READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
THE ASSYRIAN EMPIRE. TABLE OF CONTENTSCHAPTER XXIV
THE GROWTH OF THE GREEK CITY-STATEI.
THE EARLIEST ORDER
THROUGHOUT the whole Greek world surveyed in the preceding
chapters, the salient feature is the city-state. Where this characteristic
institution arose, intense and continuous political and social life matured the
genius of the race. To Athenians of the fifth and fourth centuries, life not in
cities was half way to barbarism, and the republican city-state seemed to
belong to the order of nature. Aristotle, defending the city-state as
‘natural,’ argued that man, being a ‘political animal,’ naturally formed
unions, each including its predecessor—the household, the village, the city.
But so many Greeks failed for so long to discover this invincible necessity of
their nature and omitted to complete the Aristotelian progression, that it
seems truer to say that a variety of causes, economic, geographical, military
and social, brought them to dwell in cities, and that it was life in the polis that made of the Greek a political
animal. To discover and evaluate these causes involves a somewhat hazardous
process of reconstruction, for the growth of the city-state was, in the main,
completed before the full light of history, and when it occurs later, as in the
formation of the Arcadian Megalopolis, it is not permissible to assume that the
conditions were the same as in earlier times. In the absence of record we must
rely, as best we can, on the evidence of excavations, of names and language,
and of the institutions of the city-states in their historical form, while some
help may be gained from the analogy of primitive peoples like the Germans and
of other city communities such as arose in Phoenicia and Italy.
In the period which preceded the Trojan wars, the
mainland of Greece was occupied or dominated by people to whom may be applied, for convenience, the name Achaean. These were not originally
dwellers in cities; they are not called after the names of cities; their names
are those of peoples and of tribes. The bond which unites them is the bond of
tribal membership, and the stage from which they begin to develop is that of
the Tribal State. They acknowledge the rule of kings or leaders and each head
of a household is the ruler of his family. Between the paterfamilias and the head of the tribe lies one intermediate institution, the
brotherhood—the phratry. This is in origin a voluntary association of
comrades in war, but, as the tribes settle down, the association, from being at
first fortuitous, becomes local and at the same time hereditary. The ‘clan’,
the genos, which is the reflection of aristocracy, is as yet in the future.
Each of the three associations of family, phratry and tribe was strengthened by
the religious bond of cult. The tribe felt itself united in the worship of its
god and, even in much later times when it had become only a convenient piece of
mechanism in the city-state, the tribe stood before the gods, united in
worship. The phratry might look up to Zeus Phratrios, and Zeus of the Hearth
guarded the religious centre of the household. These three simple loyalties
suffice; the tribe needs no capital city, the place where the king worships the
god of the tribe is enough of a meeting-place in moments of emergency or at
times of festival.
It may be assumed that the tribesmen did not live in
isolated homesteads but, as by instinct, in villages which were not, in any
formal sense, political units. Of the early sites excavated in Thessaly two,
Sesklo and Dimini, were little towns with stone walls, the remainder were not
fortified except possibly with stockades which have long since perished. In the
rest of Greece, except in Phocis, the settlements lie near strongholds, which
from being places of safety were to become seats of government. Wealth and
labour were needed to build stone fortifications, and petty villages had no
defence except flight. The security of their most valued possessions, their
flocks and herds, demanded some permanent place of refuge from raids by land
and sea, by kinsmen or aliens. These ancient asyla continued in use far into
historical times, where conditions remained like those of the tribal state.
When Philip V of Macedon led a foray into Elis in 218 BC, he captured many head
of cattle in such a refuge. This phenomenon, the result of recurrent needs, is
not peculiar to the Greeks or to antiquity. Refugia existed on the west coast of
Scotland and in the territory of the Saxon tribes in Germany down to the time
of Charlemagne, and it is reasonable to suppose that like causes among peoples
at a like stage of culture produced like results.
This common place of refuge was a natural place for
the king to live, not at first within it, as the space was needed for flocks
and fugitives, but near by. So at Goulas in Boeotia there has been found a
fortress with walls three-quarters of a mile round, and against the north wall
a palace. At Tiryns, besides the upper fortress-palace, there was a lower
citadel which was left uninhabited. Many of these refuges trusted to their
position alone, others were no doubt roughly fortified with palisades, so that
no traces of their use remain. With the stage when the ruler lives by the place
of refuge we reach the beginnings of a local centre for the tribal state. But
in parts of Greece where Minoan culture sophisticated the Achaeans and the
example of the East was known, what may have been a refuge with a king’s
dwelling by it became a fortified citadel-palace as at Mycenae or at Tiryns.
