|
HISTORY OF CIVILIZATION IN THE FIFTH CENTURY.
CHAPTER
V.
ROMAN
LAW.
We have seen what
roots the old religion of Rome had struck out, how their dislodgment was the work
of centuries, and how the highest degree of wisdom, of courage, and of tact was
necessary to stifle error without doing violence to human nature, to destroy
Paganism without breaking the innocent symbols of the commerce between heaven
and earth. But its religious belief did not make up the essence of the Roman
civilization; its primitive dogma had come from the Etruscans—Greece had
brought to it its fables—the conquered East had yielded her mysteries; but that
which was the exclusive property of Rome was her genius for action, her destiny
was to realize on earth the idea of justice and found the empire of Law.
A time arrived
when Rome no longer remembered the art of conquest, but she was never to forget
the secrets of government. The moment even of her deepest decline, when the
barbarians revenged themselves upon her in every place, ordered her
proceedings, and debated with her the figure of her ransom—when they seemed to
have entirely fettered her action—was the period in which all her power was
reflected and gathered up into the codes of that legislation which was sooner
or later to achieve the conquest of the barbarians, to retain the world under
her tutelage after the fall of her empire, and compel the descendants of the
Visigoths, Burgundians, and Franks to seat themselves in the schools, and grow
pale over the text of the Roman law. We must study now this great victory of
thought over strength, and find the hidden force which bore up the Roman
constitution at the beginning of the fifth century, and what were to be its
respective losses or gains under the mighty blows which demolished the empire
of the West.
In
the first place stood the mass of jurisprudence of the classic epoch,
comprising the works of the entire succession of jurisconsults from Augustus to
the reigns of the Antonines. In order that no doubt might arise as to the
binding force of these decisions, a well-known constitution, issued under
Theodosius II and Valentinian III, in a.d. 426, laid down that in future the
writings of Papinian, Paulus, Gaius, Ulpian, and Modestinus should alone have
force of law; that in case of difference of opinion the view supported by the
majority should prevail, or, in the case of equality, the position taken by
Papinian. It might seem a rash measure to canonize, as it were, opinions,
controversy, consultations, often contradictory and full rather of subtlety
than genius, but there may be seen in it that great principle of Tradition
providentially preserved at Rome, and it is a happiness for posterity that
those maxims which the disasters of the Empire might well have crumbled into
dust were thus preserved, and invested with the character of inviolable law.
On the other
hand stood the ever-increasing collection of the constitutions of princes, and
especially of Christian princes. In 429, Theodosius the Younger and Valentinian
III, to remedy the confusion which had sprung up among them, appointed a
commission of nine jurisconsults, or men of official rank, to make a regular
compilation, in sixteen books, under their respective titles, of those
legislative enactments which bore on public or civil life, and to leave the
primitive text, as far as necessary correction and clearness would allow, free
from contradictory comments. Thus the whole series of legislation of the
Christian emperors was preserved to us, and respect was shown, notwithstanding
the thoroughness of the reaction which had followed them, even to the works of
Julian.
Accordingly the
Roman society possessed, in 430, two systems of law, and the barbarians found
face to face, on the one hand ancient Paganism tempered by the philosophy of
the jurisconsults themselves, acting, as we shall see, under Christian
influences, and on the other Christianity tempered by the timidity of the
emperors, who only embraced reforms already rough-hewn by their philosophic
lawyers, and measured out carefully the blows they were bound to strike at the
old institutions: here pagan law just gilded by the rising of Christianity
—there the beginning of Christian jurisprudence still entangled in the last
shades of the darkness from which the world was issuing.
