of
Heliopolis and himself made observations. The Observatory between Heliopolis
and Cercesura used by him was still pointed out in
Augustus’s time; he also had one built at Cnidos. He
wrote two books entitled respectively the Mirror and the Phaenomena;
the poem of Aratus was, so far as verses 19-732 are concerned, drawn from the
Phenomena of Eudoxus. He is also credited with the
invention of the arachne (spider’s web) which,
however, is alternatively attributed to Apollonius, and which seems to have
been a sun-clock of some kind.
Eudoxus’s system of concentric spheres was improved upon by Callippus (about 370-300 B.C.), who added two more spheres
for the sun and the moon, and one more in the case of each of the three nearer
planets, Mercury, Venus and Mars. The two additional spheres in the case of the
sun were introduced in order to account for the unequal motion of the sun in
longitude; and the purpose in the case of the moon was presumably similar.
Callippus made the length of the seasons, beginning with the
vernal equinox, ninety-four, ninety-two, eighty-nine and ninety days
respectively, figures much more accurate than those given by Euctemon a hundred years earlier, which were ninety-three,
ninety, ninety and ninety-two days respectively.
With Callippus as well as Eudoxus the system of concentric spheres was purely
geometrical. Aristotle (384-322 B.C.) thought it necessary to alter it in a
mechanical sense; he made the spheres into spherical shells actually in contact
with one another, and this made it almost necessary, instead of having
independent sets of spheres, one set for each planet, to make all the sets part
of one continuous system of spheres. For this purpose he assumed sets of
reacting spheres between successive sets of the original spheres. E.g. Saturn
being carried by a set of four spheres, he had three reacting spheres to
neutralize the last three, in order to restore the outermost sphere to act as
the first of the four spheres producing the motion of the next lower planet,
Jupiter, and so on. The change was hardly an improvement.
Aristotle’s other ideas in astronomy do not require
detailed notice, except his views about the earth. Although he held firmly to
the old belief that the earth is in the centre and
remains motionless, he was clear that its shape (like that of the stars and the
universe) is spherical, and he had arrived at views about its size sounder than
those of Plato. In support of the spherical shape of the earth he used some
good arguments based on observation. (1) In partial eclipses of the moon the
line separating the dark and bright portions is always circular—unlike the line
of demarcation in the phases of the moon which may be straight. (2) Certain
stars seen above the horizon in Egypt and in Cyprus are not visible further
north, and, on the other hand, certain stars set there which in more northern
latitudes remain always above the horizon. As there is so perceptible a change
of horizon between places so near to each other, it follows not only that the
earth is spherical but also that it is not a very large sphere. Aristotle adds
that people are not improbably right when they say that the region about the
Pillars of Heracles is joined on to India, one sea connecting them. He quotes a
result arrived at by the mathematicians of his time, that, the circumference of
the earth is 400,000 stades. He is clear that the
earth is much smaller than some of the stars, but that the moon is smaller than
the earth.
The systems of concentric spheres were not destined to
hold their ground for long. In these systems the sun, moon and planets were of
necessity always at the same distances from the earth respectively. But it was
soon recognized that they did not “save the phenomena”, since it was seen that
the planets appeared to be at one time nearer and at another time farther off.
Autolycus of Pitane (who flourished about 310 B.C.)
knew this and is said to have tried to explain it; indeed it can hardly have
been unknown even to the authors of the concentric theory themselves, for
Polemarchus of Cyzicus, almost contemporary with Eudoxus,
is said to have been aware of it but to have minimized the difficulty because
he preferred the hypothesis of the concentric spheres to others.
Development along the lines of Eudoxus’s theory being thus blocked, the alternative was open of seeing whether any
modification of the Pythagorean system would give better results. We actually
have evidence of revisions of the Pythagorean theory. The first step was to get
rid of the counter-earth, and some Pythagoreans did this by identifying the
counter-earth with the moon. We hear too of a Pythagorean system in which the
central fire was not outside the earth but in the centre of the earth itself. The descriptions of this system rather indicate that in it
the earth was supposed to be at rest, without any rotation, in the centre of the universe. This was practically a return to
the standpoint of Pythagoras himself. But it is clear that, if the system of Philolaus (or Hicetas) be taken
and the central fire be transferred to the centre of
the earth (the counter-earth being also eliminated), and if the movements of
the earth, sun, moon and planets round the centre be
retained without any modification save that which is mathematically involved by
the transfer of the central fire to the centre of the
earth, the daily revolution of the earth about the central fire is necessarily
transformed into a rotation of the earth about its own axis in about
twenty-four hours.
HERACLIDES OF PONTUS.
All authorities agree that the theory of the daily
rotation of the earth about its own axis was put forward by Heraclides of Pontus (about 388-315 B.C.), a pupil of Plato; with him in some accounts is
associated the name of one Ecphantus, a Pythagorean.
We are told that Ecphantus asserted “that the earth,
being in the centre of the universe, moves about its
own centre in an eastward direction”, and that “Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean make the earth move, not in the sense of translation, but by
way of turning as on an axle, like a wheel, from west to east, about its own centre”.