Such a stronghold is what was first called a polis. At its foot clustered the
houses of the king’s dependants, the ministers of his government or his pomp,
and peasants or serfs who tilled the lands that stretched around it. At Mycenae
in the times of the great Tholos Dynasty there were houses within the citadel
for the officers of the king, and the size of the cemeteries below suggests a
considerable population at the foot of the fortress hill.
This collection of dwellings below the citadel is what
the Greeks called Asty (acmi). In the Homeric poems conventional epithets still
mark a distinction between Asty and Polis. The Asty is simply ‘big’ or
‘famous’, and once a passage which may well be later than the rest
‘wide-spaced’. The epithets of splendour and strength and wealth—well-built,
towering, well-walled, high-gated, towered, holy, rich, full of gold, full of
bronze—are reserved for the Polis. In the sixth book of the Iliad Hecuba
collects the old women in the Asty and thence goes up to the ‘high city’. Here
and there, as is natural, the archaism fails and the words
are used interchangeably, and in one passage comes in the word acropolis
meaning, it would seem, a citadel. But the old meaning of polis died hard. In
426 BC the Peloponnesian commander Eurylochus could not force the Hyaei, a
branch of the western Locrians, to give him hostages until he had reduced a
village which bore the name Polis. At Athens until the fourth century the word
was officially used for the Acropolis, asty for the city in which men lived. At
Ialysus in Rhodes the old citadel was called polis as late as the third
century.
We may then assume that in parts of Greece, as early
as the Heroic Age, there was the word polls and the
conjunction of palace-citadel and open settlement. But such a combination— ‘the
rich man in his castle, the poor man at his gate’—was far from being the
city-state, the intensely alive and all-absorbing centre of political and civic
life. The king counted for too much, the common people for too little. But the
idea of a fixed political centre had come and come to stay.
Such was the legacy of the first stage, the time of
the splendour and power of Mycenae, which ended with what has been well called
the Viking Age of Greece. The overseas expeditions of the Achaean princes
culminated in the great adventure of the Trojan war.
And then the plundering bands became bands of refugees as successive shocks of
invasion broke up the Mycenaean order. Dorians and the north-western peoples
who came with them and after them destroyed the old monarchies, burned Mycenae
and the other centres of Mycenaean power and civilization and proceeded to
settle down. They seized on the good land, assigned demesnes (temene) to their
kings and their gods, and divided the rest of the soil democratically into lots
(kleroip Attica remained secure from the invasion and there the development
from Mycenaean times was continuous, while Arcadia afforded a refuge for pre-Dorians
of the Peloponnese. But elsewhere in Greece, from Thessaly southwards, the old
order disappeared, and the process of political growth from the tribal state
began anew.
II.
THE GROWTH OF THE NEW GREEK CITIES
For a time, in most of Greece, political development
towards a city-state was arrested. But if the invaders were not city-states
themselves, they were the cause of city-states in others. For the successive
shocks of their coming drove the pre-Dorians overseas, no longer to plunder and
return in triumph, but to find new homes. The Aeolians and Ionians, to
anticipate a conscious differentiation, go out in bands to settle where they
have not the moral support of contiguous kinsmen. These settiers are linked
together not by the easy relationship of the tribe but by the fact of a common
adventure. They have to face the opposition of the peoples of the hinterland
where they find their new homes, and their settlements are strung along the
coast of Asia Minor or dotted in the islands, not, at first, in deserted places
but where there were already inhabited sites. At least the Greek traditions of
settlement in Asia Minor at this stage are uniform in describing it as the
occupation of known existing places. And excavations show that in the islands
of the Cyclades the inhabitants had lived for centuries in little walled towns.