We must examine
these two principles in order, and the result which they had brought about. We
see, on opening the text-books of the classic jurisprudence of the vaunted
epoch of the Antonines, that all the lawyers whose writings Valentinian had
codified, recognized still as a thing of the remote past but as supreme and
permanent, the law of the Twelve Tables. They cite, comment on, and often evade
it, but still did it homage in refusing to ignore, contravene, or abjure the
edicts graven on its bronze by the iron hand of the decemvirs: it was still
thus a master from whose scourge they sought in vain to escape. Let us sketch
in a few words, not the precepts but the tendency of that ancient pagan and
theocratic law-system whose authority, secular in its essence, the
jurisconsults did not as yet dare contemn. It was a half-sealed book, a
collection of traditions, sacramental formulas, and sacred rites, enveloping
the law under the same veils as a religion—a mass of mysteries whose secret the
patricians alone possessed, who as descendants of the gods could alone know and
enounce law (jus; fas, what is permitted; fatum, the
right, the Divine will). Law, in its primitive aspect, was the true and only
recognized religion of Rome. Its first act was to deify Rome herself, who
became not only the shrine and dwelling-place of an unknown genius to whom
altars were raised, and whose name was known only to the initiated, but herself
the mighty goddess who had altars not only in her peculiar territory, but
amongst her conquered nations, and even in Asia, on the shores of the Troad. As
divine, her will was justice; the law decided through her curies was legitimate
if ratified by consent of the gods in the taking of the auspices, and which
assumed a commerce between earth and heaven.
To give an act
life and a divine character, its accomplishment must be surrounded by rites
and ceremonies. God Himself intervened in the judgments and under the strokes
of the magistrate to give peace to His earth; execution was an act of
sacrifice; the tribunal, as asacred place, was to be turned to the East, to be
closed when the sun, type of the ray of intellect by which judgment is
enlightened, had set on the earth. This powerful theocratic imprint was
everywhere to be seen, and underlay all the civilization of Paganism. As Rome
was supreme in her sphere, so was every father a god in his own family, a
genius sent for a time here below. His will had all the features of law and
resistless destiny, admitting no limit, stretching to the right of life and
death over his dependants,—over his wife, whom he could judge; his son, whom he
could expose; his slave, whom he could put to death.
Authority, the
presence of irresistible will in all human actions, marked Roman law, gave to
it mystery, and also provoked the greatest awakening of liberty which had yet
been seen. Rome’s very function, in thus overstraining her principle of
authority, was to give a greater volume to the outburst of freedom, and the
most remarkable sight her history offers to us is that of the rigour of the
private prison, the sale of the debtor cut piecemeal, Virginia’s blood spirting
over the decemvirs, acting as God’s incentive to that very people to show us
as an example their eight-century-long delivery. This was first seen when the
plebs, straining to enter upon the sacred enclosure, long defended by the
patrician order, tore from their grasp in succession the connubium, the
magistrate’s offices, the auspices; lastly, the very secrets of the Law, and
when the freedman Flavius stole from Appius the Actions of Law, the formulas
of which that patrician had drawn up.
The movement,
begun under the Republic, lived on under the Empire, which did not close, as
has been erroneously supposed, the history of liberty; but the game changed,
and whilst under the Republic we see the patrician city stormed and carried by
the plebs, the Empire shows us every province, the whole West, besieging the
imperial city to gain a place at the sanctuary of law and public justice. The
emperor, often himself a foreigner, like Galba or Trajan, sprung from Spain,
acted as their representative, as invested with proconsular rank, and so
becoming familiar with the provinces whose natural protector he was. Caracalla,
after a long period of resistance and partial concession, threw down every
barrier, and in proclaiming Rome the common capital, with as many citizens as
she had subjects, impelled the Empire to its definitive destiny.
Such was the
history of the enfranchisement of the plebs and of the Western provinces, and
as races and men were pressing with such energy into the precinct so
obstinately guarded, Justice also began to find her place there through the
efforts of the praetor.
Every year that
magistrate, on entering office, proclaimed by edict the principles on which he
would administer justice. He was used to interpret the iron law of the Twelve
Tables with equity and clemency, to supply its lacunae, to throw light on its
obscurity, and softness over its rigour; and in this commenced that struggle
entered on by the magistrate against a text he was obliged to apply, regretting
its harshness, yet submitting to its authority while blunting its sharp edge.