Heraclides was born at Heraclea in Pontus. He went to Athens not
later than 364 B.C., and there met Speusippus, who
introduced him 'into the school of Plato. On the death of Speusippus (then at the head of the school) in 338, Xenocrates was elected to succeed him; at this election Heraclides was also a candidate and was only defeated by a few votes. He was the author of
dialogues, brilliant and original, on all sorts of subjects, which were much
read and imitated at Rome, e.g. by Varro and Cicero. Two of them “On Nature”
and “On the Heavens” may have dealt with astronomy.
In his view that the earth rotates about its own axis Heraclides is associated with Aristarchus of Samos; thus Simplicius says: “There have been some, like Heraclides of Pontus and Aristarchus, who supposed that the
phenomena can be saved if the heaven and the stars are at rest while the earth
moves about the poles of the equinoctial circle from the west to the east,
completing one revolution each day, approximately; the ‘approximately’ is added
because of the daily motion of the sun to the extent of one degree”.
Heraclides made another important advance towards the Copernican
hypothesis. He discovered the fact that Venus and Mercury revolve about the sun
as centre. So much is certain, but a further question
naturally arises. Having made Venus and Mercury revolve round the sun like
satellites, did Heraclides proceed to draw the same
inference with regard to the other, the superior, planets? The question is
interesting because, had it been laid down that all the five planets alike
revolve round the sun, the combination of this hypothesis with Heraclides’ assumption that the earth rotates about its own
axis in twenty-four hours would have amounted to an anticipation of the system
of Tycho Brahe, but with the improvement of the substitution of the daily
rotation of the earth for the daily revolution of the whole system about the
earth supposed at rest. Schiaparelli dealt with the question in two papers entitled I
precursori di Copernieo nell’ antichita (1873), and Origine del sistema panetario eliocentrico presso i Greci (1898). Schiaparelli tried to show that Heraclides did
arrive at the conclusion that the superior planets as well as Mercury and Venus
revolve round the sun; but most persons will probably agree that his argument
is not convincing. The difficulties seem too great. The circles described by
Mercury and Venus about the sun are relatively small circles and are entirely
on one side of the earth. But when the possibility of, say, Mars revolving
about the sun came to be considered, it would be at once obvious that the
precise hypothesis adopted for Mercury and Venus would not apply. It would be
seen that Mars is brightest when it occupies a position in the zodiac opposite,
to the sun; it must therefore be nearest to the earth at that time.
Consequently the circle described by Mars, instead of being on one side of the
earth, must comprehend the earth which is inside it. Whereas therefore the
circles described by Mercury and Venus were what the Greeks called epicycles
about a material centre, the sun (itself moving in a
circle round the earth), what was wanted in the case of Mars (if the circle described
by Mars was to have the sun for centre) was what the
Greeks called an eccentric circle, with a center which itself moves in a circle
about the earth, and with a radius greater than that of the sun’s orbit. Though
the same motion could have been produced by an epicycle, the epicycle would
have had to have a mathematical point (not the material sun) as centre. But the idea of using non-material points as
centers for epicycles was probably first thought of, at a later stage, by some
of the great mathematicians such as Apollonius of Perga (about 265-190 B.C.).
Not only does Schiaparelli maintain that the complete
(but 'improved) Tychonic hypothesis was put forward by Heraclides or at least in Heraclides’s time; he goes further and
makes a still greater claim on behalf of Heraclides,
namely, that it was he and not Aristarchus of Samos, who first stated as a
possibility the Copernican hypothesis. Now it was much to discover, as Heraclides did, that the earth rotates about its own axis
and that Mercury and Venus revolve round the sun like satellites; and it seems
a priori incredible that one man should not only have reached, and improved
upon, the hypothesis of Tycho Brahe but should also have suggested the
Copernican hypothesis. It is therefore necessary to examine briefly the
evidence on which Schiaparelli relied. His argument rests entirely upon one
passage, a sentence forming part of a quotation from a summary by Geminus of the Meteorologica of Posidonius, which Simplicius copied from Alexander Aphrodisiensis and embodied in
his commentary on the Physics of Aristotle. The sentence in question, according
to the reading of the MSS., is as follows: “Hence we actually find a certain
person, Heraclides of Pontus, coming forward and saying
that, even on the assumption that the earth moves in a certain way, while the
sun is in a certain way at rest, the apparent irregularity with reference to
the sun can be saved”. (The preceding sentence is about possible answers to the
question, why do the sun, the moon and the planets appear to move irregularly?
and says, “we may answer that, if we assume that their orbits are eccentric
circles or that the stars describe an epicycle, their apparent irregularity
will be saved, and it will be necessary to go further and examine in how many
different ways it is possible for these phenomena to be brought about”.)