The newcomers cannot spread out, but must concentrate generally within or
within reach of walls. One settlement is called the New Fort (Neon teichos), the harbour town of Colophon is called the South Fort
(Notion teichos) as the early settlements of the East India Company are called
Fort St George and the like. Possibly the colonists remembered the places of
refuge and now they are always refugees. Erythrae for example spread from a fortified
hill, and Strabo describes how, about 700 BC, Miletus consisted of an Acropolis
and the original settlement half a mile away. The open villages in which the
non-Greek peoples of Asia Minor were accustomed to live were left to the
natives who were dependent, often serfs.
Besides the pressure of danger from men there was the
need to exploit natural advantages or to evade problems of navigation. A good
or conveniently-placed harbour, a good water-supply, a position on an isthmus
which may spare traders a long or dangerous sea-voyage, the outlet of some good
trade route all led to a clustering market1. Freed from retarding traditions
these new communities had realized the idea of the city-state before the era of
secondary colonization in the eighth and seventh centuries. How quickly these
new conditions had their effect may be seen in Crete when Dorian invaders
passed on to occupy it. The same stock, which, settled in Greece, was
comparatively slow to develop cities, found in Crete an island already dotted
with towns. The Minoan glory was departed; there were no centralized Minoan
princedoms, but the Dorians like the earlier invaders of Crete quickly became
divided into separate city-states until Crete possessed over forty cities and
was credited with a hundred. The Dorian cities here clung firmly to their unity
of birth as Dorians but politically they were fissiparous.
In Greece proper the process was slower, the causes
more complex. By the year 600 there were city-states in Thessaly, Boeotia,
Phocis, Locris, Euboea, the Argolid, possibly in
Achaea, besides Corinth and her western neighbours and the city-state par
excellence Athens. Sparta, which in so many respects stands outside the
political development of Greece, is hardly a city-state, but rather a tribal
state compacted by pride and danger. As late as the fifth century Thucydides
could write of Lacedaemon ‘for it was no union in a city but a life in villages
in the old Greek manner.’ In Arcadia it is doubtful if Tegea and Heraea were city-states
before the sixth century, Mantinea before the fifth, and it was not till then
that the Eleans made a city called Elis. The western Locrians and Acarnanians
were in transition to the city-state at the time of the Peloponnesian War.
Throughout the north-west, apart from colonies founded as cities, the
Greekspeaking people are village-dwellers. The ‘ancient life in villages’ was
the life of perhaps half the Greeks of the mainland in the early Classical
period.
This is not to say that these remained untouched by
political development. Where the people lived in villages there arose what may
be called ‘canton-units,’ as the tribes split up into sub-tribes each master in
its own glen. This led to varying degrees of independence. Separate action by
the several communes is far from unusual. The sanction of a
pact made by ‘the Eleans’ is directed against ‘any freeman or magistrate or
commune’ who may deface it. Where the complex influences which produced
the city-state were not active, these parts of Greece remained almost devoid of
political life, rallying to make or repel raids, otherwise quiescent, while
elsewhere the tiny city republics pursued high policy and produced literature
and art and thought for the whole race.
The ‘conquest’ communities in the Peloponnese show a
variation from the Eleans of the north-west who remain in villages or districts
called damoi to the Dorians of the north-east who are split up into cantons
each dominated by a single city-state. Between these lies the Spartan state
which is concentrated into a kind of standing camp in Hollow Lacedaemon. The
primary cause of concentration, whether in city or in camp, was the fact that
these Dorian conquerors took the best land and planted in each area a strong
point no doubt fortified by the inherited skill of the people whose forefathers
had laboured on the citadels of Mycenaean kings and barons. Round these strong
points stretched the land cultivated by serfs for whom the conquerors found
contemptuous names, ‘dusty foot,’ ‘sheepskin-wearers,’ ‘club-bearers.’ In some communities at least, the hill
country was left to nonDorians who lived in political dependence and slowly
acquired political privilege, possibly because they were needed for war. Thus a
distinction between town and country was sharply established. It may be too
that in these parts of Greece where the Mycenaean power was most centralized
the conquerors had taken example from the strongholds which they had destroyed.
That they did not occupy the chief sites may be due to the fact that places
like Mycenae were not near enough to the plain; perhaps, also, the newcomers
felt a parvenu’s uneasiness before the memory of the splendour which they had
ruined.
