ATHENS . 478—401 B.C.
CHAPTER IV
THE PERICLEAN DEMOCRACY
I
EPHIALTES’
REFORM OF THE AREOPAGUS
IT would appear that no
measures of constitutional reform are to be attributed to the period between
the invasion of Xerxes and the ostracism of Cimon. There are indeed two changes
of great importance which are assigned to this epoch, the one by Aristotle and
the other by Plutarch. It is asserted by Aristotle that the patriotism of the
Areopagus in the crisis of the evacuation of Athens in 480 b.c. secured for it the revival
of its old ascendancy in the state, and that the supremacy thus restored
continued for some seventeen years until the fall of Cimon from power. On the
other hand, it is asserted by Plutarch that Aristides, in recognition of the
services rendered by Athenians of every rank and grade in the repulse of the
Persians, threw open the archonship, apparently in 479 or 478 b.c., to all four of the Solonian Classes.
There are good grounds for regarding both these statements as mere inventions.
It is not until we come to the fall and ostracism of Cimon that we enter on a
further stage in the development of the democracy.
The measure which comes
first in point of date, if not of importance, is Ephialtes’ Reform of the
Areopagus. That, under the provisions of his law, the Areopagus was deprived of
all its powers except its jurisdiction in cases of homicide, and that the
powers of which it was deprived were divided between the Council, the Assembly,
and the popular courts of law, may be regarded as certain. But what these
powers were, other than the guardianship of the laws, is quite uncertain. It is
probable that by the ‘guardianship of the laws’ we are to understand, not the
right of vetoing any proposed alteration of the law, but merely the right of
compelling the magistrates to conform to the laws in the administration of
their office. It is more than likely that the importance of the measure lay,
not so much in its practical results, as in the assertion of a principle. The
principle involved was none other than that of the Sovereignty of the People.
If sovereignty were vested in the people, it seemed to follow that the will of
the people, as expressed either in the Assembly or in the law-courts, must be
final. The right of either directly overruling the decisions of the people, or
indirectly interfering with their execution, could be conceded to no other body
in the state. If the guardianship of the laws is to be interpreted as the right
of veto, it meant that the Areopagus could directly overrule the decisions of
the Assembly and the law-courts; but even if it meant nothing more than the
right of compelling the magistrates to conform to the laws, it gave the
opportunity for indirect interference with the popular will. The constitution
too of the Areopagus can have been hardly less offensive to democratic
sentiment; for the members of the Areopagus were appointed indirectly, and they
held office for life. The archons, it is true, were appointed by sortition in
conformity with democratic principles, but they entered automatically into the
Council of the Areopagus at the end of their term of office, and hence over
their appointment as Areopagites the people had no direct control. In the
democracy of the fifth century no other office could be held for more than a
year; even a strategos autocrator,
such as Pericles, had to be annually re-elected. The Areopagite alone held
office for life.
Whatever may have been the
importance of the Reform in its practical results, there can be no question of
its importance as the assertion of a principle. By the Athenians themselves it
was always regarded as the turning-point in the history of their constitution.
It was the first of a series of reforms which changed the moderate constitution
of the epoch of the Persian Wars into the extreme democracy of the
Peloponnesian War. The virtual disestablishment of this venerable Council must
have come at the time as a severe shock to a great body of religious sentiment
at Athens, and it is not unlikely that in this religious sentiment we are to
find the explanation of the hold which the Areopagus seems to have retained on
the Athenian mind for more than a century after the reform of Ephialtes. Not
only was Ephialtes’ measure repealed by the Thirty, but it was to the Areopagus
that Athens turned in its hour of need, alike after Aegospotami and Chaeronea.