Now it is impossible that Geminus himself can have spoken of an astronomer of the distinction of Heraclides as “a certain Heraclides of Pontus”. Consequently there have been different attempts made to emend the
reading of the MSS. All the emendations proposed are open to serious
objections, and we are thrown back on the reading of the MSS. Now it “leaps to
the eyes” that, if the name of Heraclides of Pontus
is left out, everything is in order. “This is why one astronomer has actually
suggested that, by assuming the earth to move in a certain way, and the sun to
be in a certain way at rest, the apparent irregularity with reference to the
sun will be saved”. This seems to be the solution of the puzzle suggested by
the ordinary principles of textual criticism, and is so simple and natural that
it will surely carry conviction to the minds of unbiassed persons. Geminus, in fact, mentioned no name but meant Aristarchus
of Samos, and some scholiast, remembering that Heraclides had given a certain motion to the earth (namely, rotation about its axis),
immediately thought of Heraclides and inserted his
name in the margin, from which it afterwards crept into the text.
It is only necessary to add that Archimedes is not
likely to have been wrong when he attributed the first suggestion of the
Copernican hypothesis to Aristarchus of Samos in express terms; and this is
confirmed by another positive statement by Aetius, already quoted, that “Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean made the earth move, not in the sense of translation, but with
a movement of rotation”.
PART II.
ARISTARCHUS OF SAMOS.
WE are told that Aristarchus of Samos was a pupil of Strato of Lampsacus, a natural
philosopher of originality, who succeeded Theophrastus as head of the
Peripatetic school in 288 or 287 B.C., and held that position for eighteen
years. Two other facts enable us to fix Aristarchus’s date approximately. In
281-280 he made an observation of the summer solstice; and the book in which he
formulated his heliocentric hypothesis was published before the date of Archimedes’s Psammites or Sandreckoner,
a work written before 216 B.C. Aristarchus therefore probably lived circa
310-230 B.C., that is, he came about seventy five years later than Heraclides and was older than Archimedes by about
twenty-five years.
Aristarchus was called “the mathematician, no doubt in
order to distinguish him from the many other persons of the same name;
Vitruvius includes him among the few great men who possessed an equally
profound knowledge of all branches of science, geometry, astronomy, music, etc.
“Men of this type are rare, men such as were in times past Aristarchus of
Samos, Philolaus and Archytas of Tarentum, Apollonius
of Perga, Eratosthenes of Cyrene, Archimedes and Scopinas of Syracuse, who left to posterity many mechanical
and gnomonic appliances which they invented and explained on mathematical and
natural principles”. That Aristarchus was a very capable geometer is proved by
his extant book, On the sizes and distances of the sun and moon, presently to
be described. In the mechanical line he is credited with the invention of an
improved sun-dial, the so-called scaphe, which
had not a plane but a concave hemispherical surface, with a pointer erected
vertically in the middle, throwing shadows and so enabling the direction and
height of the sun to be read off by means of lines marked on the surface of the
hemisphere. He also wrote on vision, light, and colors. His views on the latter
subjects were no doubt largely influenced by the teaching of Strato. Strato held that colors
were emanations from bodies, material molecules as it were, which imparted to
the intervening air the same color as that possessed by the body. Aristarchus
said that colors are “shapes or forms stamping the air with impressions like
themselves as it were”, that “colors in darkness have no coloring”, and that “light
is the color impinging on a substratum”.
THE HELIOCENTRIC HYPOTHESIS.
There is no doubt whatever that Aristarchus put
forward the heliocentric hypothesis. Ancient testimony is unanimous on the
point, and the first witness is Archimedes who was a younger contemporary of
Aristarchus, so that there is no possibility of a mistake. Copernicus himself
admitted that the theory was attributed to Aristarchus, though this does not
seem to be generally known. Copernicus refers in two passages of his work,
De revolutionibus caelestibus,
to the opinions of the ancients about the motion of the earth. In the
dedicatory letter to Pope Paul III he mentions that he first learnt from Cicero
that one Nicetas (i.e. Hicetas)
had attributed motion to the earth, and that he afterwards read in Plutarch
that certain others held that opinion; he then quotes the Placita philosophorum according to which “Philolaus the Pythagorean asserted that the earth moved round the fire in an oblique
circle in the same way as the sun and moon”. In Book I. c. 5 of his work
Copernicus alludes to the views of Heraclides, Ecphantus, and Hicetas, who made
the earth rotate about its own axis, and then goes on to say that it would not
be very surprising if anyone should attribute to the earth another motion
besides rotation, namely, revolution in an orbit in space: “atque etiam (terram) pluribus motibus vagantem et unam ex astris Philolaus Pythagoricus sensisse fertur, Mathematicus non
vulgaris”. Here, however, there is no question of the earth revolving round the
sun, and there is no mention of Aristarchus. But Copernicus did mention the
theory of Aristarchus in a passage which he afterwards suppressed : “Credibile est hisce similibusque causis Philolaum mobilitatem terrae sensisse, quod etiam nonnulli Aristarchum Samium ferunt in eadem fuisse sententia”.
It is desirable to quote the whole passage of
Archimedes in which the allusion to Aristarchus’s heliocentric hypothesis
occurs, in order to show the whole context.