The praetor and jurisconsults, who also had the right of extenuating law
principles, then created the Useful Actions, in order to supply what was
clearly wanting in the primitive system; and the emperors, opening their minds
to the light, called to their aid such men as Gaius, Ulpian, and Paulus, who
were influenced by the Stoic philosophy, and supported it by their authority,
not in Rome alone but throughout the Empire. The effort of human reason
developed under their sanction a new law-system, in which the law of the gens stood opposed to the civil law; to the civil family, composed only of agnats,
or relations on the male side, the natural family (cognatio), comprising
those related through females only; to the property of the Quirites, the
property by natural right, called in bonis; to succession to legitimate
descendants only as established by the Twelve Tables, the right of succession
in all alike to whose being nature had given the same author.
This was the
work of many centuries, at last effected by the conscience-cry of the plebs and
the help of philosophy in the shape of the Stoic lawyers. It was one of the
greatest spectacles reason could offer, not only as showing, as in the
jurisprudence of the Antonines, a triumph of good sense, of lucidity of
thought, a perfect purity of form, an edifice giving with unexpected felicity
space and clearness of arrangement to the former chaos of public and domestic
relations, but as a first-fruit of satisfaction to humanity, as tempering
woman’s lot by dower; paternal authority, by suppressing its right of life and
death ; the condition of slaves, by declaring, through Antoninus Pius, to
whoever could escape from his master’s rod and embrace the prince’s statue, the
protection of a magistrate, who must descend from the tribunal, cover him with
a fold of his robe, and compel his owner to transfer him to another more humane
than himself.
While
recognizing the services of human reason, and the merits of this ancient
jurisprudence, we see beneath the surface what was wanting to this first effort
of man’s intelligence, the vices still inevitably lurking in it, which gave it
up to the time of which we treat that pagan character so difficult to
eradicate. Fiction appears everywhere; a superstitious respect for a past
openly belauded, but secretly disdained. The entire labour of the praetor was
lavished on a succession of subterfuges by which to evade a law he dared not
overturn, to escape from their inflexible Twelve Tables, not one of whose
long-traced lines he dared efface. If, for instance, they only granted
succession to relations on the male side, to grant it to those of defunct
female descent a fiction was necessary by supposing in the formula of
deliverance the new possessor to be the heir. As the old law willed that
certain chattels, called mancipia, could only pass by mancipation,
or by usucaption, had an article of that class been delivered to a
claimant by simple tradition, and been lost before possession had been
acquired by usucaption, property in it, according to strict law, was
gone, yet the praetor allowed a revendication, by supposing a previous usucaption after the forms of the publician action. Roman law, again, taking no cognizance
of foreigners, afforded them no action to enforce respect of their rights. The actio
furti would not, for instance, lie, as, according to strict civil law, it
was not open to a foreigner; but the praetor would grant it by the fiction of
supposing him a Roman citizen.
Such things
were calculated sooner or later to bring into contempt so essentially simple a
system of law. This faithless superstition and dishonest interpretation
represents what was passing in Paganism at large—maintenance of form and
absence of faith. The old law stood on the same footing as the mythology. It
was a mere fable (carmen serium); serious in the sense of having much
which was evil on its pages, and also a mere song, in that its inspiration had
ceased. Men listened to its frequent repetition, and then passed on to other
and graver occupations. Not an education of some years alone, but that of an
entire life, was necessary to find the way through its mazes, which again
began to contain a mystery in which very few were adepts; only it was no longer
the patricians who held the deposit, but the school, the family of jurisconsults,
the few devoted by the state to the study of law, and who alone, in diving into
its recesses, could exercise that species of priestly office which Ulpian
defined, Jus est ars boni et cequi cujus merito quis nos sacerdotes appellet.