It is probable that a substitute
for the guardianship of the laws hitherto exercised by the Council of the
Areopagus was provided by the institution of the Graphe Paranomon, one of the most characteristic
features of the Athenian State in the latter part of the fifth century. It is
remarkable that no hint is given in the Constitution of Athens as to the date
of its enactment, although it is referred to in the account of the Revolution
of the Four Hundred, by which time it had come to be regarded as the chief
constitutional safeguard of the democracy. It was an indictment for bringing
before the Assembly measures which were unconstitutional; i.e. in conflict with
the laws of the state. Although any Athenian citizen was at liberty to bring
forward a motion for a new law, or for the amendment of an old one, the
proposer was liable to be prosecuted on the ground that the proposed enactment
was inconsistent with the law, or contrary to the public interest. Even if the
proposal had become law, its author was still liable to prosecution under the Graphe Paranomon until the
expiration of a year from the passing of the measure.
II.
ADMISSION
OF THE ZEUGITAE TO THE ARCHONSHIP
Ephialtes’ Reform of the
Areopagus was effected in the archonship of Conon (462—1 b.c.), probably after the ostracism of Cimon early in the year
461 b.c. The next measure of reform recorded by Aristotle belongs to the year of Mnesitheides, 457-6 b.c. The archonship, in common
with the more important magistracies, had hitherto been confined to the two
highest classes in the Solonian system, the Pentacosiomedimni and Knights. It was now thrown open to the third class, the Zeugitae.
From a passage in the Constitution of Athens it would appear that the
disability of the lowest class, the Thetes, was never
formally removed, although in practice the disqualification was evaded by a
legal fiction. It may well be, however, that the legal fiction belongs to the
restored democracy of the fourth century b.c., and that the Thetes were
ineligible for this office, in practice as well as in theory, throughout the
fifth century. Once more it is probable that the reform was more important as
the assertion of a principle than in its practical effect. The introduction of
sortition in 487 b.c. had reduced the archonship to a magistracy with purely routine duties. So far
as the conduct of the business of the state was concerned, it mattered little
who held this office; but in virtue of the old associations which gathered
round its name, the archonship must still have made some appeal to the
imagination, and it had thus become a position of dignity such as was admirably
calculated to reward the modest ambition of the humbler class of citizens. The
principle, however, which was asserted by the reform, that of the equal
eligibility of all, was fundamental in the ancient conception of democracy.
III.
PAYMENT
FOR THE JURORS AND THE RESTRICTION OF THE FRANCHISE
The next change in the
constitution to which we come is of a very different character. It is possibly
the most far-reaching of all the reforms of this period in its effect on the
working of the constitution. In the fully developed democracy there is no
feature more characteristic than the system of payment for service. It meant
the assertion of the principle of equal opportunity for all, and in its
practical effect it enabled even the poorest members of the citizen body to
take part in the work of administration, in a degree, and to an extent, that is
well-nigh inconceivable to those who are familiar with democracy only in its
modern forms. The first step in the introduction of this system was taken by
Pericles himself, when he introduced payment for the dicasts, or jurors. The
precise date of this measure, and the original amount of the payment, are both
uncertain. The only indication of date is afforded by the statement of
Aristotle that the measure was brought forward by Pericles as a bid for popular favour, and in order to counterbalance the wealth of
Cimon. This would point to a period when Pericles had succeeded to the
leadership of the popular party, and Cimon was still the leader on the other
side. The date, therefore, cannot be before the ostracism of Cimon, for Ephialtes,
not Pericles, was then the leader of the popular party; and it cannot be during
the exile of Cimon, for Aristotle’s statement implies his presence at Athens.
It must, therefore, fall between his return from exile, which happened probably
in 451 b.c., and his sailing for Cyprus in 450 b.c. It will
be seen that the question of date is of some importance in its bearing on the
connection between this reform and another measure attributed to Pericles, that
of the restriction of the franchise. In the period of the Archidamian War (431-21 b.c.) the jurors were paid at the rate of
three obols, or half a drachma, a day, but there is some evidence that the fee
was originally fixed at two obols, and that it was raised to three obols by
Cleon in 425 B.C.