“You are aware [‘you’ being King Gelon]
that ‘universe’ is the name given by most astronomers to the sphere the center
of which is the center of the earth, while its radius is equal to the straight
line between the center of the sun and the center of the earth. This is the
common account as you have heard from astronomers. But Aristarchus brought out
a book consisting of certain hypotheses, wherein it appears, as a consequence
of the assumptions made, that the universe is many times greater than the
‘universe’ just mentioned. His hypotheses are that the fixed stars and the sun
remain unmoved, that the earth revolves about the sun in the circumference of a
circle, the sun lying in the middle of the orbit, and that the sphere of the
fixed stars, situated about the same centre as the
sun, is so great that the circle in which he supposes the earth to revolve
bears such a proportion to the distance of the fixed stars as the centre of the sphere bears to its surface”.
The heliocentric hypothesis is here stated in language
which leaves no room for doubt about its meaning. The sun, like the fixed
stars, remains unmoved and forms the center of a circular orbit in which the
earth moves round it; the sphere of the fixed stars has its center at the
center of the sun.
We have further evidence in a passage of Plutarch’s
tract, On the face in the moon’s orb: “Only do not, my dear fellow, enter an
action for impiety against me in the style of Cleanthes, who thought it was the
duty of Greeks to indict Aristarchus on the charge of impiety for putting in motion
the Hearth of the Universe, being the effect of his attempt to save the
phenomena by supposing the heaven to remain at rest and the earth to revolve in
an oblique circle, while it rotates, at the same time, about its own axis”.
Here we have the additional detail that Aristarchus
followed Heraclides in attributing to the earth the
daily rotation about its axis; Archimedes does not state this in so many words,
but it is clearly involved by his remark that Aristarchus supposed the fixed
stars as well as the sun to remain unmoved in space. A tract “Against
Aristarchus” is mentioned by Diogenes Laertius among Cleanthes’s works; and it
was evidently published during Aristarchus’s lifetime (Cleanthes died about 232
B.C.).
We learn from another passage of Plutarch that the
hypothesis of Aristarchus was adopted, about a century later, by Seleucus, of Seleucia on the Tigris, a Chaldean or
Babylonian, who also wrote on the subject of the tides about 150 B.C. The
passage is interesting because it also alludes to the doubt about Plato’s final
views. “Did Plato put the earth in motion as he did the sun, the moon and the
five planets which he called the ‘instruments of time’ on account of their
turnings, and was it necessary to conceive that the earth ‘which is globed
about the axis stretched from pole to pole through the whole universe’ was not
represented as being (merely) held together and at rest but as turning and
revolving, as Aristarchus and Seleucus afterwards
maintained that it did, the former of whom stated this as only a hypothesis,
the latter as a definite opinion?”
No one after Seleucus is
mentioned by name as having accepted the doctrine of Aristarchus and, if other
Greek astronomers refer to it, they do so only to denounce it. Hipparchus,
himself a contemporary of Seleucus, definitely
reverted to the geocentric system, and it was doubtless his authority which
sealed the fate of the heliocentric hypothesis for so many centuries.
The reasons which weighed with Hipparchus were
presumably the facts that the system in which the earth revolved in a circle of
which the sun was the exact center failed to “save the phenomena”, and in
particular to account for the variations of distance and the irregularities of
the motions, which became more and more patent as methods of observation
improved; that, on the other hand, the theory of epicycles did suffice to
represent the phenomena with considerable accuracy; and that the latte, theory
could be reconciled with the immobility of the earth.
ON THE APPARENT DIAMETER OF THE SUN.
Archimedes tells us in the same treatise that
“Aristarchus discovered that the sun’s apparent size is about 1/720 part of the
zodiac circle”; that is to say, he observed that the angle subtended at the
earth by the diameter of the sun is about half a degree.
ON THE SIZES AND DISTANCES OF THE SUN AND MOON.
Archimedes also says that, whereas the ratio of the
diameter of the sun to that of the moon had been estimated by Eudoxus at 9:1 and by his own father Phidias at 12:1,
Aristarchus made the ratio greater than 18:1 but less than 20:1. Fortunately we
possess in Greek the short treatise in which Aristarchus proved these
conclusions; on the other matter of the apparent diameter of the sun Archimedes’s statement is our only evidence.
It is noteworthy that in Aristarchus’s extant treatise
On the sizes and distances of the sun and moon there is no hint of the
heliocentric hypothesis, while the apparent diameter of the sun is there
assumed to be, not but the very inaccurate figure of 2º. Both circumstances are
explained if we assume that the treatise was an early work written before the
hypotheses described by Archimedes were put forward. In the treatise
Aristarchus finds the ratio of the diameter of the sun to the diameter of the
earth to lie between 19:3 and 43:6; this would make the volume of the sun about
300 times that of the earth, and it may be that the great size of the sun in
comparison with the earth, as thus brought out, was one of the considerations
which led Aristarchus to place the sun rather than the earth in the centre of the universe, since it might even at that day
seem absurd to make the body which was so much larger revolve about the
smaller.
There is no reason to doubt that in his heliocentric
system Aristarchus retained the moon as a satellite of the earth revolving
round it as centre; hence even in his system there
was one epicycle.