Ammianus Marcellinus, living at the close of the fourth century, leaves us the
following | picture of the lawyers of his da :—“You would think they professed
the drawing of horoscopes or unfolding the Sibylline oracles, to see the deep
gravity of their faces, in loudly boasting of a science wherein one can merely
grope.” So the chief vice of Paganism had not vanished; still there appeared
the adepts, few in number and without the vulgar herd; philosophy had succeeded
the old religions, detesting, like them, the common people—that is to say, the
multitude, humanity itself. Its second vice was the maintenance of the absolute
sovereignty of the state over not property only, but life, souls, and
consciences, carrying out the old principle according to which Rome was divine
and so was her will; and to its legitimate laws human will could find no place
of resistance, as no one could be right in contradicting the gods. But a
considerable change had still come about, for the name of the genius hitherto
dwelling in mystery on the Capitol was at last revealed. It was sometimes named
Tiberius, or Nero, or Heliogabalus, and its works were known as well. The
Empire became an idolatry, of which the Emperor was priest and god. Altars were
raised to him in his lifetime; his images were sent in all directions, to be
greeted with light and perfume, and thousands of Christians died rather than
cast on the fire at their feet some grains of frankincense. He was a true god,
in fact, while living as after death, ordaining this, willing the contrary on
the morrow, exercising a tyranny the more intolerable from its being exercised
in a moral sphere, and suffering no other will; declaring to the Christians by
the organ of the jurisconsults that their existence could not be permitted, “non licet esse vos;” crushing the state-right itself in placing the prince
above the law, princeps legibus solutus; to which privilege it was
determined that the sovereign, acceding to her the half of his rights, could
also raise his Empress. The will of one thus placed above all law naturally
became imperious and irresistible, and the conclusion of the jurisconsults, quod
principi placuit legis habet vigorem utpote cum lege regia populus ei et in eum
omne suum imperium et potestatem conferet, led to that formula so insulting
to humanity wherewith princes so often have terminated their acts, “for such is
our good pleasure.” Not only did the prince’s pleasure become the world’s law,
but he owned beside the pontifical office, the absolute power of making and
unmaking legislation, and nearly the whole Roman territory. The soil of the
provinces had been divided into two great parts: the tributary, under the
Emperor, and the stipendiary, depending on the Roman people. In course of time
the former succeeded to the latter, and thus the whole property in the
provinces devolved on the sovereign so thoroughly that no private person was considered
an actual proprietor, but only a stipendiary maintained and guaranteed till
further notice in its use by the Imperial will. Hence no subject could complain
when the most sacred treasury sacratissimum ararium claimed some portion
of his goods, or when taxes, indictions, or superindictions were imposed, or
the land itself distrained, as the prince only took his own. On this principle
stood the fiscal system of Rome, full of exactions, which reduced the groaning
provinces to such a pitch of distress that the curia responsible for the levy
of the impost was gradually deserted by the decurions, whose place was filled
by men of evil life and broken fortunes, by concubinous priests and their
bastard offspring, since the honour had come to be looked on rather as a
disgrace. The provincials, tortured, forced to sell wife and child to satisfy
these requirements, began to abandon their lands, and to call upon the
barbarians in aid, assured of finding in them less exacting masters, and
preferring to render them one or two thirds of the soil than be subject to a
system which carried off the total of their revenues. All the confusion at the
beginning of the Lower Empire, the responsibility of which has been fixed upon
the Christian emperors, flowed naturally from principles long before
established. When Aurelian took to himself the diadem of Persia and the pomps
of the East, then Diocletian established that hierarchy of officials which was
to crush the Empire with its weight, and the government in the days of its
strength sowed the seeds of its ruin.
A third radical
vice in Paganism, an unmistakable sign of its last catastrophe, was that
terrible inequality which no effort of reason could justify. At the root of its
legislation, written though it were by the immortal pen of a Gaius or an
Ulpian, lay that heathen emanation principle which supposed that some men
sprang from the head, others from the belly or feet of the all-pervading deity.