Next to Argos, which controlled the largest plain of
the northeastern Peloponnese, the most important city was Corinth. The rise of
Corinth was, most likely, due to trade; Mycenae had controlled a network of
roads which now became less safe and ran through little states which might levy
tolls on travellers. So it was wiser to take to the paths of the sea, and trade
now ran up the Saronic gulf and gave to Corinth the
double advantage of lying on routes north and south, as well as east and west.
Corinthian commerce may well have been served by the jealousy which led Argos
to destroy the port of Nauplia, though Epidaurus must have inherited some of
the trade which Nauplia had lost. The states on the Saronic gulf,
despite their concentric Amphictyony, must have been politically educated by their
trade with the more advanced cities of Asia Minor.
To like economic causes may be attributed the rise of
the two chief cities in Euboea, Chaicis and Eretria, aided by the fact that
their prosperity depended in part on metal-working which concentrated the
population. In Thessaly there had been some fortified towns, and cities like
Crannon and Larissa became the centres of aristocratic dynasties. But the wide
plain of Thessaly, which put the serfs at the mercy of their mounted
conquerors, prevented the need and probably the desire for such a concentration
as Sparta. Nor did new political ideas easily penetrate into Thessaly, which
was shielded by mountains and a rock-bound coast from the invasion of political
progress. In Central Greece we may attribute more importance to the existence
of Mycenaean-poleis. In Locris, Phocis and Boeotia there was no sharp division
into conquerors and conquered, and such cities and
communities as arose seem to have owed their existence to the occupation of
earlier sites rather than to the causes which were most powerful in the
Peloponnese. Locris came to be dominated by the one Locrian community which
succeeded in developing a true political state, the city of Opus. Boeotia, even
after the fertile plain was diminished by the disastrous extension of the
Copaic Lake was an area which seemed to invite union under a single great city.
But the rising power of Thebes in the south was faced by the tenacious
resistance of the declining state of Orchomenus in the north, and for centuries
the Boeotians refused to pass beyond federation to a closer unity.
The fortune of Attica was otherwise. Here the
development from Mycenaean times was continuous, the
population was in the main homogeneous. Athens itself was singled out for
greatness both as an old Mycenaean polis and as lying at the base of a fan of
roads near the best harbour of the Saronic gulf with a
fertile plain behind it. The view that Attica was a political unity
continuously from Mycenaean times is made unlikely by evidence of the
fortification of separate communities, of a primitive wall which protected the
plain of Athens from the plain of Eleusis, and of traditions which speak of
political individualism within Attica itself. But the natural divisions of
Attica are not so marked as to make separatism permanent, or to counteract the
centripetal influence of Athens reinforced perhaps by a precocious political
instinct. The unification of Attica did not however take the form of the
concentration in Athens itself of the bulk of the population, though no doubt
the nobles would come to have their town houses at the place of central
government. The union of Attica was rather the extension of an idea than the
concentration of a people, and is more strictly described by the Greek word
sympoliteia, the sharing of citizenship.
Here and there village communities by a deliberate act
abandoned their villages and set up house together. This process is
synoikismos in the narrower sense. It is seen at work in the plain of eastern
Arcadia which was occupied by two groups of rural communities each
possessing its place of refuge, called in the northern group Polis, in the
southern group ‘the fort’. The southern group, probably through fear of Spartan
aggression, joined together and made the city-state of Tegea, and, later on,
the northern made the city-state of Mantinea. The reason for the synoikismos of
Mantinea may have been fear of the military power of her southern neighbour
reinforced by the desire to control the water-supply of the northern plain. In
the same way the Heraeans were impelled by the growing aggressiveness of the
Eleans to form the city-state of Heraea. The mere proximity of city-states no
doubt inspired village communities to imitation, and the impulse to the
formation of city-states in northwest Greece seems to have proceeded from the
presence of a fringe of Corinthian city-state colonies.
Besides the attractions of trade and the fears of
conquerors, social causes helped to advance and to mould the growing polis. The
development of justice is the shadow of the development of the city-state. On
the Shield of Achilles in the Iliad is depicted in a famous scene the lawsuit
in the market-place, where justice is not administered by the king, but by a
group of elders. In fact justice had ceased to be the divine prerogative of the
sceptred king. It was no longer a revelation or interpretation of the will of
Heaven to which the king alone had access. It was something more
mundane—arbitration. When two peasants could not agree they appealed, not to
Heaven, but to the judgment of a Solomon, and the Solomon might be some old
noble whose shrewdness could detect the surest way of justice just as well as
some warlike king. But not all judges were just and not all suitors were
satisfied: Hesiod’s ‘gift-devouring’ kings, who give crooked judgments, are the
nobles of Boeotia.