The treatise On sizes and distances being the only
work of Aristarchus which has survived, it will be fitting to give here a description of its contents and special features.
The style of Aristarchus is thoroughly classical as
befits an able geometer intermediate in date between Euclid and Archimedes, and
his demonstrations ate worked out with the same rigor as those of his
predecessor and successor. The propositions of Euclid's Elements are, of
course, taken for granted, but other things are tacitly assumed which go beyond
what we find in Euclid. Thus the transformations of ratios defined in Euclid,
Book V, and denoted by the terms inversely, alternately, componendo, convertendo, etc., are regularly used in dealing
with unequal ratios, whereas in Euclid they are only used in proportions, i.e.
cases of equality of ratios. But the propositions of Aristarchus are also of
particular mathematical interest because the ratios of the sizes and distances
which have to be calculated are really trigonometrical ratios, sines, cosines,
etc., although at the time of Aristarchus trigonometry had not been invented,
and no reasonably close approximation to the value of π, the ratio of the circumference of any circle to its
diameter, had been made (it was Archimedes who first obtained the approximation
22/7). Exact calculation of the trigonometrical ratios being therefore
impossible for Aristarchus, he set himself to find upper and lower limits for
them, and he succeeded in locating those which emerge in his propositions
within tolerably narrow limits, though not always the narrowest within which it
would have been possible, even for him to confine them. In this species of
approximation to trigonometry he tacitly assumes propositions comparing the
ratio between a greater and a lesser angle in a figure with the ratio between
two straight lines, propositions which are formally proved by Ptolemy at the
beginning of his Syntaxis. Here again we have proof that textbooks containing
such propositions existed before Aristarchus’s time, and probably much earlier,
although they have not survived.
Aristarchus necessarily begins by laying down, as the
basis for his treatise, certain assumptions. They are six in number, and he
refers to them as hypotheses. We cannot do better than quote them in full,
along with the sentences immediately following, in which he states the main
results to be established in the treatise:—
[Hypotheses.]
1. That the moon receives its light front the sun.
2. That the earth is in the relation of a point and
center to the sphere in which the moon moves.
3. That, when the moon appears to us halved, the great
circle which divides the dark and the bright portions of the moon is in the
direction of our eyes.
4. That, when the moon appears to us halved, its
distance from the sun is then less than a quadrant by one-thirtieth of a
quadrant.
5. That the breadth of the (earth's) shadow is (that)
of two moons.
6. That the moon subtends one-fifteenth part of a sign
of the zodiac.
We are now in a position to prove the following
propositions:—
1. The distance of the sun from the earth is greater
than eighteen times, but less than twenty times, the distance of the moon (from
the earth); this follows from the hypothesis about the halved moon.
2. The diameter of the sun has the same ratio (as
afore-said) to the diameter of the moon.
3. The diameter of the sun has to the diameter of the
earth a ratio greater than that which 19 has to 3, but less than that which 4.3
has to 6; this follows from the ratio thus discovered between the distances,
the hypothesis about the shadow, and the hypothesis that the moon subtends
one-fifteenth part of a sign of the zodiac.
The first assumption is Anaxagoras’s discovery. The second
assumption is no doubt an exaggeration; but it is made in order to avoid having
to allow for the fact that the phenomena as seen by an observer on the surface
of the earth are slightly different from what would be seen if the observer’s
eye were at the centre of the earth. Aristarchus,
that is, takes the earth to be like a point in order to avoid the complication
of parallax.
The meaning of the third hypothesis is that the plane
of the great circle in question passes through the point where the eye of the
observer is situated; that is to say, we see the circle end on, as it were, and
it looks like a straight line.
Hypothesis 4. If S be the sun, M the moon and E the
earth, the triangle SME is, at the moment when the moon appears to us halved,
right-angled at M; and the hypothesis states that the angle at E in this
triangle is 87º or, in other words, the angle MSE, that is, the angle subtended
at the sun by the line joining M to E, is 3º. These estimates are decidedly
inaccurate, for the true value of the angle MES is 89° 50', and that of the
angle MSE is therefore 10'. There is nothing to show how Aristarchus came to
estimate the angle MSE at 30, and none of his successors seem to have made any
direct estimate of the size of the angle.
The assumption in Hypothesis 5 was improved upon
later. Hipparchus made the ratio of the diameter of the circle of the earth’s
shadow to the diameter of the moon to be, not 2, but 2’5 at the moon's mean
distance at the conjunctions; Ptolemy made it. at the moon’s greatest distance,
to be inappreciably less than 2’3/5.