This kept women in perpetual tutelage, not in the legitimate guardianship of
her agnate alone, but in a dative tutelage restraining her capacity in
the most trifling actions of civil life. It subjected the child to not only
the paternal right of life and death, but to that of sale. He was open to
exposal on his birth, condemned to a continual minority, whatever his age or
dignity might be, deprived of every kind of property, up to the time of
Constantine, except the “peculium castrense,” or military pay. It kept up the
servile system, the well-known horrors of which existed not only in the heroic
and mythical ages, but throughout those centuries of light and philosophical
wisdom that were for so many a time of freedom. The opinions of Greek
philosophers on the subject were not doubtful. Plato did not admit slavery into
the Republic, but dared not condemn it in his native city; and Aristotle gave
human nature itself for its cause, saying that some were made for rule and
others for obedience. Cicero held the same view. Cum autem hi famulantur qui sibi moderari nequeant nulla
injuria est. “There is no
injustice in making slaves of those who know not self-government.” In his
admirable treatise De Officiis, the masterpiece of ancient morality, he
relates, without commentary, certain cases of conscience proposed by a
philosopher named Hecaton. Is a master in a famine time bound to feed his
slaves? Economy says No; humanity Yes. Hecaton decides against it. Suppose
one’s self adrift in a small boat with a bad slave and a good horse on board; a
storm comes on, which of the two should be thrown overboard? Hecaton and Cicero
will not pronounce upon it. Such was the philosophy of the best epoch of Rome,
which time did not do much to modify. To come down to Libanius : in his
discourse on slavery he takes care not to repeat Christian complaints about
it, nor to let slip any of the old pagan traditions on the subject. Slavery is
an evil common to all mortals; all men serve either their passions or their
business or their duty—the peasant is the slave of wind and rain, the professor
of his audience. Slaves in name are least slaves in reality, but happiest of
all in knowing nothing of hunger, that pitiless master; happy in their state of
careless lethargy, leaving their master the care of finding them food; and it
is thus that passion and selfishness have argued in every age as to slaves of
every colour.
The opinion of
the philosophers became the doctrine of the jurisconsults, whose duty it was to
inspire theory and reduce it to practice. The ancient law had a punishment of
death for the slaughterer of a steer; but when Q. Flaminius, the senator, to
amuse an abandoned youth, who was his companion, and was regretting at never
having seen any one put to death, cut the head off one of his slaves, it was
silent, having no penalty for that kind of fault. They had instituted a fine
for the murder of a slave, but hastened to remedy their weakness by taking back
from liberty what they had granted to slavery; and by the laws Aelia Sentia,
Junia Norbana, and Fusia Caninia, they calmed the terrors of the
serious, who feared revolution on seeing at some funeral games a few freedmen,
clad in their caps of liberty, taking their place among citizens, by
restraining the frequency of enfranchisement, and closing the city of Rome to
the freed. Different orders were distinguished in the Servile ranks, such as deditii,
who could never become citizens, and the Latini Juniani, who could only
become citizens in certain cases. The senatus-consult of Silanian, drawn up
under Claudius, had ordained torture to all his slaves upon the violent death
of any man; and Tacitus paints the terrified stupor of the city when it was one
day announced that a senator had died by violence, and that his four hundred
slaves were to be put to the torture. Hanging a slave was forbidden, but he might
die under the torment, and then his price must be paid to the master.
Nourishment was due to him, and Cato tells us how a prudent head of the family
should arrange the matter. “Pour two amphorae of sweet wine into a cask; add
two of very sharp vinegar, and as much boiled wine, to the dilution of
two-thirds, with fifty amphorae of fresh water. Stir up the whole with a stick
for five consecutive days, and then pour in sixty-four measures of sea-water.”
Paganism appears clearly here, and the bitter beverage that Cato used to give
his slaves reminds us of a certain sponge of vinegar and gall which another
Roman, a soldier, was to offer on the lance’s point to that other slave who was
dying on a cross for the redemption of slaves.