With the economic elevation of the nobles and the
economic depression of the commons, which marked the eighth and seventh
centuries, justice became more the exhibition of power than the guarantee of
fair dealing. Thereupon arose the demand for the
formulation of justice in a code of laws, and the second half of the seventh
century and the beginning of the sixth was the age of lawgivers. This is not
only so in states where we know the name of some great lawgiver. At Chios about
the year 600 are found institutions which presuppose a code of laws, though
there is no record of any great Chian lawgiver. The administration of justice
now becomes much more a state matter, and it is concentrated where the
government of the state resides. The desire for stabilization, reflected in
the agreements between states limiting the practice of reprisals, helps to
promote the city-state. It may, indeed, be said that the sovereign idea of the
city-state is the idea of law, something permanent which transcends the will of
the people or the governors at any given moment. Even under tyrants the law
persists, and the earlier tyrants are usurpers of executive government, but respecters
of civil law. The lawlessness which Greek theorists attributed to all tyrants
is a reflection rather of the later military tyranny than of the earlier
usurpations.
A second cause which promoted the growth of
city-states was a change of military methods. Warfare had been the fighting of
chiefs in which the common people counted for little, till the seventh century
when the aristocratic cavalry had been supplanted by the citizen phalanx of
hoplites. The Euboeans at the time of the Lelantine war fight in this way, and
later, in the closing decades of the seventh century, the Spartans become
virtuosi in the new art of war and develop the tactical flexibility which was
to make them invincible for so long. The old kind of fighting was well enough
managed where the country was inhabited in villages. The noblemen came from
their castles and constituted the real fighting force. But first chariots and
then cavalry went out of fashion and the knights became mounted infantry. The
new method of fighting, the fighting of the middle classes, spearmen acting
together, made for unity if only because of the importance of practising
together. Uniformity in arms and uniformity in tactics assisted the movement
towards the centralized city-state.
III.
THE CHARACTER OF THE CITY-STATE
Thus in Greece proper there grew up many cities and,
in the days before the growth of democracy, indeed in the days before tyranny,
the city-state had already become a conscious social unity. That this was so is
suggested by the character of Greek codes of law, which seek to regulate so
much in the private life of the citizens. For the Greek codes not only mark the
supplanting of self-help by the authority of the state, and the triumph of state interests over the instinctive rights of family and
clan units, but also impose on citizens all manner of rules of conduct. The
laws were meticulous in prescribing for the citizens, regulating, for example,
expense at funerals and the dress of women; not because an obvious interest of
the state was endangered, but because the state was the people and crystallized
public sentiment.
A result of this social consciousness was to prevent
the state from remaining inclusive. When once a state reached a certain size,
its tendency was to become, like a club, unwilling to admit new members, until
birth in the city-state became as exclusive as birth in the tribe had been, or
more exclusive. In the heroic age strangers moved about freely, and later the
mixture of peoples in overseas settlements destroyed the sense of tribal
exclusiveness. In some Peloponnesian cities, besides the three purely Dorian
tribes, we find non-Dorians grouped in a tribe of their own. But presently arose a movement towards exclusiveness, except where
enlightened lawgivers, such as Solon, realized its economic disadvantages.
Equally within the state the idea of caste was strengthened by the defining of
political privilege where before there had been only superior influence.
Such civic exclusiveness was not inconsistent with
practices of hospitality to non-citizens, especially to the helpless who might
invoke the powerful aid of Zeus Xenios the patron god of strangers. In the
Milesian colonies on the Black Sea the shipwrecked alien was received by the
state and dismissed, like Odysseus, with gifts to help him on his way. Social
exclusiveness admitted temporary exceptions. In Crete at the public meals two
tables were set for foreigners who were served before the magistrates
themselves. At the very time when the Athenian democracy had hedged its
citizenship about by barriers of birth, Sophocles and Euripides glorified the
ancient hospitality of Athens which sheltered against powerful neighbours the
suppliant who sought her protection. But city-states as a rule refused to
non-citizens the rights to hold land, to marry into the citizen body or to join
such religious unions as sanctified membership of the state.