The sixth hypothesis states that the diameter of the
moon subtends at our eye an angle which is 1/15th of 30°, i.e. 2°, whereas
Archimedes, as we have seen, tells us that Aristarchus found the angle subtended
by the diameter of the sun to be ½º (Archimedes in the same tract describes a
rough instrument by means of which he himself found that the diameter of the
sun subtended an angle less than but greater than 1/164th of a rightangle). Even the Babylonians had, many centuries
before, arrived at 1º as the apparent angular diameter of the sun. It is not
clear why Aristarchus took a value so inaccurate as 2º. It has been suggested
that he merely intended to give a specimen of the calculations which would have
to be made on the basis of mote exact experimental observations, and to show
that, for the solution of the problem, one of the data could be chosen almost
arbitrarily, by which proceeding he secured himself against certain objections
which might have been raised. Perhaps this is too ingenious, and it may be
that, in view of the difficulty of working out the geometry if the two angles
in question are very small, he took 30 and 2° as being the smallest with which
he could conveniently deal. Certain it is that the method of Aristarchus is
perfectly correct and, if he could have substituted the true values (as we know
them to day) for the inaccurate values which he assumes, and could have carried
far enough his geometrical substitute for trigonometry, he would have obtained
close limits for the true sizes and distances.
The book contains eighteen propositions. Prop. 1
proves that we can draw one cylinder to touch two equal spheres, and one cone
to touch two unequal spheres, the planes of the circles of contact being at
right angles to the axis of the cylinder or cone. Next (Prop. 2) it is shown
that, if a lesser sphere be illuminated by a greater, the illuminated portion
of the former will be greater than a hemisphere. Prop. 3 proves that the circle
in the moon which divides the dark and the bright portions (we will in future,
for short, call this “the dividing circle”) is least when the cone which
touches the sun and the moon has its vertex at our eye. In Prop. 4 it is shown
that the dividing circle is not perceptibly different from a great circle in
the moon. If CD is a diameter of the dividing circle, EF the parallel diameter
of the parallel great circle in the moon, O the center of the moon, A the
observer’s eye, FDG the great circle in the moon the plane of which passes
through A, and G the point where OA meets the latter great circle, Aristarchus
takes an arc of the great circle GH on one side of G, and another GK on the
other side of G, such that GH = GK = 1\2 (the arc FD), and proves that the
angle subtended at A by the arc HK is less than 1/44º; consequently, he says,
the arc would be imperceptible at A even in that
position, and a fortiori the arc FD (which is nearly in a straight line with
the tangent AD) is quite imperceptible to the observer at A. Hence (Prop. 5),
when the moon appears to us halved, we can take the plane of the great circle
in the moon which is parallel to the dividing circle as passing through our
eye. (It is tacitly assumed in Props. 3, 4, and throughout, that the diameters
of the sun and moon respectively subtend the same angle at our eye.) The proof
of Prop. 4 assumes as known the equivalent of the proposition in trigonometry
that, if each of the angles α, β is
not greater than a right angle, and α>β, then
tan α/
tan > α/β > sin α /sin β
Prop 6 proves that the moon’s orbit is “lower” (i.e.
smaller) than that of the sun, and that, when the moon appears to us halved, it
is distant less than a quadrant from the sun. Prop. 7 is the main proposition
in the treatise. It proves that, on the assumptions made, the distance of the
sun from the earth is greater than eighteen times, but less than twenty times,
the distance of the moon from the earth. The proof is simple and elegant and
should delight any mathematician; its two parts depend respectively on the
geometrical equivalents of the two inequalities stated in the formula quoted
above, namely,
tan α/
tan > α/β > sin α /sin β’
where α, β are
angles not greater than a right angle and α > β. Aristarchus also, in this proposition, cites 7/6 as an approximation
by defect to the value of √2, an approximation found by the Pythagoreans and quoted by
Plato. The trigonometrical equivalent of the result obtained in Prop. 7 is
1/18>sin 3º> 1/20
Prop. 8 states that, when the sun is totally eclipsed,
the sun and moon are comprehended by one and the same cone which has its vertex
at our eye. Aristarchus supports this by the arguments (1) that, if the sun
overlapped the moon, it would not be totally eclipsed, and (2) that, if the
sun fell short (i.e. was more than covered), it would remain totally eclipsed
for some time, which it does not (this, he says, is manifest from observation).
It is clear from this reasoning that Aristarchus had not observed the
phenomenon of an annular eclipse of the sun; and it is curious that the first
mention of an annular eclipse seems to be that quoted by Simplicius from Sosigenes (second century, A.U), the teacher of
Alexander Aphrodisiensis.
It follows (Prop, 9) from Prop. 8 that the diameters
of the sun and moon are in the same ratio as their distances from the earth
respectively, that is to say (Prop. 7) in a ratio greater than 18:1 but less
than 20:1. Hence (Prop. 10) the volume of the sun is more than 5832 times and
less than 8000 times that of the moon.