As to their
housing, Columella prescribed “ergastula subterranea”, in which openings
were to be contrived out of reach of the hand, either for the purpose of preventing
escape, or of cutting off the sight of the world, which was denied them. Those
employed at the mill carried a large wheel round their necks to prevent their
raising to the mouth a handful of the flour that they spent the day in
grinding. This deprives the Chinese of the honour of having invented their
peculiar mode of torture, and it was the mildest method of treatment, as the
law of Antonine had not taken away the right of making eunuchs of slaves, and
they were to be counted by troops, greges puerorum, as well as crowds of
gladiator-slaves who assembled in the lanista, and took the terrible oath to
let themselves be burnt, fettered, scourged, and slaughtered, uri, vinciri,
verberari, ferroque necari, if not
men at least merchandise, subject-matter for contracts of sale and purchase,
and therefore obliging, in some manner, the attention of the jurisconsults.
Gaius, in examining the difficulties which might arise in certain cases, in
declaring a contract to be one of sale, or merely of hiring, proposed the
following question:—“If I tender you a number of gladiators at the rate of
twenty denarii ahead for those who survive, as wages for their toils, and a
thousand ahead for the dead and wounded, is there a sale or a letting? The
prevailing opinion is that, as to the survivors, it is a hiring; as to dead or
wounded a sale, the event deciding it, as if each slave was conditionally an
object either of sale or hire, for there is no doubt that either
contract may be subject to conditions.” It is a question which is the most
wonderful, the calm of the lawyer, or the horror of the prevailing manners. And
those manners did not soften; we find Trojan, on his return from Dacia, putting
to death ten thousand gladiators. Fear was expressed lest oxen should fail, but
no one seemed to fear a scarcity of gladiators. The Roman law of the classic
period, as modified by the legislation of the Antonines, was certainly like the
Coliseum, a splendid monument, wherein men were thrown to lions! At the
beginning of the fifth century, all this jurisprudence still had force, and had
just been invigorated by the law of Citations, under Valentinian III, but
happily for a Christian period, a rival system was rising in the code
inaugurated by Theodosius.
Christianity
had early penetrated the Empire, coming as a doctrine that hated fiction,
unable by reason of its liberty to suffer enslavement of conscience, or by its
charity all those social inequalities which were an outrage to nature. Yet it
did not aspire to change violently the world’s aspect, but rather to win its
point slowly and with patience, and like the Saviour to destroy slavery in
becoming itself a slave, formam servi accipiens. While Plato daily
thanked the gods that he had been born male rather than female, free and not a
slave, a Greek instead of a barbarian, it proclaimed by St. Paul that there was
no longer male nor female, free nor slave, Greek nor barbarian, but one body in
Christ Jesus, a saying strong enough to effect as ages passed the great changes
which God had determined. It could not tolerate imperial pretensions over the
conscience of mankind, and whilst praying for its persecutors proclaimed that
God rather than man was to be obeyed. Finally it repulsed all the pagan
fictions, but yet in its contempt for a law which was reserved for a little
band of experts, and hidden perforce from the multitude, it did not profess to
despise the Roman law-system. As was declared in the Apostolic Constitutions,
“God did not will that His justice should be shown forth only by us, but let it
shine in the Roman laws;” and St. Augustine said, “Leges Romanorum
divinitus per ora principum emanarunt.” It received these laws with
admiration, recognizing in them the light which lightens every man coming into
the world that he might know and adore his God, and was forced to toil with
patience to reform in accordance with its principles the legislation whose
vices we have examined. Its presence was early suspected and soon perceived,
but this is not the place for showing how the new society toiled in its
catacombs, hidden deep under another hostile society whose reform it had
entered upon; how in every rank of public and domestic life, in the senate and
the foulest ergastula, it knew how to mould disciples and to enlighten
and modify the manners of the time. It has been pointed out how St. Paul, by
his speech on Areopagus, his dispute with Stoics and Epicureans, his apology at
Corinth before the Roman magistrate, Annaeus Gallio, must have roused the
opinions of his contemporaries and of those Greeks and philosophers so greedy
of novelty; in particular, Gallio must have informed his beloved brother Seneca,
who dedicated to him his treatises De Ira and De Vita Beata, of
the fame and doctrines of that Graecized Jew who went to make proselytes at
Rome in the very palace of Nero. Seneca’s own doctrines bear witness to the
necessary contact between Pagan and Christian philosophy. His stoicism put in
the place of the ancient fatum, the third arbiter of our destinies, a
Providence, a Divine Father, to honour and obey; it gave him faith in the
soul’s immortality, and the conflict here below between spirit and flesh, an
enemy to be conquered only by Divine help, namely grace, and filled him with a
singular pity for all human sorrow, and especially for his enslaved fellow-
creature. It is pleasant to believe that this Stoic bore the impress of a
Christian philosopher, who was at Rome in the time of Seneca, and was destined
to die there more gloriously than himself.