This last restriction follows naturally upon the
conception of the city as a social unity. For perhaps the most vivid social
sense of the Greeks was religion. ‘Greek religion permeated every action or
relation of the individual towards other members of society.’ In the tribal
state the common cults of tribe, phratry or family had bound men together. And
a like bond came to link together the members of the city-state. It was not for
nothing that Athens was the city of Athena and Apollonia the city of Apollo.
While one tendency in Greek religion was Pan-Hellenic, another was towards the
separate highly self-conscious city-state. The older Amphictyonies, with their
religious centre at a shrine, are an anticipation of the narrower union under
the protection of the chief god or goddess of a city. All Greeks might meet at
Olympia or at Delphi, but, besides that bond, there was the closer feeling for
Athena at Athens, and Hera at Argos. The Greeks conceived of their gods
politically. Olympus itself was no anarchy but a society, and Zeus is the king
of gods. And the city as well as the tribe and phratry might be under his care.
There is not only Zeus Phratrios but Zeus Polieus, and in the market at Athens
stood Zeus Agoraios the god of the meeting-place. A city might gather at some
notable cult-centre and, once the city began to form-, its growth was under the
care of the god or hero of the place. The colonies often set up the worship of
their oecist (the leader of their first settlement) so as to have a cult which was
peculiarly theirs.
This social and religious sense of union had a
reaction which goes far to explain why there were so many city-states in Greece
proper and the islands. States took on a kind of personality, and the more
highly developed and the more self-conscious they became, the less they were
willing to make even the partial sacrifice of this personality implied in
federalism. It is significant that in later times federalism was mainly the achievement of the intellectually more backward
communities, like the Achaeans and Aetolians. Each city-state claimed from its
neighbours the full recognition of its freedom and autonomy, its right to
manage its own affairs as it would. And this claim was not only fiercely held
but in point of fact readily admitted. For the city-state, while intolerant of
any division of authority within its borders, was tolerant of its neighbour’s
independence. The will to defend exceeded the will to attack. In fact the
instinct of territorial expansion, the imperialism which dominated the Empires
of the East, was singularly weak among the Greek city-states. The Greeks lacked
the sense of the political significance of territorial extent. The more
conscious they became of the social unity of their state and religion the less
they desired expansion, for expansion meant relaxing the intensity of their
common life. They were prepared to dominate their neighbours but not to absorb
them, still less to surrender their individuality in a larger union.
The demands of a system, the need for land, turned
Lacedaemon into a territorial state but, outside Sparta, Attica is the only
part of Greece where any considerable territory was guided constantly by a
single will. Compared with the thousand square miles of Attica, the territory
controlled by any other Greek city-state was very small. The Boeotian cities
apart from Thebes govern on an average about 70 square miles, Sicyon 140,
Phlius 70, Corinth 350, the eight cities of Euboea on an average 180, even
islands with a single city like Chios little more than 300, and this island is
the greatest. In Ceos, which is less than half the size of the county of
Rutland, there were, in the sixth century, four independent cities and three
independent currencies. The stage on which the drama of Greek high politics was
played was small indeed. Servius Sulpicius writes to Cicero ‘As I returned from
Asia and sailed from Aegina to Megara, I began to view the lands which lay
around me. Behind me I could see Aegina, before me Megara, on my right the Piraeus,
on my left, Corinth.’ By this limitation of the area which each controlled, the
Greek cities escaped many of the problems which perplex the territorial state,
and political life, concentrated within these bounds, quickly matured and
quickly exhausted the political capacity of the race.
IV.
ARISTOCRACY
The period which witnessed the growth of the
city-state witnessed too the decline of kingship. The Homeric poems were
written for nobles; the Heroic age was seen across an interspace of adventure
in which the nobles had played the leading part, and what is presented to us is
a dissolving view of monarchy. The archaism of the Epic is not everywhere
complete, and in the Sixth Book of the Odyssey the curtain seems to be lifted
and to disclose the new settlement where the king has at his side a formal
established aristocratic government. Nausithous had led his people harried by
the Cyclopes
And moved and settled them in Scheria’s isle
Aloof from all oppressors; round their town
He raised a wall and built their homes, and reared
Shrines to their gods and meted out the fields.