The last of the reforms
enumerated by Aristotle is the law of Pericles, passed in the archonship of Antidotus (451—50 b.c.) which confined the franchise to those of citizen birth on
both sides. From two other references to this measure it may be inferred that,
although the law was passed in 451—50 b.c., it was not carried into effect until half-a-dozen years
later. In the year 445 b.c. an Egyptian pretender named Psammetichus sent a
present of 30,000 medimni (c. 45,000 bushels)
of corn, in order to secure the support of Athens. As a preliminary to the
distribution of the corn, the list of citizens was revised, and nearly 5000
names were struck off the register.
To those who are
unacquainted with the Greek conception of democracy it may seem a paradox that
the name of the most famous champion of the popular cause in the ancient world
should be associated with a measure which seems to the modern mind so
essentially undemocratic. It may at once be admitted that few measures of
constitutional reform at Athens have a better right to be called reactionary.
Cleisthenes had broken down the old barriers which excluded, not only the
resident alien, but the offspring of mixed marriages, from the franchise, and
the presence within the citizen body of a numerous class who were partly of
non-Athenian origin must have constituted a strong link of sentiment between
the sovereign people and its subject-allies. The repeal of the liberal
legislation of Cleisthenes, and the restriction of the franchise to those who
could prove Athenian parentage on both sides, meant the assertion of the
principle of privilege in its most offensive form. It proclaimed that the
Empire existed for the benefit of Athens. But, although the measure was reactionary,
it was not undemocratic in the ancient sense of the term. Democracy in the
modern world has had monarchy and the feudal system as its antecedents, and it
has meant the overthrow of privilege. Democracy in the ancient world had
oligarchy, not monarchy, as its predecessor, and it was a form of oligarchy
which had little in common with the feudalism of the Middle Ages. To the Greeks
democracy meant, not the overthrow of privilege, but merely the extension of
its area. To them it seemed that democracy was as much rooted in privilege as
oligarchy itself. It was the grounds on which privilege was based and the
number of the privileged that constituted the difference between the two forms
of government. Cleisthenes was a reformer born out of due time. The pretext for
the law of Pericles is stated to have been the excessive number of the
citizens; in other words, it was alleged that the citizen body had become
unmanageably large. It may be surmised, however, that the real motive of the
measure was to enhance the value of the lucrative privileges attaching to the
franchise, by limiting the number of those entitled to share in them. Hence it
is not difficult to trace an organic connection between the two measures of
reform of which Pericles was the author; the introduction of pay, and the
restriction of the franchise. It is a connection which becomes all the more
evident, if we are at liberty to assume that both these laws were passed within
the same twelve months, and that both were bids for popular favour in the strife of parties which had broken out afresh on Cimon’s return from
exile.
IV.
THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE
DEMOCRACY
There are two questions
that are suggested by Aristotle’s enumeration of the successive changes in the
constitution between the Persian and Peloponnesian Wars. It may be
asked whether Aristotle’s list of reforms is complete; it may also be asked how
far the development of the democracy was due to causes other than mere
legislative enactment.
To the first question
there can be but one answer; the list of changes is clearly incomplete. As has
been pointed out there is no mention of the Graphe Paranomon although its institution almost certainly
belongs to this period. The payment, again, of the jurors is the only form of
payment for public service which is mentioned by Aristotle in this passage; yet
in a preceding chapter he has himself enumerated the various other forms of
payment, both civil and military, which were in force at this epoch. We may
safely ascribe to the period of Pericles’ ascendancy the introduction of
payment for the members of the Council, who received a drachma a day, and for
all the magistrates, with the exception of the generals and the other military
officers. The number of these magistrates is put by Aristotle as high as 700.
To Pericles, too, there are probably to be ascribed two other forms of payment;
a payment of three obols a day for the soldiers and sailors on active service,
over and above the allowance for rations which they had previously enjoyed, and
a payment of two obols a day from the Theoric Fund to
the poorer classes for each of the three days of the performance of the plays
in the theatre. In regard to this latter measure it may be assumed that at this
period the system was confined to giving the poor citizen the price of his
theatre ticket. In the next century, however, the principle was established of
making large distributions of money from this source on the occasion of the
more important religious festivals, the whole surplus revenue of the year being
ultimately credited to this Fund, which thus became a most serious drain on the
financial resources of the State. It may be presumed that no such extended
application of the principle could have been anticipated by Pericles and his
contemporaries.