It seems
inevitable that the Christians, daily increasing in numbers, filling the
forum, the senate, and the army, with the apologies of Quadratus, Bishop of
Athens, of Athenagoras, St. Justin, Tertullian, and the senator Apollonius,
circulating through every rank of society, should influence the Stoic
philosophy and the jurisconsults through it. Their admission to the councils
of Alexander Severus, who adored amongst his lares the image of Christ,
and inscribed in golden letters on his palace walls the maxims of Christianity,
points to the growing force of the new religion. The plagiarism of the
jurisconsults from its sources, though denied on account of their inveterate
hostility, was but the last resource of a baffled enemy, trying to disarm truth
by borrowing its principles, which were attracting every heart. Julian meant
this in advising the pagans about him to imitate the Christian priests and open
hospitals; and the jurisconsults laboured to disarm the Gospel by infusing it
into Roman law, that there might remain no excuse for reforming a society open
to legitimate progress, or to destroy a religion so capable of wholesome
reform.
When Christianity
ascended the throne with Constantine, far from exacting too much and assuming
empire as a conqueror, it continued its course with the same calmness.
Constantine acted with caution, retaining the title of Supreme Pontiff, and
still issuing edicts as to the manner of consulting the auspices. The tactics
of his successors were similar: one advanced, another drew back, but all
hesitated, and the Theodosian Code still preserved slavery, divorce,
concubinage, inequality between man and wife, and father and son, though three
great novelties found place in it. In the first place an effort was made to
give to law a character of publicity and sincerity. Under Constantine the
sacramental formulas relating to wills, stipulations, and other acts of civil life,
the sacramental syllables, called by the Christian emperors aucupatio
syllabarum, as well as the whole system of juridical subtleties, fell to
the ground ; and by determining the names of the jurists whose decisions should
have force, and uniting in one code, as was the case under Theodosius and
Valentinian, the scattered edicts of the Christian princes, a popular and
accessible form was given to the law. Secondly, the temporal and spiritual
orders were separated, and in this respect advance was less easy, for, as
Constantine had retained the title of pontiff, his successors were willing to
believe that the religion of the Empire alone had changed, and not their old supremacy
over the conscience. The Church had to labour perseveringly in preventing their
usurpation of the right of convoking and presiding in her councils, saying in
the words of Lucifer of Cagliari, “What! are we to respect your diadems,
bracelets, and earrings, and despise the Creator?” The declaration wrung from
Theodosius and Valentinian, “ It is worthy of a prince’s majesty to pronounce
himself bound by the laws,” ended the struggle by the victory of the Church,
and then the monarch became subject to law, and the temporal power took up the
less splendid but firmer position assigned it in the Gospel: “Let him who would
be first be the servant of all.” In the last place, the hands of the emperors
touched with healing the three great wounds humanity bore in the injury done to
women, children, and slaves. Constantine gave mothers a larger share in
succession to their children, forbade exposing infants, and punished the child
murderer in the same measure as the parricide. He abolished crucifixion as a
punishment for slaves, issued an edict against the gladiatorial combats, “not
willing,” as he said, “such bloody sights in the midst of the Peace of the
Empire,” and condemned to death the master who had killed a slave. “Let
masters use their right with clemency, and let that man be held a murderer who
shall have slain his slave voluntarily by blows of rods or of stones, or by
mortally wounding him with a dart, who shall have hung him by a halter, or by
cruel order had him thrown into an abyss, or made him drink poison, or caused
savage beasts to tear his body, or branded his flesh with burning coals, or in
frightful torment caused life to flee from his bloody and foam-flecked limbs
with a fierceness worthy only of barbarians.” This eloquent law, dated a.d. 319, well expresses the Christian indignation
at the horrors of slavery, and shows the Church, just clothed with the purple,
hastening to make a law in favour of her enslaved children.