And there side by side with the material splendour of
the old order is found the social structure of the new. There is a council of
twelve nobles to advise the King Alcinous, Nausithous’ son. There is the public
place of assembly where the Phaeacians gather, but not to vote; they gather to
see the stranger Odysseus.
In Ithaca we have monarchy without the king; the royal
birth of Telemachus, Odysseus’ son, is a claim to rule but a claim which may be
set aside. Laertes the father of Odysseus has long become a country gentleman
powerless and hardly respected. When Odysseus himself returns he must prove his
kingship by deeds, not merely proclaim it. But in Scheria is order; it is the
foreshadowing of the aristocratic state, and the king, as at Ephesus or
Erythrae, belongs to the line of the oecist or creator of the settlement. The
nobles are not the king’s deputies any more than are the nobles who judge the
suit in the scene on the Shield of Achilles. The king was not
the fountain of honour, nor were the cause of monarchy and that of
aristocracy necessarily one. The king was no more than an eminent noble among
nobles equally well born, nor did the early kings detect the secret of empire
and base their power on the goodwill of the commons. That secret was reserved
for some of the tyrants after the power of the commons had shown itself. The
ancient Greek monarchy had no depth of earth, and the nobles sprang up and
choked it. The aristocracy, while it pulled down the king, did not raise up the commons but took into its strong hands the
government of the city-state and devoted to the task the ordering genius of its
race.
Thus the constitutional frame in which the city-state
was built was aristocracy. With settled life personal leadership had given
place to the steady influence of a class. Overseas this class was sometimes the
original settlers who kept political power in their own hands. In Greece proper
long-established wealth or pride of birth, displayed in the keeping of horses
or the membership of aristocratic clans, had shown itself too in the service of
the state. As the king had dwindled, so the old assembly of freemen disappeared
or counted for little. The state was the possession of those who had the
freedom to serve it. The chief organ of government was the Council, which was
either an inner ring of nobles or the whole body of privileged citizens. This
body which had succeeded to monarchy is imposing in its unity. Those whose ambition
made them unwilling to fit into the ordered scheme of city life might go out
and make new cities.
The nobles did not live in parochial leisure but
learned to be colleagues in the Council chamber. The magistrates were usually
subordinate to them, for membership of the Council was generally for life and
its steady influence controlled the state, while within its ranks was gathered
experience in an age which lived by inherited wisdom. There are few outstanding
figures in early Greek history. This is not only because of the lack of record.
It was because the city-state, so long as no new forces rose to disturb it,
could dispense with great men who did not fit its ordered scheme of things. The
state was greater than its rulers. Kingship either became a
magistracy among others or remained, in the shadow of this imposing
aristocracy, an embarrassed phantom haunting the altars of the gods, reduced,
in the phrase of Aristotle, ‘to the conduct of the traditional sacrifices.’ At
Miletus, in a copy of an inscription first set up not later than in the sixth
century, appears the clause ‘At these sacrifices the King is present but
receives no more than the other Singers of the Guild’.
The essence of the Greek state is that it is the state
of a class; ‘the constitution is the governing class,’ and the state is within
a ring-fence. That is the legacy of aristocracy. Oligarchy extended membership
of the class to wealth as well as to good birth, democracy to race, but even
the extremest democracy excluded aliens and women and was jealous of granting
citizenship. Where the defence of the city was, above all, the work of the
hoplites, political privilege could hardly be denied to those who were the
state in arms. Thus beside the Council there might arise, in larger states, an assembly
of the hoplite class, and the franchise might be wide enough to give stability
and the possibility of political development. But in many states, as new
economic stresses broke down the easy order of more primitive times, the
governing class was tempted to use its political and legal power to exploit the
rest of the community. And where this happened Nemesis followed, and
aristocracy yielded or was broken. Tyrants arose, sometimes suspicious of
concentrated urban life, and the shocks of revolution from time to time shifted
the balance of political power, but the city-state outlasted change. Its main
lines had been drawn too firmly and clearly to be erased, and the history of
Greece in the classical period will show how new needs and new ideas were adapted
and limited within the frame in which Greek political life had been set in the
age of aristocracies.
|
CAMBRIDGE ANCIENT HISTORY. EDITED BY J. B. BURY - S. A. COOK - F. E. ADCOCK : VOLUME III |