By the usual geometrical substitute for trigonometry
Aristarchus proves in Prop. 11 that the diameter of the moon has to the
distance between the centre of the moon and our eye a
ratio which is less than 2/45 but greater than 1/30. Since the angle subtended
by the moon’s diameter at the observer’s eye is assumed to be 2°, this
proposition is equivalent to the trigonometrical formula
1/45> sin 1º>60
Having proved in Prop. 4 that, so far as our
perception goes, the dividing circle in the moon is indistinguishable from a
great circle, Aristarchus goes behind perception and proves in Prop. 12 that
the diameter of the dividing circle is less than the diameter of the moon but
greater than 89/90 of it. This is again because half the angle subtended by the
moon at the eye is assumed to be 1º or 1/90 of a right angle. The proposition
is equivalent to the trigonometrical formula
1>cos 1°>89/90
We come now to propositions which depend on Hypothesis
5 that “the breadth of the earth’s shadow is that of two moons”. Prop. 13 is
about the diameter of the circular section of the cone formed by the earth’s
shadow at the place where the moon passes through it in an eclipse, and it is
worthwhile to notice the extreme accuracy with which Aristarchus describes the
diameter in question. It is with him “the straight line subtending the portion
intercepted within the earth’s shadow of the circumference of the circle in which
the extremities of the diameter of the circle dividing the dark and the bright
portions in the moon move”. Aristarchus proves that the length of the straight
line in question has to the diameter of the moon a ratio less than 2 but
greater than 88:45, and has to the diameter of the sun a ratio less than 1:19
but greater than 22:235. The ratio of the straight line to the diameter of the
moon is, in point of fact, 2 cos² 1° or 2 sin² 89°, and Aristarchus therefore
proves the equivalent of
2>2 cos² 1º>1/2(89/45) or 7921/4050
He then observes (without explanation) that
7921/4050>88/45 (an approximation easily obtained by developing 7921/4050 as
a continued fraction ( =1 + 1/1+ 1/21 +1/2); his result is therefore equivalent
to
1 >cos2 1º>44/45
The next propositions are the equivalents of more
complicated trigonometrical formulae. Prop. 14 is an auxiliary proposition to
Prop. 15. The diameter of the shadow dealt with in Prop. 13 divides into two
parts the straight line joining the center of the earth to the center of the
moon, and Prop. 14 shows that the whole length of this line is more than 675
times the part of it terminating in the center of the moon. With the aid of
Props. 7, 13. and 14 Aristarchus is now able, in Prop. 15, to prove another of
his main results, namely, that the diameter of the sun has to the diameter of
the earth a ratio greater than 19:3 but less than 43:6. In the second half of
the proof he has to handle quite large numbers. If A be the center of the sun,
B the center of the earth, and M the vertex of the cone formed by the earth’s
shadow, he proves that MA : AB is greater than (10125 x 7087):(9146 x 6750) or
71755875 =61735500, and then adds, without any word of explanation, that the
latter ratio is greater than 43:37. Here again it is difficult not to see in
43:37 the continued fraction 1 + 1/6+1/6; and although we cannot suppose that
the Greeks could actually develop 71755875/61735500 or 21261/18292 as a
continued fraction (in form), “we have here an important proof of the
employment by the ancients of a method of calculation, the theory of which
unquestionably belongs to the moderns, but the first applications of which are
too simple not to have originated in very remote times” (Paul Tannery).
The remaining propositions contain no more than
arithmetical inferences from the foregoing. Prop. 16 is to the effect that the
volume of the sun has to the volume of the earth a ratio greater than 6859:27
but less than 79507:216 (the numbers are the cubes of those in Prop. 15); Prop.
17 proves that the diameter of the earth is to that of the moon in a ratio
greater than 108:43 but less than 60:19 (ratios compounded of those in Props. 9
and 15), and Prop. 18 proves that the volume of the earth is to that of the
moon in a ratio greater than 1259712:79507 but less than 216000:6859.
ARISTARCHUS ON THE YEAR AND “GREAT YEAR”
Aristarchus is said to have increased by
1/1623rd of a day Callippus’s figure of 365’1/4
days as the length of the solar year, and to have given 2484 years as the
length of the Great Year or the period after which the sun, the moon and the
five planets return to the same position in the heavens. Tannery has shown
reason for thinking that 2484 is a wrong reading for 2434 years, and he gives
an explanation which seems convincing of the way in which Aristarchus arrived
at 2434 years as the length of the Great Year. The Chaldean period of 223
lunations was well known in Greece. Its length was calculated to be 6585’1/3
days, and in this period the sun was estimated to describe to|° 10’2/3º of its
circle in addition to 18 sidereal revolutions. The Greeks used the period
called by them exeligmus which was three times the
period of 223 lunations and contained a whole number of days, namely, 19756,
during which the sun described 32º in addition to 54 sidereal revolutions. It
followed that the number of days in the sidereal year was—
19756/54+32/360 = 19756/54+4/45 = 45 x 19756/2434 =
889020 /2434 = 365’1/4 + 3/4868
Now 4868/3 = 1623 – 1/3, and Aristarchus seems to have
merely replaced by the close approximation. The calculation was, however, of no
value because the estimate of 10’2/3° over 18 sidereal revolutions seems to
have been an approximation based merely on the difference between 6585’1/3 days
and 18 years of 365’1/4 days, i.e. 6574’1/4 days; thus the 10’2/3° itself
probably depended on a solar year of 365’1/4 days, and Aristarchus’s evaluation
of it as 365’1/4 1/1623 was really a sort of circular argument like the similar
calculation of the length of the year made by Oenopides of Chios.
LATER IMPROVEMENTS ON ARISTARCHUS’S FIGURES.