In this manner
did the Theodosian Code remedy the triple outrage offered by the old system to
liberty, truth, and humanity, in slavery and domestic inequality. It was no
wonder that the reading, by the Prefect of Rome and the consuls, of the edict
inaugurating the Theodosian Code throughout the Empire was received by the
senate with magnificent applause. The last minutes of its sittings contained
this ratification, and its acclamations must have penetrated to the camp of the
barbarians, already established in a.d. 438, on Roman territory. At the very
moment when the Vandals were masters of Africa, the Burgundians and Visigoths
of Gaul and Spain, and Attila was advancing at the head of his Huns, by a
sublime coincidence the legislation was proclaimed which was destined to master
the future. Its fame was to reach those barbarians, whose kings would seek to
know the great idea of Roman law which was never to abandon them. The edict of
Theodosius, in the year 500, proclaimed the Theodosian Code the law of the
Ostrogoths; Alaric gave his subjects, a few years later, the “Breviarium
Alaricanum,” extracted from the same code; and in 534 the “Papiani Responsa,”
in great measure collected from it again, appeared for the use of the Roman
subjects of the Burgundians. Nor was its destiny to end there; it was taught
throughout Gaul, particularly in the schools of Clermont, during the sixth and
seventh centuries. Carried into England to the school of York, into Germany in
the peaceful train of conquering Boniface, it was to serve as basis to the
capitularies of Frankish kings, and thus penetrating into all the barbarian
legislation, to give it temper, enlightenment, and system.
It is true that
the barbarian chiefs were no less taken by its faults than by its merits, and
did not shrink from assuming the heirship of the Roman emperors with regard to
their subjects’ goods. In this spirit Frederick Barbarossa caused his lawyers to
decide, at Roncaglia, that as Trajan’s heir he was absolute master of his
subjects’ property; the same doctrine was adopted by Louis XIV in speaking of
his royal goods, “of which part are comprised in our demesne, the rest left by
our good pleasure in the hands of our subjects;” and such pagan traditions have
been handed down to become, under other forms, the gravest danger of the
present day.
The last
traditions of divorce in the family were to disappear in the great struggle of
the Papacy against Philip Augustus and Henry IV. Slaves gradually were to
become serfs, and serfs freemen. Lastly, the great principle of the separation
of the spiritual and temporal orders was to gain its victory at the moment when
Gregory VII gave out his dying cry, “I fought for justice, and therefore am
dying in exile.” He died, but the principle which he supported so vigorously
gained a stronger life, for the ideas which save the human race are those which
suffer all that is mortal in them to perish.
Roman law was
to rule the world on condition of the fall of the Roman Empire; nothing less
was required to dissipate the mist of legal fiction and the remnant of that
deep discord which was rooted in the old system. The swords of Attila and
Odoacer were to banish the lingering phantom of the imperial
throne, and to give breathing space to the world, to revive the soul of the old
law on that principle of natural equity which began its struggle in the blood
of Virginia and on the Sacred Hill, continued it by tribune’s word and praetor’s
edict, found a new power in the Stoic philosophy, and its ultimate triumph in
Christianity. When stripped of its trappings of gold and purple, of imperial
pomp and human circumstance, it issued forth lord of the world at the moment
of its apparent dissolution.
|