On the other hand, it
seems certain that payment for attendance at the meetings of the Assembly,
which is one of the most familiar features of the extreme democracy of the
fourth century b.c., found no place in the constitution of
the Periclean Age. A comparison between the Acharnians of Aristophanes (produced in 425 b.c.), in which it is implied that there was at times a difficulty in securing a
quorum, with two other of his plays, the Plutus and the Ecclesiazusae (both later than the restoration of the democracy in 403 b.c.), in which there are frequent references to this form of
payment, is sufficient to establish the fact. If further proof is needed, it
may be found in Aristotle’s statement that it was Agyrrhius,
a leading statesman in the early days of the restored democracy, who was
responsible for this further extension of the system of payment. The rate was
fixed in the first instance at one obol a day, and subsequently raised to
three.
Critics of the Athenian
democracy, both in ancient and in modern times, have not been slow to direct
their attacks against this system of payment for service. Plato, in a
well-known passage, brings against
Pericles the charge of having corrupted the Athenian character by the
introduction of pay. He had made the citizens, it is alleged, indolent,
cowardly, greedy of filthy lucre, and loquacious. To the ancients who had
watched the effects of the system when carried to its logical conclusion in
the course of the century after Pericles even so sweeping a condemnation might
seem not unwarranted, and the authority of Aristotle can be adduced in support
of Plato’s view. He asserts that the number of those maintained by the state in
the fifth century b.c. was not less than 20.000; i.e. one-third of the citizen body, if we accept
Eduard Meyer’s estimate of 60,000 for the total number of citizens, or one-half
of the whole, if we accept the alternative estimate of 40,000. He regards the
system of payment for service as a means of maintaining the poorer classes in
idleness; ‘a nation of salaried paupers’ seems to be implied in the passage. It
would be, however, in the highest degree uncritical to accept either
Aristotle’s figures or Plato’s verdict, as applying to the fifth century b.c. Any such
number as 20,000 can only be arrived at by including the sailors and soldiers
when engaged on active service. The jurors constituted the larger part of those
who received payment for other forms of service, and they appeared to have
been, as a rule, elderly or old. The conditions of life in ancient Athens were
so extraordinarily simple that for those who were past middle life, and whose
working days were at an end, the modest rate of pay that was offered might
serve as a sort of Old Age Pension. It is difficult to believe that it could
have appealed to the vigorous and young.
It would also be
uncritical to confuse the conditions of the Demosthenic age with those of the Periclean. In the fifth century b.c. the source from which
payment was provided was the tribute of the subject-allies; in the fourth
century b.c. Athens had no empire, and consequently no tribute. In the age of Pericles,
payment for the jurors, the members of the Council, and the magistrates,
imposed on the state a burden that could be borne, although it was inevitable
that, in the course of a war so protracted as the Peloponnesian, it should
become a burden that was felt. In the Athens of the fourth century b.c., with its payment for attendance at the
Assembly and its abuse of the Theoric Fund, and with
no source save the internal revenue from which the expenditure could be defrayed,
the effects of the system may well have been as demoralizing for the character
of the citizens as they were, beyond all question, for the finances of the
state. It may be assumed that when the system was introduced by Pericles it was
intended, not as a means of maintaining in idleness any class of the citizens,
but as the means, and the sole means, of enabling all classes of the citizens
alike to take their full share in the work of government. If government by the
people, in the strictest sense of the term, is an ideal that was attained more
completely in Periclean Athens than in any other society of which we have any
record, this was in some degree at least the result of the introduction of
payment for public service.