It may interest the reader to know how far
Aristarchus’s estimates of sizes and distances were improved upon by later
Greek astronomers. We are not informed how large he conceived the earth to be;
but Archimedes tells us that “some have tried to prove that the circumference
of the earth is about 300.000 stades and not
greater”, and it may be presumed that Aristarchus would, like Archimedes, be
content with this estimate. It is probable that it was Dicaearchus who (about 300 B.C.) arrived at this value, and that it was obtained by taking
24º (1/15th of the whole meridian circle) as the difference of latitude between Syene and Lysimachia (on
the same meridian) and 20.000 stades as the actual
distance between the two places. Eratosthenes, born a few years after
Archimedes, say 284 B.C., is famous for a better measurement of the earth which
was based on scientific principles. He found that at noon at the summer
solstice the sun threw no shadow at Syene, whereas at
the same hour at Alexandria (which he took to be on the same meridian) a
vertical stick cast a shadow corresponding to 1/50th of the meridian circle.
Assuming then that the sun’s rays at the two places are parallel in direction,
and knowing the distance between them to be 5000 stades,
he had only to take 50 times 5000 stades to get the
circumference of the earth. He seems, for some reason, to have altered 250,000
into 252,000 stades, and this, according to Pliny’s
account of the kind of stade used, works out to about
24,662 miles, giving for the diameter of the earth a length of 7850 miles, a
surprisingly close approximation, however much it owes to happy accidents in
the calculation.
Eratosthenes’s estimates of the sizes and distances of
the sun and moon cannot be restored with certainty in view of the defective
state of the texts of our authorities. We are better informed of Hipparchus’s
results. In the first book of a treatise on sizes and distances Hipparchus
based himself on an observation of an eclipse of the sun, probably that of 20th
November in the year 129 B.C., which was exactly total in the region about the
Hellespont, whereas at Alexandria about 4/4ths only of the diameter was
obscured. From these facts Hipparchus deduced that, if the radius of the earth
be the unit, the least distance of the moon contains 71, and the greatest 83 of
these units, the mean thus containing 77. But he reverted to the question in
the second book and proved “from many considerations” that the mean distance of
the moon is 67’1/3 times the radius of the earth, and also that the distance of
the sun is 2490 times the radius of the earth. Hipparchus also made the size
(meaning thereby the solid content) of the sun to be 1880 times that of the
earth, and the size of the earth to be 27 times that of the moon. The cube root
of 1880 being about 12’1/3, the diameters of the sun, earth and moon would be
in the ratio of the numbers 12’1/3,1,1/3. Hipparchus seems to have accepted
Eratosthenes’s estimate of 252,000 stades for the
circumference of the earth.
It is curious that Posidonius (135-51 b.c.), who was much less of an astronomer,
made a much better guess at the distance of the sun from the earth. He made it
500,000,000 stades. As he also estimated the
circumference of the earth at 240,000 stades, we may
take the diameter of the earth to be, according to Posidonius,
about 76,400 stades; consequently, if D be that
diameter, Posidonius made the distance of the sun to
be equal to 6545D as compared with Hipparchus's 1245D.
Ptolemy does not mention Hipparchus’s figures. His own
estimate of the sun’s distance was 605D, so that Hipparchus was far nearer the
truth. But Hipparchus’s estimate remained unknown and Ptolemy’s held the field
for many centuries; even Copernicus only made the distance of the sun 750 times
the earth’s diameter, and it was not till 1671-3 that a substantial improvement
was made; observations of Mars carried out in those years by Richer enabled
Cassini to conclude that the sun’s parallax was about 9.3" corresponding
to a distance between the sun and the earth of 87,000,000 miles.
Ptolemy made the distance of the moon from the earth
to be 29’1/2 times the earth’s diameter, and the diameter of the earth to be
3’2/5 times that of the moon. He estimated the diameter of the sun at 18’4/5
times that of the moon and therefore about 5’1/2 times that of the earth, a
figure again much inferior to that given by Hipparchus.
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
J. L. E. Dreyer, History of the Planetary System: from Thales to KeplerSir Thomas Heath's Aristarchus of Samos, the ancient
Copernicus; a history of Greek astronomy to Aristarchus, together with
Aristarchus's Treatise on the sizes and distances of the sun and moon
CHRONOLOGY.
(Approximate where precise data are not known,)
B.C.
624-547. Thales
610-546. Anaximander.
585-326 Anaximenes.
572-497. Pythagoras.
516-540. Parmenides.
500-428. Anaxagoras.
494-434. Empedocles.
5th century : Oenopides of
Chios. Philolaus.
427-347. Plato
408-355. Eudoxus.
388-315. Heraclides of
Pontus.
384-322. Aristotle.
370-300. Callippus.
310-230. Aristarchus of Samos.
387-212. Archimedes.
284-203. Eratosthenes.
265-190. Apollonius of Perga.
3rd century : Aratus.
Fl. 150 Hipparchus.
135-51. Posidonius.
A.D.
50-125. Plutarch.
100-178. Ptolemy.
|