But even if Aristotle had
given us a complete enumeration of all the measures of reform which were placed
on the Statute Book in the second and third quarters of the fifth century b.c., the sum total of these measures would
have failed to explain the change from the constitution as it stood in the time
of Themistocles to the full blown democracy of the days of Cleon. The
explanation is to be sought, not merely in any list of legislative enactments,
but also in the change in the conditions, social, economic, and political, of
the Athenian State. It may be permissible to look for an analogy in the history
of that constitution which is as typical of modern, as the Athenian
constitution was of ancient, democracy. No changes of any importance, with the
exception of the Articles relating to the Abolition of Slavery, were effected
in the constitution of the United States during the first hundred years or
more of its existence; yet the whole character of the constitution was
profoundly modified in the course of the nineteenth century. When we reflect on
the extension of the area of the United States, and on the increase in its
population during this period; on the industrial revolution which had
transformed a society mainly agricultural into one in which the predominant
interests were commercial, manufacturing, and financial; on the influx of a
vast foreign population, and on the introduction of railways, steamships, and
telegraphs, we need not be surprised to find that, while the letter of the
constitution remained unaltered, the spirit in which it was worked was no
longer the same. Things have doubtless moved far more rapidly in the modern
world than they ever moved in the ancient, but movement there was at Athens in
the fifth century b.c., and the character of Athenian society,
and of the Athenian State, underwent modification in more respects than one in
the period that followed the Persian Wars.
V.
THE
RISE OF THE DEMAGOGUES
By far the most important
of the changes in the character of the Athenian constitution during this period
is to be found in the rise of the Demagogues. Hitherto it had been the rule
that the political leader should have held office as General, and this meant
that he must belong to one of the old families who had a tradition of military
skill and command. Shortly before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War a
leader of a new type appears on the scene. He is of humble origin (a tradesman
or a skilled mechanic), and he has never held office as General. As yet the
popular party had been content to find its leaders among the members of the old
families, just as in England after the first Reform Bill the Liberal Party was
content to find its leaders among the Whig peers. It was only to be expected
that a time would come when ‘the People’ would claim to be led by those who
were themselves men of the people. The first demagogue of any importance in the
constitutional history of Athens is Cleon, but it is commonly inferred from a
passage in Aristophanes that he had two predecessors, at least; Eucrates and Lysicles. From Cleon
to the Battle of Chaeronea the succession is unbroken. The contrast between the
new type of political leader and the old is thus twofold. In the first place,
there is the social contrast. Miltiades and Cimon, Xanthippus and Pericles, Thucydides, son of Melesias, and
Nicias, even Aristides and Ephialtes, all belonged to what may be called the
‘county families’. Themistocles is the one exception to this rule. The
demagogues were town-bred men, whose manners and mode of speech were alike
offensive to the aesthetic sense of well-bred Athenians. It is a common charge
against them that they were violent and unrestrained in gesture; and the fact
that in the Old Comedy they are twitted with foreign birth and a foreign accent
may possibly find an explanation in the vulgarity of their language and
pronunciation.
The second contrast lies
in the unofficial character of the demagogue. To Grote the demagogue is
‘essentially a leader of opposition’. He illustrates, for example, the
respective positions of Cleon and Nicias by the relations of the Leader of the
Opposition to the Prime Minister in the British Parliament. He even goes so
far as to excuse the part played by Cleophon in
securing the rejection of the terms of peace proposed by Sparta after the
battle of Cyzicus on the ground that ‘a mere opposition speaker like Cleophon did not look so far forward into the future as
Pericles would have done’. In short, the demagogue is, first and foremost, a
critic of measures, not a formulator of policy. Grote, who was much better
acquainted with our Parliamentary system than most of those scholars in other
countries who have either accepted his premisses or
attacked his conclusions, intended the comparison of the demagogue with the
Leader of the Opposition as a mere illustration; as an analogy that was not to
be pressed. What is fundamentally true in Grote’s view is that the demagogue
need not, and commonly did not, hold any office whatever. His legal position
differed in no respect from that of any other member of the Assembly.
That it was possible for
one who held no official position to ‘exercise,’ for all that, ‘by far the
greatest influence over the people’, as Cleon did at the time of the debate on
the fate of the Mytilenean prisoners, finds its
explanation in one of the most characteristic principles of the Athenian
constitution, the initiative of the individual. To critics of the constitution
it appeared one of its gravest defects that any individual citizen had the
right to put forward any proposal, however insane it might be. It is true that
no decree could be submitted to the people unless it had been sanctioned by the
Council, but the liberty of amendment allowed to the Assembly was so large as
to render this constitutional safeguard far less effective in practice than
had doubtless been intended. In no respect does the Athenian constitution
differ more profoundly, both from the Roman Republic, and from the modern
systems of Representative Government, than in this. At Rome the initiative lay
with the magistrate, while in a parliamentary system even the Private Member,
to say nothing of the individual citizen, has surrendered almost all his right
of initiative to the Cabinet. Hence no change in the letter of the constitution
was required to enable the new type of political leader to emerge. His
influence, however, extended far beyond that of the mere critic. Measures of
the first importance could be carried in the Assembly in direct opposition to
the advice of the Board of Generals, and if this happened no political crisis
was involved. Neither the Board as a whole, nor any individual General, was
called upon to resign. Consequently, the policy of Athens might be that of ‘the
Leader of the Opposition,’ rather than that of ‘the Cabinet.’
It was the rise of the
demagogues that first revealed one of the most fatal defects in the Athenian
system. There are few constitutions in history that have made more ample
provision for official responsibility. By the system of Euthynae every magistrate, civil or military, was called upon to render an account at
the end of his year of office, and prosecutions for peculation, or other
offences, on the part of the official were not infrequent. For political
responsibility, however, there was no such provision; indeed, the very theory
of political responsibility, i.e, of the responsibility
of the statesman for the policy which he advocates, was imperfectly apprehended
by the ancient mind. Thucydides, in one passage, seems to imply that in his
view the responsibility for the Sicilian Expedition lay with the Assembly which
had voted it, rather than with the speakers who had advised it. This defective
theory of responsibility mattered little as long as the political leader held
an office; for, so long as this was the case, the political responsibility was
merged in the official, and could be brought home to the statesman because he
was also a magistrate. Miltiades could be convicted for his failure in the
Parian Expedition, Cimon ostracized in consequence of his dismissal from Ithome, and Pericles himself brought to trial for the
disappointing results of his plan of campaign in the Peloponnesian War, because
each one of these was accountable for the execution of the policy which he had
himself proposed. But how could responsibility for a policy be brought home to
the orator who had proposed it, when its execution had necessarily to be
entrusted to others? It was inevitable that the statesman should contend that
his policy had failed, not because it was faulty in itself, but because the
soldiers, or the envoys, who were commissioned to carry it out had proved
incompetent or corrupt. To take a single example from the history of the
Peloponnesian War, the first Sicilian Expedition failed because it was bound to
fail under the existing conditions, but the penalty for failure was visited,
not on Hyperbolus and the other demagogues whose
scheme it was, but on the unfortunate generals, Pythodorus,
Sophocles, and Eurymedon, who were fined and exiled, after the Congress of Gela
in 424 b.c., because they had failed where failure
was inevitable.
The rise of the demagogues
was itself a symptom of a change in the economic conditions of Attica, which
affected the working of the constitution in more ways than one. Down to the
Persian Wars the landed interest was still predominant in the state, but in the
course of the next half century industry and commerce became serious rivals to
agriculture. The centre of gravity was shifting
steadily from the country to the town. If we include in our estimate the slave
as well as the free and the alien as well as the citizen, we may assume that at
the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War the larger part of the population was
resident in Athens and the Piraeus, although it is clear from a passage in
Thucydides that, if the citizens proper are alone taken into account, the
reverse of this would be true. He expressly says that the majority of the
Athenians down to the year 431 b.c. still
lived in the countryside. The plays of Aristophanes afford ample evidence, if
evidence were needed, that the country population was conservative in
instinct. It was natural that the small farmer should look up to the wealthier
landowners who were his neighbours, and that he
should be disposed to follow their lead. No such ties of sentiment could exist
between the old families and the population of the town. It was in the urban
proletariat that the demagogues found their chief support. Whatever may have
been the relative proportion of the rural and urban populations so far as they
consisted of citizens, it is quite certain that it would be the urban
population, rather than the rural, that would furnish a majority of the voters
in the Assembly. The inhabitant of Athens or the Piraeus was on the spot; it
would cost him little time or trouble to attend. The dweller in the more
distant demes of Attica would hesitate before he sacrificed a day’s work on his
farm (and it must often have meant two days rather than one), in order to
exercise his political rights. When payment was once introduced, the
attractions of office, as magistrate, or on the Council, or in the law-courts,
would make a stronger appeal to the town than to the country. Even a drachma a
day would hardly be a sufficient compensation to the farmer or the fisherman;
to the poorer sort of citizens in the City and the Port half this amount proved
an alluring bait. It was from this class that the jurors, at any rate, must
have been chiefly recruited. It followed that the policy of Athens came to be
determined more and more by the votes of the urban population, and that the
interests of the country were subordinated to those of the town. Nor can we
take the tone and temper of the Assembly in the Periclean Age as a fair
criterion of the sentiment of the citizen body as a whole. It hardly admits of
doubt that the Assembly was more radical in its views than the people.
VI.
THE DEMOS AND THE EMPIRE
Two other changes remain
to be noticed, each of which contributed to render the constitution still more
democratic in spirit. Both were the outcome of the rise and development of the
Athenian Empire.
Down to the beginning of
the fifth century b.c., Athens was a land, rather than a sea
power. Its navy was insignificant, and the military strength of the state
resided in the quality of its hoplites or heavy’ infantry. This force, being
mainly recruited from the small farmers of the countryside, was conservative in
sentiment. The Persian Wars and the policy of Themistocles converted Athens
into a naval power of the first rank, and with the growth of her Empire her
superiority at sea to all other states in the Greek world became more and more
marked. After the Thirty Years Peace it was evident that it was to her fleet,
and solely to her fleet, that Athens must look for the maintenance of that Empire.
Those of the seamen who were citizens were drawn from the class of Thetes, who for the most part were resident in Athens and
the Piraeus, and formed the radical element in the community.
In one of the most striking passages in the
Athenian Constitution, wrongly ascribed to Xenophon, the writer is at pains to
point out the connection between the Athenian Empire and the Athenian
Democracy. The Empire, he argues, depends on the navy, and the navy on the
seafaring population, and it is precisely because it is the navy that maintains
the power and prestige of Athens that the class from which the crews are drawn
is paramount in the Assembly. The first article in the programme of the Reactionaries after the failure of the Sicilian Expedition was the disfranchisement
of this class; but if the disfranchisement were to be permanent, the price
which would have to be paid for this reform was the surrender of the Empire. To
the conservative thinkers of the next century, to Isocrates and Aristotle, it
seemed that the policy of Themistocles and Pericles had been the undoing of
Athens. It is Isocrates who, amid the humiliations of the Social War in the
middle of the fourth century b.c., preaches the doctrine that the one
chance for Athens lies in the renunciation of her last claims to empire or
supremacy in the Aegean.
The second of these changes is to be found in the gradual process by which the Athenian courts acquired jurisdiction over the whole body of the subject-allies. It would be difficult to exaggerate the effect of this jurisdiction as an instrument of political education. It rendered a large proportion of the citizen body familiar with the circumstances and conditions of any number of states within the Empire; and it was the experience thus gained by the jurors in the courts of law that qualified them to deal with questions of imperial policy, when they came before them in the Council or the Assembly. It would also be difficult to exaggerate the influence of this imperial jurisdiction on the character of the constitution, and on the spirit in which it was worked. It was the citizen of the poorest class who was attracted by the pay, and it was he who sat enthroned in the courts. It is a remark of Aristotle’s that it is by means of the popular courts of law that the masses have gained their strength, since, when the democracy is master of the voting power in the courts, it is master of the constitution. The courts were in almost perpetual session; their jurisdiction extended to every aspect and department of public life; and from their decision there was no appeal. In the age of Cleon the sovereignty of the people finds expression in the lawcourts even more effectively than in the Council and Assembly.
CHAPTER VATTIC DRAMA IN THE FIFTH CENTURY
|